Faith and Philosophy 11 (1994), Pp. 592-625.: Stoic Psychotherapy in Descartes and Spinoza
Faith and Philosophy 11 (1994), Pp. 592-625.: Stoic Psychotherapy in Descartes and Spinoza
Derk Pereboom
Penultimate draft
Although the influence of the Stoic outlook on sixteenth and seventeenth century
European culture has been well-documented, it is seldom recalled how, in particular, Stoicism
affects the views of the early modern European philosophers.ii The works of Descartes and
Spinoza supply remarkable illustrations of this impact. Some of the most interesting of these
Stoic influences can be found in their writings on therapy for the passions. Both Descartes and
Spinoza ground their discussions in the psychotherapeutic theory of the Stoics, and their final
views bear the imprint of the Stoic model, although in different respects.
The Stoic theory embraces two controversial claims, each of which gives rise to a
therapeutic strategy. The first claim is that we have much more voluntary control over our
actions and passions than one might ordinarily suppose, and the associated therapeutic strategy
advises that we exercise this control as a means to well-being. The second claim is that the
universe is wholly determined by the providential divine will, which is identical with the laws of
nature, and the correlated therapeutic proposal recommends that we align our concerns with
God's so that we will achieve equanimity even in the most trying of circumstances. Descartes
advocates each of these controversial claims and the associated therapeutic strategies. But
although Spinoza accepts the Stoics' belief about divine determinism, he rejects their
1
understanding of our voluntary control over the actions and passions. Nevertheless, Spinoza
attempts to preserve some of the key intuitions behind each of the two therapeutic strategies,
A thorough and persuasive account of the first claim is presented by Brad Inwood in his
Ethics and Human Action in Early Stoicism.iii According to the Stoic theory, human action has
three main stages. In the first, the possibility of an action is presented to the agent. For
example, the possibility of eating a piece of pie might be presented to you by your seeing it on
the kitchen table. This stage is called phantasia, presentation or impression. Corresponding
to a phantasia is a lekton, a proposition or sayable, for example, it is fitting for me to eat that
piece of pie, which the agent entertains but does not necessarily endorse when she has a
phantasia.
In the second stage, synkatathesis, assent, comes into play. A mature human agent
normally has the power to freely and voluntarily assent to, dissent from, or suspend judgment
with regard to the lekton corresponding to a phantasia. (In the Stoic view, this power is not
possessed by animals or by young children.iv) Its source is the rational, ruling, part of the soul -
- the hêgemonikon. (The other parts of the soul are the five senses, the linguistic part, and the
reproductive part). When an agent dissents or suspends judgment with regard to the initial
lekton, the development of an action ceases. But if the agent assents, the third stage, hormê,
impulse, results. According to Cleanthes and Chrysippus, the mind is made up a pneuma, a
2
composite of air and fire, and hormê (which also means shock or attack) is a forceful motion of
this substance that results from assent to a lekton corresponding to a phantasia.v Hormê is a
psychological (as opposed to physical) component of an action; for instance, the setting of
oneself to eat the piece of pie is a hormê. Parallel to (and quite clearly causing) the hormê is a
self-directed judgment, which results from assenting to the lekton corresponding to the
phantasia. In our example, the judgment would be 'Yes, it is fitting for me to eat that piece of
pie,' and if Inwood is right, the hormê is also linked with an imperative like 'Eat that piece of pie!'vi
The Stoics' theory of action is, in part, a subspecies of their theory of judgment. In
general, judgment results from the agent's exercise of its power of assent on the occasion of a
phantasia. According to Chrysippus, the (normal) function of a phantasia is to "reveal itself and
its cause" to its recipient, and hence "the word 'phantasia' is derived from 'phôs,' [light]; just as
light reveals itself and whatever else it includes in its range, so phantasia reveals itself and its
cause."vii Nevertheless, there are both accurate and misleading phantasiai, which the Stoics
The cataleptic, which they say is the criterion of things, is that which arises from what is
and is stamped and impressed exactly in accordance with what is. The acataleptic is
either that which does not arise from what is, or from that which is but is not exactly in
accordance with what is: one which is not clear and distinct (mê tranê mêde ektupon).ix
An agent guided by reason would refuse assent upon entertaining an acataleptic phantasia, and
would grant assent only to the cataleptic sort.x In the Stoic view, what is distinctive about a
phantasia that functions as a component of action is that it reveals to the agent something that
3
might motivate her, for example, something that would contribute to her health or well-being.
Such a phantasia potentially gives rise to hormê, and hence it is called phantasia hormêtike
(hormetic presentation).xi An agent guided by reason would refuse assent upon considering a
hormetic presentation when, for example, the result would be an action not directed towards
the good.
A prominent feature of the Stoic picture is that passions (given a certain specific
conception of a passion) are a type of hormê, and hence fit into the theory in just the way hormê
does.xii Thus for an agent to experience a passion, she must first have an appropriate phantasia.
She must then assent to a lekton corresponding to the phantasia, perhaps to a lekton such as 'it
is fitting for me to fear my reputation being ruined by the media.' From assent to such a lekton
a hormê of a special type results, one which is identical with the passion. In the Stoic
conception, therefore, passions do not happen to an agent. Rather, whenever an agent has a
passion, it has in a sense been chosen by that agent. And accordingly, an agent can avoid
struggling against passions altogether, because simply by exercising its power of assent, she can
In the chapter on Zeno of Citium in his Lives of the Philosophers, Diogenes Laertius
recounts the Stoic classification of the passions.xiv In the classical Stoic view, the word 'pathos,'
(which is standardly but often misleadingly translated as 'passion,') always denotes a state to be
avoided, a state upon whose presentation (phantasia) one must never assent. Citing treatises
by Zeno and Hecato,xv both entitled Peri Pathôn, Diogenes observes that for the Stoics there are
four great classes of the pathê: craving (epithumia), fear (phobos), pleasure (hêdonê), and
4
distress (lupê). Each of these types of pathos is irrational (alogos). Craving is irrational
appetite (alogos orexis), fear is irrational avoidance (alogos ekklisis), pleasure is irrational elation
or expansion (alogos eparsis), and grief or distress is irrational contraction (alogos sustolê).
Craving and fear are irrational attitudes towards what one thinks to be good and bad respectively,
while pleasure and distress are irrational attitudes towards getting and failing to get what one
wants.xvi
Diogenes Laertuis reports that the Stoics also maintain that there are three classes of
"good passions" (eupatheia, which are not pathê, by the classical Stoic characterization); joy
(chara), caution or watchfulness (eulabeia), and will or wishing (boulêsis). xvii Joy is rational
elation (eulogos eparsis), and thus corresponds to pleasure, caution is rational avoidance
(eulogos ekklisis) and is the counterpart to fear, while will as opposed to craving is rational
appetite (eulogos orexis). (The Stoic classification includes no rational counterpart to grief or
pain -- perhaps they think that mental contraction is never rational.) In certain circumstances
the eupatheiai are appropriately experienced. Joy, for example, is fitting when one
What then is your own? The use of external presentations (chrêsis phantasiôn).
Therefore, when you are in harmony with nature in the use of external presentations,
then be elated; for then it will be some good of your own at which you will be elated.
(Epictetus, Encheiridion 6)
Hence, joy is appropriate when one's employment of one's power of assent towards external
5
Chrysippus characterizes the pathê as contrary to nature and thereby irrational.xix But
why are they irrational in this sense? Diogenes attributes to Zeno the claim that the pathê are
analogy (reported by Galen), a pathos is like running as opposed to walking. When one runs,
one cannot stop precisely when one wants to; similarly, once one has a pathos, one cannot cease
having it just by wanting to.xx But a pathos' resistance to voluntary control is not precisely what
makes it bad for an agent. Rather, a pathos is harmful because of its resistance to voluntary
control under the guidance of reason, and further, its tendency to impair one's more general
ability to exercise rational voluntary control.xxi A fragment from Stobaeus illustrates this view:
'Irrational' and 'contrary to nature' are not used in their ordinary senses: 'irrational' is
states of pathos frequently see that it is not suitable to do this but are carried away by
the intensity, as though by a disobedient horse, and are induced to do it... The sense of
contrary to the right and natural reason. Everyone in states of pathos turns aside from
reason, but not like those who have been deceived in something or other, but in a special
way. For when people have been deceived, for instance over atoms being first
principles, they give up the judgment, once they have been taught that it is not true. But
when people are in states of pathos, even if they realize or are taught to realize that one
should not feel distress or fear or have their soul, quite generally, in states of pathos, they
still do not give these up, but are brought by them to a position of being controlled by
6
their tyranny. (LS I 411)
Even if one's reason would proscribe the pathos that one presently has, the pathos will
nevertheless resist and overpower one's capacity for rational voluntary control, and one would
therefore persist in the pathos despite the counsel of reason. Consequently, the wise person,
Inwood illuminates the Stoic theory of the pathê by a fragment from Epictetus:
Presentations in the mind... with which the intellect of man is struck as soon as the
appearance of something which happens reaches the mind are not voluntary or subject
to one's control; but by a force of their own they press themselves on men to be
acknowledged. But the assents... by which the same presentations are acknowledged
are voluntary and are subject to human control. Therefore, when some frightening
sound from the sky or a collapsing building or the sudden announcement of some danger,
or something else of the sort occurs, it is inevitable that even the sage's soul be moved
for a short while and be contracted and grow pale, not because he has formed an opinion
of anything evil but because of certain rapid and unreflective movements which forestall
the proper function of intellect and reason. Soon, though, the sage in question does not
give assent... to such presentations... but rejects and refuses them and judges that there
In the Stoic conception, mere perception of the threat of a dangerous event is causally insufficient
to produce the pathos of fear. Rather, the occurrence of the pathos of fear requires that the
7
threatening event cause in the agent a presentation of the pathos, and that he freely assent to a
lekton corresponding to this presentation. The sophos will always refuse to assent upon a
presentation of a pathos, although such a presentation may initially jar his capacity for reasoning.
