Bond Hegel Madness
Bond Hegel Madness
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted
digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about
JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
This content downloaded from 147.188.128.74 on Sat, 25 Jun 2016 09:19:09 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
History of Philosophy Quarterly
Volume 11, Number 1, January 1994
I. INTRODUCTION
FREUDorder
proposed as aatbasic
to arrive whatprinciple
is normal of
andhis psychoanalytic
apparently theory
so simple, that
we shall "in
have
to study the pathological with its distortions and exaggerations."2 An exami
nation of Hegel's generally overlooked theory of madness (Verr?cktheit) re
veals a similar position. Hegel holds that "insanity [is] an essential...[and]
necessarily occurring form or stage...in the development of the soul"?not, of
course, in the sense that we are all inevitably destined to derangement, but
rather because madness represents a constantly threatening and yet seductive
possibility prepared for by our encounter with the fundamentally alienating
character of life. Further, there are certain essential "contradictions" and
"oppositions" that Hegel sees as inherent in madness which are "still pre
served" and mirrored in the rational mind (PM ?408 Z)3?for example, the
contradictions between the unconscious and the conscious, between nature and
spirit, and between the inner world of desire and the outer world of "otherness"
which stands opposed to our private desires. These contradictions are ineluc
table features of all mind, and since they appear much more vividly in madness,
a study of madness affords us a particularly illuminating perspective from
which to view the "normal."4
But it is not only a study of madness which allows us to look at what Freud
calls the "distortions and exaggerations" of psychic life in order to gain insight
71
This content downloaded from 147.188.128.74 on Sat, 25 Jun 2016 09:19:09 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
72 HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY QUARTERLY
into the "normal." Hegel's philosophy is one which emphasizes the inherently
alienating character of life: human history is a "slaughterbench" of happiness
(RH 27); the path of development of consciousness is one of loss, doubt, and
despair (PS 49); and the life of spirit is continually confronted by "the tremen
dous power of the negative," or more starkly put, by "devastation" {Verw?s
tung) (PS 19/PG 36). As such, consciousness is delivered over to a state of
yearning for wholeness, for peace, for redemption from discord, without ever
being able to achieve it in any lasting way. This leads to the construction of
strategies for realizing harmony which often become desperate. This is in fact
the origin of many forms of madness, according to Hegel, when consciousness
"reverts" or "sinks back" into disease in response to the devastation of its
desires. But there are what we might call "transitional" or "borderline" strate
gies as well, desperate to be sure, yet still located by Hegel within the terrain
of the "normal" or rational consciousness. These are extreme forms of alienated
existence which still cling to rationality but which struggle with the alluring
promise of release that madness offers.5
The forms of consciousness which occupy positions on the borderline between
the "normal" and the "deranged" offer sufficient "distortions and exaggera
tions" in their own right to provide, along with madness, the desired goal of a
point of access to the "normal" through the distortion of the normal. But more,
their peculiar positioning within the between-space of the rational and mad
souls promises a unique vantage point from which to examine the intersection
of rationality and madness, a psychical interstice in which we are forced to ask
the question of what really separates the two.
A clear example of such a transitional or borderline state of being is despair,
or the "unhappy consciousness." The unhappy consciousness is the "grief and
longing" of the self which yearns for unity but experiences only inner division
and estrangement (PS 456f), and shares with madness the characteristic of a
double personality, "the duplication of self-consciousness within itself which
is experienced only as "self-contradiction" (PS 126).6 Many other examples
occur in Hegel's Phenomenology as well: "scepticism" is described as an "un
conscious, thoughtless rambling" {bewu?tlose Faselei) (PS 125/PG 162), and
Faselei is a subcategory ofBl?dsinn, one of the three main categories in Hegel's
typology of insanity; the "law of the heart," when pushed to its extreme, is
characterized as "derangement" {die Verr?cktheit des Bewu?tseins) (PS
225/PG 280); the attitude of "virtue" is an internal contradiction which culmi
nates in madness (Verr?cktheit) (PS 229/PG 285); the standpoint of "absolute
freedom and terror" (PS 359) is explicitly diagnosed in the Encyclopaedia as a
form of "frenzy" {Wahnsinn, a major category of madness, PM ?408 Z); and the
"beautiful soul" is a "lost soul" consumed by a yearning for unity which it cannot
attain, finally becoming "disordered to the point of madness" {zur Verr?cktheit
zerr?ttet) (PS 407/PG 491).
The present essay will explore a comparison of madness with yet another
Hegelian theme which exists on the border of madness, a theme which not only
This content downloaded from 147.188.128.74 on Sat, 25 Jun 2016 09:19:09 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
HEGEL ON MADNESS AND TRAGEDY 73
plays a key role in his phenomenological project, but also has a larger meta
physical and aesthetic significance: that of tragedy. Like despair, skepticism,
the law of the heart, and the other forms of consciousness which exist in the
between-space of madness and rationality, tragic action, while not pathological
in principle, shares many of the same mental structures and strategies as
madness. It is striking, indeed, to see how frequently the language of madness
is evoked on the tragic stage. As Bennett Simon notes of the ancient Greek
stage, not only "madness in metaphorical terms...is extremely common in the
plays of the three great tragedians,.. .but frank clinical madness, complete with
hallucinations and delusions,...is also rather common."7 While Hegel does not
draw out the connections between madness and tragedy, either in his phenome
nology or in his aesthetics, the two in fact share a large constellation of themes
which are critical to his philosophy as a whole.
The purpose of this article is to explore several of the most important of these
themes. It will be shown that both madness and tragic action involve ontologies
of disunion?both are inwardly divided, "doubled" forms of consciousness?and
as such highlight Hegel's elaboration of an ontology of alienation at the center
of his phenomenology. Further, within this divided state, both exhibit what
Hegel calls the "double center of reality," the reality of the inner world and that
of the outer world, in particularly poignant ways: outer reality is experienced
as the dreadful world of an alien fate, and in their confrontations with fate,
both the mad and tragic selves recenter their desires and designs around an
inner reality which is essentially dislocated from the outer world. This recen
tering in turn uncovers a world of constant inversion, reversal, and peripety, a
world and a way of acting which is perpetually inscribed within double mean
ings and ambiguous implications. Additionally, it is just this inwardly divided
and inverted world which enables the phenomena of madness and tragic action
to reveal the human struggle with guilt and the nature of evil in especially
dramatic ways. And finally, madness and tragedy each involve an intimate
relation to "nature," to the domain of feeling, passion, and unconscious drives,
and allow us to see how Hegel develops a "depth psychology" to explore the
dynamics of unconscious mental life.
