Brooks 1969, The Meaning of Real' in Advaita Vedānta PDF
Brooks 1969, The Meaning of Real' in Advaita Vedānta PDF
Brooks 1969, The Meaning of Real' in Advaita Vedānta PDF
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
University of Hawai'i Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend
access to Philosophy East and West
This content downloaded from 131.111.184.109 on Sun, 06 Oct 2019 07:26:25 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Richard Brooks The meaning of 'real' in Advaita Vedanta
That is to say, there is only one thing which can, properly speaking, be called
"real" (sat), and that is Brahman. All else which we might call "real,"
including the human soul, is identical with that one reality. Anything which
cannot be so identified with that one reality is "false" (mithyd), or in other
words is only apparently real-is only an appearance, an illusion (maya).
This is a remarkable claim, indeed! It implies that the whole of the world
of our ordinary experience is an illusion. It implies that you are not really
reading this article, that I did not really write it, that the room you are in does
not really exist, that you cannot really look out your window and see real
buildings, sky, and clouds, etc. It implies that all these things are only
apparently so. This is what Advaita means when it claims that the world is
"false."
And when Advaita states that the world is "false," in the sense of illusory,
that must mean not only the external physical world, but the internal psychical
world as well, since both are experienced as pluralistic and Advaita maintains
that reality is unitary. As Ras Vihari Das puts it in his article, "The Falsity
of the World":
The world does not mean merely the external visible world with its sensible
qualities. It means this and more than this.... In fact whatever can be pre-
sented to us either externally or internally, to the mind or the senses forms
part of the world which as a whole as well as every item in it is said to be
false. Falsity is thus asserted of everything that we can sense or feel, think of
or imagine as an object.l
But clearly, the world cannot be totally unreal in the sense of being fictitious
or nonexistent. We do, after all, perceive it. Falsity, then, although it excludes
This content downloaded from 131.111.184.109 on Sun, 06 Oct 2019 07:26:25 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
386 Brooks
reality (sat), does not entail unreality (asat). This is what is meant by calling
the world an illusion. Although an illusion has a peculiar ontological status,
it is not that of nonbeing or nonexistence. The very word 'mithya' seems to
me to bring this out.
The word 'mithya' is a contraction of 'nsithuyd' derived from the root
'/mith', which means either (1) "unite" or "couple," (2) "meet" or "engage"
(in altercation), or (3) "alternate." The word 'mithyd' comes from the third
sense and is used adverbially (often with respect to a person's behavior)
as meaning "invertedly," "contrarily," "improperly," or "incorrectly." This
sense is extended to a nominal form meaning "false." Actually, it would seem
more literal to extend it to "mistaken," that is, "taken or perceived incor-
rectly," even though that translation might not always read well in English,
such as in the sloka quoted above. Such a translation would bring out more
clearly Advaita's claim that the judgments we normally make about the world,
on the basis of our sense perception of it, are mistaken. Certainly, if reality is
unitary, then the plurality of the world cannot be real; we must be mis-per-
ceiving the world and then mis-judging it on the basis of our ignorance of the
truth of the matter.
But why, one might ask, does Advaita take this very unusual attitude
toward the world? Why does Advaita refuse to accept anything except
Brahman to be worthy of the title "real"? Time and again in Advaita liter-
ature, one is confronted with arguments like: "This cannot be real because it is
changing," or "That cannot be real because it is dependent upon something
else for its existence." On the other hand, words like 'eternal', 'immutable',
'unlimited', 'unchanging', and 'permanent' are constantly used in conjunction
with the word 'real' (sat). Why do Advaitins refuse to acknowledge a thing
to be real unless it is eternal, immutable, unlimited, and unchanging? There
are, I believe, a number of considerations involved in an answer to these
questions, but perhaps the most basic of them involves Advaita's definition of
the word 'real'. A discussion of this may help throw light on some of the
basic tenets of Advaita and make those tenets a bit more intelligible-even if
no more credible.
Before turning to Advaita's definition of the word 'real', however, it
would be well to review first what we ordinarily mean in the West by that
term. We find that the word is not used in one single sense, but rather has
a number of different meanings. The following seem to me to be the most
important of these:
1. One common use of the word 'real' is "genuine"-as opposed to
"fraudulent" or "fake." This is what we mean when we speak of "real
diamonds" (as opposed to "paste" diamonds) or "a real Rembrandt" (as
opposed to a forgery).