The fragment from Epictetus helps us correct several often-misunderstood features the
Stoic theory of the passions. First, a phantasia that introduces a pathos does not leave the
agent motivationally unaffected. Rather, a presentation of this sort gives rise to an interest in
the agent, and this is the force of classifying it as phantasia hormêtikê. Furthermore, given our
terminology, we might classify such a presentation as a passion. When I discover that someone
as the passion of anger. One cannot tell whether the Stoics would agree with this
categorization, since they have no term corresponding to our word 'passion.' The distinctive
claim of the Stoics is that an emotional state that seriously impairs one's capacity for voluntary
rational control -- a pathos -- cannot occur unless one voluntarily assents to a lekton that
corresponds to a presentation that introduces such a state. In addition, they maintain the
optimistic view that since a presentation of this sort occurs involuntarily, it cannot by itself
seriously impair one's capacity for voluntary rational control, and that by exercising one's power
to voluntarily refuse assent, one can avoid altogether states that hinder reason in this way.
The second therapeutic strategy flows from the Stoics' deterministic view of the universe;
"Chrysippus says that fate is a certain everlasting ordering of the whole; one set of things follows
on and succeeds another, and the interconnection is inviolable."xxiii Both Zeno and Chrysippus
maintain that all things are determined by God (Zeus) which is identical to reason (logos),
8
providence (pronoia), and nature (phusis). God is a physical substance, apparently identical
either to pneuma, a combination of air and fire, or just to fire, which is in everything as its
The Stoics made God out to be intelligent, a designing fire which methodically proceeds
toward creation of the world, and encompasses all the seminal principles according to
which everything comes about according to fate, and a breath (pneuma) pervading the
whole world, which takes on different names owing to the alterations of the matter
Chrysippus is willing to speak of many gods; for example, in his view Neptune is the air which
diffuses itself through the sea. But at the time of the periodic conflagration (ekpurôsis) in a
Great Year, all the gods are destroyed except Zeus.xxv Furthermore, according to Chrysippus
the gods are providential, since they are beneficial and friendly toward human beings, and they
"made us for our own sake and for each other, and the animals for our sake."xxvi Hence, Zeus
determines the universe in a manner that is providential for human beings (at least for human
beings generally considered, but apparently not in a way that aims at the good of each individual
human being.)
In the Stoic conception, one should accommodate oneself to the determinism of the
universe by, as Epictetus puts it, seeking to have things happen as they do happen (Encheiridion
8). One should do so even if what happens might be bad from one's personal point of view,
that is, from the perspective of one's ordinary human aspirations for personal survival, happiness,
and success. The Stoic recommendation is that one should cease to appraise the events of
9
one's life from one's personal point of view, and to evaluate them instead from the divine
perspective. That is, one should appraise the events of one's life solely by the purposes God
has in creating and preserving the universe, aims which are distinct from, and may conflict with,
This abstracted stance towards one's life is expressed in the Stoic conception of
reservation (hupexairesis, literally 'exception'). xxvii In our universe, much is not within our
control, and thus we may find ourselves rationally aiming to achieve ends we are not certain to
obtain. This sort of difficulty might result either from our lack of power or from our lack of
knowledge. If a someone aspires to become president, he may not have the capability to
achieve his end, and further, even if he will in fact succeed, he will likely not come to know this
when he forms his intent. One strategy for handling this type of difficulty is to avoid striving for
anything one cannot be assured of acquiring. But the Stoics do not encourage this approach.
Whenever one acts, one does so by assenting to a lekton that corresponds to the
presentation of the action. If one is to act in accordance with the will of God, the judgments
one makes as a result of assenting must conform to this will. Thus if one aims to set sail
tomorrow, one should not simply resolve to set sail tomorrow, but as Seneca advises in On
Tranquility, to say "I will set sail tomorrow unless something intervenes," or "if it is so fated." In
the explicitly theological formulation one would resolve "I will set sail tomorrow unless it goes
against the will of God." If the judgment that results from one's assent includes a clause such
as 'unless it goes against the will of God,' a reserved impulse will ensue.xxviii Accordingly, the
10
propositional aspect of acting with reservation is matched by a type of mental state. At this
level, reservation involves a degree of psychological detachment from any outcome that is not
up to us. As a result of this detachment we will not be (as) distressed if an attempt to achieve
some end fails. In Seneca's view, "the suffering that comes to the mind from the abandonment
of desire must necessarily be much lighter if you have not certainly promised it success."
successes and failures. It ultimately requires that we evaluate the outcomes of our ventures
from the point of view of God's purposes. If we supplement this stance with the belief that
everything that happens is providentially ordained by God, perhaps we will be able to accept the
result of any endeavor with equanimity, and even to regard any outcome with joy. Marcus
You must consider the doing and perfecting of what the universal Nature (tê koinê physei)
decrees in the same light as your health, and welcome all that happens, even if it seems
harsh, because it leads to the health of the universe (tên tou kosmou hygieian), and the
welfare and well-being of Zeus. For he would not have allotted this to anyone if it were
If we align our desires with the good of the Whole, we will welcome anything that happens to us,
even our own impending death, for "cessation of life is no evil to the individual, since ... it is good
if it is timely for the Whole, bringing benefit to it, and benefitted by it" (Meditations XII, 23).xxix
These two Stoic approaches to therapy for the passions, one which affirms the power of
assent, and the other divine determinism, might be thought incompatible, and the early Stoics
11
attempted to respond to this sort of challenge. Chrysippus holds that despite universal divine
determinism, assent is voluntary and free. This is possible because events can be determined
to occur in accordance with our free voluntary control: "we contribute much assiduous and
zealous effort with respect to these things because it has been ordained that they occur in
conjunction with our wills".xxx Although upon considering a presentation we have the capacity
to assent, dissent, or suspend judgment, yet whatever our decision turns out to be, it has been
determined by God. As we shall see, Spinoza's rejection of Stoic compatibilism is part of his
motivation to disavow the power of assent and the associated form of therapy, while Descartes'
endorsement of this position is an issue in his correspondence with Elizabeth, to which we now
turn.
II
In 1645 Descartes learns that Princess Elisabeth, with whom he has already enjoyed a
rewarding correspondence, has been ill with a fever for three or four weeks. He diagnoses the
you would be unable to be delivered from all these things, unless, by the force of your
virtue, you render your soul content, despite the disgraces of fortune. (AT IV 201/B119).
A few months later, Descartes proposes that his future correspondence benefit "from the reading
of a certain book, namely, from the book Seneca has written concerning the blessed life..." (to
Elisabeth, 21 July, 1645, AT IV 252-3/B131). That same year Descartes also begins work on The
Passions of the Soul, published in 1649, in which he revises and develops the views he discusses
12
with Elisabeth.
The form of therapy Descartes advocates in these writings is clearly Stoical.xxxi In the
following excerpt from the letter to Elisabeth of October 6, 1645, the important distinctions
dispose one to some passion with the passion itself, but nevertheless they can easily be
distinguished from the passion. For example, when one announces to a city that
enemies are coming to besiege it, the first judgment (jugement) the inhabitants make
concerning the evil that can happen to them is an action of their soul (action de leur ame),
not a passion. And though this judgment is similarly found in many people, they are
nevertheless not equally moved; rather, some are moved more and others less, according
as they possess a greater or lesser habit or inclination towards fear. And before their
soul receives the excitation (emotion) in which alone the passion consists, it is necessary
that she make this judgment; or else, without judging, that she at least conceive the
danger and imprint the image of it upon the brain (which happens by a different action
This passage reflects several central elements of the Stoic theory of the passions. The
judgments the inhabitants of the city make concerning the evil that might occur, which are
actions and precede the passions, seem akin to the judgments that result from assent to lekta
that introduce passions. And the claim that a passion such as fear comes about as a result of
13
account, a judgment is formed by the will's assenting to a preliminary representation, just as the
Stoics affirmed (AT VII, 52-62). This view is repeated in the Principles:
In order to make a judgement, the intellect is of course required since, in the case of
something which we do not in any way perceive, there is no judgement we can make.
But the will is also required so that, once something is perceived in some manner, our
We can infer that the judgments Descartes refers to in the letter to Elisabeth also have this
structure, and thus, that a judgement that results in a passion is preceded by a representation to
Significantly, however, he does allow that a passion might occur without judgment, as
long as the soul "conceive the danger and imprint the image of it upon the brain." In Inwood's
interpretation of classical Stoicism, the pathê, by their very conception, can occur only as a result
of judgment. The Stoics do maintain, however, that in animals and in young children states
analogous to pathê occur without assent and judgment, and they call the process by which an
action or pathos-analogue occurs without assent yielding (eixis). xxxii Descartes could be
allowing that passions might also come about without judgment in adult human beings, but the
excerpt does not specify the circumstances under which this can happen. As we shall see,
however, a departure from the classical Stoic view along these lines is more definite in The
An earlier passage in this same letter might initially appear to conflict with the Stoic
theory:
14
...in man [impressions are formed] by the action of the soul, which has the force to change
the impressions in the brain as, reciprocally, these impressions have the force to excite in
her the thoughts that do not depend upon her will. In consequence of this, one can
generally name 'passions' all the thoughts that are thus excited (qui sont ainsi excitées) in
the soul without the concurrence of her will (sans le concours de la volonté), and
consequently, solely by the impressions in the brain, and without any action that
proceeds from her -- for everything that is not an action is a passion. (AT IV 310/B160)
But there is really no disagreement with Stoicism here. Descartes might at first seem to be
saying that a passion, by its very definition, cannot result from an act of will. But such an initial
impression would be mistaken. Descartes' claim is rather that a passion is never the immediate
effect of the will, but always an immediate effect of impressions in the brain, and thus, in his
terminology, passions are excited without the concurrence of the will. Actions, by contrast, are
immediate effects of the will, and thus occur "with the concurrence of the will." But actions, of
which judgments are a subspecies, can generate passions by causing impressions in the brain
which in turn cause thoughts that do not depend on the will. And thus, in Descartes' view, the
will can mediately cause passions. He provides an illustration of such a process in the passage
...and it is also necessary that, by the same means [i.e. judgment or imagination] the soul
determines the spirits (esprits) that travel from the brain by the nerves into the muscles
to enter those muscles that serve to close the openings of the heart, thus retarding the
circulation of the blood; in consequence, all the body becomes pale, cold, and trembling,
15
and the new spirits, which come from the heart to the brain, are agitated in such a manner
that they can assist in forming there those images that excite in the soul the passion of
fear -- all of which events so closely follow each other that it seems but a single operation.