As an investigation of these connections between madness and tragedy, this
essay will also serve to lay the foundation for a fresh look at Hegel's anatomy
of the "normal" mind. For again, madness and tragedy are not so much opposite
ways of being to that of the fully rational consciousness, as they are distorted
images of it. This is what allows Sophocles' Odysseus to look upon Ajax's
madness and see there his own "dim shape" and "shadow" (Aj 1. 126). As such,
madness and tragedy highlight in a graphic way basic features of the everyday
world of "normal" experience: we are all inwardly divided and doubled selves;
we all exist within a double center of reality and must struggle with the sense
of an alien fate; we all act within a world of double meanings, of ambiguity,
inversion and reversal; we are all subjects of guilt in our very being; and we
are all creatures of nature as well as spirit, of unconscious motives and drives
as well as conscious intentions.
This content downloaded from 147.188.128.74 on Sat, 25 Jun 2016 09:19:09 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
74 HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY QUARTERLY
Further, the broken and divided character of the world effects a similar inner
division of consciousness. The "gulf between "inward strivings and external
reality" (HP I 52) means that satisfaction can only be achieved momentarily,
that fulfillment is ephemeral, that desire is constantly rekindled, and that
consciousness experiences itself as inwardly torn between its desire for whole
ness and its feeling of being dispossessed. The whole course of Hegel's Phe
nomenology may be read as an account of different therapeutic efforts on the
part of consciousness to heal the wounds of the spirit, to struggle for a sense
of reconciliation of its inner division.
But while madness and tragedy fall within the universal experience of a
broken world, and share with all forms of consciousness the struggle to heal
their inner disunity, they are extreme cases, and thus greatly magnify the
contours of Hegel's phenomenological landscape of alienation. Abrief sketch of
some of the key ideas in Hegel's definitions of madness and tragedy will allow
us to see the central place of the ontology of disunion in these two dramatic
forms of alienation.
This content downloaded from 147.188.128.74 on Sat, 25 Jun 2016 09:19:09 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
HEGEL ON MADNESS AND TRAGEDY 75
The motive for this movement of withdrawal and separation is to heal the
sense of alienation by effectively removing the external world, which is expe
rienced as the theater of infinite pain. Very much in anticipation of the
Freudian theory of mental illness, Hegel sees the mad self as replacing reality
with a substitute formation, a subjectively projected reality, a "shadow cast by
the mind's own light" (PM ?385 Z). Again prefiguring Freud, Hegel draws a
connection between this gesture of projective wish-fulfillment and dreams:
madness, in fact, is described as a sort of "dreaming while awake" (PM ?408
Z), where the insane self projects its inward dreams of unity onto the world
and treats them as real.9
This content downloaded from 147.188.128.74 on Sat, 25 Jun 2016 09:19:09 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
76 HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY QUARTERLY
This double center of reality is evident in both of the basic forms of ancient
tragic collision Hegel identifies, represented by Sophocles'Antigone and Oedipus
the King, respectively. In the Antigone the opposition is between the demands of
social-political life and those of the family; between the divinities of light and
darkness, the "daylight" gods of the state and the "nether" gods of instinct, feeling,
and blood-ties; and between what Hegel configures as the masculine and the
feminine powers of life (FAI, 293; FAII, 215; FAIV, 318; PS 267ff, 284). In Oedipus
This content downloaded from 147.188.128.74 on Sat, 25 Jun 2016 09:19:09 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
HEGEL ON MADNESS AND TRAGEDY 77
the King the collision is between the principles of consciousness and the uncon
scious, between what is open and what is hidden, between volitional and unin
tentional acts (FA I 276; FA IV 319; PS 283f, 446-48; LR 354n).
More will be said about these two plays later, but already some similarities
between the ontology of disunion in tragic action and madness are discernible.
Just as madness presents a world which is doubled between the desires of
internal reality and the relentlessly alienating force of external reality, tragic
action is situated in a world which is divided against itself, between the tragic
actor's "pathos"14?that is, the "power of the emotional life," or "the essential
cravings of the human heart" (FA I 308f, 292)?and the opposing authority of
external reality which is experienced as "the eternal necessity of a dreadful
fate" (PS 279). Just as madness "clings to itself and has its objectivity within
itself," recentering reality within the "fixed idea" of its own interior life (PM
?408 Z), the tragic actor has the "center of unity" within his or her own "pathos"
(FA I 321)?Antigone, for example, in the "pathos" of family, of instinct, of the
gods of the underworld, and Oedipus in the "pathos" of the dominion of
consciousness, the sovereignty of what is open to sight. And just as madness
cannot escape alienation, but is haunted by the trace of reality and ration
ality it seeks so desperately to efface, the tragic actor is undone by the
center of existence which opposes it?Antigone by light, Oedipus by dark
ness, Antigone by the power of the political state, Oedipus by the power of
the unconscious.
Similarly, just as it was shown that the doubling of the center of reality in
madness effected a corresponding splitting of consciousness into a double
personality, the collisional nature of reality in tragedy also reveals an inward
duality of character. Given Hegel's claim that modern, or Romantic tragedy
locates the conflict of powers within the character itself, while in ancient
tragedy, "the tragic character possesses a definite type, a single fully self-con
sistent pathos" (FA I 321, and see IV 310, 335), this double personality of the
tragic actor is in principle more clearly present in modern tragedy?for exam
ple, in Hamlet's spirit of revenge and his debilitating inertia; in MacBeth's
commitment to evil and his simultaneous revulsion by it, in his inclination to
brutality and his desire to resist it; in Othello's powerful faith and the doubt
which unhinges it, in his great love and the corrosive jealously which
destroys it; in Caesar's wisdom and self-deception, in his courage and
superstition; in Cleopatra's paradoxical nature as both harlot and goddess,
simultaneously corrupt and holy; and in Iago's lament that "I am not what
I am" (Othello I, i).
