Figures of Rhetoric - Figures of Music
Figures of Rhetoric - Figures of Music
Figures of Rhetoric - Figures of Music
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless
you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you
may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.
Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at
http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=ucal.
Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed
page of such transmission.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We work with the
scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that
promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
University of California Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to
Rhetorica.
http://www.jstor.org
Brian Vickers
lrThe pioneer in modern times was Arnold Schering, in "Die Lehre von den
musikalischen Figuren im 17. und 18. Jahrhundert," Kirchenmusikalisches Jahrbuch, 21
(1908), pp. 106-114; see also his "Geschichtliches zur Ars inveniendi," Peters-Jahrbuch
(1925). Heinz a a Berlin dissertation,
wrote Studien zur
Brandes, pupil of Schering's,
a broader
musikalischen Figurenlehre im 16. Jahrhundert 1935), while
(Berlin, study was
attempted by Hans-Heinrich Unger, Die Beziehungen zwischen Musik und Rhetorik im
16.-18. Jahrhundert (W?rzburg, 1941; repr. Hildesheim, 1969). A brief but important
article by Willibald Gurlitt, "Musik und Rhetorik. Hinweise auf ihre geschichtliche
(Indiana U. diss., 1955; University Microfilm Pub. no. 14, 674), and the articles "Af
fektenlehre" and "Figuren, musikalisch-rhetorisch", in Die Musik in Geschichte und
2
See Claude V. Palisca, "A Clarification of 'M?sica Reservata' in Jean Taisnier's
Astrologiae'," 1559, Acta Musicologica 31 (1959), pp. 133-161, cited here as "Palisca
(1)"; and "Ut Oratoria M?sica: the Rhetorical Basis of Musical Mannerism," in The
Meaning of Mannerism, ed. F. W. Robinson and S. G. Nichols, Jr. (Hanover, New
Hampshire, 1972), pp. 37-65, cited here as "Palisca (2)"; Gregory G. Butler, "Fugue
and Rhetoric," Journal ofMusic 21 (1977), pp. 49-109, here as "Butler (1)," and
Theory
"Music and Rhetoric in Early Sources," The Musical
Seventeenth-Century English
Quarterly 66 (1980), pp. 53-64 (here as "Butler (2)").
3See Martin Ruhnke, Joachim Burmeister. Ein zur Musiklehre um 1600
Beitrag
(Kassel und Basel, 1955), and his facsimile re-edition of Burmeister's M?sica po?tica
(Kassel and Basel, 1955).
A"ln immenso rerum omnium atque artium campo libere vagari": Institutiones ora
toriae (1545), p. 8, cit. Basil Munt?ano, Constantes en Litt?rature et en His
Dialectiques
toire (Paris, 1967), pp. 151-2.
5On the place of rhetoric in education the Renaissance see W. H. Wood
during
ward, Studies in Education the Age of the Renaissance 1400-1600
during (Cambridge,
1906); T. W. Baldwin, Shakespere's "Small Latine and Lesse Greeke", 2 vols. (Urbana,
111., 1944); Friedrich Paulsen, Geschichte des gelehrten Unterrichts auf den deutschen
Schulen und Universit?ten vom des Mittelalters bis zur Gegenwart, 2 vols., ed.
Ausgang
3 Figures of rhetoric/Figures of music?
P?dagogisches Magazin, Heft 803 (1921), pp. 1-150; Munt?ano, op. cit., pp. 177-184;
pp. llff; and E. R. Curtius, European Literature and the Latin Middle Ages, tr.
Unger,
W. R. Trask (New York, 1953), passim (cf. index).
8For Soarez, see De Arte Rhetorica, translated by L. J. Flynn, S. J. (University of
Florida Ph.D., 1955; University Microfilms Order no. HUJ 100-16926), and articles
by Father Flynn in Quarterly Journal of Speech 42 (1956), pp. 367-374, and 43 (1957),
pp. 257-265.
9J. J.Murphy, Renaissance Rhetoric: A Short-Title Catalogue (New York, 1981), and
my review in Quarterly Journal of Speech 69 (1983), pp. 441-444, and 70 (1984).
10See, e.g. Sister Miriam Joseph, Shakespeare's Use of the Arts of Language (New
York, 1947, 1966); Brian Vickers, The Artistry of Shakespeare's Prose (London, 1968,
1979), and "Shakespeare's Use of Rhetoric" in A New Companion to Shakespeare Stud
ies, ed. K. Muir and S. Schoenbaum (Cambridge, 1970), pp. 83-98; idem, Francis
Bacon and Renaissance Prose (Cambridge, 1968); Peter France, Racine's Rhetoric (Ox
ford, 1965); Alex L. Gordon, Ronsard et la Rh?torique (Geneva, 1970); D. L. Clark, John
Milton at St. Paul's School (New York, 1948); P. Topliss, The Rhetoric of Pascal (Leicester,
1966). Further bibliography in Brian Vickers, Classical Rhetoric in English Poetry (Lon
don, 1970), and "A Bibliography of Rhetoric Studies 1970-1980," in Comparative Criti
cism 3 (1981), pp. 316-322.
