Iii.-Ambiguity.: B Y Richard Robinson
Iii.-Ambiguity.: B Y Richard Robinson
Iii.-Ambiguity.: B Y Richard Robinson
B Y RICHARD ROBINSON.
141
1 0
Only once in the early dialogues is there anything near a suggestion- that the definiendum is ambiguous. The idea that
perhaps virtue is not the same in all virtuous persons is made to
come from the somewhat stupid Meno; Socrates takes only a
page to refute this, and is evidently perfectly confident of its
untenability {Meno, 72-73). The essence of the Socratio search
for definitions is precisely the insistence that the word mutt mean
the same in all its uses, however various they at first Bight appear.
The theory of Ideas, as set forth in Plato's middle dialogues,
rests on the same naive assumption about language. ' We are
accustomed to assume that there is some one Idea related to
each collection of things to which we give the same name'
(Rp. 596A). TO each name there corresponds an Ideaand only
one Idea, however various the uses of the name may appear to be.
Not that these dialogues are perfectly unconscious of ambiguity.
In the Euthydemut Plato first depicts and then exposes at considerable length Borne fallacious arguments resting on the- ambiguity of the word fjuwBavtw. But he thereupon dismisses all
such matters as puerile. ' Even if a man knew many such
things, or all there are, he would not thereby know anything
more about reality; he would merely be able to play jokes on
men by means of the difference of words, tripping them up and
overturning them, like those who pull the chairs away from
persons about to sit down and rejoice to see them fall over backwards ' (Eutht. 278B). This profound contempt for the jugglers
of language, and this serene confidence that their art can have
nothing to do with the serious business of science, are dominant
in Plato's early dialogues; and they are characteristic of the
naive stage of human beliefs about ambiguity.
That these naive beliefs are false is easy to realise in this age
of many-volume dictionaries. The Oxford English Dictionary
assigns more than one sense to practically every word in the
language. Ambiguity is not a rare freak ; it permeates language
as much as water permeates an organism. Let us review some of
its forms.
First we may notice those ' singular' terms which ambiguously denote more than one particular or HingnUr One class
of these includes ' this ', ' now ', ' he '. Such words have a
different meaning practically every time they are used ; but they
are usually intelligible because there is a rule by which we can
tell in any case which particular is being denoted then. Another
and a stranger class of singular terms are the proper names,
which appear to denote different particulars ambiguously without
any rule to determine which is being denoted at any given time.
142
BICHABO ROBINSON:
The hearer just has to divine from the whole situation which of
several persons is now being meant by the word ' John '.
Passing from singular to general words, we may note first that
kind of ambiguity which Locke describes neatly, though he
perhaps regards it as explaining more of our speech than it does.
A general word to Locke is a man's arbitrary name for an arbitrary collection of simple ideas, and men vary slightly as to what
they put into the collection. The set of simple ideas which one
man collects under the word ' animal' is not quite the same as
his neighbour's ; and hence arises ambiguity between the two of
them. To Locke, perhaps, no word is ambiguous to a single
person, but every general word is ambiguous in the mouths of
more than one person.
Then comes what may be called ' sliding ambiguity', the
ambiguity of the term that covers a wide area and refers now to
a larger and now to a smaller part of it. Such a term embraces
a big complex of conceptions, put together under one word
because we feel them to be somehow connected, or because we
have not clearly distinguished them ; and it has varying uses in
which varying parts and selections of the complex are intended
and omitted. Our common moral terms are of this order.
' Virtue ' slides from monogamy to all moral desiderata ; and the
Greek ' arete' slides on to all the desiderata of character and
intellect and body. The word ' calon ' covers a complex including
most of what can be covered by our words beautiful and noble
and honourable. The account in the Symposium of the lover's
progress towards the absolutely ' calon' gives representative
samples of its field. In the Oorgias Socrates' more formal proofs
of his important positive theses are all based on the ambiguity
of this word or the corresponding ambiguity of its opposite
' aeschron '. For example, his proof that doing injustice is worse
(than suffering it) consists in inferring it from the three premises,
first, that doing injustice is more ' aeschron ' ; second, that the
more ' aeschron' is either the more painful or the worse or both ;
and, third, that doing injustice is not more painful. The first
premise, that doing injustice is more ' aeschron ', takes a part of
' aeschron ' roughly corresponding to our word shameful; but
the second, that the more ' aeschron ' is either the more painful
or the worse or both, consists in explicitly taking other parts of
the complex that can be covered by the word. The words
' good ' and ' agathon' are ambiguous to much the same degree
and in much the same way as ' calon'. They are always deceiving us, especially by sliding from the object of desire to the
morally good or contrariwise. The Qorgiaa (506D) provides a very
AMBIGUITY.