And yet it is possible to see this doubleness in all tragic figures?certainly
in Oedipus, who is torn between what he knows and what he is, who is the
subject of a "double striking curse," with "darkness on his eyes, that now have
such straight vision," who knows not "where he lives, nor whom he lives with"
(OK 11. 414-19), whose mother/wife Jocasta invokes the gods to "keep you from
This content downloaded from 147.188.128.74 on Sat, 25 Jun 2016 09:19:09 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
78 HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY QUARTERLY
the knowledge of who you are" (OK 1. 1068).15 And Antigone too is a double
self, a self divided between her past history and the self so transformed by the
crisis of her brother's unburied corpse, the self who was betrothed to Haemon
and the self who goes to the "marriage chamber" of her tomb (A 1. 891).
Indeed, while Hegel says that ancient tragic characters "adhere to the one
ethical state of pathos which alone corresponds to their own already formed
personality" (FA IV 335), these characters are tragic precisely because they are
engaged in intimate struggle with their opposite. Oedipus "adheres" tena
ciously to the rights of consciousness, but his very actions solicit the opposite
power, that of the unconscious, which finally destroys him. Antigone unbudg
ingly clings to the pathos of blood-ties, but her character is equally defined by
her "other," by her confrontation with the laws of social and political reality
which circumscribe her destiny. Again, this is analogous to the situation in
madness, where the insane, despite their imprisonment within a "fixed idea,"
are nevertheless double personalities precisely because of the continued rela
tion to otherness, to what surrounds, as a sort of constantly encroaching
negative space, the fixity of their internal dream lives.
The kinship of madness and tragedy through their related ontologies of
disunion can also be seen in their shared affinity with the state of despair, or the
"unhappy consciousness." Hegel sees despair as a continually present possibility,
indeed as the "center" and "birthpang" of all the shapes of spirit (PS 456f),
expressing the fundamental fact of consciousness'inner division {Entzweiung).
The unhappy consciousness is the pain of the failure to reach self-unity, the
experience of "self-duplication" and "self-contradiction" (PS 126). This self is
torn between the sense of its own finitude, of being caught up in the consuming
fire of change?"bound upon a wheel of fire," as Lear says (IV, vi)?in a world
of accident and caprice, and its desire for self-identity, for immutability, for
completeness?the desire, ultimately, for the divine. "The unhappy conscious
ness," Hegel writes, "is the tragic fate of the... self that aims to be absolute" (PS
455)?the age-old longing of human beings to become God, to become complete
and whole, to overcome the sense of estrangement from our world. It is in this
sense that Hegel sees Goethe's Faust as an "absolutely philosophical tragedy,"
showing "the tragic quest for harmony between the Absolute...and the
individual's knowledge and will" (HA II 1224). Despair reflects the sense of
loss of the divine, the forfeiture of a world redeemed from alienation and
protected from the irrational force of contingency. It is the "grief which ex
presses itself in the cruel words that 'God is Dead'" (PS 455).
The "cruel words" of despair are encountered many times in the language of
tragedy.16 Euripides, a contemporary of Thucydides and Plato, and like them
deeply suspicious of the nostalgic invocation of a pantheon of gods whose
irrationality and arbitrariness had become embodied in the destructive mad
ness of the Peloponnesian Wars, is perhaps the most stark in his expression of
this language of despair. His Hecuba perfectly represents Euripides' sense of
the tragic absence of the divine:
This content downloaded from 147.188.128.74 on Sat, 25 Jun 2016 09:19:09 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
HEGEL ON MADNESS AND TRAGEDY 79
This content downloaded from 147.188.128.74 on Sat, 25 Jun 2016 09:19:09 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
80 HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY QUARTERLY
Why are you waiting [to pronounce my doom]? Nothing that you say
fits with my thought. I pray it never will.
Nor will you ever like to hear my words. (A 11. 499-501).
This content downloaded from 147.188.128.74 on Sat, 25 Jun 2016 09:19:09 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
HEGEL ON MADNESS AND TRAGEDY 81
This content downloaded from 147.188.128.74 on Sat, 25 Jun 2016 09:19:09 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
82 HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY QUARTERLY
This content downloaded from 147.188.128.74 on Sat, 25 Jun 2016 09:19:09 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
HEGEL ON MADNESS AND TRAGEDY 83
This content downloaded from 147.188.128.74 on Sat, 25 Jun 2016 09:19:09 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
84 HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY QUARTERLY
This content downloaded from 147.188.128.74 on Sat, 25 Jun 2016 09:19:09 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
HEGEL ON MADNESS AND TRAGEDY 85
Hegel insists, against readings which see Creon as simply a tyrant who acts
unjustly,29 that Creon too is a genuinely tragic figure, he focuses his attention
much more fully on the psychology of Antigone. Creon is in some respects more
like Ajax, whose tragedy (and madness) results from an inability to come to
terms with the interior world of "nature." Antigone, on the other hand, is in
essence all interior for Hegel. Her "pathos" coincides with that more primordial
region of the psyche which most of us have repressed. She is the other of
culture, its underground woman, so to speak, who is denied only at great cost
to the health of communal life. Hence her tragic situation promises to teach us
more about ourselves than Creon's situation does, more about the domain of
the unconscious, of instinct, of nature, which Hegel sees as the "presupposition"
of all spirit, the originary scene of life which is gradually sublimated, and hence
lost from view and darkened over in the developmental progression of spirit.30
Here too, as in the case of madness, it is through acquaintance with what lies
on the outside, or the underside, of the everyday, that we are able to learn more
fully about the contours of the "normal."
It must be said, however, that what Antigone teaches is made problematic
by Hegel's persistent tendency to move beyond the general psychological prin
ciples entailed by her immersion in nature, to make claims about gender. In
Hegel's reading, it is not accidental that the human law is represented in the
tragedy by a man, Creon, but is essentially male; and the divine law is not
merely coincidentally represented by a woman, Antigone, but is essentially
female. Thus Hegel associates the opposing principles of human and divine,
culture and nature, light and darkness, with essential gender distinctions. As
such, the concerns of a literary and psychological theory of tragic action are
superseded as the argument shifts to the terrain of social and political com
mentary on gender. Antigone's "pathos," her identification with the "infernal
regions of nature," her position of otherness in relation to the privileged laws
of culture, take on the weight of the "nature of woman" in contest with the
"nature of man" (PR ?166; PS 267ff). While the son eventually passes from the
bonds of the family (blood-ties, emotion, nature) to the sphere of human law
(the universal, rational, political), the daughter is never able to transcend
nature (PS 275). Hence there is a "natural antithesis" of man and woman (PS
276), and "womankind in general" is the "internal enemy" and "everlasting
irony" of the state, culture, the laws of the political community (PS 288).