5 Figures of rhetoric/Figures of music?
that musicians and music theorists should look to this highly suc
a happy conflu
cessful aesthetic system for guidance. Indeed, by
ence of interests, Quintilian's Institutes,11 with its plea for the orator
to learn from the musician, became to the writers of this period at
once a great classic and a work of immediate contemporary signifi
cance. In Book One, chapter ten, Quintilian made a survey of other
studies necessary to complete the general education of the ideal or
ator, and wrote a praise of music which was to be echoed and imi
tated many times over. Of particular relevance to music and rheto
ric are the passages recalling that grammar and music were once
united, that there were famous teachers of both (such as Sophron:
I.X.17), and that the study of music has played a major role in the
education of philosophers, generals, and rulers, ever since "those
remote times when Chiron taught Achilles"
(I.x.13, 18, 30; ed.cit.,
Vol. I, pp. 167-73).
The immediate practical advantages to the orator are said to
concern the body, as in dancing and gesture (the sections on ges
ture and pronunciation were taken over sometimes literatim by Re
naissance music theorists12), and the voice. From music and musi
cians the orator must learn and master variety of voice-inflexion,
otherwise we must assume that "unlike music, has no in
oratory
terest in the variation of arrangement and sound to suit the de
mands of the case" . . non et sonus in oratione
[". compositio quo
que varie pro rerum modo adhibetur sicut in musice"]. Quintilian
then underlines the way that both music and eloquence adapt form
to content, and to expression, in a passage which was of great im
portance in the Renaissance:
nCited from the Loeb edition, 4 vols., tr. H. E. Butler (London, 1920).
12Burmeister took over the sections on and gestus wholesale:
pronuntiatio
Ruhnke, pp. 94-7; ibid., pp. 99f on the influence of Quintilian's concepts of moderatio
and mediocritas on seventeenth theorists.
century
6 RHETORICA
of . . . an orator will
reproducing speech. [Thus,] assuredly pay spe
cial attention to his voice, and what is so specially the concern of mu
sic as this?13 (I.x. 22-27; ed.cit. pp. 171-3).
17Ruhnke, 120f.
18
See James Hutton, "Some English Poems in Praise of Music/' English Miscel
lany 2 (1951), pp. 1-63; pp. 7ff. This rich study is essential reading.
19Hutton, p. 20.
20
See D. P. Walker, "Musical Humanism in the sixteenth and early seventeenth
centuries/' The Music Review 2 (1941), pp. 1-13, 111-121, 220-227, 288-308; and
3 (1942), pp. 55-71; also available in German, with additional note,
bibliographical
as Der musikalische Humanismus im 16. und fr?hen 17. Jahrhundert (Kassel and Basel,
1949); and "The Aims of Ba?f's Acad?mie de po?sie et de musique," Journal of Renais
sance and Baroque Music 1 (1946), pp. 91-100.
21
See Joachim Dyck, Ticht-Kunst. Deutsche BarockpoetiK und rhetorische Tradition
(Bad Homburg, 1966, rev. 1969), especially pp. 81-90; Barner, op. cit.; H. F. Plett,
Rhetorik der Affekte. Englische Wirkungs?sthetik im Zeitalter der Renaissance (T?bingen,
1975); Erwin Rotermund, "Der Affekt als literarischer Gegenstand: Zu Theorie und
der Passiones im 17. Jahrhundert," in H. R. Jauss (ed.) Die nicht mehr
Darstellung
sch?nen K?nste (M?nchen, 1969), pp. 239-69, and Affekt und Artistik. Studien zur Lei
Praxis (Frankfurt, 1974), especially pp. 1-77; and Gerard Le Coat, The Rhetoric of the
Arts, 1550-1650 (Bern and Frankfurt, 1975), pp. 21-2 and note 66.
^Quintilian, VIII pref. 13-17; Unger, p. 5f, rightly stresses this point, which
has been overlooked some historians of rhetoric: see Vickers, "On writing the
by
history of elocutio," op. cit.
23
Compare the quotation from Quintilian, note 13 above, with Minervius'
praise of the composer, "quod ceu Po?ta quidam egregius et verbis gestum et eorum
qui audiunt animi affectus, tonis suis inspiret, dum grandia elate, moderata leniter,
iucunda dulciter, tristia moeste, inflat ac modulatur, arte cum affectibus
totaque
consentit": cit. Gurlitt, p. 76.
24Ruhnke, p. 99; cf. Ad Herennium, I.ii.3.
25Brandes, pp. 63, 99ff.
9 Figures of rhetoric/Figures of music?
["If you would have me weep, you must first feel grief yourself']
Weil nun aber das rechte Ziel aller Melodie nichts anders
unstreitig
ist, als eine solche Vergn?gung des Geh?rs, dadurch die Affecten
so kann mir
rege werden; ja keiner dieses Ziel treffen, der keine
nicht an
Absicht darauf hat, selber bewegt wird, ja kaum irgend eine
Leidenschafft . . .Wird er aber und will auch
gedenckt. ger?hrt,
andere r?hren, so muss er alle des Hertzens, durch blosse
Neigungen
and deren ohne Worten, aus
Kl?nge, Zusammenfassung, dergestalt
zudrucken wissen, dass der Zuh?rer daraus, als ob es eine wirklicher
Rede w?re, den Trieb, den Sinn, die Meynung und den Nachdruck,
mit allen Ein- und Abschnitten und verstehen kann.