(AT IV 312-3/B161-2)
For the passion of fear to arise, the soul must determine the spirits in the brain either by
judgment or by imagination. Thereupon the spirits cause a physiological change in the body,
which causes new spirits that travel to the brain to be agitated and thereby to assist in forming
It is noteworthy that the term 'esprits' is derived from 'spiritus,' the Latin equivalent of
'pneuma.' Descartes' view accordingly mirrors the classical Stoic conception insofar as he
maintains that a passion occurs when a judgment causes a movement in the spirits. For
Chrysippus, however, passions, and the judgments that cause them, are actually states of the
pneuma, of which the mind is wholly constituted. For Descartes, by contrast, passions are
states of the immaterial soul, as are the judgments that often occasion them, and the spirits
...all our passions represent the goods to whose pursuit they incite us as very much
greater than they are; and also, that the pleasures of the body are never so durable as
those of the soul, nor so great when one possesses them as they might appear when one
looks forward to them. We must pay careful attention to this, so that when we feel
16
ourselves moved by some passion, we may suspend our judgment (nous suspendions
notre jugement) until the passion is calmed, and so that we do not easily allow ourselves
to be deceived by the false appearances of the goods of the world. (to Elisabeth, 15
Descartes advocates suspending judgment when one is moved by a passion of a certain sort, and
his claim would be altogether Stoical had he not affirmed that "we may suspend judgment until
the passion is calmed." There are two ways to reconcile this assertion with the Stoic view. The
first is to interpret 'passion' as it occurs here as 'presentation that introduces a passion,' or, as
The second is by reading Descartes as extending the Stoic view to a strategy one might adopt
once one is already beset by a debilitating passion. Supposing that the judgment that causes
the passion is still in place after the passion has developed, Descartes could be recommending
that when one is plagued by a harmful passion, one should withdraw one's assent by suspending
one's judgment, because this procedure will allow the passion to subside. In the context of
already troubled by the passions of sadness and anger, and that she therefore needs a way to
Descartes amplifies several aspects of this theory in his later work, The Passions of the
Soul. In Part I we find a passage that might again initially seem anti-Stoical:
Our passions cannot likewise be directly excited (excitées) or removed (ostées) by the
action of our will, but they can be indirectly by the representation of things which are
17
usually joined to the passions we will to have and opposed to the ones we will to reject.
Thus, in order to excite boldness and remove fear in oneself, it is not sufficient to have
the volition to do so -- one must apply oneself to attend to reasons, objects, or precedents
that convince [one] that the peril is not great, that there is always more security in
defence than in flight, that we will have glory and joy from having conquered, whereas
one can expect only regret and shame for having fled, and similar things (I 45/AT XI 362-
3/V43).
As a result, one may "easily overcome the lesser passions, but not the most vigorous and the
strongest, until after the excitation of the blood and spirits has abated" (I 46/AT IX 364/V44).
What might at first appear to conflict with the Stoic conception is Descartes' assertion that our
passions cannot be directly excited or removed by the action of the will. He means to argue
that the will cannot excite or remove a passion simply by willing that it be excited or removed.xxxiv
The Stoics, however, do not claim that a pathos can be directly excited by the will in the sense
that Descartes intends, since they believe that for a pathos to come about, a presentation of the
pathos must first occur. Hence, they might agree with Descartes that passions can only be
indirectly excited "by the representation of things which are usually joined to the passions we
will to have," that is, by entertaining or imagining presentations. Furthermore, the Stoics also
do not maintain that a pathos, once it has come to exist, can be directly removed by the action
of the will. Our inability to remove a pathos directly by the power of assent is one of their
primary reasons for recommending their avoidance, as Chrysippus' analogy to walking and
18
...there is one particular reason why the soul cannot readily alter or check its passions,
which has led me to put in their definition above that they are not only caused but are
also maintained and strengthened by some particular movement of the spirits. This
reason is that they are almost all accompanied by some excitation taking place in the
heart, and consequently also throughout the blood and the spirits, so that until this
excitation has ceased they remain present to our thought, in the same way as objects
capable of being sensed are present to it while they are acting upon our sense organs. (I
46/AT XI 363/V44)
The Passions of the Soul reflects a more mature view about the power the will has to
prevent a passion:
It is also useful to know that although the movements -- both of the gland and of the
spirits and brain -- which represent certain objects to the soul are naturally joined with
those [movements] which excite certain passions in it (soient naturellement joints avec
ceux qui exitent en elle certaines passions), they can nevertheless by habituation be
separated from them and joined with other quite different ones... (I 50/AT XI 369/V48)
Descartes claims that although physiological motions that cause representations of certain
objects may naturally be joined to other physiological motions that excite certain passions in the
soul, motions of the first type do not inevitably result in those passions. We have the ability to
join such motions to states distinct from the passions to which they are naturally joined.
Descartes' picture can be viewed as reflecting two Stoic themes: first, a distinction between a
19
passion proper and a mental state which, like a phantasia, precedes it, and second, our capacity
to avoid the passion usually associated with such a state. That this capacity is a function of the
will is clear from the discussion that immediately precedes the above passage, for there
Descartes repeatedly attributes to the will the ability to combat the passions (I 48-9/AT XI 366-
8/V46-7).
This conception is embellished in Descartes "general remedy for the passions" at the close
of the treatise (III 211/AT XI 485/V132). Although throughout The Passions he maintains that
passions are very often good, he also calls to mind the Stoic conception of the pathê when he
argues that passions are bad when they hinder one's capacity for rational action by causing
certain reasons to seem stronger than they are (III 211/AT IX 486-7/V134).xxxv In an important
respect, however, Descartes now more clearly diverges from the classical Stoic view:
... I have included among these remedies the forethought and skill whereby we can
movements of the blood and spirits from the thoughts to which they are usually joined, I
grant that there are few people who are sufficiently prepared in this way against all sorts
of contingencies, and that these movements, excited in the blood by the objects of the
Passions, immediately follow so swiftly from mere impressions formed in the brain and
from the disposition of the organs, even though the soul may in no way contribute to
them, that there is no human wisdom capable of withstanding them when one is
As we have seen, the Stoics attribute yielding -- a presentation's causing an impulse without the
20
mediation of the power of assent -- to young children and animals, but argue that this process is
not a feature of (normal) adult human psychology. But in this passage Descartes suggests that
passions can arise independently of any contribution on the part of the soul in human beings
considered generally. Thus, by contrast with the Stoics, he now seems to maintain that a
process like yielding may often underlie passions in any human being. And hence, he might well
deny the Stoic doctrine that normally, whenever an adult comes to have a pathos, she must have
But even if he deviates from Stoicism in this way, he nevertheless reaffirms that we always
have the power to avoid or (indirectly) to remove a passion by an appropriate act of will:
And those who are strongly inclined by their constitution to the excitations of Joy, Pity,
Fear, or Anger cannot keep from fainting, crying, trembling, or having their blood all
stirred up just as though they had a fever, when their fantasy is greatly affected by the
object of one of these Passions. But what can always be done on such an occasion, and
what I think I can set down here as the most general remedy for all the excesses of the
Passions and the easiest to put into practice, is this: when one feels the blood stirred up
like that, we should take warning, and recall that everything presented to the imagination
tends to deceive the soul, and to make the reasons for favoring the object of its Passion
appear to it much stronger than they are, and those for opposing it much weaker. (III
211/AT IX 486-7/V134)
At this point Descartes distinguishes two sorts of passion. One motivates the agent to a goal
the achievement of which requires delay, and the other motivates the agent to a goal that
21
requires immediate action:
And when the Passion favors only things whose execution admits of some delay, one must
abstain from making any immediate judgment about them (il faut s'abstenir d'en porter
sur l'heure aucun jugement), and to distract oneself by other thoughts until time and rest
shall have completely calmed the excitation in the blood. Finally, when it incites one to
action requiring one to reach some resolution at once, the will must be inclined above all
to take into consideration and to follow the reasons opposed to those the Passion
represents (que la passion represente), even though they appear less strong. As is the
case when one is unexpectedly attacked by some enemy, the situation does not allow one
When the blood is agitated by an object of a passion, one can always perform certain acts of will
which allow the agitation to subside. Significantly, in this passage Descartes makes a stronger
claim for the power of the will than any the Stoics maintained, since he argues that even if the
passion is already in place one has the power to suspend judgment until it is calmed.
As did the Stoics, Descartes advocates consulting reason when confronted with a
passionate attitude towards an object or an inclination towards such a passion. For him, the
appropriate role of the will in this type of situation is to initiate consideration of reasons against
having the passionate attitude. Reflection of this sort involves recalling the tendency of the
agitation of the blood to make reasons for having the passion seem stronger than they are, and
reasons against seem weaker. Sometimes such deliberation should lead us to suspend
judgment, so that the agitation in the blood will be calmed. At other times, when one does not
22
have the time to allow the agitation to abate, the consideration of contrary reasons can permit
one to refrain from performing actions that the passion inclines one to perform.xxxvi Cultivating
In summary, Descartes' theory is similar to its Stoic counterpart in several core respects.