This content downloaded from 147.188.128.74 on Sat, 25 Jun 2016 09:19:09 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
86 HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY QUARTERLY
The second point to be made is that the equation of a withdrawal into nature
with the feminine which we see in his reading of the Antigone is not an
equation Hegel extends (at least in any explicit way) to his readings of other
tragedies. And third, the tragic figure Hegel most often compares with Antigone
is not even a woman, but that paragon of the purportedly "masculine" values
of rationality, "wisdom, discretion, temperance, moderation, justice, courage,
inflexibility,...[and] sobriety" (HP I 394)?Socrates. Socrates, like Antigone,
represents "the tragedy of Greece itself for Hegel?namely, the irreconcilable
collision of two opposed formulations of law, the divine and the human, the
principle of individual conscience as opposed to the privileged "legalized con
science" of the state (HP I 443-47). Just as Antigone is the "everlasting irony"
of the state, Socratic irony represents a direct challenge to the status quo.
True, Socrates is not tied to the underworld gods as Antigone is. Indeed he
is guilty of creating new gods, "rational" gods. Nor is he tied to the family, but
This content downloaded from 147.188.128.74 on Sat, 25 Jun 2016 09:19:09 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
HEGEL ON MADNESS AND TRAGEDY 87
This content downloaded from 147.188.128.74 on Sat, 25 Jun 2016 09:19:09 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
88 HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY QUARTERLY
This content downloaded from 147.188.128.74 on Sat, 25 Jun 2016 09:19:09 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
HEGEL ON MADNESS AND TRAGEDY 89
This content downloaded from 147.188.128.74 on Sat, 25 Jun 2016 09:19:09 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
90 HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY QUARTERLY
human and divine laws, public and private spheres, culture and nature, light
and darkness, consciousness and the unconscious. Central to Hegel's analysis
of tragedy is his view that each power, in being put into action, becomes
destroyed by its opposite. The significance of the tragic act is to solicit its
opposite, revealing an inversion or reversal {Verkehrung) of meaning.
"[T]hrough the deed a transition of opposites" occurs "in which each proves
itself to be the non-reality, rather than the authentication, of itself (PS 279).
This is because each side of the tragic collision is ultimately "linked in the
essence with its opposite," so that "the fulfillment of the one evokes the
other,...calls it forth as a violated and now hostile entity demanding revenge"
(PS 283). Agamemnon's act calls forth the furies of his slain daughter; Clytae
mestra's justice evokes the justice of her son; Orestes' honor is converted into
shame by "the Furies that rise out of the shadow of his action" (FA I 377); Creon
and Antigone are equally one-sided and their deeds elicit the mutual destruc
tion of each other; and Oedipus' insistence on his own lucidity can only tempo
rarily conceal the power of the unconscious which, when revealed, unhinges
him.
The tragic stage is thus explicitly defined as an inverted world: tragic action
is "this inversion {diese Verkehrung) of the known [that is, of the "pathos"
which the tragic actor identifies with] into its opposite,...the changing-round
(das Umschlagen) of the Tightness based on character [pathos]...into the
Tightness of the very opposite..." (PS 447/PG538). All tragic action is funda
mentally ambiguous and double in meaning. What is intended, the expression
of the purity of the character's own "pathos," inevitably reveals its own one
sidedness and the justice of its opposite. Thus Hyllus explains his mother
Deianira's crime to his skeptical father Heracles: "In all that she did wrong she
had intended good" (WT 1. 1136). And the chorus of Euripides' Orestes ex
presses its bewilderment at the double meaning of the actors' deeds, and the
inverted world they beget:
In large measure, there is nothing new about Hegel's portrait of the tragic
stage as an "inverted world." It is a commonplace, after all, of aesthetic theory
to emphasize the fundamental role of peripety or reversal in tragedy. What is
distinctively Hegelian is the way he works out his theory of equally justified
universal "powers," embodied in the "pathos" of individual actors, "soliciting"
or "evoking" their opposites when put into action. More generally, this theory
perhaps goes further than others in not merely emphasizing peripety on the
level of character?the fate of individual actors to realize "How strange in their
reversals are our lives" (H 1. 846)?but in expanding the idea of reversal or
inversion to characterize the world of tragedy itself. When the chorus in
This content downloaded from 147.188.128.74 on Sat, 25 Jun 2016 09:19:09 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
HEGEL ON MADNESS AND TRAGEDY 91
Euripides' Medea, for example, calls out desperately, "Flow backward to your
sources, sacred rivers,/And let the world's great order be reversed" (11. 41?11),
it is expressing a sense of the world itself being out of joint, inverted, a place
of "poisonous" demonic madness and fury. It is this larger sense of inversion,
above and beyond the reversals of fortune that befall individual actors, which
interests Hegel. Finally, it is really not Antigone or Creon or Oedipus as
characters that preoccupy Hegel?much less even than they do Aristotle, who
emphasizes plot over character?but what their acting out of the collision
between cosmic forces tells us about "the broken and confused" world (die
zerrissene verworrene Welt) (Wl: 228) in which these collisions occur.
Apart from questions of Hegel's contribution to an understanding of reversal
in tragedy, what is germane here is how this portrait of the inverted world of
tragic action may be linked in an important way to the inverted world of
madness. Essential to Hegel's anatomy of inversion in madness is his psychol
ogy of the regressive turn into nature, where the logic of the unconscious
supplants and enters into opposition with the logic of rationality. The role of
the unconscious with respect to Antigone has already been discussed, and now
it may be added that Hegel proposes as one of the main forms of tragic collision
the conflict between consciousness and the unconscious (FA I 284f, IV 319-21).