v?llig begreifen
C. P. E. Bach gave the same advice to the musician in 1759.29 But not
only performers were evaluated in rhetorical terms: composers
also. Coclicus praised Niclas Payen as one of the kings of music,
who knew how to express all the passions (omnes omnium affectus
exprimere).m The first humanist writers on music believed that the
main agent in arousing the feelings, as in performing the duties of
prodesse and delectare, was the text, the poem or fabula that con
tained an
image of human behaviour, often impassioned. While
leading to an conception of mu
excessively language-dominated
sic,31 this theory did highlight the significance of the text and the
importance of adjusting the music to it, with admirable results in
the work of such composers as Josquin des Prez, Orlando di Lasso,
and Monteverdi. Those perennial categories of ancient rhetoric, res
and verba, were revived and united with sonus, as in Sir Thomas
More's description of the Utopians' church music:
something more than mere clearness, since the latter merely lets
itself be seen, whereas the former thrusts itself upon our notice."37
Enargeia is a general imaginative quality that the orator, or artist,
must possess. The specific verbal figures which communicated vi
sual impressions included illustratio, evidentia, demonstratio, descrip
tio, ekphrasis, hypotyposis. The important point to note is that these
were usually classed among the figurae sententiae, and?since sight
was said to be the strongest of the senses?were granted the great
est emotional power. To quote one typical Renaissance rhetoric
book, in The Garden of Eloquence (1593), Henry Peacham writes that
such figures make the oration "verie sharp and vehement, by which
the sundrie affections and passions of the mind are properly and
elegantly uttered," for these figures "do attend upon affections, as
ready handmaids at commandement to expresse most aptly what
soever the heart doth affect or suffer."38
Given the connotations of emotional intensity associated with
setting ideas "before the eyes," and the affective force deriving
from the proper fitting of verba to res, in the rhetoric-dominated
culture of the sixteenth century, humanists who praise composers
in these terms are paying them the highest possible compliment.
Glareanus, the Swiss humanist, praised Josquin des Prez in his
Dodekachordon (1547), by ranking him with Virgil:
No one has more the of the soul in mu
effectively expressed passions
sic than this . . . For as Maro, with his natural facil
symphonist. just
was accustomed to his poem to his so as to set
ity, adapt subject
matters before the eyes of his readers with
weighty close-packed
39Tr. O. Strunk, in Strunk (ed.) Source Readings inMusic History (New York,
1950), pp. 220-1. The Latin reads "Nemo hoc Symphoneta affectus animi in cantu
efficatius . . .Ut enim Maro naturae felicitate carmen rebus aequare est
expressit.
solitus, res grav?is coacervatis ante oculos poner?, veloci
quemadmodum spondeis
tatem meris ... Ita hie noster accelerantibus
dactylis exprimere. Jodocus aliquando
ac praepotibus, ubi res postulat, notulis incendit, aliquando tardantibus rem phthon
. . ."
gis intonat. (p. 362 of Basle, 1547 edition).
40Tr. Gustav Reese, in Reese, Music in the Renaissance, rev. ed. (London, 1954),
p. 513. Palisca (1), pp. 154 f, translates: "Lassus expresses these psalms so appropri
menting and plaintive tones, in expressing the force of the individual affections, in
placing the object almost alive before the eyes." Gerald Abraham renders: "music
to the whole text and to each word, emotion and put
every
'conforming expressing
before the as if actually Abraham, The Concise
ting things imagination happening'":
Oxford History of Music (London, 1979), p. 175. M. van Crevel, in Adrianus Petit
Coclico. Leben und Beziehung eines nach Deutschland emigrierten Josquinsch?lers (The
1940), pp. 317-9, thinks that Quickelberg's source was More; but
Hague, perhaps,
Glareanus was also well-known; and humanist on rhetoric offered a gen
teachings
eral model.
14 RHETORICA
41
Trattato della M?sica Scenica, cit. Walker, op. cit. p. 119.
42Banchi?ri, Cartella musicale nel canto figurato (1614); cit. Unger, pp. 123 ff.
43Cit. Palisca (1), p. 143.
"Cit. ibid., p. 150.
45
summarizes the evidence as follows: weisen aber alle
Unger "Gleichzeitig
diese Zeugnisse darauf hin, dass jetzt in der Reserva ta dem Wort, der Sprache und
den Affekten der gebietende Platz in der Musik einger?umt wird" (p. 28). Reese,
more cautious, believes that the only firm connotations, based on Quickelberg's
of Lassus, are "music of the emotions delineated by the text"
praise expressive
514). Brandes to m?sica reservata as a shift from the arousal
(p. attempted distinguish
15 Figures of
rhetoric/Figures of music?
bis dass auf unsere Zeiten die M?sica so hoch kommen, dass wegen
der absonderlich aber in dem neu erfundenen und
Menge Figuren,
bisher immer mehr Recitativo sie wohl einer Rheto
ausgezierten Stylo
rica zu
vergleichen.
of feeling to the representation of feeling: "An die Stelle des alten Affectus mover?'
tritt das Affectus exprimerez Die Musik will nicht erregen sondern darstellen. Damit
ist der Kern des Reservastils ber?hrt" (p. 71). But of course the passions cannot be
aroused withoutbeing first represented, and felt.
