0% found this document useful (0 votes)
29 views2 pages

Moore, George E., Principia Ethica (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1903)

The document summarizes George Moore's open question argument against attempts to define 'good' through synonymy with other concepts like pleasure. It argues that for any proposed definition of good, it is always an open and meaningful question to ask if something with that property is itself good, showing the property and good must be distinct concepts.

Uploaded by

sem_dionatas
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
Download as pdf or txt
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
29 views2 pages

Moore, George E., Principia Ethica (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1903)

The document summarizes George Moore's open question argument against attempts to define 'good' through synonymy with other concepts like pleasure. It argues that for any proposed definition of good, it is always an open and meaningful question to ask if something with that property is itself good, showing the property and good must be distinct concepts.

Uploaded by

sem_dionatas
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1/ 2

Moore, George E.

, Principia Ethica (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,


1903)

§13 In fact, if it is not the case that good denotes something simple and indefinable,
only two alternatives are possible: either it is a complex, a given whole, about the
correct analysis of which there could be disagreement; or else it means nothing at all,
and there is no such subject as Ethics. In general, however, ethical philosophers have
attempted to define good, without recognising what such an attempt must mean. They
actually use arguments which involve one or both of the absurdities considered in §
11. We are, therefore, justified in concluding that the attempt to define good is chiefly
due to want of clearness as to the possible nature of definition. There are, in fact, only
two serious alternatives to be considered, in order to establish the conclusion that
good does denote a simple and indefinable notion. It might possibly denote a
complex, as horse does; or it might have no meaning at all. Neither of these
possibilities has, however, been clearly conceived and seriously maintained, as such,
by those who presume to define good; and both may be dismissed by a simple appeal
to facts.

(1) The hypothesis that disagreement about the meaning of good is disagreement with
regard to the correct analysis of a given whole, may be most plainly seen to be
incorrect by consideration of the fact that, whatever definition may be offered, it may
always, be asked, with significance, of the complex so defined, whether it is itself
good. To take, for instance, one of the more plausible, because one of the more
complicated of such proposed definitions, it may easily be thought, at first sight, that
to be good may mean to be that which we desire to desire. Thus if we apply this
definition to a particular instance and say When we think that A is good, we are
thinking that A is one of the things which we desire to desire, our proposition may
seem quite plausible. But, if we carry the investigation further, and ask ourselves Is it
good to desire to desire A? it is apparent, on a little reflection, that this question is
itself as intelligible, as the original question, Is A good?—that we are, in fact, now
asking for exactly the same information about the desire to desire A, for which we
formerly asked with regard to A itself. But it is also apparent that the meaning of this
second question cannot be correctly analysed into Is the desire to desire A one of the
things which we desire to desire?: we have not before our minds anything so
complicated as the question Do we desire to desire to desire to desire A? Moreover
any one can easily convince himself by inspection that the predicate of this
proposition—good—is positively different from notion of desiring to desire which
enters into its subject: That we should desire to desire A is good is not merely
equivalent to That A should be good is good. It may indeed be true that what we
desire to desire is always good; perhaps, even the converse may be true: but it is very
doubtful whether this is the case, and the mere fact that we understand very well what
is meant by doubting it, shews clearly that we have to different notions before our
mind.

(2) And the same consideration is sufficient to dismiss the hypothesis that good has no
meaning whatsoever. It is very natural to make the mistake of supposing that what is
universally true is of such a nature that its negation would be self-contradictory: the
importance which has been assigned to analytic propositions in the history of
philosophy shews how easy such a mistake is. And thus it is very easy to conclude
that what seems to be a universal ethical principle is in fact an identical proposition;
that, if, for example, whatever is called good seems to be pleasant, the proposition
Pleasure is the good does not assert a connection between two different notions, but
involves only one, that of pleasure, which is easily recognised as a distinct entity. But
whoever will attentively consider with himself what is actually before his mind when
he asks the question Is pleasure (or whatever it may be) after all good? can easily
satisfy himself that he is not merely wondering whether pleasure is pleasant. And if he
will try this experiment with each suggested definition in succession, he may become
expert enough to recognise that in every case he has before his mind a unique object,
with regard to the connection of which with any other object, a distinct question may
be asked. Every one does in fact understand the question Is this good? When he thinks
of it, his state of mind is different from what it would be, were he asked Is this
pleasant, or desired, or approved? It has a distinct meaning for him, even though he
may not recognise in what respect it is distinct. Whenever he thinks of intrinsic value,
or intrinsic worth, or says that a thing ought to exist, he has before his mind the
unique object—the unique property of things—that I mean by good. Everybody is
constantly aware of this notion, although he may never become aware at all that it is
different from other notions of which he is also aware. But, for correct ethical
reasoning, it is extremely important that he should become aware of this fact; and as
soon as the nature of the problem is closely understood, there should be little
difficulty in advancing so far in analysis.

“Moore’s Open Question Argument” by Bruno Verbeek

The general form of the Open Question Argument is the following:

P1. Suppose that the predicate ‘good’ is synonymous with some other predicate
N (e.g., ‘pleasurable’).
P2. ‘X has the property N’ will mean ‘X is good’.
C1. Anybody who would ask whether an X with property N is good, would ipso facto
betray conceptual confusion. She is unaware what ‘good’ means (symmetry of
identity, P2).
P3. However, for every N it is always an open question whether an X with
property N is good. It is a meaningful question that does not demonstrate conceptual
confusion.
P4. If for every N it is always an open question whether an X with property N is good,
then ‘N’ cannot be synonymous with ‘good’.
C2. ‘N’ cannot be synonymous with ‘good’ (modus ponens, P3, P4).
P5. If N cannot be synonymous with ‘good’, then only ‘good’ can be
synonymous with ‘good’, therefore, good is a simple (primitive) concept and cannot
be defined.
C3. Only ‘good’ can be synonymous with ‘good’, therefore, good is a simple
(primitive) concept and cannot be defined (modus ponens, C2, P5).

You might also like