143
The word ' being ' has many senses, bat they are all related to one
thing, to some one nature. The word is not ambiguous, but is like
the word ' healthy '. Everything ' healthy ' is related to health,
BOHTfttini|1 u uimoi ving hnaltihi sometimes as causing it, sometimes
as indicating it, sometimes as being capable of exemplifying it.
Metapk. T. 2, 1003a33.
144
BICHABD ROBINSON :
Since we cannot introduce the realities themselves into our discussions, bat have to use words as symbols for them, we suppose that
what follows in the words will follow in the realities too, like people
reckoning with counter*. But it is not the same. For whereas
words and the quantity of sentenoes are Limited, realities are unlimited in number. It is therefore inevitable for the same sentence
and the one word to mean more than one thing. As, therefore, those
who are not good at using oounters get deceived by tbose who understand them, just so in the case of sentences those without experience
of the power of words reason fallaciously both when speaking themselves and when listening to others. (BE 1, 165a6 ff.)
AMBIGUITY.
145
f 0 .
know the fact. It is true that our memory for words is limited ;
but our memory for abstract things is equally limited, because
only by means of words can we think of abstract things at all.
The reasons for the ambiguity of language lie elsewhere than
this passage of Aristotle's suggests. Some of them are obvious
and others are hidden. An obvious one is that people make
shifts in the meaning of a word through ignorance. They begin
to use a word which they have heard or seen, without consulting
the dictionary ; and the sense which they have divined from the
contexts turns out to be not quite what the authors had in mind.
Another obvious cause of ambiguity is that people make shifts
in the meaning of a word for a purpose, though not for an
analysed and deliberated purpose. They can think of no old
word for what they want to say ; but they see that in the present
context a certain word would, by the principle of relational
univocity, be forced to take on the new sense which they require.
There are also three less obvious and more important reasons
for the ubiquity of ambiguity. The first is the fact that we have
not yet completely discriminated the parts of reality. The
growth of our understanding is among other things an increase
in our discrimination, by which the big blooming buzzing confusion from which we start is gradually distinguished into its
components. Now our words must reflect the extent to which
we have carried this process, the extent to which we have detected
differences in things. They discriminate what we have discriminated, and confuse what we are still confusing. But, since
we shall never have done clearing up confusions, our words
will always be concealing differences, and there lies an eternal
possibility of ambiguity. Mr. Stuart Chase will therefore be disappointed in his hope that there will one day be a semantic
technique ' which will let us take a political speech . . . and tell
specifically what is wrong with it V because what is wrong with
any language always depends in part on what the facts are, and
we shall never have done ascertaining what the facts are. The
very same sentence in the same context may be ambiguous if
reality is this way but univocal if reality is that way. For
example, whether ' 257c' is an ambiguous reference to Plato's
writings depends on whether Stephanus, in bis edition of Plato,
recommenced with page one at the beginning of each volume.
It follows, as Alfred Sidgwick well shows, that every question,
however much it seems now to be a question of fact, may turn
out some day to be a question of definition, since definition or
146
KICHAED B0B1N80N I
TktVMoJ
AMBIGUITY.
147
148
RICHARD ROBINSON :
AMBIGUITY.
149
160
BICHABD ROBINSON :
situations we must fall back upon the indefinite total of our symbols, which is relatively unorganised, does not clearly distinguish
axioms from theorems, and consists mostly of undefined and
ambiguous symbols.
This does not mean that first-class originality is non-existent
in mathematics, but that it occurs not in the march from axioms
to theorems within the system, but in the groping to the system
as such from and by means of the mass of ambiguity outside.
Nor does mathematics ever reach a stage whence it can proceed
without any more use of indefinite symbols. He who effectively
renounces indefinite symbols merely adds theorems to an established system. But the discoverers of non-Euclidean geometry,
and all such geniuses, did so by daring to wade again into tie
sea of ambiguity. Mathematicians sometimes say that their
science requires no words, no verbal symbols. However this
may be, their science, in its most creative moments, does require
the use of ambiguous and indefinite symbols, whether verbal or
otherwise. The exact part of mathematics will always be surrounded by an umbra of inexactitude.
There is a danger that this doctrine may encourage some of
our bad tendencies, may invite us to mistake obscurity for profundity and slipshodness for fertility. Part of our precaution
against this danger must be to remember that ambiguity is bad
as well as good, and to try to bring before our minds as fully and
distinctly as possible the difference between the two. We most
balance'the advantages of ambiguity against the undoubted need
for exact concepts, and try to define the use and abuse of each.
We must not let our hard-won habits of exactitude faint and lose
courage at the realisation that they are not the whole of virtue.
All that can be here undertaken towards this end is a brief
examination of what constitutes bad ambiguity.
There are two obvious sorts of bad ambiguity which we can
quickly note and pass on. The first occurs when the words a
person chooses convey to his hearer a meaning other than he
intends. It is possible, for example, that an American who
intended to tell an Englishman that there was on the highway
a commercial road vehicle driven by internal combustion should
choose words which would in fact give to the Englishman the
impression that there was on the sidewalk a railroad freightcar.