46Palisca(1), p. 159. His identification here, and at greater length in Palisca (2),
of m?sica reservata with "mannerism," seems to me extremely doubtful. Gurlitt had
used the term in 1944 to describe the age of the "stile rappresentativo"
(p. 76), and it
was used by Robert. E. Wolff in 1955 (Palisca
subsequently [1], p. 159 note). Yet the
term itself, from art history, is still so fluid and indeterminate that it seems of du
bious value to apply it to another art. For a good recent discussion of the concept in
the visual arts (but with some very questionable of it to literature and
applications
see Mannerism
music) John Shearman, (Harmondsworth, Middx., 1967). A wide
ranging and vigorous study, too complex for a brief summary, isMaria R. Maniates,
Mannerism in Italian Music and Culture, 1530-1630 (Chapel Hill, N.C., 1979).
47See, for instance, the anthology collected pp. 135-141.
by Ruhnke,
48Gurlitt, pp. 76.
16 RHETORICA
II
^George J. Buelow, "Rhetoric and Music/' The New Grove Dictionary ofMusic
and Musicians, ed. Stanley Sadie (London, 1980), XV, pp. 793-803, at p. 794.
17 Figures of rhetoric/Figures of music?
51
Gurlitt, p. 65.
52Unger, p. 22, who also records that the oldest notational system for Grego
rian chant, "die Neumenschrift," owes its existence to rhetorical a kind of
practice,
punctuation system ("ekphonetischen Zeichen") to elocutio and from thence
applied
to the rhythms of music. On the general similarities music
between and oratory see
"Egmont" Overture: "Der Tod k?nnte ausgedr?ckt werden durch eine Pause"), 140
and note (a very interesting of Sch?tz's use of the pause for intense
analysis sparing
moments in his Passions: he only uses the general pause seven times in his whole
work); and Ruhnke, pp. 135,137,138,156.
54Unger, pp. 64-6.
18 RHETORICA
(a question begged by Unger with his use of the word "Sinn"), and
failure to punctuate, or phrase properly in music will spoil ele
gance or clarity, but cannot destroy meaning. A later theorist cited
by Unger, Forkel (1788), pushes the models drawn from grammar
and rhetoric to the point where analogy becomes identification,
both in terms of the "syntax" of music and its "meaning."55 But if
there is one thing that is sure about the application of models from
one sphere to another, it is that the comparatum and the comparans
must be different. A metaphor is a translation of something differ
ent, not of something identical.
It is surely in the nature of things that we can describe one
art in the language of another only up to a point. No doubt the
general processes of creation in rhetoric?inventio, dispositio, elo
cutio, pronuntiatio, memoria?could be adapted to music?given
some ingenuity?without causing any great distortion. Inventio
and dispositio were usually thought to be given by the text chosen
for setting, and the text further determined, through its meaning,
the mood of the music and its tempo, within such broad categories
as happy-therefore-fast, or sad-and-thus-slow. This belief that the
text provided the first two stages of composition is still found in
Athanasius Kircher in 1650, but as the treatises on musical rhetoric
in the eighteenth century followed rhetoric's natural tendency to
elaboration, more and sometimes bizarre hints
increasing complex,
were given to the composer. Vogt, in his Conclave Thesauri magnae
artis musicae (Prague, 1719), suggests that he use four "Hufn?gel"
(aciculas), bend them into distinct shapes, put them in a random
order, and write musical themes imitating the resulting pattern; or
throw dice; or resort to alcohol. More traditional, and responsible,
was the advice of Johann David Heinichen, in Der Generalbass in der
Composition (1728), who devoted fifty pages to showing how musi
cal invention, like rhetorical invention, could use the loci topici, the
standard doctrine of the "places" of invention, an idea
developed,
typically enough, in much greater detail by Mattheson in 1739.56
As for elocutio, that was assimilated to music both in general
and particular terms. Elocutio determined the overall structure of
an oration, which was conventionally divided into between five
and eight parts. Early humanist theorists enthusiastically identi
fied the eight parts of an oration with the eight tones of the scale, a
rather unhelpful instance of fitting numerical categories together.57
Later writers matched the linear, or sequential movement-in-time
nature of the two arts, working from the general position that
works of music, like those of language, have a beginning, a middle,
and an end. Yet when this analogy is applied in detail difficulties
arise. Dressier, in 1563, can use the terms exordium and conclusion
Burmeister is already applying
quite broadly, but by 1606 Joachim
to the musical exordium the injunction from rhetoric that it should
be a captatio benevolentiae, winning the listener's attention (yes) and
sympathy (how?).58 Even more questionable, in musical terms, are
the sections usually found in the middle of an oration, confutatio
and confirmatio, by which one's opponents' arguments are refuted,
and one's own confirmed. Who are the "enemies" in a musical
Mattheson, never at a loss for proofs of the identity
composition?
of music and rhetoric, defines in music as the removal of
confutatio
oppositions, including false harmonies, while confirmatio involves
the repetition and variation of musical material?a notably weak
more elaborate attempts have been made to
sequence.59 Although
link musical with the structure of an oration,60 I am
composition
bound to say that I find them misguided and unconvincing. Where
music theory can draw on such general concepts
as decorum, or the
three styles,61 it can adapt alien ideas without either distorting
them or compromising its own language.
