Atmanspacher - Double Aspect
Atmanspacher - Double Aspect
Atmanspacher - Double Aspect
net/publication/273402686
CITATIONS READS
22 1,686
1 author:
Harald Atmanspacher
ETH Zurich
217 PUBLICATIONS 4,064 CITATIONS
SEE PROFILE
Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:
All content following this page was uploaded by Harald Atmanspacher on 05 September 2015.
Abstract
1. Kinds of Naturalism
The basic idea connected with the term naturalism is that “reality
is exhausted by nature, containing nothing “supernatural”, and that the
scientific method should be used to investigate all areas of reality, includ-
ing the “human spirit”, – so Papineau (2007) in his entry in the Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy. It is evident that this characterization is not
particularly informative, as he himself admits, if not only for its lacking
precision than also because it just offsets the explanatory load from the
notion of “nature” to the notion of “reality” and leaves open how the
latter should be understood.
Papineau’s entry focuses on an understanding of nature whose devel-
opment began in the early 20th century and, eventually, led to the almost
246 Atmanspacher
Note that this quote refers to the development of general relativity in the
physics of the 1910s. As we will see in Sec. 3, the rise of quantum theory
after the mid 1920s contains material which makes Russell’s thesis even
more compelling. Anyway, with this prelude, he settles his standpoint
about the mind-matter issue in the following words (Russell 1921, pp. 4f):
The view that seems to me to reconcile the materialistic tendency
of psychology with the anti-materialistic tendency of physics is the
view of William James and the American New Realists, according
to which the “stuff” of the world is neither mental nor material,
but a “neutral stuff”, out of which both are constructed. ...
The stuff of which our experience is composed is, in my belief,
neither mind nor matter, but something more primitive than either.
Both mind and matter seem to be composite, and the stuff of which
20th Century Variants of Dual-Aspect Thinking 249
The final part of this quote connects well with Russell’s statement
about physics and psychology. But from a systematic point of view, its
first part is more significant. Both “ordering influence” and “reaction
back” together constitute a bidirectional interchange between the psy-
chophysically neutral domain and its two aspects. While the “ordering
influence” is a structural feature leading to persistent mind-matter corre-
lations (such as so-called neural correlates of mental states), the “reaction
back” is induced by all kinds of contexts, and the resulting correlations
are unstable and evasive. The systematic analysis of these types of cor-
relations yields a compact and transparent classification of so-called ex-
ceptional experiences (e.g., coincidence phenomena, dissociation phenom-
ena) which significantly improves our understanding of several classes of
254 Atmanspacher
extraordinary mental states. Since this is not the place for more details,
interested readers should consult a recent paper by Atmanspacher and
Fach (2013), as well as commentaries and replies to it.
The concept of synchronicity (Jung 1952) finds a natural place in the
category of coincidence phenomena within this classification. Crucial cri-
teria for synchronicities between mental and material events are (i) their
connection by a common meaning and (ii) the absence of a direct causal
interaction. With respect to (i), Pauli (1952b, translated by HA) gave
a succinct characterization which clearly alludes to the induced type of
mind-matter correlations mentioned above:
synchronistic phenomena ... elude being captured in natural “laws”
since they are not reproducible, i.e., unique, and are blurred by the
statistics of large numbers. By contrast, “acausalities” in physics
are precisely described by statistical laws (of large numbers). Wanted:
a type of natural laws consisting of a “correction of chance fluc-
tuations by meaningful or purposeful coincidences of non-causally
connected events”.
Needless to say, these basic laws are yet to be discovered – perhaps the
Weber-Fechner law of psychophysics may be regarded as a historical pre-
cursor. The classification of mind-matter correlations in Sec. 3 may be of
some general relevance in this direction. Truly psychophysical phenomena
in this spirit are neither physical nor psychological, and they are subject
to psychophysical laws, neither to physical laws nor to psychological laws
(Atmanspacher 2014b).