In this "antithesis of the conscious and the unconscious" (PS 280), the act brings
out into consciousness what was hidden in the unconscious, an opposite power
"that conceals itself and lies in ambush" (PS 446). This power is really "nature"
itself, the domain of instinct, passion, and unconscious drives, the life of the
"feeling soul" which is the primordial center of existence in madness.
Oedipus and Ajax are Hegel's favorite examples of this conflict. Both "stand
in the power of the unconscious" (LR 354n), so that an explicit dichotomy arises
between intended action?Oedipus killing a "stranger," Ajax slaughtering the
"Greek leaders"?and the real44 act which remains unconscious?Oedipus has
killed his father, and Ajax has really slaughtered the Greeks' cattle. Reality
and appearance are here completely inverted, when consciousness, the world
of lucidity and light, is revealed as a mere surface, veiling the deeper reality
of the unconscious, the world of concealment and darkness. Both Oedipus and
Ajax are forced to confront their darker, hidden selves: "this darkness is my
world," Oedipus says (OK 1. 1325), and Ajax sings a haunting song to his new
homeland, Darkness:
O
Darkness that is my light,
Murk of the underworld, my only brightness,
Oh, take me to yourself to be your dweller,
Receive and keep me. (Aj 11. 395-7).
And for both, this new, dark underworld of the unconscious is the homeland of
madness:
Madness has seized our noble Ajax;
He has come to ignominy in the night.
...Insanity stands here revealed indeed! (Aj 11. 215-16, 355).
This content downloaded from 147.188.128.74 on Sat, 25 Jun 2016 09:19:09 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
92 HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY QUARTERLY
Darkness!
Horror of darkness enfolding, resistless, unspeakable...
madness and stabbing pain and memory
of evil deeds I have done! (OK 11. 1314-17).
And indeed Oedipus accepts his guilt: after initially blaming the gods, he
finally refuses this as an excuse and declares that "[t]o this guilt I bore witness
against myself (OK 1. 1384). And just as Oedipus appropriates the whole
weight of his deed, identifying himself with his unconscious, so too does Ajax:
while Ajax's conscious intention was not to slaughter the cattle, he refuses the
fatalistic option of Teucer, that "this was the gods' contrivance" (Aj 1. 1037),
and accepts Tecmessa's harsh claim that it is "you yourself and no one else"
that is responsible; he stands "naked" in his guilt (Aj 11. 261, 463).
In his Aesthetics, Hegel makes a great deal of "our modern"-day "repug
nance" to the idea that someone might take responsibility for an act which he
or she did not intend due to ignorance of the circumstances, or acting under a
delusion or in madness. The Greek tragic hero, however, "adheres simply to all
the consequences" of his or her action, "and makes good his personal responsi
bility for the whole" (FA I 252). "We moderns" tend to "throw guilt into the
background as far as possible" (FA I 253), but we must learn "above all to place
on one side the false notion of guilt or innocence" we cling to, which leads us
to see tragic actors as innocent because, after all, they didn't know what they
were doing: "one can in fact urge nothing more intolerable against a hero of
this type than by saying that he has acted innocently. It is a point of honor with
such great characters that they are guilty" (FA IV 320-21).46
What then is guilt for Hegel? A little patience is required here, since an initial
response suggesting that Hegel simply incorporates a highly moralistic reading
of the Christian notion of original sin is misleading. It will turn out, however,
that Hegel's position is characteristically idiosyncratic, and that nothing could
be farther from the truth than to cast Hegel's interpretation of the guilt of
madness and tragic action in a moralistic or orthodoxly Christian light.
This content downloaded from 147.188.128.74 on Sat, 25 Jun 2016 09:19:09 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
HEGEL ON MADNESS AND TRAGEDY 93
Yet all is not what it seems. Appearances to the contrary, Hegel never falls
into the stance of contrasting "nature" and "spirit" on moralistic grounds, nor
ever suggests that the goal of spiritual life is to seek to distance oneself as fully
as possible from the body, nor ever claims that the "good life" is to be found in
a denial of the instincts. Elsewhere Hegel's theory of the sublimation of nature
and the unconscious has been discussed,47 showing that he is no more a
"slanderer of nature," to use Nietzsche's phrase,48 than is Nietzsche himself.
The point to be made here is that Hegel avoids all moralistic interpretations
of guilt and evil for the unimpeachable reason that guilt and evil are not
essentially moral phenomena for him at all! They are ontological terms. Hegel
thus anticipates Heidegger's idea that human beings uare guilty in the very
basis of their Being," so that "'Being-guilty'cannot be defined by morality, since
morality already presupposes [guilt] for itself."49
"Evil," for Hegel, means finitude, incompletion, and disunity (see, e.g., SL
?24 Z; HP III 5; PS 468-74). This is why nature is "evil," because it awaits the
"awakening of consciousness," the "education and culture" (Bildung) of spirit,
to complete it (SL ?24 Z). It is "evil" because it is embryonic, a mere beginning,
not yet subject to the historical enactment of "the labor of its own transforma
tion" (PS 6). And given this understanding of evil, guilt for Hegel is an
inescapable ontological feature of human existence, our being grounded in
nature and hence our being eternally subject to incompleteness.
The guilt of tragedy and madness shows this state of disharmony in poignant
and extreme ways. But it is seriously wrong to condemn morally the tragic hero
This content downloaded from 147.188.128.74 on Sat, 25 Jun 2016 09:19:09 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
94 HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY QUARTERLY
or the insane. Tragic figures are guilty, but their guilt shows us not a lack of
moral integrity, not "evil" in the common ethical sense. Hegel explicitly asserts
that the depiction of evil in this sense is "inartistic," something "merely
repulsive" which could never serve as the subject of tragedy (FA I 295). Rather,
the tragic actor's guilt exposes the existential fact of a world in which funda
mental collisions of value are unavoidable, a world inwardly divided between
culture and nature, consciousness and the unconscious, the "upper" and "lower"
aspects of our being.
And the insane are guilty too for Hegel, but their guilt is not an ethical guilt.
While Hegel follows the French physician Phillippe Pinel's call for a "moral
treatment" of the insane,50 he makes it clear that the assumptions of this
treatment are not that the insane are suffering from a moral lapse, but that
we must treat them morally, and presuppose that they are moral beings (PM
?408 Z). The guilt of madness is, like that of the tragic actor, an extreme
expression of the ontology of disunion which characterizes us all, a particularly
dramatic constituting of the double center of reality which is incipient in all
human experience. Ours is a broken world, a world where every achievement
of harmony is evanescent and subject to collapse into the experience of loss,
despair, and alienation.