This content downloaded from 131.111.184.109 on Sun, 06 Oct 2019 07:26:25 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
387
2 For a detailed discussion of the fact that 'sat' means both "real" and "existent," see
P. T. Raju, "The Conception of Sat (Existence) in anikara's Advaita," Annals of the
Bhandarkar Oriental Research Institute XXXVI (1955), 33-45.
This content downloaded from 131.111.184.109 on Sun, 06 Oct 2019 07:26:25 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
388 Brooks
This is also what we do when we see a stick apparently "bent" where it enters
the water; we pull the stick out of the water, see that it is straight, and
decide that its bent appearance in the water must be an illusion. In all such
cases, we examine the object in question under a wide range of circumstances
and determine that our initial perception of it must have been mistaken
because that perception is not consistent with the rest of our experience. Ex-
amining its consistency with a wider range of experience, then, is another
way we have of determining that a thing is unreal in the sense of "illusory"
or "imaginary."
We are now in a better position to appreciate Advaita's use of the word
'real' (sat), since both sublation and consistency are important considerations
in its use. In fact, Advaitins, I maintain, use the word 'real' in a combination
of the third, fourth, and fifth senses suggested above. That is to say, in order
for Advaitins to apply the word 'real' to something, that thing must be (1)
experienceable, (2) nonillusory or nonimaginary, and (3) stable, lasting, or
permanent. Three rather unusual consequences follow from this.
First, the third criterion, as was mentioned previously, seems to confuse
axiology and ontology. At best, it uses the word 'real' in a very special
philosophical sense. Advaita has, I must hastily add, a reason for this use of
the word. It comes from Advaita's basic claim that Brahmajiina-the direct
realization or knowledge of Brahman-is the experience which sublates all
other experiences but is itself unsublatable. I do not intend to question that
claim here, but it may be pointed out that if sublation is a criterion for
This content downloaded from 131.111.184.109 on Sun, 06 Oct 2019 07:26:25 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
389
This content downloaded from 131.111.184.109 on Sun, 06 Oct 2019 07:26:25 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
390 Brooks
5 Raju (op. cit., p. 35) makes the same claim, quoting in support of it the phrase "sadathle
sarvam abhrantarh prakare tu viparyayah," i.e., "all [things] are nonillusory in [their]
aspect of existence, but with regard to [their] form are mistaken." Raju gives no refer-
ence for this phrase.
6 Cf. Karl H. Potter, Presuppositions of India's Philosophies (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.:
Prentice-Hall, 1963), p. 221. (Hereafter cited as Presuppositions.)
7 Karl H. Potter, "Reality and Dependence in the Indian Darshanas," in Essays in
Philosophy, ed. C. T. K. Chari (Madras: Ganesh & Co., 1962), p. 155. See also his
Presuppositions, pp. 140-141, 162, and 226.
8 Cf. Potter, Presuppositions, p. 141; and a!iakara, Brahmasatrabhasya 2.2.26 and 3.2. 3.
This content downloaded from 131.111.184.109 on Sun, 06 Oct 2019 07:26:25 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
391
common and structurally similar analogy, we realize that the shell we picked
up on the beach is not a piece of silver when we "carry it to the market and
try to get a metallurgist to assay its worth."9 But a nonillusory man does
respond to our shout, and nonillusory silver has purchasing power in the mar-
ketplace. Even if the Advaitin wants to claim that, in the final analysis, the
man and the silver (as well as the post and the shell) are illusory along with
the rest of the world, nevertheless he can accord a degree of reality to them
on the basis of their possessing practical efficacy, that is to say, possessing two
of the three criteria of reality.
Another obvious meaning of 'real' in Indian philosophy must be "being the
subject of a valid means of knowledge" (pramana), otherwise there would be
little sense in the elaborate defense of these praminas.l0 This is not the place
to go into a detailed discussion of what Advaita accepts as a valid means of
knowledge, but it may be observed that one such means-indeed, the first and
most fundamental one-is perception (pratyaksa). Insofar as the first cri-
terion of 'real' which I have suggested is experienceability, we might say
that this very minimal criterion is reflected in the definition of real as "being
the subject of a valid means of knowledge," although that definition will have
a wider application also. In this sense, even the illusory "rope-snake," "shell-
silver," etc., will have some degree of reality.
To sum up Advaita's use of the word 'real': in the very minimal sense of the
word, as Ras Vihari Das puts it, "Nothing experienced is absolutely unreal,
hence there must be levels of reality culminating in Brahman as the substratum
of all experienced objects."" In fact, Advaita "is so realistic that it grants some
reality even to illusory objects."12 But, on the other hand, more strictly
speaking, only Brahman is real, since Brahmajiina sublates all other ex-
periences.