But the major challenge to the theorists of musical rhetoric has
been, and remains, to the techniques of elocutio down to the
apply
last detail, in the lore of the tropes and figures of rhetoric. The pio
neer in this attempt at cross-fertilization was Joachim Burmeister
who, in a series of books published between 1599 and 1606, gave
the first extended list of specific musical-rhetorical figures, and
the first (and for many years the only) rhetorical analysis
performed
57See Ruhnke pp. 135ff for Rhau (1538), Schneegass (1591), and Dressier (1563);
also Unger, p. 31 for Dressier.
58M?sica po?tica, ed. Ruhnke, p. 72; Butler (1) p. 56, accepts this identification,
as he does others, all too easily.
59Unger, p. 52.
^See Butler (2), especially pp. 65-73: the increasingly assertive tone of these
62 . . .
Burmeister published Hypomnematum Musicae Poeticae Synopsis (Rostock,
. . .
1599); M?sica autoschediastike (Rostock, 1601), repeating and reworking much
material from his first book; Musicae . . .
practicae (Rostock, 1601), which reprints
part four of the preceding; and M?sica po?tica (Rostock, 1606), which sums up all his
work. The best account of his life and work is given by Martin Ruhnke, but there are
discussions of his musical rhetoric in Brandes, Unger, Palisca (2), and Butler (1). For
his of the Lassus motet see Brandes, pp. 80f; Ruhnke, pp. 162-6; and
analyses
Palisca (2), the fullest account; although I am bound to say that in places he seems to
me to overstate the congruence of the rhetorical and the musical effect.
analysis
63See Table 1, pp. 64-7, and the discussion of forty-six figures in detail, pp. 68
90; Table 2, pp. 92-3 and the discussion pp. 94-8; and appendix 3, pp. 151-4.
64See Vickers, "On writing the history of elocutio," Comparative Criticism
3 (1981), and Classical Rhetoric in English Poetry (London and New York, 1970), espe
cially Chapter 3, 'The Functions of Rhetorical Figures" (pp. 83-131).
65
On the functional of ornament in the Renaissance see W. H. Wood
concept
21 Figures of rhetoric/Figures of music?
ward, Vittorino da Peltre and other Humanist Educators 1897; 1912), p. 230,
(Cambridge,
and Studies in Education during the Age of the Renaissance 1400-1600 (Cambridge,
1906), pp. 132-4; and W. J. Ong, in E. P. Corbett (ed.), Rhetorical Analyses of Literary
Works (Oxford, 1969), p. 139.
66
Directions for Speech and Style (c. 1599), ed. H. Hudson (Princeton, 1935), p. 12.
67Longinus, On the Sublime, ?22, tr. A. H. Gilbert in Literary Criticism: Plato to
Accordingly in the first figure it seems that the arm draws back and
the hand whirls about to bring the sword to the adversary's body,
while in the second his body is as itwere pierced with quick and re
peated thrusts.69
Ill
72See Ruhnke, p. 150, who rejects Unger's conclusion that the musical figures
derived from the figures of rhetoric: "Dass sich analoge Namen finden Hessen, be
weist eine innere Verwandschaft beider K?nste, nicht jedoch die der
Abh?ngigkeit
einen von der anderen/' Yet the relationship was
always that the rhetoricians of mu
sic went to the already-existing categories of rhetoric to argue that identical, or analo
73
his Handbuch der literarischen Rhetorik, 2 volumes, in 1960
Lausberg published
(Munich: Hueber), and an abridgement of it, Elemente der literarischen Rhetorik, in
1963 (Munich: Hueber). It has been translated into Italian.
74London, 1968: Routledge & Kegan Paul. See my review in Critical Quarterly,
12 (1970), pp. 382-3.
75See Sonnino, pp. 53f on congeries, 103 and 64 on plok?.
25 Figures of rhetoric/Figures of music?
76Butler (1), pp. 51-2. Buelow has described Sonnino as "an excellent aid":
cit. in note as
op. 26 above, p. 251. He also describes Unger's book "outstanding":
p. 252.
77
The Compleat Gentleman (1622); ed. V. B. Heltzel (Ithaca, N.Y., 1962), p. 116. Cf.
Butler (1)pp. 60f and Butler (2)pp. 57f.
78A Midsummer Dream, 4.1.215, 5.1.194: cf. Joseph, pp. 54-7, 288,
Night's
294, 295.