For Hegel, every human being must struggle with this "negativity" of exist
ence, and every pursuit of self-realization must ultimately risk the "pathway
of doubt" and "way of despair" (PS 49). While there are many different strate
gies Hegel sees open to meet this challenge, the prospects of tragedy and
madness are constantly real possibilities. This is perhaps why Hegel charac
terizes what he calls the "absolute position" of spirit as itself intrinsically
tragic, and writes of "the tragedy which the Absolute eternally enacts with
itself (NL 108,104). The tragedy spoken of here is the unavoidable "surrender"
of spirit to self-separation and -division, and "the Absolute" is explained as the
ultimately "doubled-nature" {gedoppelte Natur) of spirit, its constant striving
for unity, reconciliation, and self-harmonization, and yet its perpetual "self
othering" or "place[ment] outside itself (sich gegen?berstellen) (NL 104-9/W
1: 386-91).
Jean Hyppolite makes an analogous claim for the role of madness in Hegel's
philosophy: "the essence of man is to be mad [for Hegel], that is, to be himself
in the other, to be himself by this very otherness."51 But Hyppolite is working
with too broad a sense of "madness" here, and Hegel would resist seeing the
human essence as inherently insane.52 Still, Hegel does say, as remarked at
the very outset of this essay, that "insanity [is] an essential... [and] necessarily
occurring form or stage...in the development of the soul." For "all existing
reality [is] unstable and disunited" (RH 38), so that consciousness will be
forever confronted with the lure of withdrawal from reality into a communing
with the more primordial harmony of the "feeling soul." In the extreme case,
where this withdrawal amounts to a severing of the connections with the outer
This content downloaded from 147.188.128.74 on Sat, 25 Jun 2016 09:19:09 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
HEGEL ON MADNESS AND TRAGEDY 95
world, and reality is reduced to a shadow of the mind's own projection, our
attempt at healing the wounds of spirit will have led directly to madness.
Madness and tragedy are in this way not so much the opposites of "normality"
or "rationality" or "health," their antipodes, as they are extreme potentialities
of our entirely normal encounter with alienation. They are mirrors?broken,
perhaps, and darkened, but mirrors nonetheless?of our normal selves.
Bard College
Received April 2, 1993
NOTES
1. All citations from Greek tragedies are from The Complete Greek Tragedies, ed.
David Greene and Richmond Lattimore (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1959-60),
4 vols. References will be abbreviated as follows:
AESCHYLUS:
Ag Agamemnon, tr. Richmond Lattimore
LB Libation Bearers, tr. Richmond Lattimore
E Eumenides, tr. Richmond Lattimore
SOPHOCLES:
A Antigone, tr. Elizabeth Wyckoff
Aj Ajax, tr. John Moore, Jr.
OK Oedipus the King, tr. David Greene
WT Women ofTrachis, tr. Michael Jameson
EURIPIDES:
B Bacchae, tr. William Arrowsmith
H Hecuba, tr. William Arrowsmith
O Orestes, tr. William Arrowsmith
TW Trojan Women, tr. Richmond Lattimore
2. All references to Freud will be to the Standard Edition of the Complete Psycho
logical Works of Sigmund Freud, 24 vols., ed. James Strachey (London: Hogarth,
1953ff). The present citation is from the metapsychological paper "On Narcissism," SE
vol. 14, p. 82.
3. References to Hegel will be given parenthetically and abbreviated. Abbreviations
are as follows:
FA The Philosophy of Fine Art, 4 vols., tr. F. P. B. Osmaston (London: G. Bell,
1920)
HA Hegel's Aesthetics: Lectures on Fine Art, 2 vols., tr. T. M. Knox (Oxford:
Clarendon, 1975)
HP Lectures on the History of Philosophy, 3 vols., tr. E. S. Haldane and F. H.
Simson (New York: Humanities Press, 1974)
LR Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion (The Lectures of 1827), ed. Peter
Hodgson (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1988)
NL Essay on Natural Law, tr. T. M. Knox (Philadelphia: University of Penn
sylvania Press, 1975)
PG Ph?nomenologie des Geistes, ed. Eva Moldenhauer and Karl Markus
Michel (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag, 1970)
PH Philosophy of History, 3 vols., tr. J. Sibree (New York: Willey, 1900)
This content downloaded from 147.188.128.74 on Sat, 25 Jun 2016 09:19:09 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
96 HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY QUARTERLY
PM Philosophy of Mind, tr. William Wallace (Oxford: Clarendon, 1978)?vol.
3 of the Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences IEnzyklop?die der
philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse, ed. Friedhelm Nicolin
and Otto P?ggeler (Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 1959)
References to the Encyclop dia IEnzyklop?die are to sections (?), and "Z" following
section numbers designates editors' additions (Zus?tze) to the original text (see note
below).
PR Philosophy of Right, tr. T. M. Knox (London: Oxford University Press,
1976)
PS Phenomenology of Spirit, tr. A. V. Miller (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1977)
RH Reason in History, tr. Robert S. Hartman (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill,
1953)?the Introduction to Hegel's Lectures on the Philosophy of History
SC "The Spirit of Christianity and its Fate," in T. M. Knox, ed., Early Theo
logical Writings (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1977)
SL Logic ("shorter" Logic), tr. William Wallace (Oxford: Clarendon, 1975)?
vol. 1 of the Encyclop dia
W Hegel's Werke, ed. D. Hotho (Berlin: Duncker und Humblot, 1837)
A word about the Zus?tze to the Enzyklop?die is in order. These passages were added
to the Enzyklop?die after Hegel's death by a variety of editors (Leopold von Henning,
Karl Ludwig Michelet, Ludwig Boumann), based on Hegel's lecture manuscripts and
the detailed notes they and other students (K G. J. von Greisheim, H. Hotho, H. von
Kehler, and others) had taken on the lectures. There has been considerable debate about
the value of these additions, but the view that they are largely reliable reflections of
Hegel's lectures is made persuasively by M. J. Petry in his Introduction to Hegel's
Philosophy of Subjective Spirit, 3 vols. (Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel, 1979), Vol. 1,
pp. cx-cxv. Similarly, T. F. Geraets, W. A. Suchting, and H. S. Harris, translators of
Hegel's Encyclopaedia Logic (Cambridge: Hackett, 1991), conclude that "there is no
serious doubt that we have a generally reliable record of what Hegel said" (p. viii). See
also J. N. Findlay's Foreword to Hegel's Philosophy of Mind, tr. William Wallace
(Oxford: Clarendon, 1978), pp. vi-vii.