But let us return to a more detailed characterization of the abstract
information spaces. They are assumed to be endowed with combinatorial
structure and relational structure in the following way (Chalmers 1996,
p. 279):
Starting around 2000, Tononi and collaborators (see, e.g., Tononi and
Balduzzi 2008) have developed and refined a theory of integrated infor-
mation that can be seen as a concrete implementation of many features
of Chalmers’ proposal. Tononi’s theoretical framework assigns different
levels of phenomenal experience to a system, depending on the measure
of integrated information characterizing that system. And Balduzzi and
Tononi (2009) even proposed a way to construct structures in so-called
qualia spaces which represent qualia by their shape.
Because phenomenal and physical realizations of information states
always go hand in hand, panpsychism is straightforwardly entailed by
naturalistic dualism. The integrated information approach predicts that
simple and purely reactive systems like photodiodes or thermostats have
non-vanishing – though not terribly interesting – phenomenal conscious-
ness. In recent work, it was shown that very complex networks, simulated
as feed-forward systems, can perform a high degree of functionality and
yet have zero (“zombie”) consciousness. This and many other interesting
results of Tononi’s work were recently published by Oizumi et al. (2014).
Naturalistic dualism shares with neutral monism that the mental and
the material, here the phenomenal and the physical, are reducible to the
psychophysically neutral, here the information states. Their realization
depends on the way they are composed – but also, importantly, on the
difference between their external and intrinsic features. So the overall
picture that naturalistic dualism presents is of the atomistic, not of the
holistic variety.
At the end of the chapter, Chalmers (1996, p. 305) discusses the meta-
physical dimension of his proposal:
262 Atmanspacher
6. Discussion
Acknowledgments
I am grateful to David Chalmers, Paavo Pylkkänen, and three referees
for their helpful comments on how to improve earlier versions of this
manuscript.
References
Alter T. and Nagasawa Y. (2012): What is Russellian monism? Journal of
Consciousness Studies 19(9-10), 67–95.
Anderson M. L. (2010): Neural reuse: A fundamental organizational principle
of the brain. Behavioral and Brain Science 33(4), 245–266.
Atmanspacher H. (2014a): Roles of causation and meaning for interpreting
correlations. Journal of Analytical Psychology 59, 429–434.
20th Century Variants of Dual-Aspect Thinking 267
Hampe M. (2014): Science, the body and hidden nature: On the variations of
naturalism Mind and Matter 12(2), this issue.
Hiley B.J. (2001): Non-commutative geometry, the Bohm interpretation and
the mind-matter relationship. In Computing Anticipatory Systems - CASYS
2000, ed. by D. Dubois, Springer, Berlin, pp. 77–88.
James W. (1904): Does consciousness exist? Journal of Philosophy, Psychology,
and Scientific Methods 1, 477–491.
Jung C.G. (1969): On the nature of the psyche. In The Structure and Dynamics
of the Psyche. Collected Works, Vol. 8, Princeton University Press, Princeton,
pp. 159–236.
Jung C.G. (1952): Synchronizität als ein Prinzip akausaler Zusammenhänge. In
Naturerklärung und Psyche, Rascher, Zürich, pp. 1–107.
Lowe E.J. (2000): Causal closure principles and emergentism. Philosophy 75,
571–585.
Meier C.A., ed. (1992): Wolfgang Pauli und C. G. Jung: Ein Briefwechsel
1932–1958, Springer, Berlin.
Montero B. (2003): Varieties of causal closure. In Physicalism and Mental
Causation: The Metaphysics of Mind and Action, ed. by S. Walter and H.-D.
Heckmann, Imprint Academic, Exeter, pp. 173–187.
Oizumi M., Albantakis L., and Tononi G. (2014): From the phenomenology
to the mechanisms of consciousness: Integrated information theory 3.0. PLOS
Computational Biology 10(5): e1003588.
Papineau D. (2007): Naturalism. In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed.
by E.N. Zalta, accessible at plato.stanford.edu/entries/naturalism/.
Pauli W. (1952a): Der Einfluss archetypischer Vorstellungen auf die Bildung
naturwissenschaftlicher Theorien bei Kepler. In Naturerklärung und Psyche,
Rascher, Zürich, pp. 109–194.
Pauli W. (1952b): Letter to Fierz of 3 June 1952. In Wolfgang Pauli. Wissen-
schaftlicher Briefwechsel, Band IV, Teil I: 19501952, ed. by K. von Meyenn,
Springer, Berlin, 1996, pp. 634–635.