Like the Stoics, he maintains a distinction between representations that precede and incline one
towards a passion and the passions themselves. Furthermore, in his correspondence with
Elisabeth he seems to favor the Stoic view that in the typical case, a passion results only when an
appropriate judgment is made, where a component essential to any judgment is the will's assent
upon entertaining a preliminary representation. And, although in The Passions of the Soul
Descartes suggests that passions can occur without judgment, still he does claim that a passion
can always be avoided by an act of will. And finally, adopting a position more radical than the
traditional Stoic view, he argues that even when one is already in the grip of a passion, that
passion can be eliminated by the voluntary act of suspending judgment, whereby it is allowed to
subside.xxxvii
III
In his correspondence with Elisabeth Descartes also develops the second Stoic
therapeutic strategy for the passions, together with its theological underpinning. In his letter
of October 6, 1645, he advances the view that God is the cause of every effect:
...it seems to me that all the reasons that prove the existence of God, and that he is the
first and immutable cause of all the effects that do not depend upon the free decision of
23
men, likewise prove in the same way that he is also the cause of all those that do depend
on it. For one could not demonstrate that God exists save by considering him as a being
sovereignly perfect; and God could not be sovereignly perfect if something could happen
in the world that did not come entirely from him... philosophy alone suffices to give us
the knowledge that the least thought cannot enter the mind of man if God had not wished
and willed from all eternity that it enter therein. (AT IV 313-4/B162)
God is the cause of everything that exists or happens; he is the total cause (cause totale) of
everything, whether it is something that depends on a free decision or whether it is not, and
"thus nothing can happen without his will" (AT IV 314/B163). Descartes later indicates to
Elisabeth that he believes the infinitude of divine power to entail God's being the cause of
everything, and that in his view, if human actions did not depend on God's will, his power would
In the letter of October 6 Descartes also claims that no change can occur in God's decrees
on the occasion of some free decision on our part. He then points out a consequence of this
claim for the proper objective of prayer. We should not pray "that we might teach [God] what
we have need of, nor that we might try to persuade him to change something in the order
established by his providence from all eternity: both would be blameworthy." Rather, "we pray
only so that we might obtain what he has wished from all eternity to be obtained by our prayers"
take on our lives should not be the one we might ordinarily have, but rather the divine
perspective. We should pray only for what God has wanted for us from all eternity, and indeed,
24
only for what God has wanted for us from all eternity to be obtained by our prayers.
The passage that most dramatically advocates his version of the second Stoic strategy
occurs in a letter to Chanut, the French ambassador to Sweden. Descartes intended this letter
to reach Christina, the queen of Sweden, by whom he was later employed. In this excerpt, he
sets out "the path one ought to follow to arrive at the love of God":
But if, in addition, we heed the infinity of his power, through which he has created so
many things, of which we are the least part; the extension of his providence that makes
him see in one thought alone everything that has been, is, shall be, and could be; the
infallibility of his decrees (decrets), which, although they do not disturb our free will (libre
arbitre), nevertheless cannot in any fashion be changed; and finally, if, on the one hand,
we heed our insignificance, and if, on the other hand, we heed the grandeur of all created
things, by noting the manner in which they depend on God and by considering them in a
fashion that has a relationship to his omnipotence, without confining them in a globe, as
do they who think the world finite: meditation upon all this so abundantly fills the man
who hears it with such extreme joy that, realizing he would have to be abusive and
ungrateful toward God to wish to occupy God's place, he thinks himself as already having
lived sufficiently because God has given him the grace to reach such knowledge (il pense
déja avoir assez vécu de ce que Dieu luy a fait la grace de parvenir à de telles
connoissances); and willingly and entirely joining himself to God, he loves God so perfectly
that he desires nothing more in the world than that God's will be done. That is the
reason he no longer fears either death, or pains, or disgraces, because he knows that
25
nothing can happen to him save what God shall have decreed; and he so loves this divine
decree, esteems it so just and so necessary, knows he ought so entirely to depend upon
it, that even when he awaits death or some other evil, if per impossibile he could change
that decree, he would not wish to do so. But if he does not refuse evils or afflictions,
because they come to him from divine providence, he refuses still less all the goods or
licit pleasures one can enjoy in this life, because they too issue from that providence; and
accepting them with joy, without having any fear of evils, his love renders him perfectly
In this passage, Descartes advocates abstraction from the personal point of view, from the
perspective of one's ordinary human aspirations for personal survival, happiness, and success,
just as Marcus Aurelius does. In Descartes' understanding, if our love for God were of the right
sort, our identification with the divine perspective would be so complete that even if we could,
we would not refuse our own death or other evils, since they proceed from the decree of God.
In this letter to Chanut, Descartes' picture of how we identify with the divine perspective
does differ in an important respect from the classical Stoic view. One of the most pressing
issues for the Stoic therapeutic theory is to provide reason and motivation for making this
identification. The doctrine of reservation and Marcus Aurelius' injunctions suggest that we
align ourselves with the divine point of view so that we will enjoy equanimity no matter what
happens, even if what happens conflicts with the good as conceived from the personal point of
view. One might doubt whether such a reason is sufficient to motivate many of us; Thomas
Nagel remarks that normally "one is supposed to behold and partake of the glory of God, for
26
example, in a way in which chickens do not share in the glory of coq au vin."xxxix By analogy,
imagine that one's ruler has a utilitarian concern for the aggregate community which is seldom
disappointed, but her scheme causes one to be poverty-stricken so that many others might be
well-off. Trapped in this situation, one might consider assuming the sovereign's concerns while
abandoning one's personal perspective on the good, for the reason that making these
psychological moves would result in one's achieving equanimity. But very few of us are capable
of being motivated by this reason in such circumstances. Consequently, for Descartes' version
of the second strategy to be feasible, we need another proposal for a reason that might motivate
In his letter to Elisabeth of 15 September 1645, Descartes argues that "it is necessary to
prefer always the interests of the whole, of which one is a part, to the interest of one's own
person in particular," although "this is to be done with measure and discretion." He points out
that one is sometimes motivated to behave accordingly; "by considering oneself as part of the
public, one takes pleasure in doing good to everyone," and as a result, one does not even fear to
One is naturally led to act from such a consideration when one knows and loves God as
one ought: for then, abandoning oneself completely to his will, one rids oneself of one's
particular interest (on se despouille de ces propres interests) and has no other passion
save to do what one believes to be agreeable to him; in consequence of which one has
satisfaction of mind and contentments incomparably more valuable than all the small
fleeting joys that depend upon the senses. (to Elisabeth, 15 September, 1645, AT IV
27
294/B152)
Love may be what most commonly provides reason and motivation for other-regarding actions
and attitudes, and perhaps it is therefore plausible for Descartes to advocate love for God as the
reason and motivation for identifying with the divine point of view.xl
But the love required for the second strategy must be a very powerful sort, since it must
be capable of causing a person to resign her personal concerns to the extent that Descartes
envisions. Developing a love of this strength would seem unlikely if one were aware that God,
despite his capacities, had no special regard for one's personal good, and all the more so if one
had no hope of his attitude ever changing. There are people who on occasion develop a self-
sacrificing love for someone who, although he could, has no regard for the lover's personal good.
Sometimes such love arises even toward someone who shows no sign of developing such a
concern. But we would not want to model love for God on such pathological cases. In non-
pathological situations, a love so powerful requires that one believe that the person one loves,
It is surprising that Descartes does not here advocate the Pauline Christian conception by
which God's concern is directed toward the good of each individual who loves God; "for in all
things God works for the good of those that love him" (Romans 8:28), and even towards the good
of each individual "as in Adam all die, so in Christ all will be made alive" (I Corinthians 15:22).xlii
Rather, just as in Marcus Aurelius's understanding, in the picture Descartes advances in his letters
to Elisabeth and Chanut the divine conception of the good need make little concession to the
good as conceived from any individual's personal perspective. We might draw the following
28
contrast. By the Pauline idea, one's personal good is also a concern of God's, and thus, although
one might have to renounce mistaken conceptions of one's personal good in order to assume the
divine point of view, one need not disengage from any personal conception of one's good
whatsoever. According to the Stoic and Cartesian picture, one must abandon one's personal
conception of the good -- one's ordinary human aspirations for survival, happiness, and success
-- and adopt instead the divine vision of the good, which may not have such a personal conception
as a component. The persistent problem for the Stoic and Cartesian view is that we lack a
satisfying model by which human beings, given their psychological character, will have reason
IV
The stark compatibilism of this set of Stoic beliefs presents a challenge for Descartes, as
it did for Chrysippus. If God causes everything, how can we have the power to assent, dissent,
with this issue, he responds with an illustration.xliv Imagine a king who has condemned duelling,
but who knows that there are two gentlemen in his kingdom who would duel if they met. The
king gives each gentleman travelling instructions so that the two will assuredly meet on the road.
Descartes argues that although the king's will (and arrangement of events) results in the
gentlemen duelling, they still freely do so, and consequently they can justly be punished (AT IV
352-3/B174-5). But in this illustration the role of the king is disanalogous with the part God
plays in the Cartesian universe, where he is the cause of every effect, whether it be dependent
29
on human free decisions or not. Thus if the king's role were comparable to God's, the king
would, in addition, cause the gentlemen to be motivated as they are, and if that were so, our
Spinoza believes that a reconciliation between divine determinism and the free and
voluntary power of assent is impossible, and he therefore denies that we have such a power.
