Strawson Intention and Convention in Speech Acts
Strawson Intention and Convention in Speech Acts
Author(s): P. F. Strawson
Source: The Philosophical Review , Oct., 1964, Vol. 73, No. 4 (Oct., 1964), pp. 439-460
Published by: Duke University Press on behalf of Philosophical Review
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
Duke University Press and are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend
access to The Philosophical Review
439
440
II
44I
442
443
not owed to any conventions other than those which help to give
it its meaning. Surely there may be cases in which to utter the
words "The ice over there is very thin" to a skater is to issue a
warning (is to say something with the force of a warning) without
its being the case that there is any statable convention at all
(other than those which bear on the nature of the locutionary act)
such that the speaker's act can be said to be an act done as con-
forming to that convention.
Here is another example. We can readily imagine circum-
stances in which an utterance of the words "Don't go" would be
correctly described not as a request or an order, but as an en-
treaty. I do not want to deny that there may be conventional
postures or procedures for entreating: one can, for example,
kneel down, raise one's arms and say, "I entreat you." But I do
want to deny that an act of entreaty can be performed only as
conforming to some such conventions. What makes X's words to
r an entreaty not to go is something-complex enough, no doubt-
relating to X's situation, attitude to r, manner, and current
intention. There are questions here which we must discuss later.
But to suppose that there is always and necessarily a convention
conformed to would be like supposing that there could be no
love affairs which did not proceed on lines laid down in the
Roman de la Rose or that every dispute between men must follow
the pattern specified in Touchstone's speech about the counter-
check quarrelsome and the lie direct.
Another example. In the course of a philosophical discussion
(or, for that matter, a debate on policy) one speaker raises an
objection to what the previous speaker has just said. X says (or
proposes) that p and r objects that q. r's utterance has the force
of an objection to X's assertion (or proposal) that p. But where
is the convention that constitutes it an objection ? That r's utter
has the force of an objection may lie partly in the character of the
dispute and of X's contention (or proposal) and it certainly lies
partly, in r's view of these things, in the bearing which he takes
the proposition that q to have on the doctrine (or proposal) that
p. But although there may be, there does not have to be, any
convention involved other than those linguistic conventions
which help to fix the meanings of the utterances.
444
III
445
446
447
448
IV
449
450
45'
452
453
I remarked earlier that the words "Don't go" may have the
force, inter alia, either of a request or of an entreaty. In either
454
455
456
457
458
459
P. F. STRAWSON
University College, Oxford
460