Prentner R. (2014): A framework for critical materialists. Mind and Matter
12(1), 93–118.
Primas H. (2009): Complementarity of mind and matter. In Recasting Reality.
Wolfgang Pauli’s Philosophical Ideas and Contemporary Science, ed. by H.
Atmanspacher and H. Primas, Springer, Berlin, pp. 171–209.
Putnam H. (1987): The Many Faces of Realism, Open Court, LaSalle.
Pylkkänen P. (2007): Mind, Matter, and the Implicate Order, Springer, Berlin.
Pylkkänen P. (2014): Can quantum analogies help us to understand the process
of thought? Mind and Matter 12, 61–92.
Quine W.V.O. (1969): Ontological relativity. In Ontological Relativity and
Other Essays, Columbia University Press, New York, pp. 26–68.
Russell B. (1913): On the notion of cause. Proceedings of the Aristotelian
Society 13, 1–26.
20th Century Variants of Dual-Aspect Thinking 269
Russell B. (1921): The Analysis of Mind, George Allen and Unwin, London.
Seager W. (2010): Panpsychism, aggregation and combinatorial infusion. Mind
and Matter 8(2), 167–184.
Seager W. and Allen-Hermanson S. (2010): Panpsychism. In Stanford Ency-
clopedia of Philosophy, ed. by E.N. Zalta, accessible at plato.stanford.edu/
entries/panpsychism/.
Skrbina D. (ed.) (2009): Mind That Abides: Panpsychism in the New Millen-
nium, John Benjamins, Amsterdam.
Stubenberg L. (2010): Neutral monism. In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy,
ed. by E.N. Zalta, accessible at plato.stanford.edu/entries/neutral-monism/.
Tononi G. and Balduzzi D. (2008): Integrated information in discrete dynamical
systems: Motivation and theoretical framework. PLOS Computational Biology
4(6): e1000091.
Wheeler J.A. (1990): Information, physics, quantum: The search for links.
In Complexity, Entropy, and the Physics of Information, ed. by W.H. Zurek,
Addison-Wesley, Reading, pp. 3–28.
Commentaries to Atmanspacher
one underlying reality that itself is neutral with respect to the mind-
matter split. This is the key point of dual-aspect approaches. They
combine an (epistemic) dualism with an (ontic) monism and, in this
way, suggest an alternative to the conventional physicalist program
of naturalizing the mind. In fact, dual-aspect approaches consider
both mind and matter to be naturalized by their underlying reality.
Showing that these views are distinct allowed me then in my main pa-
per to demonstrate that both panpsychism and dual-aspect theories have
various problems that neutral monism does not have. I will not reiter-
ate all those problems now, but for example, compositional panpsychism
as traditionally conceived is just dualism writ small, connecting qualia
or little-minds to particles rather than neurons or larger regions of the
brain. This tiny-dualism leads in turn to various combination problems.
True, one can mitigate these problems by moving to non-compositional
panpsychism, but in so doing the very compositional logic that drives
panpsychism is thrown out the window. If reality is not made of fun-
damental parts with primitive thisness and intrinsic properties such as
qualia, then panpsychism is a non sequitur.
If one is willing to reject this compositional picture of reality as con-
textual emergence does, then there is no reason to seek out fundamental
units of mind (whether they be correlated with individual particles or
entangled quantum states) and somehow “cohere” them into an individ-
ual human mind. I am trying to get Atmanspacher to acknowledge that
contextual emergence is already a thoroughgoing rejection of the kind of
atomistic thinking that breeds panpsychism to begin with. Dual-aspect
theories are certainly better off than panpsychism, but they are still stuck
with essentially different mental and physical properties that are not re-
ducible to one another, and yet somehow need to be correlated with one
another.
Most importantly of all, I want Atmanspacher and others to see that
the promise of neutral monism characterized as a form of contextual emer-
gence is to pull the mind/body problem out by the root, along with all the
odious assumptions that generated it. Given neutral monism as a form of
contextual emergence, the mind/body problem is simply and thoroughly
deflated. Neither panspsychism nor dual-aspect theories, as traditionally
conceived, hold out that promise. I understand that Atmanspacher him-
self and the thinkers he canvasses are open to embracing neutral monism.