4. Dietrich von Engelhardt makes a similar point when he says that for Hegel,
"illnesses show the structure of reality in especially sharp relief, more so than does
health." "Hegel's Philosophical Understanding of Illness," in Robert Cohen and Marx
Wartofsky, eds., Hegel and the Sciences (Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel, 1984), p.
130.
5. As Hegel notes in one of the last of his Berlin lectures on the History of Philosophy,
"the extravagances of subjectivity constantly pass into madness [VerriicktheitT (HP III
510).
6. Compare PM ?408 Z for the double personality of madness. And see p. 76 below.
7. Bennett Simon, Mind and Madness in Ancient Greece: The Classical Roots of
Modern Psychiatry (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1978), p. 101.
8. Freud, Civilization and its Discontents, SE vol. 21, pp. 64-72. To be precise, while
Freud rejects the hypothesis of his friend Romain Rolland that the "oceanic feeling" is
a religious sensation of eternity, he argues that some such feeling does exist as a
primitive narcissistic desire.
9. I discuss Freud's theory of projection in "Freud's Critique of Philosophy," Metaphi
losophy, vol. 20 (1989), pp. 285-86.
10. See Freud's notion of "secondary gain" and "the need for illness": Introductory
Lectures, SE vol. 15, pp. 382?T; The Ego and the Id, SE vol. 19, p. 49; Inhibitions,
Symptoms and Anxiety, SE vol. 20, pp. 99f.
This content downloaded from 147.188.128.74 on Sat, 25 Jun 2016 09:19:09 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
HEGEL ON MADNESS AND TRAGEDY 97
11. See, for example, Freud's distaste for the moralistic attitude of clinical psychiatry
towards neurotics:
Psychiatry insists that those who suffer from these symptoms are 'degenerates'.
This gives small satisfaction; in fact it is a judgment of value?a condemnation
instead of an explanation. (Introductory Lectures, SE vol. 15, p. 260)
12. Lectures on Aesthetics, vol. I, pp. 240ff, vol. II, pp. 229ff, vol. IV, 238ff; Phenome
nology, pp. 267-89, 443ff; Essay on Natural Law, pp. 104f, 108; Philosophy of Right,
pp. 81, 102, 112, 115, 140; Lectures on the Philosophy of History, pp. 237ff; Lectures
on the Philosophy of Religion, pp. 330?T; Lectures on the History of Philosophy, vol.
I, pp. 426ff.
13. For discussions of Hegel's distinction between ancient and modern, see Stephen
Bungay, Beauty and Truth: A Study of Hegel's Aesthetics (Oxford: Oxford U P, 1987),
pp. 166-78; A. C. Bradley's now classic essay, "Hegel's Theory of Tragedy," in his Oxford
Lectures on Poetry (London, 1950), pp. 69-95; and Walter Kaufmann, "Hegel's Ideas
About Tragedy," in Warren E. Steinkraus, ed., New Studies in Hegel's Philosophy (New
York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1971), pp. 201-20.
14. The German Pathos means "passionate commitment," or as Hegel says, "the
power of the emotional life." It must not be confused with the English meaning of the
word as "pitifulness." For this reason I will leave "pathos" in quotes.
15. These lines are virtually identical to the words of Dionysus to Pentheus in
Euripides'Bacchae: 'You do not know/what you do. You do not know who you are" (B 1. 506).
16. I should note that while Hegel sees despair as the "center" and "birthpang" of all
the shapes of spirit, within the chronological account of his Phenomenology, he locates
the unhappy consciousness within the Christian era (see PS 454ff).
17. See FA IV 321, 338. For discussions of Hegel's reservations about Euripides, see
Bungay, pp. 172f, and Stephen Houlgate, Hegel, Nietzsche and the Criticism of
Metaphysics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986), p. 199.
18. This citation comes from the "Kunstreligion" section of the Phenomenology,
where Hegel is referring to the general principle of all of the arts of ancient Greece?sculp
ture, the religious cults and festivals, and epic and comic literature as well as tragedy.
19. Hegel refers to Antigone 1. 451: "that Justice who lives with the gods below [did
not]/mark out such laws to hold among mankind" (emphasis added).
20. See M. J. Petry's historical notes in his translation of Hegel's Philosophy of
Subjective Spirit (Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel, 1978), Vol. 2, p. 503.
21. Kant, for example, writes that "der Verr?ckte ist also ein Tr?umer im Wachen."
Versuch ?ber die Krankheiten des Kopfes (1764), in Gesammelte Schriften (Berlin:
Georg Reimer, 1905), Vol. 2, p. 265.
22. Foucault, Madness and Civilization, tr. Richard Howard (New York: Random
House, 1973), p. 94 (see also pp. 93-104).
23. Nietzsche, Beyond Good and Evil, in Walter Kaufmann, Basic Writings of
Nietzsche (New York: Random House, 1968), p. 221.
24. Beyond Good and Evil, pp. 350-51.
25. I discuss Hegel's interpretation of the Fall and Original Sin in "Evolution and
Nostalgia in Hegel's Theory of Desire," Clio, vol. 19 (1990), pp. 367-88.
26. The infliction of madness is indeed one of the specialties of the furies:
Over the beast doomed to the fire
this is the chant, scatter of wits,
frenzy and fear, hurting the heart,
song of the Furies
binding brain and blighting blood
in its stringless melody. (E 11. 328-33 and 341-46 [repeated])
This content downloaded from 147.188.128.74 on Sat, 25 Jun 2016 09:19:09 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
98 HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY QUARTERLY
27. William Arrowsmith, "A Greek Theater of Ideas," Arion, vol. 2 (1963), p. 50.
28. Michael Davis, "Politics and Madness," in Greek Tragedy and Political Theory,
ed. J. Peter Euben (Berkeley: U California P, 1986), pp. 142-61. The following remarks
on the Ajax y and particularly the idea that the sane Ajax lacks an "inside," are indebted
to this essay.