Noting that by the will he understands "a faculty by which the mind affirms or denies something
true or something false, and not the desire by which the mind wants a thing or avoids it" (II/129-
130), he claims
IIP48: In the Mind there is no absolute, or free, will (In Mente nulla est absoluta, sive libera
voluntas), but the Mind is determined to will this or that by a cause which is also
The crucial element in the proof of this proposition is divine determinism, that "all things have
been predetermined by God, not from freedom of the will or absolute good pleasure, but from
God's absolute nature, or infinite power" (I Appendix, II/77). Spinoza later affirms, by way of
explanation, that "experience itself, no less clearly than reason, teaches that men believe
themselves to be free because they are conscious of their own actions and ignorant of the causes
Spinoza also rejects another fundamental element of the first strategy. According to the
Stoic and Cartesian view, one's assent, dissent, or suspension of judgment is an act distinct from
entertaining the proposition to which one directs the act of will. This claim is crucial because
the first strategy requires that one's assent, dissent, or suspension of judgment be subsequent
30
to (and thus distinct from) entertaining the proposition that expresses the possibility of a passion.
Spinoza argues, however, that in general acts of will are not distinct from acts of entertaining
propositions; "The will and the intellect are one and the same," and this is because "the will and
the intellect are nothing apart from the singular volitions and ideas themselves" and "the singular
volitions and ideas are one and the same" (IIP49C, II/131). In Spinoza's understanding, the will
and the intellect are identical because every token idea is identical to a token volition, and every
token volition is identical to a token idea. It turns out that for him the assent that results in a
passion would not be distinct from one's entertaining the proposition to which the assent is
granted.
Spinoza's demonstration of the thesis that there is no distinction between token volitions
and token ideas assumes the following principle: A and B are token-identical just in case A cannot
be conceived without B, and B cannot be conceived without A (IIP49d). xlv His illustration
features the token idea that the sum of the measures of the internal angles of a triangle is 180°
(m=180°, for short), and token the affirmation that m=180°. First, Spinoza plausibly claims that
the token affirmation that m=180° cannot be conceived without the token idea that m=180°.
But then, more controversially, he argues that the token idea that m=180° cannot be conceived
without the token affirmation that m=180°. One might object to this view on the grounds that
in general one can entertain an idea without affirming it. Indeed, Spinoza's own
counterexample expresses this objection: "someone who feigns a winged horse does not on that
account grant that there is a winged horse; i.e., he is not on that account deceived unless he at
the same time grants that there is a winged horse" (IIP49s, II/132-3).
31
But Spinoza responds by arguing that the absence of affirmation in such cases results
either from background ideas or from the perception that one's idea is inadequate (i.e. lacks
some intrinsic qualities of a true idea, such as internal consistency and not from an idea-
independent act of will (IID4, II/134)). xlvi When one is in possession of one's faculties and
imagines a winged horse, one also has background ideas that undermine the affirmation-aspect
of the idea of the winged horse. Nevertheless, there is no voluntary act of dissent or suspension
of judgment, occasioned by these background ideas, and distinct from any idea, that accounts
for the absence of affirmation. On the contrary, it is explained solely by the causal influence of
Spinoza's response is interesting, but even if his theory is plausible for belief, this
plausibility does not clearly extend to action and passion. He believes it does, for he concludes
his discussion of the triangle example by remarking: "...what we have said concerning this volition
(since we have selected it at random), must also be said concerning any volition, viz. that it is
nothing apart from the idea" (IIP49d, II/130). Spinoza believes that to will an action is to
perceive it in a certain way, perhaps as one's best available option for action. By this
conception, my deciding to eat a piece of pie would not be distinct from my entertaining the
proposition that eating it is my best available course of action. Spinoza illustrates his view by
claiming that someone "who perceives nothing but thirst and hunger, and such food and drink as
are equally distant from him... will perish of hunger and thirst." Presumably Spinoza believes
this because the person does not perceive any one course of action as better than every other
(II/135). Since there is no act of will distinct from something's being perceived in a certain way,
32
the person will not act in one way rather than the other.
If Spinoza has shown that we have no free will, and that assenting to a proposition is not
distinct from entertaining it, then he has undermined the foundation for the first therapeutic
strategy as the Stoics conceived it. And this is precisely what he believes he has done. At the
outset of Part V of the Ethics, Spinoza reproaches the Stoics for thinking that the affects "depend
entirely on our will, and that we can command them absolutely" (II/277), and he subsequently
But if the first Stoic strategy has been undermined, must we abandon any hope of
controlling our passions? Spinoza thinks not. While the will may not be the source of such
Therefore, because the power of the Mind is defined only by the understanding (sola
knowledge alone (sola Mentis cognitione determinabimus) the remedies for the affects.
(II/280)
Since he maintains that we cannot keep passions from arising by exercise of the will, Spinoza
looks instead to the intellect for a therapeutic technique. xlvii And as I shall now argue, his
scheme can be viewed as an attempt to develop wholly intellectual analogues for the two main
Stoic strategies.
The Stoics maintain that the power of assent gives us absolute control over whether or
33
not we will have pathê. Spinoza proposes that the intellect provides us with a similar kind of
absolute control:
An affect which is a passion ceases to be a passion as soon as we form a clear and distinct
idea of it. (Affectus, qui passio est, desinit esse passio, simulatque ejus claram, &
There is no affection of the Body of which we cannot form a clear and distinct concept.
(Nulla est Corporis affectio, cujus aliquem clarum, distinctum non possumus formare
Together, VP3 and VP4 entail that one has the ability to form a clear and distinct idea of any of
one's passions, thereby eliminating what makes them passions. xlviii And hence, Spinoza is
arguing that not our will, but rather our intellect has the power to keep us entirely free from
passions.
To understand the claim of VP3, we must consult Spinoza's definitions of terms. Let us
first consider 'clear and distinct idea' and 'adequate idea.' At IP8s2 Spinoza characterizes a clear
and distinct idea as a true idea (II/50), and in IA6 he states that "a true idea must agree with its
object" (II/47). Subsequently, he defines an adequate idea as "an idea which, insofar as it is
considered in itself, without relation to its object, has all the properties, or intrinsic
denominations, of a true idea" (IID4, II/85). In his explication of this definition, Spinoza remarks:
"I say intrinsic to exclude what is extrinsic, viz. the agreement of the idea with its object." One
might conclude that in his picture an idea is clear and distinct just in case it has the extrinsic
denomination of a true idea, i.e. it agrees with its object, and an idea is adequate just in case it
34
has the intrinsic denominations of a true idea, such as internal consistency. But for all that,
perhaps we need to keep in mind only that each of these notions is somehow closely tied to
veridicality. For as Bennett argues, Spinoza often conflates them, and in fact he appears to do
In the summary of the definitions of Part III Spinoza distinguishes actions from passions
...if we can be the adequate cause of any of these affections, I understand by the Affect
an action (tum per Affectum actionem intelligo); otherwise a passion (alias passionem).
(II/139)
A cause is adequate "whose effect can be clearly and distinctly perceived through it" (IIID1,
II/139). By contrast, a cause is partial or inadequate "if its effect cannot be understood through
it alone" (IIID1; II/139). Thus an affect is an action of A just in case it can be clearly and distinctly
understood (or perceived) through A alone. Correlatively, an affect is a passion of A just in case
it cannot be clearly and distinctly understood through A alone (cf. IIID2, II/139). Spinoza
maintains that we have passions in virtue of being causally affected by other natural things
(IVP2).l Accordingly, it would seem that a passion can be clearly and distinctly understood only
Given these characterizations, we can now exhibit a difficulty for the claim that one has
the ability to form a clear and distinct idea of any of one's passions, and thereby to eliminate
whatever makes it a passion. What Spinoza has in mind is that if I clearly and distinctly
understand my passion, it will be transformed into an action. The definitions of Part III entail
35
that for my present passion to become an action, I would have to become the adequate cause of
a state of which I am not now the adequate cause. And for this to occur, I would have to clearly
and distinctly understand my passion through my nature alone. But this would seem impossible
given Spinoza's view that we have passions because we are affected by other things in nature.
My clear and distinct understanding would reveal rather than eliminate the external causes of
my passion, and hence could not make it any less true that I am not the adequate cause of it.
As Bennett suggests, the distinction between passion and action turns on causal history, and
coming to understand the causal history of a passion will not change that causal history.li
The justification Spinoza cites for the crucial step in the proof of VP3 is
IIIP3: The actions of a Mind arise from adequate ideas alone; the passions depend on
a claim which figures prominently throughout Part V. This proposition, by Spinoza's account,
IIIP1: Our Mind does certain things [acts] and undergoes other things, viz. insofar as it has
adequate ideas, it necessarily does certain things, and insofar as it has inadequate ideas,
In his proof for this last proposition Spinoza assumes that "from any given idea some effect must
(1) but if God, insofar as he is affected by an idea that is adequate in someone's Mind, is
the cause of an effect, that same Mind is the effect's adequate cause (by IIP11C)
and
36
if something necessarily follows from an idea that is adequate in God, not insofar as he
has in himself the Mind of one man only, but insofar as he has in himself the Minds of
other things together with the Mind of that man, that man's Mind (by the same IIP11C) is
Here we encounter Spinoza's fundamental error. In the last analysis, this demonstration is the
one that is supposed to underwrite the claim that when one forms a clear and distinct idea of
one's passion, it ceases to be a passion. More precisely, if Spinoza's attempt to establish VP3
(2) A person cannot have an adequate (= clear and distinct) idea of a passion,
that is, a person cannot form a clear and distinct idea of a passion and it remain a passion. But
(1) provides no support for (2). Even if a Mind is the adequate cause of an effect whenever God
is the cause of that effect insofar as he is affected by an adequate idea in that Mind, it does not
follow that a Mind is the adequate cause of an effect whenever it simply has an adequate idea of
that effect. For although it may be impossible for an effect not to be wholly caused by an
adequate idea in a Mind if God is the cause of that effect insofar as he is affected by that adequate
idea, it is still possible for an effect not to be wholly (or even partially) caused by an adequate
idea in a Mind if God is not the cause of that effect insofar as he is affected by that adequate idea
in that Mind. It might be, for example, that an effect of which a Mind has an adequate idea is
partially caused by the Mind and partially caused by natural things external to that Mind. Given
Spinoza's view that passions are partially externally caused, this is precisely the situation one
would expect to obtain when a Mind forms a clear and distinct idea of a passion. Hence,
37
Spinoza's reasoning fails to secure VP3.lii
Although taken together VP3 and 4 suggest that we can actually form clear and distinct
ideas of any of our passions, and thereby eliminate whatever makes them passions, Spinoza's
We must, therefore, take special care to know each affect clearly and distinctly (as far as
this is possible), so that in this way the Mind may be determined from an affect to thinking
those things which it perceives clearly and distinctly, and with which it is fully satisfied, so
that the affect itself may be separated from the thought of an external cause and joined
Spinoza now seems to admit that there may be a limit to understanding one's affects clearly and
distinctly. Furthermore, he appears to be suggesting that by forming clear and distinct ideas
we separate affects from their external causes, rather than eliminating these external causes.liii
Perhaps Spinoza's view is that if one acquires clear and distinct ideas of one's passions, one's
attention will be directed towards one's own causal role in the production of these passions, and
this, in turn, will result in one's ignoring their external causes. But why would such a procedure
be therapeutic?