Spinoza and the so-called “causal closure of the physical” (the principle
that every physical event has an entirely sufficient purely physical cause).
Atmanspacher writes:
... causal closure in Spinoza is violated in a subtler way [as com-
pared to Cartesian dualism]. Since the modes, which do not interact
directly, derive from the one substance, this substance may inject
effects, intrusions as it were, into the modes so that they cannot be
causally closed in principle.
Causal closure of the physical would be, in Spinoza’s terminology, causal
closure over the attribute of extension. By and large, the modes of ex-
tension are material bodies (leaving aside the infinite modes, which are
generally taken to be the laws of nature). How could the realm of exten-
sion fail to be causally closed?
One way is the Cartesian postulate that mind and matter are in gen-
uine causal interaction with one another and represent entirely distinct
substances. In Spinozistic terms, this would have to be cross-attribute
causation and would thus illicitly violate the independence of the at-
tributes. Spinoza holds that “each attribute of a substance must be
conceived through itself” (Spinoza 1677/1985, Part I, Prop. 10). Since
Spinoza also holds as an axiom that to know an effect is to know its cause
(Spinoza 1677/1985, Part 1, Axiom 4), it is impossible for one attribute to
be causally involved with another (else one could conceive of one attribute
through the conception of another’s causal powers). For Spinoza the sys-
tem of modes of each attribute form a closed causal system, but one that
is isomorphic to the similarly isolated causal system of each of the other
attributes. Spinoza (1677/1985, Part 2, Prop. 7, scholium) illustrates this
in a famous passage:
... a circle existing in nature and the idea of the existing circle,
which is also in God, are one and the same thing ... therefore,
whether we conceive nature under the attribute of Extension, or
under the attribute of Thought ... we shall find one and the same
order, or one and the same connection of causes ...
This disjunction of ways of conceiving nature is exclusive, since the
attributes are what “the intellect perceives of a substance, as constituting
its essence” (Spinoza 1677/1985, Part 1, Definition 4; my italics). For
Descartes, this exclusivity led to the conclusion that what Spinoza calls
distinct attributes are distinct substances. Against Descartes, Spinoza
rightly points out that nothing prevents a substance from having more
than one attribute (Descartes actually had to admit this, but took it that
each substance had a defining “principle attribute”).
Spinoza then attempts to prove that there is but one substance that
possesses all possible (conceivable) attributes. Nor is it clear how sub-
stance could generate anything like what Atmanspacher calls “intrusions
274 Atmanspacher
... into the modes”. The modes are the expression of the attribute (and
hence ultimately the substance) to which they belong, be it extension,
thought or any of the infinitely many other unknown and unknowable
attributes hidden from the human mind. The independence of the at-
tributes, again, guarantees that there could be no such intrusions.
This is of some importance if only to prevent premature foreclosure
of the range of positions possible within a dual-aspect approach. The
significance of Spinoza’s position is that it can both (1) endorse the causal
closure of the physical, which many take to be a regulative principle of and
perhaps even entailed by the structure of our most fundamental physical
theories, and (2) deny that mentality must be in some way reducible to
the physical.
Though perhaps not often noted, the same advantage can be found
in neutral monism. From an admittedly somewhat strained Spinozistic
perspective, the neutral monists can be regarded as denying what is some-
times called attribute parity: the view that all the attributes are equally
fundamental. The neutral monists by contrast hold a view that is akin to
selecting one attribute – in this case the “neutral” – as truly fundamental,
and relative to which all the other attributes are derivative.
Alternatively, the neutral could be likened to Spinoza’s substance, with
the attributes then compared to the derivative mind and matter, although
this is not a particularly apt analogy since the neutral monists find the
neutral “in” both mind and matter, in unchanged form, differing only in
the structure of relations under which they are “organized”. In Spinozistic
terms this seems to be another violation of attribute independence.
As Atmanspacher points out, Russell is probably the most famous
proponent of neutral monism, even though he came late to the party
after initially being strongly opposed to the view. But neutral monism
has a natural affinity for one of Russell’s core principles, that “whenever
possible, logical constructions are to be substituted for inferred entities”.
This was perhaps first articulated in Russell (1914), but the sentiment is
frequently expressed in his writings.