26 RHETORICA
But if the modern scholar confuses the two figures, so, it seems,
did Henry Peacham before him. Nor was he alone in so doing. One
of the distinctive musical devices of Josquin des Prez, not original
to him but certainly used with full artistic awareness, is interrupt
ing the flow of polyphony with homophonic passages in order to
stress important words in the text, such as at suscipe deprecationem
and incarnatus est in the mass. Josquin used this stylistic contrast at
these passages in all but one of his masses, and Palestrina did the
same in all of his 93 masses.79 Burmeister named this technique
noema, which in rhetoric is connected with indirect, allusive dis
course, as is shown by its Latin name, intimatio. Burmeister evi
wanted to refer to a device that would describe the marking
dently
off of a section of the text, but unfortunately he used an indirect
mode to name passages of direct emphasis; he also consistently
confused auxesis with climax or gradation Johann Nucius (1613), who
frequently used figures in an eccentric sense, or renamed them,
equated homoioteleuton, which is where succeeding clauses or sen
tences end with words which have identical case endings (similiter
desinens), with aposiopesis, which is the sudden breaking off of a sen
tence yet in such a way that the listener can complete the sense.81
Two more dissimilar figures can hardly be imagined. But Moritz
Vogt (1719) made an equally eccentric identification of epanadiplosis,
where the same word that ends one clause or sentence begins the
next one, with epanalepsis, where the same word is placed at the
and end of a clause or sentence.82 I draw attention to
beginning
these errors not in a spirit of superiority, since to err is human, but
to stress the hazards involved in using the detailed techniques of
rhetoric. Whether the error is due to the writer's lapse of concen
tration, or to the fault of the authority he relies on, does not matter:
closer, but later, definition); on auxesis Iclimax see Brandes pp. 15, 53f; Unger, pp. 77 i;
Palisca(2), pp. 50, 56.
81
For Nucius' confusion see Brandes p. 16, Unger p. 79; and for his general ec
centricity Ruhnke p. 141, and p. 151 on variations in terminology among the rhetoric
books.
82For Vogt's confusion see Unger, p. 76; and ibid., p. 77 on the confusion of
noema with exclam?tio.
27 Figures of rhetoric/Figures of music?
In both cases
the brevity of the discussion, and the raising of im
portant issues by the question form without attempting to answer
them, reminds one of another celebrated question, from Bacon's
own Essay "Of Truth": "'What is truth?' said jesting Pilate, and
staid not for an answer."83 Neither Peacham nor Bacon was jest
ing, indeed Bacon subsequently gave a more extended list of sug
gested identifications84, but these are questions which it is easier to
raise suggestively than to answer systematically. Ipropose to review
a dozen or so of the rhetorical figures claimed for music
by Burmei
ster and others, and to investigate the degree of translatability of a
model from one art-system to another, beginning with the simple
figures of repetition. An important preliminary point, however, is
that all discussions of music and rhetoric assume that notes in mu
sic behave in the same way as do words in language. That is, since
notes can be repeated, as words can, then the effect will be similar.
Insofar as we consider the shape of the resulting figure, that may
be true; yet what of the meaning of the words? How can music be
83Bacon, Works ed. J. Spedding et al., 14 vols. (London, 1857-1874), III. 348-9;
also IV. 339, II. 388-9.
84For Bacon's suggestions see the thorough discussion in Palisca (2), pp. 42-6.
Professor Palisca claims to find a "progression of Bacon's from a recognition
thought
of the analogy between musical effects and the movements of the affections toward
the identification of musical devices with the tropes, or figures, of rhetoric" (p. 46):
that seems to me, rather, the progression made some modern students, from
by
analogy to identification.
28 RHETORICA
85Palisca (2), p. 65 n. 38; Unger, p. 68: Burmeister (1606) calls it a fugue, Thurin
gus (1625) limits it to the bass. Butler (1) p. 59 attempts to relate anaphora to "report"
and "fugue" in its strictest sense, but slants his case to begin with by defining the
in rhetoric as "the of the same subject at the beginning of successive
figure repetition
clauses of sentences" italics: for read 'word'). His argument seems to
(my 'subject'
me overambitious.
or complexio as the repetition
86Unger pp. 73, 77. Nucius' definition of symplok?
of the opening motif of a musical period at its ending confuses it with epanalepsis,
in fact.
29 Figures of
rhetoric/Figures of music?
87Unger, p. 77, records that it was called auxesis or climax [sic!) in the seven
teenth century, gradatio in the eighteenth. Perhaps the later theorists were better in
formed, or were using more reliable sources.
88Translated Palisca (2), p. 50; see also Brandes, pp. 15 (who defines it as put
two noemas, the second an increased created
ting together having expressiveness
either by a rise of pitch or an enlargement in the number of voices), 53, and Unger,
p. 78, who claims that the idea of incrementum, as with and in
harmony growing
creasing, points to a far-reaching between both arts. Clearly the phenome
analogy
non is frequent and important in music (often coupled, as Forkel recommended,
with crescendo), but the specificity of the rhetorical structure seems to have been
lost. In his analysis of Lassus' In me transierunt Palisca uses the term to refer to "the
repetition of a motive in the Bass a tone higher" (Palisca [2], p. 56), a rather drastic
reduction of the figure's range or reference.
89Palisca (2), p. 65 n. 38; also Brandes, pp. 53ff, and Unger, p. 157: the repetition
of a melodic motif at the same pitch ("Es gen?gt dabei, wenn nur der
jeweils
Anfang
notengetreu wiederholt wird").
30 RHETORICA
"Do you hear how he misplaces?," the audience might have said,
as Escalus does in Measure for Measure when Elbow, in his court
case, confuses the accused (Pompey) with the judges:
Prove it before these varlets here, thou honourable man.
In musical rhetoric the term has lost both its humour and its spe
cific structure. Unger concedes that it is not directly applicable to
music, since Burmeister describes it as a "Gegenfuge," or a "suc
cession of intervals inverted." Gregory G. Butler, translating thus,
comments:
92See Brandes, p. 26; Unger, p. 84; Ruhnke, p. 151; Palisca (1), p. 142; Palisca (2),
p. 64; Butler (1), p. 51?admitting that the use of this term in musical rhetoric is
"highly general."