Stuart Hampshire has suggested that Spinoza's strategy foreshadows Freudian theory.liv
But although Spinoza and Freud do share the view that acquiring knowledge of one's affects is
that here Spinoza is attempting to secure a benefit of the first Stoic strategy despite having
challenged its theoretical foundations. An important feature of this first strategy is that it
38
encourages us to hold ourselves causally responsible for our pathê despite their external
triggering causes. Given Stoic psychology, such a stance can be reasonable. I can reasonably
consider myself causally responsible for my pathê, for no matter what the external
circumstances, I can keep myself from having pathê by dissenting or suspending judgment upon
entertaining their presentations. But taking this stance can have a benefit that we have not yet
encountered. The following passage from Epictetus suggests what this benefit might be:
It is not the things themselves that disturb humans, but their judgements (dogmata)
about these things. For example, death is nothing dreadful, or else Socrates too would
have thought so, but the judgement that death is dreadful, this is the dreadful thing.
When, therefore, we are hindered, or disturbed, or grieved, let us never blame anyone
but ourselves, that is, our own judgments. It is the part of an uneducated person to blame
others where he himself fares ill; to blame himself is the part of one whose education has
begun; to blame neither another nor his own self is the part of one whose education is
Among the more harmful passions are those that involve absorption in negative attitudes
towards others. Anger and fear might be the principal examples. Thinking of oneself as
causally responsible for one's anger, however, could undermine the inclination to hold an
external agent responsible for it, and hence might decrease one's tendency to be absorbed in
negative attitudes towards that agent. Perhaps this type of benefit can be achieved by
acquiring clear and distinct ideas of one's passions, if, as Spinoza believes, this would occasion
one's attention to be directed towards one's own part in the production of one's passions, which
39
would in turn cause one to disregard their external causes. Such a strategy might diminish one's
preoccupation with the other's causal role, and thereby mitigate the debilitating power of the
VI
In Part V of the Ethics Spinoza also advances a view that has the outline of the second
Stoic strategy. He claims that "the greatest satisfaction of Mind there can be results from
having the third kind of knowledge" (VP27), knowledge that "proceeds from an adequate idea of
certain attributes of God to the adequate knowledge of the essence of things (VP25). To have
the third kind of knowledge is to understanding things as following from the necessity of the
divine nature, which is to conceive them sub specie aeternitatis, from the point of view of eternity
(VP29s). But "the more the Mind understands things by the second and third kind of
knowledge, the less it is acted on by affects which are evil, and the less it fears death" (VP38; the
second kind of knowledge is "from the fact that we have common notions and adequate ideas of
the properties of things" (IIP40s2). And thus, identifying with the divine point of view (and also
acquiring other types of knowledge) provides a form of therapy for the passions.
But just as rejecting the Stoics' theory of the will precludes Spinoza from endorsing their
version of the first strategy, so disavowing their conception of God prevents him from advocating
a genuinely Stoic second strategy. The crucial feature of Stoic theology he rejects is the view
that God acts for the sake of ends and concerns (I Appendix, II/77-83). Spinoza argues that if
God acted for the sake of an end, he would not be perfect, for he would then want something he
40
lacked (II/80). Consequently, Spinoza would also claim that since divine providence involves
God's acting for the well-being of the universe (as the Stoics maintain), or for the benefit of
human beings, there is no divine providence. Thus, identifying with the divine perspective
cannot amount to evaluating events that occur by the standard of God's purposes, because he
has none. And furthermore, we cannot be motivated to identify with God's point of view by
strategy, parallel to what he did for the first. Let us briefly summarize Spinoza's argument. As
we have seen, Spinoza affirms that "the greatest satisfaction of Mind there can be arises from
this third kind of knowledge" (VP27, II/297). This is because understanding things by the third
kind of knowledge is the greatest virtue of the Mind, and therefore "he who knows things by this
kind of knowledge passes to the greatest human perfection." Spinoza then claims that by his
definition of joy -- "a man's passage from a lesser to a greater perfection" (III Definitions of the
Affects II, II/190) -- it follows that a person who understands things by the third kind of knowledge
will be affected by the greatest joy, and that given that this joy is accompanied by the idea of
oneself and one's virtue, this person will experience the greatest satisfaction of Mind (III Def.
Aff.XXV). And because one can conceive of oneself through God's essence, i.e. sub specie
aeternitatis (VP30), one can understand that the joy and satisfaction that issue from having the
third kind of knowledge are caused by God (VP32). Since love is "a joy, accompanied by the
idea of an external cause" (III Def. Aff. VI), one will therefore love God. For the reason that this
affect is not love of God "insofar as we imagine him to be present, but insofar as we understand
41
him to be eternal," Spinoza calls it intellectual love of God (amor intellectus Dei) (VP32).
Further, Spinoza argues that there is something that pertains to the essence of the human
Mind which is eternal, in the sense that no temporal predicates correctly apply to it ("eternity
can neither be defined by time nor have any relation to time" (VP23s)). For there is an idea
which expresses the essence of the human body sub specie aeternitatis, "with a certain eternal
necessity" through the essence of God, and because the object of the idea constituting the
human Mind is the human body (IIP13), it follows that this idea is something eternal which
pertains to the essence of Mind (VP23d). Spinoza then affirms that the more the Mind knows
things by the second and third kind of knowledge, the more of it that remains and is eternal
(VP38d,s). But to the extent that our Mind is eternal it cannot be touched by affects contrary
to our nature (VP38d). Hence, the more of the Mind that is eternal, the less it can be harmed
by affects, like harmful passions, whose causal genesis involves things external to us.
picture is less than successful.lvi For example, in addition to the problem with the argument for
the eternity of some aspect of the human mind, one might fault his derivation of love for God
from the third kind of knowledge. Even if one acquires joy from the third kind of knowledge
(and this is not a foregone conclusion -- one can imagine acquiring such knowledge as a result of
classroom coercion and therefore failing to obtain joy), Spinoza's God may seem too impersonal
causally determined the universe, coming to know how this machine produced things would not
lead us to love this machine, even if we deeply enjoyed acquiring this knowledge and we realized
42
that our learning itself was caused by the machine.
Still, Spinoza has a certain vision of our identification with God which can be expressed
without his rigid formalism. Spinoza, just as the Stoics, is a pantheist. In his view, God or
Nature (Deus sive Natura) is the only substance, and we are modes of God. But although God
is eternal, our existence seems thoroughly temporally qualified. Our temporality allows us to
be vulnerable to things that are contrary to our nature, and therefore we can be affected by
debilitating passions. We can also die. Nevertheless, there may be a respect in which we are
eternal as God is, and if so, then in this respect we are exempt from the harmful passions and
from death. Everything that exists follows from the divine essence. Since by reason we can
come to know how things follow from the divine essence, reason allows us to identify, in our
metaphorical sense, with the divine point of view. The intellectual love occasioned by this
employment of reason can reinforce our identification with the divine perspective. But to the
extent that we so align ourselves with God, we are actually, non-metaphorically, identical with
The Mind's intellectual Love of God is the very Love by which God loves himself, not
insofar as he is infinite, but insofar as he can be explained by the human Mind's essence,
considered sub specie aeternitatis; i.e. the Mind's intellectual Love of God is part of the
Spinoza seems here to advocate an intellectualized form of the Neo-Platonic vision of mystical
union with The One. And in his view, to the extent that we are fused with the divine essence,
we are eternal, and because it makes no sense for something to be contrary to the nature of an
43
eternal entity (VP37, VP38d), to the degree we are eternal we are immune from the harmful
VII
Each of the two strategies for psychotherapy, in their original Stoic formulations, has a
radical aspect. The first embraces an extreme view about the range of our voluntary rational
control, while the second prescribes an alignment with the divine perspective that is
exceptionally difficult to attain. Descartes and Spinoza manage these radical features of the
Stoic picture in different ways. While Descartes endorses them and redevelops the surrounding
theory, Spinoza rejects them to produce a new conception that nevertheless preserves some of
the main therapeutic intuitions of the Stoic view. As we have now seen, both of these
philosophers adhere to a Stoic model despite serious difficulties for their resulting theories, and
this attests to the tenacity of the Stoic influence on the seventeenth-century European
imagination.