This is because the words ' pavement' and ' truck ' are used in
different ways by the Americans and the English. Ambiguity in
this sense, then, is what we also call misunderstanding, giving an
impression other than you intended because of a wrong opinion
about the effect of your words on your hearer. Special forms of
AMBIGUITY.
151
it occur when your words convey some but not all of what yon
intended, and when they convey all and more than you intended.
The second obvious sort of bad ambiguity is when my words
leave my hearer consciously doubting which of two things I
intended. I ask him whether he has seen John lately ; and he
finds himself thinking of two Johns and wondering which I mean.
Both of these obvious kinds of bad ambiguity involve more
than one person. Neither of them can arise between a man and
himself, except perhaps when he is reading something he wrote
a long time ago. In both of them the speaker may be perfectly
clear in his own mind about the facts he is symbolising. His
error may lie not at all in a misapprehension about the facts to be
symbolised, and wholly in his way of symbolising them. The
words he chooses do not have the effect he intends ; that is all.
He has made an error of expression ; for good expression includes
conveying to your chosen hearers exactly what you want to
convey and nothing else.
Let us turn to that more difficult form of bad ambiguity which
does not require more than one person, the error that a man
may lead himself into at the same time as he leads others. The
following phrase of Miss Stebbing's will give us a start. ' Ambiguity arises when (a person) is led on to extend to one referend
what is true only of another, without realizing that a transition
has been made.' Ambiguity is here regarded as connected with
a mental process that occupies time and is different in ite later
from its earlier parts. Part of the change involved in this
process is concealed from the thinker, to the detriment of his
inference. He knows that there has been a transition ; but he
does not see the whole nature of it, and if he did he would no
longer consider it valid. He thinks he is holding fast to some
identical referend throughout, whereas in truth he has only an
identical symbol which is changing its referend. We can think
only through our symbols ; and in this sort of erroneous ambiguity we fail to notice that the context of the symbol, changing
as our thought proceeds, has altered its reference so much that
the only identity between the earlier and the later part of our
cogitation is the word.
This ambiguity is an affair of inference, if inference is any
process of thinking in which we seem to follow an implication or
a necessitation. It occurs when both we suppose that the premises necessitate the conclusion, and the reason for our supposition is the identity of a word in successive parts of our thinking,
and also the supposition is mistaken because the word means
different things in the two parts.
152
RICHARD ROBINSON:
This account of bad ambiguity seems at first to deal satisfactorily with such philosophical arguments as we consider erroneous
owing to ambiguity. The second part of Plato's Parmemdes,
for example, consists of eight' hypotheses ', of which four consist
in affirming every conceivable predicate of a certain subject, and
the other four consist in denying every conceivable predicate
of a certain subject. The four negative hypotheses appear to
obtain their conclusion by means of one of the ambiguities of the
word is. One use of this multivocal term is to mean identity,
as when I say that Alfred Sidgwick is not Henry Sidgwick.
Another is to mean attribution, as when I say that Alfred
Sidgwick is not tall. Now the Parmenides seems to obtain its
negative conclusions, that X is neither A nor B nor G nor anything else, which are denials of attribution, by shifting from
premises which were denials of identity. The proposition that
' X is not A ' is taken in the premise in the acceptable sense that
Xness and Aness are not identical; but in the conclusion it is
taken in the unacceptable sense that X does not have the property
A. That is an example of the way in which our account of
erroneous ambiguity seems to cover these philosophical mistakes.
But, on second thoughts, even if it covers them, it surely does
not fit them. For surely this ambiguity in transition presupposes
an ambiguity without transition, an ambiguity in statement
as opposed to inference. If a man can start with the relation
of identity but end with that of attribution, and not realise
that he has made a shift, surely that must be because, at the very
time when he is thinking of identity without transition, he does
not distinguish it from attribution. He means ambiguously
both in the single statement as well as in the inference.
Let us try, therefore, to define this more fundamental kind of
bad equivocity which occurs in the statement even apart from
transition. It will not do merely to follow the dictionary and
say that it consists in a statement's having more than one meaning.
Every statement has more than one meaning, or may turn out to
have. Can we then Bay that it consists in failing to distinguish
these separate meanings, that, for example, the argument in the
negative hypotheses of the Parmenides misleads us because we
fail to distinguish non-identity from non-attribution ? No;
because, though it may be true that all bad equivocity involves
a failure to distinguish, the converse is false. The proposition
that all men are mortal is not bad for failing to distinguish
between Chinese and Japanese. On the contrary, it is essential
to every statement to overlook certain distinctions.
Narrowing the proposed definition still further, let us say that
AMBIGUITY.
163
154
BICHABD EOBINSON:
AMBIGUITY.
155