Lovecraft and Philosophy
Lovecraft and Philosophy
Lovecraft and Philosophy
ts and allusions at the terrors inhabiting his stories. The present book will co
nsider numerous examples of both sorts of gaps in Lovecraft s writings. But while
Lovecraft is a writer of gaps, he is also a writer of horror, and the two should
not be conflated. One could imagine a very different writer who used Lovecraft s
staple techniques for other purposes perhaps a sensual fantasist who would place u
s in a world of strange and indescribable pleasures, in which candles, cloves, a
nd coconut milk were of such unearthly perfection that language would declare it
self nearly powerless to describe them. A literary weird porn might be conceivable
, in which the naked bodies of the characters would display bizarre anomalies su
bverting all human descriptive capacity, but without being so strange that the e
rotic dimension would collapse into a grotesque sort of eros-killing horror. We
will see that while the stylistic production of gaps augments Lovecraft s power to
depict monstrous horrors, the horrors themselves must occur on the level of lit
eral content, not of literary allusion. Lovecraft as an author of horror writes
about horrific content (monstrous creatures more powerful than humans and with n
o regard for our welfare), while Lovecraft the author of gaps is one who could h
ave flourished in many other genres featuring many different sorts of content.
It should be obvious to readers of my previous books why Lovecraft, when viewed
as a writer of gaps between objects and their heideggerqualities, is of great re
levance for my model of object-oriented ontology (OOO). The major topic of objec
t-oriented philosophy is the dual polarization that occurs in the world: one bet
ween the real and the sensual, and the other between objects and their qualities
. The two will be described in greater detail below. One involves a vertical gap,
as found in Heidegger, for whom real objects forever withdraw behind their acces
sible, sensual presence to us. The other is a subtler horizontal gap, as found in
Husserl, whose denial of a real world beyond all consciousness still leaves room
for a powerful tension between the relatively durable objects of our perception
and their swirling kaleidoscope of shifting properties. Once we note that the w
orld contains both withdrawn real objects with both real and sensual qualities a
nd fully accessible sensual objects that are also linked with both real and sens
ual qualities, we find ourselves with four basic tensions or gaps in the world.
These gaps are the major subject matter of object-oriented philosophy, and Lovec
raft s constant exploitation of these very gaps automatically makes him as great a
hero to object-oriented thought as Hlderlin was to Heidegger.
In 2008 I published a widely read article on Lovecraft and Husserl. Having recen
tly reread this article, I find that I am mostly happy with the ideas it develop
s. Nonetheless, it also makes two proposals that I now see as unfortunately onesided. First, the article holds husserlthat there is no Kantian or noumenal aspect
of Lovecraft, and asserts that Lovecraft should be paired solely with Husserl a
s an author confined to the phenomenal plane even if he produces strange new gap
s within that plane. Second, it strongly downplays the importance of the fact th
at Lovecraft is a writer of horror and Husserl (though more weird than most people
realize) is not a philosopher of horror. My fresh reservations about these two
points are in many ways the engine of the present book. First, Lovecraft must be
read not as a Husserlian author, but as jointly Husserlian-Kantian (or better:
Husserlian-Heideggerian). This places him closer to my own position than either
Husserl or Heidegger taken singly. And second, horror as the specific content of
Lovecraft s stories must be accounted for, despite the fact that he is also an au
thor of gapsthat might be stylistically incarnated in numerous different genres
other than horror. In short, the tension between style and content now becomes v
ery important. In our efforts to fight the overly literal reading of Lovecraft a
s just a portrayer of scary monsters, we must also acknowledge that those monste
rs are his almost exclusive subject matter in a way that is true neither of Huss
erl nor of the vast majority of fiction writers. In this first part of the book
I will show why this presents a problem; in the concluding third part, I will tr
y to provide a partial solution, one that goes hand in hand with the fact that L
ovecraft works along two separate axes of gaps, not just one. In the longer seco
nd part I will examine numerous passages of Lovecraft in detail, thereby setting
Quadruple Object
Submit Comment
SHARE THIS PAGE