What is surely curious here is: How can we construct anything from
the neutral, unless we have access to it? And how can we have access to it
unless we apprehend it as falling under and within our conceptual scheme?
It would take considerable defending, but I believe that the force of these
questions is what leads neutral monists to choose mentalistic terms to label
the neutral. As Atmanspacher notes, the use of the frankly mentalistic
terms “pure experience” (James), “sensation” (Mach and Russell) and
“sense data” or “sensibilia” (Russell) has led to confusion. However, it is
worth noting that they had other terms as well such as “elements” (Mach)
and “events” or “momentary particulars” (Russell).
In my opinion, the solution to this puzzle of accessibility is to take
the neutral as what is present to consciousness, which is indeed always
20th Century Variants of Dual-Aspect Thinking 275
the whole duality of mind and matter ... is a mistake; there is only
one kind of stuff out of which the world is made, and this stuff is
called mental in one arrangement, physical in the other.
If we try to look at neutral monism this way, we can see how it is perhaps
more closely connected to the holistic dual-aspect views of Pauli and Jung,
and Bohm, Hiley and Pyllkänen than would seem initially likely.
The reason for that, which Atmanspacher emphasizes, is the remark-
able fact that quantum theory provides a striking living analogy for a kind
of holism in which systems possess many aspects without those aspects
constituting the system and in which, in a certain sense, which aspect is
presented depends on the context of observation. Perhaps it is more than
an analogy but at the very least it gives us a solid and specific model.
Holism can be roughly defined in terms of the order of ontological
priority. We are all very used to a kind of weak reductionist viewpoint
in which the property of the whole is a function of the properties of the
parts (and their arrangement, or relational structure2 ). It is probably fair
to say that it is hard not to see this viewpoint as being just obviously
correct. We have built our artifactual world according to the dictates of
this kind of reductionism. The computer, carefully devised physically out
of literally billions of microscopic and macroscopic parts and logically out
of myriads of relational structures of elementary instructions, stands as
the apotheosis of this viewpoint. It is indeed pretty obvious that things,
including human beings, are made of parts and it certainly seems to the
2 This relational structure does not have to abide by locality or be limited to “me-
case that the overall features of familiar things are determined by the rela-
tions and interactions of their parts. More grandly, there are respectable
thinkers who liken nature to cellular automata, another perfect exemplar
of the “parts have priority” viewpoint (see, e.g., the remarkable paper by
’t Hooft (2014), but also the entire digital physics movement).
But philosophically speaking, the idea that the parts have ontological
priority is not an analytic truth (for a nice presentation of philosophical
holism see Schaffer 2010). Quantum theory suggests a picture in which
the whole takes ontological priority and the “parts” are derivative. The
whole has priority in the very robust sense that there does not exist a
unique breakdown of a quantum system (as specified by the wave func-
tion) into components. On the other hand, the experimenter is free to, as
it were, generate such components by performing an appropriate measure-
ment. Orthodox quantum theory furthermore denies that prior to such
measurement the components were already present in some definite form
within the whole. Much if not all of the oddity and paradoxical nature of
quantum mechanics results from these facts.
Although stimulating and highly suggestive, the quantum model may
not smoothly fit onto a holistic dual-aspect outlook in all respects. If
we regard complementary observables as the “aspects” we find that each
precludes the other rather than being co-accessible or even, as suggested
by classical neutral monism, identically present in experience. There is
no isomorphism between the aspects; each embodies distinct information.
There is something akin to inter-attribute causation or at lease influence.
If we measure momentum, we irrevocably alter information about posi-
tion.
Such considerations suggest that quantum physics may not directly in-
form our metaphysics. The difficulty can be illustrated via Atmanspacher’s
discussion of the Pauli-Jung conception of the mind-body problem. To
take one explicit example, Pauli wrote both that “a mirror-image principle
is a natural way to give an illustrative representation of the psychophysical
relationship” (Pauli and Jung 2001, p. 159) and that “it would be most
satisfactory if physis and psyche could be conceived as complementary
aspects of the same reality” (Pauli (1952/1994). As noted, complemen-
tary observables cannot be in a mirror-image relation, since in that case
complete knowledge of one would, in principle, yield complete knowledge
of the other. And yet, a dual-aspect approach to the mindbody problem
quite naturally suggests the kind of isomorphism between them as was
envisaged by Spinoza.