93Virgil, Aeneid I, 135, tr. H. R. Fairclough (Loeb Library): "Do ye now dare, O
winds, without commend of mine, to mingle earth and sky, and raise confusion
thus? Whom I-! But better is it to calm the troubled waves: hereafter with
no like penalty shall ye atone me your trespasses." Rubens' of this incident
painting
is now in the Fogg Art Gallery, Harvard University.
32 RHETORICA
or a colon."94 Here the figure has lost all the specificity it enjoys in
language.
As has become clear in the course of this discussion the forma
tion of a musical rhetoric takes the form of a theorist looking at a
rhetorical textbook95 in order to find a figure in rhetoric that ap
or could be adapted to, a musical effect or structure. At times
plied,
the application is limited: thus apocope in rhetoric describes the
omission of a letter or syllable at the end of aword. To Burmeister it
could be applied to describe an incomplete fuga realis,96 an analogy
that was true to the shape of the rhetorical figure, on the horizontal
plane. In other cases the analogy had to transpose the rhetori
cal figure on to a different plane. In rhetoric hyperbole means the
of the normal, or probable, or truthful, an exaggera
exceeding
tion that is used to communicate truth through lies, as one rheto
rician put it. It is a figure with a complex theory,97 but is based on
some kind of norm or convention of the possible or truthful, and
works neither through the shape of words, nor their repetition, but
through their meaning. Burmeister, unable to handle the semantic
level, transposed the whole figure into a rather narrow musical
context, in which it refers to the composer writing a note that is too
a
high for the normal range of the voice, and is therefore placed on
line above the five lines of the stave. To match this figure Burmei
ster invented its complement, hypobole, when the voice descends
below the stave.98 Here Burmeister has shifted from the semantic
94Ruhnke, p. 156: "In Burmeisters Beispielen steht die aposiopesis aber nur nach
S?tzen oder nach einem Doppelpunkt." From which point, how
abgeschlossenen
ever, he reasons that the musical is not dependent on the rhetorical one: "Von
figure
Figur vom rhetorischen
einer Abh?ngigkeit der musikalischen Sinngehalt kann also
nicht gesprochen werden." But is it not rather the case that the musical concept is
on the rhetorical one, is unable to render the detailed connotations
dependent yet
into its own language?
95
We know that Burmeister drew his knowledge of rhetoric direct from Me
lanchthon's Institutiones Rhetoricae (1521), and from reworkings of Melanchthon by
Lucas Lossius: details in Ruhnke, passim.
96On apocope see Brandes, p. 70; Palisca (1) p. 142 (where it is de
p. 27; Unger,
fined as "partial imitation"), and Butler (1), p. 58.
97 in
See Brian Vickers, "The Songs and Sonnets and the Rhetoric of Hyperbole,"
John Donne, Essays in Celebration, ed. A. J. Smith (London, 1972), pp. 132-174.
98See Brandes, p. 18; Unger, p. 80 (conceding that under these terms "bezeich
net Burmeister etwas rein ?usserliches, n?mlich das Verlassen des Notensystems
nach oben oder nach unten," and describing rhetorical as "durchaus un
hyperbole
geeignet" for imitation in music); and Ruhnke, p. 158.
33 Figures of rhetoric/Figures of music?
"Brandes, whose work is of a more limited range than either Unger or Ruhnke,
nevertheless surpasses them and, in my opinion, more recent writers on this topic,
in his awareness of the basic discriminations that need to be made between music
and rhetoric. So he writes on this point: "Wenn wir nun annehmen, dass die mu
sikalische Figurenlehre in irgendeinem zur poetischen
Abh?ngigkeitsverh?ltnis
steht, so m?ssten aus der Ersteren die von vornherein aus
Figurenlehre Tropen
scheiden, da sie mit ihren inhaltlichen und gedanklichen keine Pa
Ver?nderungen
rallele in der Musik finden, weil und musikalische
sprachlich-gedankliche Logik
ganz verschiedene Voraussetzungen haben" (p. 25); also pp. 26f.
100Vickers, Classical Rhetoric, p. 110. See Butler (1), p. 61, linking antimetabole,
hypallage, and antistrophe [sic! see above, note 8] and implying some connection with
musical figures.
101
On metalepsis see Sonnino, p. 186, Sister Joseph, p. 158; Brandes, pp. lOf, 25f;
Unger, p. 82; Ruhnke, pp. 149f; and Butler (1), p. 58.
34 RHETORICA
the first words of a text while others begin later, with its continua
tion (some will begin with "De ore prudentis" and continue with the
rest of the phrase, "procedit mel") others will enter, later, only at
those words). This refers only to the form of the text, and its dis
position among the voices, not to its meaning, nor to any deduc
tions about its meaning.
The transposition effected for metalepsis was made for other fig
ures with an important semantic content. Congeries, for example,
which means in rhetoric the heaping up of words for purposes of
emphasis (the rhetoricians are divided as to whether the words
heaped up are of the same or of different meanings), is defined by
Burmeister as "an accumulation of perfect and imperfect consonant
intervals, the movement of which is permitted [by the rules of
counterpoint]." As Unger says, the connection between rhetoric
and music lies only in the concept of "heaping up," and is thus
rather external?or formal, as Iwould put it.102For distributio, which
in rhetoric is the technique of dividing a complex statement into its
parts, or dividing the general into special kinds, Unger claims that
Scheibe (1745) uses it exactly as in rhetoric, as applied to the fugue.103
But in rhetoric the division is one of ideas, or concepts, or topics of
the discussion. Music retains only the formal association, and even
here there is the major difference that the orator would have to
treat each topic one after the other, while the composer can do that
but can also sustain them simultaneously. In musical terms dubi
tatio can refer to a doubtful modulation, or a moment of indecision,
and most listeners could cite instances of a composer using hesita
tion in completing a cadence, or returning to a home key or a main
theme. But in rhetoric the figure is a combative one, from the law
courts, where, as Quintilian explains, it "may lend an impression
of truth to our statements" when we "pretend to be at a loss where
to begin or end," or express hesitation about the topic at issue.104
Music has transposed the concept into its own terms, which are
more restricted than those of rhetoric, and has inevitably substi
tuted formal properties for semantic ones.
IV
108
Brandes, p. 25.
109Ruhnke, p. 149.
110Ibid., pp. 152f, 154 (auxesis), 157 (anaphora), 159.
111
Unger, pp. 84, 85, 86; Ruhnke, pp. 153, 154.
112Ruhnke, p. 154. 113Brandes, pp. 28, 29. 114Butler (1), p. 58.
115
The New Oxford History ofMusic, Vol. IV: The Age of Humanism, 1540-1630 ed.
G. Abraham (London, 1968), p. 57.
37 Figures of rhetoric/Figures of music?
From this and other signs one derives the impression that Bur
meister, teaching in the Gymnasium at Rostock while working on
his theoretical treatises, was rather out of touch with newer devel
opments in both music and rhetoric. Brandes found it strange that
Burmeister should not use the figure exclamatio, so obviously ap
plicable to music116?especially, we might add, to the new styles of
the m?sica reservata and the madrigal. Twenty years later Martin
Ruhnke was surprised that, dealing with the figure hypotyposis,
which is the vivid presentation of the meaning and feeling of the
text, making the words visible, Burmeister should not have cited
the word-painting in the Italian madrigal.117 If rather out of touch
with new developments in music, Burmeister?whose main au
thority on rhetoric is a digest of the system of that early humanist
Melanchthon?is unaware of the increasing stress in rhetoric on
the ways in which rhetorical figures should describe and arouse
strong feelings. The figure anadiplosis, which Burmeister used for a
harmonic effect, was only supposed to be used, Scaliger taught, in
connection with great passions.118 One cannot find in Burmeister's
works anything like Athanasius Kircher's description of repetitio (or
anaphora) as a figure to express energy, and the vehement passions
of the soul: for Burmeister it is not a way of arousing the passions
but an ornament of the text.119Where parrhesia in rhetoric described
the orator's intention to speak out (libera vox), even though the
matter should be controversial, Burmeister applies it to dissonance,
but the examples he gives do not refer to especially emotional parts
of the text.120
or has an ex
by Burmeister
not every device considered is expressive
of them are constructive ar
devices,
pressive purpose. Many simply
tifices that grew out of a need to knit the voices of a composi
together
tion once the cantus firmus was abandoned as the main thread earlier
in the century. . . . mimesis, and
Fuga, anadiplosis, hypallage, anaphora
are various ways of interrelating the parts of a polyphonic composi
tion. Climax and auxesis are means of achieving continuity.121
To the hasty reader the last few pages may have seemed like a ter
between specialists, one that can be safely
minological dispute
over. Yet, in all areas of knowledge, terminology is a funda
passed
mental issue. If one mechanic understands by "clutch" what an
other understands by "accelerator," the result can only be confu
sion, and danger. Inmusical rhetoric no one is likely to get harmed
by mistaking one figure for another, yet the subject will certainly
become confused. And since the whole trend of modern scholar
is towards ever more detailed reconstructions of the past,
ship
121
Palisca (2), p. 56. Palisca goes on to argue that such devices "are artfully dis
that permit the total sound to be renewed while details are
guised repetitions being
reused. The level of redundancy essential to musical coherence would be intolerable
in prose, even in oratory. Consequently, music is a natural sanctuary for the rheto
rical figures that involve repetition." While this is partly a fair account of the differ
ent levels of "redundancy" in the two arts, it seems to me unhistorical, as an
apol
ogy for Burmeister, given the theory of rhetoric and of musical rhetoric that figures
of repetition are not mere forms of sustaining a flow of sound but are intense ex
123
Vol. XV, pp. 793-803. See also the articles "Aesthetics of music," Vol. I,
pp. 120-134; "Affections, doctrine of the," 1,135-6; "Analysis, ?11,1": I, 343-4; "Fig
ures, doctrine of musical", VI, 545.
40 RHETORICA
124Brandes, 25-9:
pp. see the in note 99 above.
quotation
Mass., 1942; are from the Mentor edition
125Cambridge, quotations paperback
(New York, 1951). All italics in the text are the author's.
42 RHETORICA