Thus, in the strict sense, we may say that reality is (1) independent, in-
sofar as Brahman is the stable end of the only significant dependence relation;
reality is (2) unlimited by anything else, insofar as it is independent of
anything else, therefore related to nothing that could limit it; reality is (3)
nonpartite and (4) unchanging, insofar as it is unlimited and unrelated;
reality is (5) indivisible, insofar as it is nonpartite, and (6) nonacting, in-
sofar as it is unchanging; reality is (7) unitary, insofar as it is indivisible;
and reality is (8) eternal, insofar as it is nonpartite and unchanging. All of
these eight characteristics are predicated by Advaitins of Brahman at one
9 Presuppositions, p. 223.
10 Cf. Surendranath Dasgupta, A History of Indian Philosophy, 5 vols. (Cambridge:
At the University Press, 1957), I, 444.
11 Ras Vihari Das, "The Theory of Ignorance in Advaitism," in R. Das, G. R. Malkani,
and T. R V. Murti, Ajiina (London: Luzac & Co., 1933), p. 82.
12 Ibid., p. 86.
This content downloaded from 131.111.184.109 on Sun, 06 Oct 2019 07:26:25 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
392 Brooks
time or another, and all of them can be traced back to Brahman's being the
substratum of the alleged world illusion. This allegation, in turn, is based
upon Brahman's unsublatability. And that is based upon accepting Brahma-
jinna as the experience which sublates all other experiences. It is that claim,
then, which underlies Advaita's definition of the word 'real' (sat).
But, if this is Advaita's meaning of the word 'real' (sat), what can Advaitins
mean by 'unreal' (asat)? anikara seems to use the word 'unreal' in three
different ways, corresponding to the contradictories of each of the three cri-
teria given for the word 'real'. He frequently applies the word 'unreal' to
everything other than Brahman. On other occasions, he will include the
commonly perceived world within the denotation of the word 'real,' reserving
the word 'unreal' for dreams, hallucinations, "rope-snakes," and the like. And
then again, he will sometimes use the word 'unreal' synonymously with 'non-
experienceable', giving as illustrations the examples so common in all Indian
philosophy: "hare's horn," "sky-flower," or "barren woman's son." Frequently,
in this latter context, he will use the phrase "completely unreal" (atyantasat)
to refer to such imaginary entities. Therefore, although Safikara is by no
means consistent in his usage of these terms, what he says implies a fourfold
distinction between the completely real, the practically real, the illusory, and
the completely unreal. More often, however, he seems to make merely a
threefold distinction between the real, the unreal, and the completely unreal.13
Later Advaitins, who tried to point up the peculiar ontological status of
the world more sharply, restricted the meaning of 'unreal' to imaginary objects.
Their usual term for the apparent world was 'false' (mithyd). Occasionally
ganfkara uses this term also.14 Their position on the distinction between 'real'
and 'unreal' is summed up by Madhusudana Sarasvati (sixteenth century)
in his Advaitasiddhi; he states that "unreality is not the contradictory of
reality, whose nature is unsublatability in the three times, but rather is what
never forms the object of cognition as reality in any substratum whatever."'5
Or to phrase it in a slightly different way, 'unreal' means "having no per-
ceived instance at all." In this case, the real (sat) is what is unsublatable in
the three times, the unreal (asat) is what is completely uninstanced, and the
category termed 'false' (mithya) is everything left over, i.e., what is neither
real nor unreal (including both the "practically real" and the illusory).
13 Although this observation about Safikara is based upon my own reading of his works
over several years, I find that A. B. Shastri has made much the same observation in his
Studies in Post-Samtkara Dialectics (Calcutta: University of Calcutta, 1936), p. 241.
14 Even if the Balabodhini is not a genuine work of aniikara, there are other references
one could cite, e.g., Atmabodha 63.
15 Madhusfdana Sarasvati, Advaitasiddhi, ed. with three commentaries and critical sum-
mary by MM. Anantakrishna Sastri (2d ed. rev.; Bombay: Nirnayasagar Press, 1937),
pp. 50-51: ". . . trikaladhyatvaripasattvavyatireko nSsattvam, kimitu kvacid apy upadhau
sattvena pratlyamdnatvanadhikaratnatvam."