Here, to use Pauli’s phrase, we need a “a new idea of reality” (from a
1948 letter from Pauli to Markus Fierz, as quoted in Atmanspacher and
Primas 2006, p. 16). Quantum theory stands as a kind of metaphorical
beacon on the road towards this new idea, but it may not itself embody
that “new idea”.
20th Century Variants of Dual-Aspect Thinking 277
For Kant, the Categories, Forms of Sensibility, and the different posits
required by theoretical, practical and teleological reasoning play a pre-
dominant role in determining the highest-level divisions of the ontology
of the phenomenal world, and transcendental analysis reveals the basic
types of operations of the mind. My Cognitive Pluralism allows for ex-
perience and conceptual innovation to play a much larger role, suggests
that there may be less overarching order to the various model-based ways
we possess of understanding phenomena, and predicts that some of them
will prove to be abidingly inconsistent with one another, even if they are
each individually apt.
On such a view, the notion of “objects as they are in themselves” turns
out to be curiously empty. On Kant’s view, the “negative” conception
of the noumena is obtained by starting with a phenomenal object and
abstracting away from all of the conceptual and sensual content. One
cannot give any kind of concrete characterization of noumena, because to
do so, one needs to apply concepts and form judgments, and once one
does that, one is no longer treating them as noumena but as phenomena.
If “natures” need to be things that can in principle be described with
concepts, noumena qua noumena can have no natures.
Multiple Aspects and Neutral Monism
Multiple-aspect theories begin with the recognition that one and the
same thing can be felicitously characterized in more than one way.3 In
itself, this does not amount to a philosophical theory; it is more like a
common-sense observation that things have many good descriptions, that
problems can be thought about from many angles, etc.
It begins to become a philosophical theory once we suppose that not
just every difference in conceptual framing makes for a distinct aspect:
that our most general ways of thinking of things, if they are sufficiently
comprehensive and sufficiently orthogonal to one another, are the real
candidates for aspecthood. Where it truly gains the status of philosophi-
cal theory is in how it elaborates its differences from other philosophical
theories. Unlike fundamentalist realism, it holds that two aspects can
apply to the same things without either aspect being derivative from the
other, but being, as it were, coeval. Unlike cognitivism, it holds the as-
pects to be features of the world itself and not merely different basic ways
of interpreting the world.
The best-known dual-aspect view, Spinoza’s, has additional charac-
teristics which, I take it, a dual-aspect view need not have: (1) each
Spinozistic Attribute is comprehensive, in the sense that everything has a
3 One usually hears them called “dual-aspect” theories, but I see no reason to limit
the number of aspects to two, and indeed Spinoza claimed that the number of At-
tributes is in fact infinite, with only our powers of grasping them limited to so small
an integer value.
280 Atmanspacher
from the notion I am more familiar with from Shannon and coding theory, and so I am
not fully confident of my reading of his view.
20th Century Variants of Dual-Aspect Thinking 281
have at least a limited amount of sense: the senses of the relational terms.
What must be avoided, of course, is having the key notions of the aspect-
languages in the description of the neutral system. But this does not
prevent the latter from amounting to an additional aspect, but merely a
different one.
Alternatively, the talk of a neutral base might simply be a way of ex-
pressing our intuitions that our ways of thinking about things through
concepts are beholden a transcendent referent, which can never be cap-
tured fully in our concepts, and certainly not concepts confined to a single
aspect. But this in itself is not a metaphysical theory, and it is not clear
that it should be turned into one. And, perhaps more directly, it is not
clear that the I-know-not-what that we posit in regarding an object or
phenomenon as transcendent should be regarded monistically. Indeed, it
seems odd to speak of counting at all except when things are interpreted
under concepts. At best, saying the ontic base is “monistic” seems intel-
ligible only in the negative sense of saying that it is not carved up into
separate partitions by the aspects, but is “the common reality” under-
stood through both aspects.
