Negri Value and Affect
Negri Value and Affect
Negri Value and Affect
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless
you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you
may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.
Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at .
http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=duke. .
Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed
page of such transmission.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Duke University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to boundary 2.
http://www.jstor.org
Value and Affect
Antonio Negri
translated by Michael Hardt
I do not think that, in the polemics that have now for two hundred
years accompanied the development of the theory of value, politicalecono-
mists have ever succeeded in decoupling value fromlabor.Even the margin-
alist currents and the neoclassical schools, whose vocation is dedicated to
this decoupling, are forced to take this relationshipinto account (along with
its support, mass livinglabor)every time they confrontpoliticaleconomy in
the concrete. In neoclassical theory, the analyses of market, entrepreneu-
rial,financial, and monetary relations all refute in principleevery reference
to labor: in fact, it is no surprise that neoclassical theorists have nothing to
say when they are faced with politicaldecisions. The theory of labor-value
springs forth again-and they are frozen in their tracks by it-precisely
where the founders of the disciplinesituated it.The place of the conflict(and
the eventual mediation)of the economic relationshipas a social relationship
reveals the ontology of economic theory.
What has irreversiblychanged, however, from the times of the pre-
dominance of the classical theory of value, involves the possibilityof devel-
Deconstruction
My first thesis, a deconstructive and historical thesis, is that mea-
suring labor,and thus orderingit and leading it back to a theory of value, is
impossible when, as today, labor-poweris no longer either outside or inside
capitalist command (and its capacity to structurecommand). To clarifyhow
this is our contemporarysituation, allow me to referto two cases.
First case: Labor-power,or really the use-value of labor-power,is
outside of capital. This is the situation in which the labor theory of value
was constructed in the classical era. Being outside of capital, labor-power
had to be broughtwithinit. The process of primitiveaccumulationconsisted
in bringingwithincapitalist development (and control) the labor-powerthat
lived outside. The exchange-value of labor-powerwas thus rooted in a use-
value that was constituted, in large part, outside of the capitalist organiza-
tion of production.What, then, was this outside? Marxspoke extensively on
this question. When he spoke of labor-poweras "variablecapital"he alluded
in fact to a mixtureof independence and subjectivitythat was organized in:
(a) the independence of "small-scale circulation"(the linkto the earth, the
family economy, the traditionof "gifts,"and so on); (b) the values proper
to "workercooperation"as such, in other words, the fact that cooperation
constitutes a surplus of value that is prior,or at least irreducible,to the capi-
talist organization of labor, even if it is recuperated by it; and (c) the set of
"historicaland moralvalues" (as Marxput it) that is continuallyrenewed as
needs and desires by the collective movement of the proletariatand pro-
duced by its struggles. The struggle over the "relativewage" (which Rosa
Luxemburgstrongly highlighted in her particularinterpretationof Marxism
from the perspective of the productionof subjectivity) represented a very
strong mechanism available to the "outside."Use-value was thus rooted
fundamentally,even if in a relativeway, outside of capital.
A long historiography(which spans from the work of E. P. Thomp-
son to that of the "workerist"Italians and Europeans of the 1970s, and
among which we could situate the brilliantwork of South Asian subaltern
historiographers) describes this situation and translates it into a militant
vocabulary.
For a long historical period, then, capitalist development has under-
gone an independent determinationof the use-value of labor-power,a de-
Negri/ Valueand Affect 81
Construction
We have thus far posed a number of affirmations:(1) that the mea-
sure of labor-value,grounded on the independence of use-value, has now
become ineffectual;(2) that the rule of capitalist command that is imposed
on the horizon of globalization negates every possibility of measure, even
monetary measure; and (3) that the value of labor-poweris today posed in
a non-place and that this non-place is s-misurato (immeasurable and im-
mense)--by which we mean that it is outside of measure but at the same
time beyondmeasure.
To address the theme of value-affect now, we would propose delving
into one among the many themes that the introductionto this discussion
has presented-that of the nexus between production and social repro-
duction-and investigating it according to the indications that the analysis
has suggested: first, from below, and second, in the immeasurable and
immense non-place.
To do this, one must still refuse the temptation to go down a simple
path that is presented to us: the path of reintroducingthe Marxianfigures of
84 boundary2 / Summer1999
use-value and pretending to renovate them in the context of the new situa-
tion. How do the philosophers and politicianswho situate themselves in this
perspective proceed? They reconstruct a fictionaluse-value that they nos-
talgically oppose to the growing processes of globalization;in other words,
they oppose to globalizationa humanistic resistance. In reality,in their dis-
course, they bringto lightagain all the values of modernity,and use-value is
configured in terms of identity.(Even when use-value is not invokedexplic-
itly,it ends up being inserted surreptitiously.)One example should suffice:
the resistance of workers' trade unions to globalization. To establish this
resistance, they resurrect the territorializationand the identity of the use-
value of labor-power,and they insist on this, blind to the transformations
of productivity,desperate, incapable of understandingthe new power that
the immeasurable and immense non-place offers to productiveactivity.This
path thus cannot be taken.
We must then search for another one. But where can we find it? We
have said "frombelow."Up untilthis point, in fact, we have reasoned on the
basis of a Marxianrelationthat led from productionto social reproduction
and thus fromvalue to the biopoliticalreality.Inthis relation-seen widely-
could be included also affect; affect could emerge as a power to act on the
lower limitof the definitionof use-value. But this end point of the deduction
of the conditions of value has only determined importanteffects when it has
been assumed abstractly as an element of the unity of calculation. Now,
then, one must change the direction of the reasoning, avoid that deduc-
tion, and assume ratheran induction--from affect to value-as the line of
construction.
This line of construction has been adopted with good results, but the
findings are nonetheless not sufficientto demonstrate to us the power of af-
fect in the radicalityand the extension of the effects that now, in postmoder-
nity,await us. I am referringhere to those historiographicaland dialectical
schools I cited earlier-from E. P. Thompson, to the European "workerists"
of the 1970s, to the "subaltern"historiographers.Now, from this theoretical
perspective, affect is assumed from below. Moreover,it is presented, in the
first place, as a production of value. Through this production, it is repre-
sented, then, in the second place, as a product of struggles, a sign, and
an ontological deposit or precipitateof the struggles. Affectthus presents a
dynamic of historicalconstruction that is rich in its complexity.And yet it is
insufficient. Fromthis perspective, the dynamic of the struggles (and their
affective behaviors) determines, in fact, in every case, the restructuringof
capitalist command (in technical terms, politicalterms, and so on). The de-
Negri/ Valueand Affect 85
Back to PoliticalEconomy
Since value is outside of every measure (outside of both the "natu-
ral"measure of use-value and monetary measure), the political economy
of postmodernity looks for it in other terrains: the terrain of the conven-
tions of mercantile exchange and the terrain of communicative relations.
Conventions of the market and communicative exchanges would thus be
the places where the productivenexuses (and thus the affective flows) are
established--outside of measure, certainly, but susceptible to biopolitical
control. Postmodern politicaleconomy thus recognizes that value is formed
inthe relationof affect, that affect has fundamentalproductivequalifications,
and so forth.Consequently, politicaleconomy attempts to control it, mystify
its nature, and limitits power. Politicaleconomy must in every case bring
productiveforce under control, and thus it must organize itself to superim-
pose over the new figures of valorization(and new subjects that produce it)
new figures of exploitation.
We should recognize here that, reshaping the system of its concepts
in this way, politicaleconomy has made an enormous leap forwardand has
attempted to present itself (withoutnegating the instance of dominationthat
Negri/ ValueandAffect 87