29. Stephen Bungay, for example, challenges Hegel's view that "Creon is not a tyrant,
but also an ethical power," which Hegel sees as necessary for having the status of tragic
figure. Bungay cannot agree with Hegel that Creon is as much in the right as Antigone,
and hence has difficulty seeing Creon's situation as fully tragic. Beauty and Truth, pp.
166-69. See also, e.g., A. J. A. Waldock, Sophocles the Dramatist (Cambridge: Cam
bridge University Press, 1966), pp. 30-31: Creon does not represent the "justified power"
of the state, he is simply a tyrant, and simply "morally wrong."
On the other hand, Hegel is equally opposed to commentators like H. D. F. Kitto who
read the play as "primarily the tragedy of Creon." Greek Tragedy: A Literary Study
(Garden City, New York: Doubleday, 1954), p. 132.
30. Thus Hegel could not be further from someone like Kitto who says that Antigone's
situation is "terrible," to be sure, and her part in the tragedy is "impressive and affecting
enough," but insists that Creon's role "has the wider range and is the more elaborate"
and "significant." Kitto, pp. 130, 131.
31. For a few of the many discussions of the idea of "rationality" as transcendence of
the feminine, see Mary Field Belenky, Blythe Clinchy, Nancy Goldberger, and Jill
Tarule, Women's Ways of Knowing (New York: Basic Books, 1986); Alison Jagger and
Susan Bordo, Gender I Body I Knowledge: Feminist Reconstructions of Being and
Knowing (New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers U P, 1991); and Genevi?ve Lloyd, The Man of
Reason: "Male" and "Female" in Western Philosophy (Minneapolis: University of
Minnesota Press, 1984).
32. Thomas Szasz quotes several appropriate passages from the Malleus: "[it is
women who are] chiefly addicted to Evil Superstitions"; "All witchcraft comes from
carnal lust, which is in women insatiable"; "Blessed be the Highest who has so far
preserved the male sex from so great a crime." Szasz, The Manufacture of Madness:
A Comparative Study of the Inquisition and the Mental Health Movement (New York:
Harper & Row, 1970), p. 8.
The Malleus Maleficarum was published in 1486, implementing a Papal bull of 1484.
33. On nature as the presupposition of spirit, see Herbert Marcuse, Hegel's Ontology
and the Theory of Historicity, trans. Seyla Benhabib (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press,
1987), pp. 312-14.
34. Froma I. Zeitlin, "Thebes: Theater of Self and Society in Athenian Drama," in
Euben, op. cit., pp. 101-41.
35. Zeitlin, pp. 126-28.
36. Zeitlin, p. 126, citing Seth Bernadete, "A Reading of Sophocles' Antigone: I"
Interpretation,vol. 4 (1975), p. 156.
37. Zeitlin, pp. 154-55.
38. Zeitlin, p. 128.
39. Richard McKeon, ed., The Basic Works of Aristotle (New York: Random House,
1941), p. 1464.
40. Hegel: The Letters, trans. Clark Butler and Christiane Seiler (Bloomington:
Indiana University Press, 1984), letter 215, p. 591 (emphasis added).
41. For commentaries on Hegel's discussion of the "inverted world" in the "Under
standing" section of the Phenomenology, see Joseph Flay, Hegel's Quest for Certainty
(Albany: SUNY Press, 1984), pp. 77-79; Quentin Lauer, A Reading of Hegel's Phenome
nology of Spirit (New York: Fordham U P, 1976), pp. 84-87; Robert Solomon, In the
This content downloaded from 147.188.128.74 on Sat, 25 Jun 2016 09:19:09 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
HEGEL ON MADNESS AND TRAGEDY 99
Spirit of Hegel (Oxford: Oxford U P, 1985), pp. 376-85; Stanley Rosen, Hegel: An
Introduction to the Science of Wisdom (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1974), pp.
140-50; and Murray Greene, "Hegel's Notion of Inversion," International Journal of
the Philosophy of Religion, vol. 1 (1970), pp. 161-75.
42. See also the "Appearance" chapter of the Encyclop dia Logic (??13Iff): "The
Essence must appear or shine forth.... Essence accordingly is not something beyond or
behind appearance..." (?131); "The appearance shows nothing that is not in the essence,
and in the essence there is nothing but what is manifested" (?139).
43. I discuss the role of intentionality in Hegel's theory of madness in "Intentionality
and Madness in Hegel's Psychology of Action," International Philosophical Quarterly,
vol. 32 (1992), pp. 427-41.
44. See FA I 125: "the unconscious act was the reality in its full significance."
45. Freud himself draws this analogy in his Introductory Lectures, SE vol. 16, p.
330.
46. For further discussions by Hegel of the theme of tragic guilt and innocence, see
HP I 445f (Socrates' tragic situation is that it is his very "innocence which is guilty"),
and SC 233 (the "most exalted form of guilt" is "the guilt of innocence").
47. Daniel Berthold-Bond, "Hegel, Nietzsche, and Freud on Madness and the Uncon
scious," The Journal of Speculative Philosophy, vol. 5 (1991), pp. 193-213.
48. Nietzsche, The Gay Science, tr. Walter Kaufmann (New York: Random House,
1974), sect. 294.
49. Heidegger, Being and Time, tr. John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson (New
York: Harper and Row, 1962), p. 332.
50. Pinel (1745-1826) was head physician at the Hospice de la Salp?tre in Paris, which
had a six-hundred bed ward for the mentally ill, from 1795 until his death. He published
his Trait? m?dico-philosophique sur l'ali?nation mental in 1801.
51. Hyppolite, "Hegel's Phenomenology and Psychoanalysis," tr. Albert Richer, in
Warren Steinkraus, ed., New Studies in Hegel's Philosophy (New York: Holt, Rinehart
and Winston, 1971), p. 64, emphasis added.
52. I discuss my reservations about Hyppolite's claim in "The Decentering of Reason:
Hegel's Theory of Madness," forthcoming in International Studies in Philosophy.
This content downloaded from 147.188.128.74 on Sat, 25 Jun 2016 09:19:09 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms