(Peter Glassen) The Senses of Ought (BookFi)
(Peter Glassen) The Senses of Ought (BookFi)
(Peter Glassen) The Senses of Ought (BookFi)
implied by it. It may just be possible that this alternative is exactly the one
that would allow the "good-reasoners" in ethics to indulge in truth-talk
about nomative and valuative sentences without going over to objectivism.
I do not myself, however, think it would break the present "deadlock in
ethics" between the objectivists and their opponents.
Received September 2, 1958
NOTES
1 The Moral Point oi View: A Rat/anal Basis of Ethics, Contemporary Philosophy,
Max Black, ed. (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1958).
The Structure oi Metaphysics (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1955).
8I seem to find an equivocation in Baier's thought which I cannot explore here
between a true reason for an action and truly a reason for an action or between stating
a true rule and truly stating a rule, which may have helped bridge the commonly recog-
nized boundary between truth (of statements) and goodness (of making them).
NOTES
I " A Mistaken Distinction in Ethical Theory," Philosophical Studies, 8:69-71
(October 1957).
Ibid., p. 69.
Ibid., p. 70.
' Ibid., p. 71.
Ibid., p. 70.
6 Perhaps the best modem discussion of this distinction is to be found in Sir David
Ross's Foundations of Ethics (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1939), Chapter 12.
This is, indeed, suggested by A. C. Ewing's discussion, in his The De~nition of
Good (New York: Macmillan, 1947), p. 121. But Ewing's failure to realize what is the
general formula for distinguishing the senses of "ought" makes his discussion unduly
prolix.
8 Ewing distinguishes (ibid., pp. 118-2 3 ) among "three different usages of ["ought"]
in ethics" as follows (I use his numbers but present them in a different order): (1) in
one usage, " 'The action we ought to do' may mean that action which is really preferable,
taking everything into account"; (3) in another usage, "we ought to perform an act if
in the light of the availab]e evidence it seems the preferable act to choose"; (2) in still
16 PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES
another usage " 'ought' . . . is . . . used in a sense in which not to do what one
ought, or to do what one ought not to do, is always morally blameworthy."
Now Ewing's sense (2) is equivalent to my second sense, since to do an action that
is morally bad is to do something for which one is morally blameworthy, and vice versa.
Ewing's senses (1) and (3) are not clearly moral senses at all, or any other specific
senses, unless we state from what point of view an action is preferable--the moral point
of view, the prudential, or some other. However, even if we state that we are speaking
about an action that is preferable from the moral point of view, we are still being am-
biguous, for we might mean from the point of view of what is right, or from the point
of view of what is morally good. Hence it will not do to discriminate among the moral
senses of "ought" in terms of what is preferable on the whole or what is preferable on
the basis of the available evidence; we must discriminate among them by reference to
the pairs of contrary moral terms in terms of which the senses of "ought" can be
specified. And so far as my observation goes "ought" is always used in moral discourse
in a sense which can be specified in terms of "right" and "wrong" and their equivalents,
or in a sense which can be specified in terms of "morally good" and "morally bad" and
their equivalents.