Jurisprudence-Classical Legal Positivism SK
Jurisprudence-Classical Legal Positivism SK
Jurisprudence-Classical Legal Positivism SK
• Industrial Revolution and the rise of the 19 th Century Capitalism meant that:
• The law needed to change rapidly to meet the needs of the industrial revolution and natural
law could not meet these demands or change with such rapidity.
• Thus, if morality is removed from the law, law can be changed more quickly to achieve the
interest of the industrialists.
• Rise of Empiricism
• Law must be empirically based
• Empiricism has its roots from David Hume who opined that nation states should base law
only on empirically verifiable data and therefore true empiricism really involved the rejection
of natural law as a system of norms because the validity of normative rules cannot logically
be treated as an objective fact.
POSITIVISM’S CENTRAL CLAIM
• Positive law consists of those commands laid down by a sovereign (or its agents),
to be contrasted to other law-givers, like God’s general commands, and the general
commands of an employer to an employee.
• The “sovereign” is defined as a person (or determinate body of persons) who
receives habitual obedience from the bulk of the population, but who does not
habitually obey any other (earthly) person or institution. Austin thought that all
independent political societies, by their nature, have a sovereign.
• Positive law should also be contrasted with “laws by a close analogy” (which
includes positive morality, laws of honor, international law, customary law, and
constitutional law) and “laws by remote analogy” (e.g., the laws of physics).
JOHN AUSTIN CONTINUED
“ With the goodness or badness of law as tried by the test of utility or by any of the
various tests which divide the opinions of mankind it has no immediate concern.”
• John Austin emphasized that law is not directly related or has no “immediate concern” to
natural or moral law. Law is not necessarily a moral concept and moral considerations do
not necessarily precede law. Whatever their relation may be is only mere accidental and
not immediate.
• In the legal positivists point of view, the body of legal rules should exist without conscious
regard for the norms of morality, although the latter’s influence are not completely denied.
There are legal rules that do not measure up to moral law but do not cease to be legal
rules.
CRITICIMS OF BENTHAM
Herbert Lionel Adolphus Hart (H.L.A Hart) criticized Austin stating that:
• law is not merely a combination of coercive orders backed by threats.
• Austin's definition also relies on the concept of the sovereign, whom he describes as someone to
whom the majority of society habitually obeys. Hart criticizes the idea of "habitual obedience" as
inadequate to explain the continuity and persistence of laws. He argues that habits of obedience to
one legislator cannot confer the right of succession to the next legislator or enable them to issue
commands. Hart suggests that a concept of rules, requiring both convergence of behavior and
attitude, is necessary to explain the existence of laws and their persistence beyond the lifespan of
individual legislators.
• Furthermore, Hart criticized Austin's belief that the sovereign possesses an unrestricted will. In
modern legal systems, legal limitations on sovereign power exist, without contradicting their
supremacy as the highest legislative authority within the legal framework. While Austin argued that
in democracies, the electorate forms the sovereign, Hart finds it absurd to conclude that the bulk of
society habitually obeys itself. Even if legislators make rules in their official capacity, such capacity
presupposes the existence of rules that confer such authority, thus conflicting with the concept of
sovereignty presented by Austin.