The Stoic view about the passions has an effect on our imagination as well, although its
force has diminished considerably since the time of Descartes and Spinoza. The type of control
the Stoics advocated, if employed to relieve the relatively minor irritations that plague us, would
undoubtedly improve our lives. But the Stoics advocated a much more ambitious conception:
With everything that entertains you, is useful, or of which you are fond, remember to say
to yourself, beginning with the very least things, "What is its nature?" If you are fond of
a jug, say, "I am fond of a jug"; for when it is broken you will not be disturbed. If you
44
kiss your own child or wife, say to yourself that you are kissing a human being; for when
When the Stoic recommendations are applied to grief upon the death of one's child, or to anger
that results from serious abuse or torture, the likelihood of self-deception and subsequent failure
to deal with one's emotions is considerable. This excessive character of Stoic psychotherapy is
at times reflected in the views of Descartes and Spinoza. If one is tempted by their advice, one
45
NOTES
The Stoics:
Encheiridion: Epictetus, in The Discourses as Reported by Arrian, The Manual, and the Fragments, with a
translation by W. A. Oldfather, in two volumes, Loeb Classical Library, (London: New York: Putnam and
Sons, 1928).
LP: Diogenes Laertius, Lives of Eminent Philosophers, with an English translation by R. D. Hicks, in two
volumes, Loeb Classical Library, (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1970).
LS: The Hellenistic Philosophers, A. A. Long and D. N. Sedley, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1987). Translations of the principal sources with philosophical commentary, in two volumes. Volume
Meditations: Marcus Aurelius; citations are from G. M. A. Grube's translation, (Indianapolis: Hackett,
1985). The original text can be found in The communings with himself of Marcus Aurelius Antonius,
Emperor of Rome, with an English translation by C. R. Haines, Loeb Classical Library, (Cambridge, Mass.:
Descartes' Works:
AT: Oeuvres de Descartes, edited by Ch. Adam and P. Tannery (revised edition, Paris: Vrin/C.N.R.S., 1964-
76. Unless otherwise indicated, translations of Descartes' works are from The Philosophical Writings of
Descartes, translated by John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff, and Dugald Murdoch, 3 volumes,
46
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985).
B: Descartes: His Moral Philosophy and Psychology, translated, with an introduction and conceptual index
V: The Passions of the Soul, translated and annotated by Stephen Voss, (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1989).
Spinoza's Works:
Translations are from The Collected Works of Spinoza, volume 1, edited and translated by E. M. Curley,
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1985). References to passages are given by volume and page
numbers provided in the margins of Curley's edition, taken from Spinoza Opera, edited by Carl Gebhardt,
4 volumes (Heidelberg: Carl Winter, 1925). For citations from Spinoza's Ethics, VP4s, for example, refers
to Part V, Proposition 4, Scholium; 'A' indicates an axiom, 'D' a definition, 'd' a demonstration, 'c' a
corollary.
ii. Stoic influences on Descartes' moral theory did not go unnoticed by his contemporaries. In Adrien
Baillet's La Vie de Monsieur Descartes (Paris: Chez Daniel Horthemels, 1691) we find the claim that
"D'autres Sçavans ont crû que nôtre Philosophe avoit voulu faire revivre la Morale des Stoiciens dans la
sienne" (volume 2, p. 534). The marginal reference is to Leibniz, it would appear to a letter to Molanus
from around 1679, in which he argues that Descartes often borrowed ideas from other philosophers. For
Descartes wants us to follow reason, or else to follow the nature of things, as the Stoics said,
something with which everybody will agree. He adds that we should not trouble ourselves with
things that are not in our power. That is precisely the Stoic doctrine; it places the greatness and
47
freedom of their much-praised wise men in his strength of mind to do without the things that do
not pertain to us, and endure things when they come in spite of ourselves. (From G.W. Leibniz,
Philosophical Essays, translated by Roger Ariew and Daniel Garber, (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1989),
pp. 240-5, at p. 241; in Gerhard, G. W. Leibniz, Die Philosophischen Schriften, (Hildesheim: Georg
Olms, 1965), v. IV, pp. 297-303, at p. 298; see also the remainder of the letter)
A fine account of the effect of Stoicism on French moral theory in the late sixteenth and the first half of
the seventeenth centuries can be found in Anthony Levi's French Moralists, (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 1964). For further descriptions of the Stoic influence in this period, see, for example, Gerhard
Oestreich, Neostoicism and the Early Modern State, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982), and
Mark Morford, Stoics and Neostoics: Rubens and the Circle of Lipsius, (Princeton: Princeton University
Press, 1991).
iii. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1985, see pp. 42-101 for the account of the theory of action. The founder
of Stoicism was Zeno of Citium (336-265 B.C.), Cleanthes (331-232 B.C.) was the second head of the Stoic
school, Chrysippus (279-206 B.C.) the third. None of the works of these philosophers of the Old Stoa
survives in complete form, but it is known that Chrysippus wrote voluminously; Diogenes Laertius reports
that there are more than 705 items in the list of his writings (LP 7.180). The main philosophers of the
Middle Stoa were Panaetius (185-109 B.C.) and Posidonius (135-50 B.C.). The most prominent Stoics of
the Roman period were Seneca (5-65), Epictetus (50-130), and Marcus Aurelius (121-180).
v. Contrary to Inwood's suggestion, it is not clear that hormê can always be the setting of oneself to do
48
something, since, as he himself point out, pathê like distress and pleasure are also hormê. Perhaps,
then, hormê is essentially a forceful motion of pneuma caused by assent to a phantasia. Such a forceful
motion can have different psychological manifestations, and the setting of oneself to do something and
vi. Inwood, pp. 46-8, 60-6; for a discussion of Inwood's view, see Gisela Striker's critical notice of Ethics
and Human Action in Early Stoicism in the Canadian Journal of Philosophy 19 (March 1989), pp. 91-100,
at pp. 96-7.
viii. Discussed by Long and Sedley, LS I 250.
ix. From Diogenes Laertius, LP 7.46 (SVF 2.53), translation from LS I 242, cf. LS I 236-259.
[Fate]... frequently produces impressions (phantasiai), in matters of very great importance, which
are at variance with one another and pull the mind in opposite directions. On these occasions
the Stoics say that those who assent to one of them and do not suspend judgment are guilty of
error; that they are precipitate if they yield to unclear impressions, deceived if they yield to false
ones, and opining if they yield to ones which are incognitive quite generally. (SVF 2.993/LS I 255)
Some of the main elements of the Stoic theory of judgment are also discussed by Cicero in his Academica:
Here first of all [Zeno] made some new pronouncements about sensation itself, which he held to
49
be a combination of a sort of impact offered from outside (which he called phantasia and we may
call a presentation (visum) ...) well, to these presentations received by the senses he joins the
act of mental assent which he makes out to reside within us and to be a voluntary act. He held
that not all presentations are trustworthy but only those that have a 'manifestation,' peculiar to
themselves, of the objects presented; and a trustworthy presentation, being perceived as such by
its own intrinsic nature, he termed 'graspable' -- will you endure these coinages?" "Indeed we
will," said Atticus, "for how else could you express 'catalêpton'? (Academica I, xi, 40-1; translated
by H. Rackham, in Cicero, De Natura Deorum and Academica, Loeb Classical Library, (London:
xii. "They [the Stoics] say that passion is impulse which is excessive and disobedient to the dictates of
reason..." (Stobaeus 2.88,8/SVF 3.378/LS I 410; cf. Galen SVF 3.462/LS I 413; SVF 3.466/LS I 416; Seneca,
On anger 2.3.1-2.4/LS I 419.) My summary of the Stoic theory of the passions is adapted largely from
xiii. See, for example, Cicero Academica (I, x, 38-9), Tusculan Disputations (Book IV, esp. iv-x), and
xv. Hecato was a Stoic from the middle period, a pupil of Panaetius of Rhodes and an associate of
50
Posidonius.
xvi. Inwood, p. 146; cf. from Andronicus, SVF 3.391/LS I 411/II 405. Each of these passions has a number
of subspecies; for example, according to Diogenes Laertius, under craving the Stoics classified "want,
xvii. LP 7.116. See also Cicero, Tusculan Disputations IV, vi, 12-14.
xviii. For the Stoics, for something to be in harmony with nature is for it to be in accordance with the will
xx. Inwood, pp. 155-6, cf. Galen, SVF 4.2.10-18, 4.5.21-5 translated in LS I 413-4.)
xxi. Galen's interpretation of the analogy of running is "when someone has the impulse he is not obedient
xxii. Inwood, p. 177, preserved by Gellius, in Noctus Atticae (P.K. Marshall, OCT, 1968) 19.1.14-20 = fr.
