Atheism and The Enlightenment Alister McGrath
Atheism and The Enlightenment Alister McGrath
Atheism and The Enlightenment Alister McGrath
At the time of giving this lecture, Alister McGrath was Professor of Theology, Ministry,
and Education at Kings College London, and head of its Centre for Theology, Religion
and Culture. He is presently the Andreos Idreos Professor of Science and Religion at the
University of Oxford, and Director of the Ian Ramsey Centre for Science and Religion. An
edited version of this lecture is reproduced in Alister McGrath, Mere Theology: Christian
Faith and the Discipleship of the Mind. London: SPCK, 2010, 139-54; North American
edition published as The Passionate Intellect: Christian Faith and the Discipleship of the
Mind. Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press, 2010, 169-85.
Leszek Koakowski, Main Currents of Marxism : The Founders, the Golden Age, the
Breakdown. New York: W. W. Norton, 2005.
1
The godfather of the New Atheism is Paul Kurtz (born 1925), one of
Americas most prominent secular humanists,2 who played a leading role in
articulating the vision of this Congress. Kurtz was instrumental in reshaping
See, for example, Paul Kurtz, What is Secular Humanism? Amherst, NY: Prometheus
Books, 2006.
2
So who are the enemies of the Enlightenment? In terms worthy of the best
conspiracy theorist, Kurtz wrote darkly of powerful forces eager to
3
For an excellent account, see Mason Olds, American Religious Humanism. Minneapolis,
MN: University Press of America, 1996.
4
Paul Kurtz, Re-enchantment: A New Enlightenment. Free Inquiry Magazine 24/3
(April-May 2004).
3
Kurtzs piece can be seen as presaging the core themes of the New
Atheism, particularly as found in the writings of Richard Dawkins and
Christopher Hitchens. Kurtzs programme for the rationalization of western
culture has negative and positive components, both of which are faithfully
reproduced by the leading representatives of the New Atheism. Most
media interest has focused on their withering ridicule of religion as toxic
superstition; after all, this makes for good headlines.
Yet the media has been virtually silent over the other leading features of
Kurtzs programme for a New Enlightenment above all, his critique of
For reflections on the importance of this development for Christian apologetics, see
Nicholas Wolterstorff, The Migration of the Theistic Arguments: From Natural Theology
to Evidentialist Apologetics. In Rationality, Religious Belief, and Moral Commitment
edited by Robert Audi and William J. Wainwright, 38-80. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University
Press, 1986.
4
It is not difficult to see how a plausible link can be suggested between the
rise of modernity and that of atheism. Indeed, historians of modern atheism
often interpret it as an integral aspect of the Enlightenment project.7 These
issues urgently need fuller analysis, if we are to gain an understanding of
the sociological factors which led to the emergence of the New Atheism
in the first place, and shape its reversionary appeal to the Enlightenment in
the second.
Although there are clearly some historical difficulties associated with the
term the Enlightenment (especially its use in the singular), it is still widely
used to refer to the great intellectual and cultural movement, originating in
the eighteenth century, that went on to sweep across much of Europe and
On this final point, see Hitchens plea for a New Enlightenment: Christopher
Hitchens, God Is Not Great : How Religion Poisons Everything. New York: Twelve, 2007,
277-83.
7
For an excellent discussion of the issues, see Winfried Schroeder, Ursprunge des
Atheismus: Untersuchungen zur Metaphysik- und Religionskritik des 17. und 18.
Jahrhunderts. Tubingen: Frommann-Holzboog, 1998.
5
It is easy to see how this quest for intellectual and social liberation, when
linked with the social and cultural situation of western Europe or North
America, could manifest itself as a critique of belief in God and of the
church as an institution. Both were held by some Enlightenment thinkers
(though in different ways) to represent a challenge to human autonomy.
Yet it proves slightly more troublesome to map this approach onto the
realities of history, which can certainly be made to fit this simplistic
The English term Enlightenment came into general circulation in the late nineteenth
century to refer to the movement previously known as les lumires and die Aufklrung.
9
See, for example, James Schmidt, What is Enlightenment? : eighteenth-century answers
and twentieth-century questions, Philosophical traditions. Berkeley, CA: University of
California Press, 1996, 1-44; Maiken Umbach, Federalism and enlightenment in
Germany, 1740-1806. London: Hambledon, 2000, 25-78.
10
For a careful and informed assessment of the historical evidence for such bold claims,
see John Robertson, The case for the Enlightenment : Scotland and Naples 1680-1760.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005, 1-50.
6
framework (with a little forcing here and there), but do not necessarily
generate it in the first place. For example, the French Enlightenments
critique of the notion of original sin has more to do with the concepts
negative implications for the vision of a rational and autonomous humanity
than its alleged intellectual imperfections.11
In this paper, I want to look at the Enlightenment in ways that are unlikely
to please the advocates of the New Atheism. Much criticism has already
been directed against the extraordinary selectivity which characterizes
Dawkinss and Hitchenss critique of religion. The well-known failings of
faith are trenchantly asserted as if that settled the matter. In most trials, it
is customary for the defence to be represented. But not, it seems, here. As
Terry Eagleton commented, with a sarcasm reflecting his obvious
exasperation at the God Delusions risible caricatures of religion: Such is
Dawkinss unruffled scientific impartiality that in a book of almost four
hundred pages, he can scarcely bring himself to concede that a single
human benefit has flowed from religious faith, a view which is as a priori
improbable as it is empirically false.12
But this extraordinary partisan bias is not my concern in this paper. Rather, I
want to consider the equally extraordinary selectivity evident in the appeal
to the Enlightenment characteristic of the New Atheism. We find the
11
Henry Vyvenberg, Human Nature, Cultural Diversity, and the French Enlightenment.
Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989. An excellent discussion of the origins and
applications of this doctrine can be found in Tatha Wiley, Original Sin: Origins,
Development, Contemporary Meanings. New York, Paulist, 2002.
12
Eagleton, Lunging, Flailing, Mispunching. For Eagletons own perceptive and critical
comments on this important issue, see Terry Eagleton, Holy Terror. New York: Oxford
University Press, 2005.
7
There can be few better guides with whom to explore this question than
Leszek Koakowski, whose eightieth birthday we celebrate this weekend. By
the late 1940s, it was obvious that Koakowski was one of the most brilliant
Polish minds of his generation. Although initially strongly committed to
Marxism-Leninism, he became disillusioned with its intellectual failings and
political excesses. His revisionism led to his expulsion from the Polish
Communist Party, and the loss of his teaching position at the University of
Warsaw. He eventually settled in the west, including a long period as Senior
Research Fellow at All Souls College, Oxford, making this an eminently
suitable location for this important symposium.
in exposing its inconsistencies and failings. His writings on these matters are
of especial importance, as they emerged from his own first-hand experience
of an imposed godlessness in Poland, then a Soviet satellite state. So what
might Koakowski, the worthy subject of our celebrations this weekend,
want to draw to our attention? Let me briefly note three points, each of
which requires substantial expansion, which is sadly impossible in our
allocated timeframe.
14
from what the New Atheism would prefer to remain concealed. For
example, Koakowski notes with concern that certain sections of the
Enlightenment came to believe that certain truths had been established
beyond question. On account of this hubris, he argues, Stalinism, Nazism,
Maoism, and other fanatical sects became inevitable.
15
It is widely accepted that part of the attitude of mind that shaped the
Enlightenment was an appeal to the universalities of reason and nature as
objective grounds of judgement, especially in the face of ecclesiastical
16
The Works of John Locke. 10 vols. London: Thomas Tegg, 1823, vol. 8, 447.
11
17
Louis K. Dupr, The Enlightenment and the intellectual foundations of modern culture.
New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2004, 12-17.
18
Alasdair MacIntyre, Whose Justice? Which Rationality? London: Duckworth, 1988, 6.
See further Jennifer A. Herdt, Alasdair MacIntyres Rationality of Traditions and
Tradition-Transcendental Standards of Justification. Journal of Religion 78 (1998): 52446.
12
This may seem a harsh judgement. But it is certainly one that Koakowski
would endorse, and might even extend. In fact, his disarmingly frank critique
of the very limited achievements of philosophical reasoning extends far
beyond a critique of the inflated notions of rationality entertained within
some sections of the Enlightenment, and extent to the philosophical
enterprise in general:19
For centuries philosophy has asserted its legitimacy by asking and
answering questions inherited from the Socratics and pre-Socratics:
how to distinguish the real from the unreal, true from false, good
from evil . . . There came a point, however, when philosophers had to
confront a simple, painfully undeniable fact: that of the questions
which have sustained European philosophy for two and a half
millennia, not a single one has been answered to general satisfaction.
All of them, if not declared invalid by the decree of philosophers,
remain controversial.
19
2.
20
See the points made by Max Horkheimer in his interview with Helmut Gumnior: Max
Horkheimer, Die Sehnsucht nach dem ganz Anderen. Ein Interview mit Kommentar von
Helmut Gumnior. Hamburg: Furche-Verlag, 1971.
13
new interest in the domain of faith, imagination, the feelings, and especially
the transcendent.21 The quest for the transcendent is so deeply embedded
in the history of human thought that it will survive political and intellectual
attempts to suppress it. The reaction of Romanticism against the soulless
rationality of the Enlightenment is an illustration of this trend, but it is much
more widely encountered than this specific example.22
21
Kestenbaum, The Grace and Severity of the Ideal: John Dewey and the Transcendent.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2002.
25
Friedrich Wilhelm Nietzsche, Human, all too human : a book for free spirits.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986, 153. For this metaphysical need, see
Tyler T. Roberts, Contesting spirit : Nietzsche, affirmation, religion. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press, 1998, 49-53.
26
Peter Poellner, Nietzsche and metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000, 9.
15
27
28
See, for example, the points made in Reinhart Koselleck, Critique and Crisis :
Enlightenment and the Pathogenesis of Modern Society. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press,
1988.
29
Zygmunt Bauman, On Writing: On Writing Sociology. Theory, Culture
& Society 17 (2000): 79-90; quote at 79.
17
The New Atheism clearly has global aspirations. Why, then, has it locked
itself into such a western way of thinking and reasoning, which merely
imprisons it? The answer, I think, is not difficult to discern. The New
Atheism is wedded to the Enlightenment metanarrative, and loses
plausibility outside that specific context. Its not really surprising, then, that
they want a new Enlightenment. The old frameworks that gave them such
stability in the past are crumbling. Their only solution seems to be to try
and put them back up again. But culture has moved on in the west, and has
bypassed the Enlightenment altogether in many developing parts of the
world.
19