The Relationship 1
The Relationship 1
Programme
(Extract from Moniteur français, 14 May 1810)
47
Introduction
‘Corporeae machinae mentibus serviunt, et quod in mente est providentia,
in corpore est fatum.’1
1
‘The bodily machines are at the service of the minds, and what in the mind is providence,
in the body is fate.’ Leibniz, Epistola ad Hanschium de Philosophia Platonic sive de
Enthusiasmo Plantonico (1707).
2
‘Nothing is in the intellect that was not first in the senses.’ Leibniz, New Essays on Human
Understanding, II , I, §2.
An impatience and a precipitation all too natural to the human mind cause
it almost inevitably to seek out causes or to establish general laws for
phenomena that it did not take the time to observe or to verify; and
imagination, the first faculty to be exercised, takes hold of these phenomena
even before the senses are accurately applied to them. If this is true for a
science whose object is palpable or immediately accessible to the senses,
how much more so shall it be for one in which the external senses have no
use, or for which one has long believed that any direct observation is
impossible!
It must therefore have happened that after imagining causes ex
abrupto, or feigning explicative hypotheses within a wholly corpuscular
philosophy – one extended these same explanations, these hypotheses, to
the most obscure phenomena of the mind and the soul, whose nature one
did not yet know how to evaluate, nor whose succession how to observe.
Here we encounter all the hypotheses that align with the atomists’ most
ancient systems, from Democritus, Leucippus and Epicurus, to Descartes and
Gassendi, hypotheses with which they claimed to explain the workings of the
senses and imagination through impressional species (espèces impressionnelles)
that emanate from objects themselves – tenuia rerum simulacra [thin images
of things]; animal spirits; vibrations or vibrationcules produced in infinitesimal
nerve fibrils, etc.: all explicative hypotheses created before the nature of each
type of sensation or idea was investigated, and before their similarities and
their differences were established.
The philosophers of antiquity, following a path contrary to that of
induction, which modern physicists since Newton have so successfully
practised, put themselves at the source of everything, and imagined general
causes to explain everything; their method, which had created nothing but
vain systems, did not have more success in Descartes’ hands. In Newton’s
(1) the sense in which the physics of the ancients and of Descartes
explained phenomena through their causes by seeking to determine
how a given cause, whether material or immaterial, acted to
produce these phenomena – the question here is to what extent any
given physical explanation of the facts of internal sense or of the
workings of the mind can be useful or justified;
(2) the type of explanation that consists in reducing to one and the
same class both the phenomena that reveal themselves (se
découvrent) only to internal sense, and the strictly physical facts,
such as they might appear (se représentent) to the external senses or
to the imagination; this reduction or assimilation being founded
upon analogies or identities believed to be observed between the
two types of facts in question, considered in their order of
succession, subordination or reciprocal dependence – this mode of
explanation would seem to be the only one in keeping with our
current mode of philosophizing in the positing of laws and the
search for causes;
(3) in the sense in which the word explain means simply to make
clearer things or ideas that are obscure by their nature, by
comparing them to other tangible (sensible) things or ideas that are
as it were their illustration (figures). One could thus seek to
Part one
Of the misuse and futility of physical doctrines and experiments in explaining
the phenomena of the mind and of internal sense. Analysis of the various
systems of explanation.
First article
Of physical and physiological methods of explanation.
In returning all the way back to ancient philosophy, one finds these
purported physical explanations of the senses and of the mind’s ideas first
introduced by the Eleatic physicists, and then more or less accredited by the
various Greek and Latin schools . . . Or better put, these first philosophers,
having not yet risen to a clear distinction between the two orders of
phenomena or operations, one of which relates to the properties of matter
and the other to the functions of the mind and of the soul, were not
yet really concerned with determining what their mutual relations, their
means of correspondence, and the ties that unite them, may consist in.
They could even less consider explaining the phenomena of the mind or
of internal sense with physical doctrines in that these phenomena
themselves were mixed up in the physical systems of those times and were
presumed to be part of them. Who indeed could recognize today the
makings of an explanation, however probable or specious, in these
thoughtless doctrines that took the ideas of the mind for the shadows or
3
Thomas Reid, An Inquiry into the Human Mind. (Note from the author.)
4
Biran uses the word ‘affection’ – which in French has a somewhat broader range of
meaning than in English – to refer to the various impressions and modifications of
sensory experience. For lack of a satisfactory equivalent in English, I have opted to
translate the word directly as ‘affection’, with the caveat that this word is used here as a
term of art rather than in its ordinary sense. (Note from the translator.)
Second article
Of the systems of physiology, and of their use in the explanation of the
phenomena of internal sense.
The real test of a hypothesis lies in the details of the phenomena they are
used to explain. It was by pushing to the limit the supposed explanations of
the physiological mechanists, who saw in the body a mere hydraulic
machine, or a composite of levers, cords and instruments intended to
transmit and carry on the movements of fluids or solids, etc., that
philosophers finally realized, owing to the incompatibility of the results,
both with each other and with nature, that it was necessary to give up
hypotheses that the imagination alone could still foster, but that experience
and reason repelled at each turn.
If the goal of such haphazard hypotheses had not first been to explain
the senses and the imagination, which by their nature are inaccessible to all
observation or experiment, perhaps their reign might have been longer. But
as soon as one tried to adapt these hypotheses to the laws of organization
and of life, there was a kind of experimental criterion to which to compare
them. To demonstrate that they could not be reconciled with the facts of
physiology was to lessen and annihilate their value with respect to another
order of much more obscure and much more uncertain explanations. It
cannot be disputed that, in this respect at least, the better-conducted