9./cf. LS I 419.
xxiii. From Gellius, SVF 2.1000/LS I 336, cited by Josiah B. Gould, in The Philosophy of Chrysippus (Leiden,
51
xxiv. From Aetius, SVF 2.1027/LS I 274-5; cf. LS I 274-277.
xxvi. SVF 2.1152/LS I 329, cited by Gould, p. 156; cf. SVF 2.1163, 2.1169-70/LS I 328-9.
xxvii. See Inwood, pp. 119-126; for some criticisms of Inwood's account, see Striker's critical notice of
Inwood's Ethics and Human Action in Early Stoicism, pp. 98-9, (cf. my note 6).
xxviii. This account, and the quotations from On Tranquility, are from Inwood, pp. 119-122.
xxix. Marcus Aurelius speculates as to why one's death might benefit the Whole:
If souls live on, how has the air of heaven made room for them through eternity? How has the
earth made room for such a long time for the bodies of those who are buried in it? Just as on
earth, after these bodies have persisted for a while, their change and decomposition makes room
for other bodies, so with the souls which have migrated into the upper air. After they have
remained there for a certain time, they change and are dissolved and turned into fire as they are
absorbed into creative Reason, and in this way make room for additional souls who come to share
xxx. SVF 2.998, cited by Gould, pp. 150-1; cf. Cicero, On fate, esp. 28-30, LS I 339-40.
xxxi. The Stoic theory of judgment, action, and passion was available to Descartes through numerous
writings, and was very much in the air during his education at La Flèche. An encyclopedic account of the
52
Stoical influence on French moral philosophy of this period can be found in Anthony Levi, French Moralists,
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1964). Some of the most important of sources of Stoic views for
Descartes' contemporaries are Cicero's Academica (I, xi, 40-1) for the theory of judgment, his On Fate
(xviii, 41-2) for theory of action, and the Academica (I, x, 38-9) and the Tusculan Disputations (Book IV,
esp. iv-x) for the theory of the passions. (In addition to the theories of judgment and the passions that
Descartes comes to adopt, we find in Cicero's Academica an account of the skeptical argument from the
unreliability of the senses (II, xxv, 75-80), a discussion of the dream argument (II, xxvii, 88), mention that
Chrysippus "carefully sought out all the facts that told against the senses and their clarity and against the
whole of common experience and against reason" before answering himself (II, xxvii, 87), and these
remarks about the size of the sun: "What can be bigger than the sun, which the mathematicians declare
to be nineteen times the size of the earth? How tiny it looks to us! to me it seems about a foot in
diameter" (II xxvi, 82; translation of Academica passages are by H. Rackham, in Cicero, De Natura Deorum,
Academica (London: Wiliam Heinemann, 1933).) Furthermore, the Stoic theory of the passions had
undergone a significant revival beginning in the last half of the sixteenth century. Two of the then-
prominent works in this area that display thorough Stoical influence are Justus Lipsius' Manuductio (1604)
and Saint Francis de Sales Traité de l'Amour de Dieu (1616). For comments on which works Descartes is
likely to have read see Levi, p. 271, n.3, and Geneviève Rodis-Lewis's introduction to Stephen Voss'
translation of The Passions of the Soul (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1989) pp. xvi-xvii, n.6.
In the Principles of Philosophy Descartes presents of rudimentary theory of the passions. His
view in this work reflects a Stoic conception, despite his caricature of one Stoic thesis:
In the same way, when we hear good news, it is first of all the mind which makes a judgement
about it and rejoices with that intellectual joy which occurs without any bodily disturbance and
which, for that reason, the Stoics allowed that the man of wisdom could experience <although
53
they required him to be free of all passion>. But later on, when the good news is pictured in the
imagination, the spirits flow from the brain to the muscles around the heart and move the tiny
nerves there, thereby causing a movement in the brain which produces a feeling of animal joy.
It was common then, as it is now, to claim that for the Stoics the sophos is without passion in a more
familiar sense of 'passion,' (not in the technical sense of the Stoic's pathos) despite clear
counterindications, for example, in Cicero's Tusculan Disputations IV, vi-vii, and in Diogenes Laertius' Lives
xxxiv. See Paul Hoffman's discussion of this issue in "Three Dualist Theories of the Passions, Philosophical
But it seems to me that what those who are accustomed to reflect on their actions can always do
when they feel themselves to be seized with fear, is to try to turn their thoughts away from the
consideration of danger by representing to themselves the reasons which prove that there is
much more certainty and honour and resistance than in flight. And on the other hand, when
54
they feel that the desire of vengeance and anger incites them to run thoughtlessly towards those
who attack them, they will recollect that it is imprudence to lose their lives when they can without
dishonour save themselves, and that, if the match is very unequal, it is better to beat an
honourable retreat or to ask quarter, than to expose oneself doggedly to certain death. (III 211/AT
XI 487-8)
xxxvii. In addition, Descartes' claim in II 144 of the Passions is very similar to Epictetus' Encheiridion 1:
"And it seems to me that the error most commonly committed in connection with Desires is to fail to
distinguish sufficiently the things that depend entirely on us from those that do not depend on us." (AT XI
xxxviii. The end of the Third Meditation (AT VII 52) reflects some of the ideas in the letter to Chanut, as
does a passage from II 146 of The Passions of The Soul (AT XI 439).
xxxix. Thomas Nagel, "The Absurd," in Mortal Questions, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979),
p. 16.
xl. In the letter to Chanut of 1 February, 1647, Descartes takes care to indicate that the notion of love he
has in mind is significantly independent of the senses. "To represent the truths that excite this love in her,
the soul must detach herself very much from dealings with the senses..." (AT IV 609/B207). But he also
maintains that the appropriate type of love involves having a passion. From the independence of this
it seems to follow [that the soul] cannot communicate it to the imaginative faculty to make a
55
passion of it. But nonetheless I have no doubt that she does communicate it. For although we
cannot imagine anything in God, who is the object of our love, we can imagine our love itself,
which consists in the fact that we wish to unite ourselves to a certain object, that is to say, as
regards God, to consider ourselves as a very small part of the entire immensity he has created;
because, according as the objects are diverse, one can unite oneself with them or join them to
oneself in different ways (on se peut unir avec eux, ou les joindre à foy en diverses facons); and
the single idea of that union suffices to excite warmth around the heart and to cause a very strong
In this way identification with the divine perspective can be assisted by our affective nature.
xli. For discussions of self-disregarding love of God, see Robert M. Adams, "Pure Love," The Journal of
Religious Ethics 8 (Spring 1980), pp. 83-99; reprinted in his The Virtue of Faith, (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 1987), pp. 174-192, and William E. Mann, "Hope," in Reasoned Faith, edited by Eleanor Stump,
xlii. cf. Romans 5:18, Romans 11:32, Colossians 1:20; but see also II Thessalonians 1:8-9. Descartes does
affirm the immortality of the soul (e.g. Second Replies, AT VII 153-4) but it seems to play no role in his of
views on identification with the divine perspective, at least as this issue is discussed in the letters to
xliii. See also the criticisms of Descartes' conception of God in Leibniz's letter to Molanus of ca. 1679 (Ariew
56
xliv. Elisabeth argues that
It necessarily follows from his sovereign perfection that he could be the cause of these effects,
which is to say, he would be capable of not having given free decision to men; but since we feel
we have it, it seems to me contradictory to common sense to believe that free deciding is
dependent upon God in its operations as it is in its being. (to Descartes, 28 October, 1645, AT IV
322-3)
...to the essence of any thing belongs that which, being given, is necessarily posited and which,
being taken away, the thing is necessarily taken away; or that without which the thing can neither
be nor be conceived, and which can neither be nor be conceived without the thing. (II/85)
xlvi. ...for if the Mind perceived nothing else except the winged horse, it would regard it as present to
itself, and would not have any cause of doubting its existence, or any faculty of dissenting, unless
either the imagination of the winged horse were joined to an idea which excluded the idea of he
same horse, or the Mind perceived that its idea of the winged horse was inadequate. (IID4, II/134)
xlvii. Spinoza's view on when affects are bad reflects the Stoic conception: "An affect is only evil, or
harmful, insofar as it prevents the Mind from being able to think" (VP9d, II 286/C I 601).
xlviii. Alan Donagan, however, argues that this conclusion fails to follow because VP4 is not about affects
as kinds but about affects as individuals. His reason is that the proof of VP4 depends on the premise
that those things common to all can only be conceived adequately. Donagan reads VP3,4 as claiming
57
that "while the mind has little or no power to form an adequate idea of the individual affect that is a
passion, it has unlimited power to form adequate ideas of the various kinds of affect, and that gives it
limited power over individual affects." (Spinoza, (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1988), p. 186.
xlix. See Bennett, p. 335, cf. pp. 175-184; see also my note 52.
l. In addition, since
it is impossible that a man should not be a part of Nature, and that he should be able to undergo
no changes except those which can be understood through his own nature alone, and of which
li. See Bennett, pp. 333-337, and also R. J. Delahunty, Spinoza, (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1985),
pp. 215-220.
lii. On Bennett's alternative analysis, Spinoza typically ignores Part II's definitions of 'adequate idea' and
'inadequate idea' in favor of causal characterizations of these notions. He claims to find in IIP24d the
view that an idea of mine is inadequate if it is caused from outside my mind, and he argues that
correlatively, an idea of mine is adequate when it is caused from within my mind (pp. 177-8). One
problem with this interpretation is that it would render the complex demonstration of the crucial IIIP1
unnecessary. As Bennett makes clear, it is also true that these causal characterizations would make
Spinoza's attempt to establish VP3 quite obviously unsuccessful. Since my passions are by definition
partially caused from outside me, and if my forming a clear and distinct idea of A entails that A is caused
58
from within me, it would seem to follow that I cannot form clear and distinct ideas of my passions (pp.
If we separate emotions, or affects, form the thought of an external cause, and join them to other
thoughts, then Love, or Hate, toward the external cause is destroyed, as are the vacillations of
liv. Stuart Hampshire, Spinoza, (London: Faber and Faber, 1961; first published by Penguin, London, in
1951), p. 106,
lv. Nevertheless, a risk accompanies this strategy, for as a result, one might come pathologically to regard
oneself as blameworthy for one's anger and envy. Perhaps, then, this strategy corroborates Epictetus'
observation that "to blame himself is the part of one whose education has begun." The strategy of divine
determinism, however, may illustrate his claim that "to blame neither another nor his own self is the part
of one whose education is complete." Spinoza believes that reflection on the nature of God will lead
one to believe that no one is ever to blame, because everything that happens follows from the divine
essence.
lvi. See, for example, Bennett, pp. 357-375, Delahunty, pp. 279-305, but also Donagan, pp. 190-207.
lvii. This paper is largely a result of a seminar I taught during the summer of 1989 on Hellenistic influences
in early modern European philosophy. I wish to thank the participants of this seminar, as well as Marilyn
59
Adams, Robert Adams, David Christensen, Jeremy Hyman, Hilary Kornblith, Don Loeb, and J. D. Pereboom,
60