Now there is another option which I think might merit the name
“monism” in a stronger sense. Mystic practitioners report a mode of ex-
perience which is non-discursive, non-conceptual, and in which the world
is not experienced as divided into objects. Certain strands of Platon-
ism/Neoplatonism and some Buddhist lineages (and, as I learned from
Silberstein’s article, Advaita Vedānta ) have held that this mode of expe-
rience presents reality more directly, and as an undivided unity. In the
Neoplatonist tradition, this mode of experience is called noesis, the name
given to the highest form of cognition in Plato’s divided line.
I think Jung may have endorsed a view of this type, and it seems
more compatible with Atmanspacher’s “decompositional” than “compo-
sitional” forms of neutral monism. Of course, one question we might then
pose is whether such a form of “access” is itself “epistemic”. Plato con-
trasts noesis with both episteme and dianoia, but perhaps this simply
reflects Plato’s own theoretical use of the term episteme and has no bear-
ing on whether it is “epistemic” in the sense that aspects are said to be
“epistemic”.
282 Atmanspacher
Replies by Atmanspacher
Let me begin with my sincere thanks to the authors of the three com-
mentaries, which reflect some of the lively discussions at the symposium
from which this issue of the journal emerged. More specifically, I am
grateful for the opportunity to expand somewhat more on a number of
points about which my target paper was not elaborate enough. Since the
commentaries contain sufficiently distinct material (though there are also
common points of concern), I think it is in the service of clarity to respond
to them individually.
under the name ontological democracy. See her lecture at the Seven Pines Symposium
XVI on “Analogy and Duality in Physics” in May 2012, accessible at http://pitp.
physics.ubc.ca/confs/7pines2012/talks/Castellani.pdf.
284 Atmanspacher
The causal closure of the physical is a principle that has almost reached
the status of an ultimate truth in analytical philosophy of mind. Seager’s
“grumpy” comment on my “obscure” note that “causal closure in Spinoza
is violated” is therefore well motivated. But I think the status of the causal
closure of the physical is not as solid as it may appear from (much of) the
literature. Its discussion also gives me an excellent opportunity to spell
out some corresponding features of dual-aspect monism which I didn’t
address in my main paper.
First of all, “causal closure” is usually understood as completeness with
respect to efficient causes: Every physical effect has a physical efficient
cause. The causal closure principle features with particular significance in
the discussion of mental causation, where it ultimately prohibits mental
efficient causes to affect physical events. In Spinoza’s terms, the modes
of the attribute of extension cannot be influenced by the modes of the
attribute of thought.
Now, Spinoza’s and other kinds of dual-aspect thinking include a
monistically conceived substance in addition to the attributes: “God” for
Spinoza, or the more profane “neutral” in other versions. Seager wants
me to clarify how this substance could “inject effects, intrusions as it were,
into the modes” if the modes are expressions of the attributes which in
turn are attributes of the substance.
I can see that Seager’s concern is plausible within a certain reading
of Spinoza as a pantheist, equating God with nature. If this equation
comes out even, it seems absurd to think of anything like causes and
effects between God and nature. However, there is a long tradition of
interpreting Spinoza as a panentheist, where God is immanent in nature
but not identical with it: God is infinite and nature is finite, and the finite
things can only have God as their cause (Lloyd 1996, p. 40).
But does “cause” here mean efficient cause? Hardly, I think, and this is
why my obscure remark needs clarification indeed. What kind of “effect”
the neutral domain in dual-aspect thinking might “inject” into its aspects
may become clearer in the following quote from a letter of Pauli to Fierz
in 1948 (von Meyenn 1993, p. 496, my italics):6
6 In this letter Pauli discusses the concept of archetypes which Jung previously
had defined as inner images of the psyche. Pauli argues correctly that this would be
inappropriate within a dual-aspect framework of thinking.
20th Century Variants of Dual-Aspect Thinking 285
The ordering and regulating factors must be placed beyond the dis-
tinction of “physical” and “psychic” – as Plato’s “ideas” share the
notion of a concept and of a force of nature (they create actions
out of themselves). I am very much in favor of referring to the “or-
dering” and “regulating” factors in terms of “archetypes”; but then
it would be inadmissible to define them as contents of the psyche.
The mentioned inner images (“dominant features of the collective
unconscious” after Jung) are rather psychic manifestations of the
archetypes which, however, would also have to put forth, create,
condition anything lawlike in the behavior of the corporeal world.