This content downloaded from 131.111.184.109 on Sun, 06 Oct 2019 07:26:25 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
393
LEVELS OF REALITY
This content downloaded from 131.111.184.109 on Sun, 06 Oct 2019 07:26:25 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Levels of reality in Indian thought
This content downloaded from 131.111.184.109 on Sun, 06 Oct 2019 07:26:25 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
395
This content downloaded from 131.111.184.109 on Sun, 06 Oct 2019 07:26:25 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
396 Brooks
The wider one's outlook-the more analytic one's apprehension-the less and
less real do the objects with their individualities and differences begin to
appear-they seem to dismantle themselves of their cloaks of false realities
one after another as one's capacity of apprehension gains in depth and min-
uteness of analysis, until finally, the absolutely paramarthika or real stage is
reached where there is no further vydvahdrika stratum possibly thinkable,
and in which the absolute reality of Brahman in its indeterminable homoge-
neous eternity is realised.26
Now, you cannot have it both ways. Either you hold a view of relativism,
abandoning any supposed "absolute reality," or else you maintain an "absolute
reality," as Advaita clearly does, and abandon the completely relativistic
position. But together the views are incompatible.
Furthermore, these philosophers overlook a very important point. As
Krishnachandra Bhattacharyya observes: "Were it not for the experience of
pratibhasika or illusory being, the possible unreality of the vyavaharika or
empirically real world-the elimination of its given-ness-would be utterly
unintelligible."27 That is to say, without clear-cut distinctions between the
paramarthika and vyavaharika realms on the one hand and the vyavaharika
and pratibhasika realms on the other, the relation of superimposition
(adhyasa), which is supposed to account for the illusoriness of the world,
would be unintelligible. Furthermore, the alleged illusoriness of the world
would be inexplicable. It is my contention, which I cannot develop here, that
Advaita attempts an explanation of the illusoriness of the world by means
of analogy. Examples such as those of the "snake" being superimposed on the
rope and of water being superimposed on the desert (in a mirage) function,
I maintain, as models to explain how the allegedly illusory world is super-
imposed on Brahman. To deny the doctrine of levels of reality is to eliminate
This content downloaded from 131.111.184.109 on Sun, 06 Oct 2019 07:26:25 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
397
the possibility of explaining the illusoriness of the world, since the analogy
must have one of its elements (the substratum) in a relatively more real
realm than its other element (the superimposed entity) in order to be analo-
gous to the relation between the completely real Brahman and the illusory
world superimposed upon Brahman.
It might be possible to hold something like a "relativity of apprehension"
doctrine within the pragmatically real realm (insofar as a sddhu has more
insight into the nature of reality than a sophomore), but the lines delimiting
the four main levels of reality must be absolutely sharp or else Advaita's hopes
of explaining the alleged illusoriness of the world are lost. It is for this reason
that Gaudapada uses the word 'sakrdvibhdta' (sudden illumination) to charac-
terize Brahmajnana.28 It is for this reason, too, that Safikara finds no con-
tinuity between the higher and lower truths.29 Professor Potter has character-
ized such a view as "leap philosophy,"30 identifying Suresvara (ninth century)
and Prakasananda (sixteenth century) as the only Advaitins explicitly holding
such a view.31 In point of fact, I believe, all Advaitins must subscribe to a
discontinuity between the vyavaharika and paramdrthika realms, so in that
sense all Advaitins are "leap philosophers."32 But, on the other hand, all
Advaitins-Suresvara and Prakasananda included-agree that there is a path
to moksa, that is, that there are certain more or less well-defined steps which
the aspirant must take, each of which leads him nearer the goal.33 There is
nothing really inconsistent between these two positions; in the final analysis,
all Indian philosophers are going to have to say that one only attains moksa
when one attains mnoksa, and until then one is still bound to the cycle of
births and deaths (saitsara). One may even have to incarnate a number of
times as a holy man (sadhu) before attaining the final insight, Brahmajiinna,
which confers release from the bondage of transmigration.34 But, it must be
evident that Advaitins will say that one has to be a holy man before one can
even be eligible for insight. Thus, the Path is that which takes one out of the
ordinary affairs of the world and up to the point of illumination; it can,
however, go no further-at that point illumination is sudden (sakrdvibhdta)
as far as Advaita is concerned. This follows, indeed, from the fact that
This content downloaded from 131.111.184.109 on Sun, 06 Oct 2019 07:26:25 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
398 Brooks
CONCLUSION
This content downloaded from 131.111.184.109 on Sun, 06 Oct 2019 07:26:25 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms