Von Muke On Goethe
Von Muke On Goethe
Von Muke On Goethe
Steinbach. Sketch B of
Strasbourg Cathedral.
Reprinted from Marcel Aubert,
The Art of the High Gothic Era,
1965.
Grey Room 35, Spring 2009, pp. 627. 2009 Grey Room, Inc. and Massachusetts Institute of Technology
in a review of the work of the well-known art critic and philosopher Johann Georg
Sulzer, which Goethe wrote around the same time as On German Architecture.
Sulzers work must not be viewed primarily in terms of its theoretical insight but
rather as a repository of what were then considered generally accepted truths about
art and aesthetic experience. Like many works of its time, going back to Charles
Batteux, Abb Jean-Baptiste du Bos, and Gotthold Ephraim Lessing, Sulzers work
also compares and contrasts the sister arts. It seeks their common purpose and
function in their vaguely defined ability to encourage the refinement of sensuality.
Goethes review characterizes Sulzers attempt to find this common denominator
as ultimately a trivializing, even distorting, enterprise:
Was lt sich durch solche Philosophie nicht verbinden? Malerei und
Tanzkunst, Beredsamkeit und Baukunst, Dichtkunst und Bildhauerei, alle
aus einem Loche, durch das magische Licht eines philosophischen Lmpgens
auf die weie Wand gezaubert, tanzen sie im Wunderschein buntfarbig auf
und nieder, und die verzckten Zuschauer frohlocken sich fast auer Atem.1
Everything can be related to anything with the aid of that philosophy.
Painting and dance, rhetoric and architecture, poetry and sculpture, all of
them will be projected onto a white wall through a tiny hole, by the magical
light of the lamp of philosophy. All colorful in this miraculous glow, they will
dance up and down, and the ecstatic onlookers will be almost out of breath
with enthusiasm.
Goethes critique takes aim at the philosophy enabling Sulzers comparison of
the arts; that is, at the theoretical framework and underlying set of distinctions that
produce the kind of thought Sulzer and his cohort of comparative art critics
engaged in. To a certain extent Goethes critical insight can be compared to Foucaults
The Order of Things, which also links the eighteenth-century episteme of representation with a specific technique of observation, the table.2 Thus Goethe characterizes the paradigm underlying Sulzers philosophy as a technical apparatus,
a hybrid of a camera obscura and a magic lantern capable of producing illusionary
tableaux for its captive audience.3 Both of the technologies combined in this hybrid
project images with the aid of light, producing fleeting, flat images that cannot
capture any of the three-dimensional features and embodied realities of sculpture,
architecture, or dance.
Goethe argues that Sulzers methodology crucially distorts the three-dimensional
arts. He supports this point by aligning the actual objects of Sulzers comparison,
in each case contrasting an art form that can be subsumed under the rubric of rep-
Grey Room 35
todays needs. This is just the same as if you wanted to rule your new Babylon
with the simple patriarchal wisdom of those times.
When Goethe makes fun of Laugiers simple patriarchal wisdom, he targets the
attempt to derive aesthetic principles from common, everyday uses and aesthetic
form from primitive, archaic function. One might think of the architect as a mere
engineer or builder who has to meet well-defined needs. For the builder, form is
dictated by function. By contrast, according to Goethe the architect as true artist
and genius finds the form of his work by allowing himself to be inspired by the
confusing, seemingly infinite multiplicity of forms in nature; that is, by a manifold
of natural forms that appears confusing but has its own harmonic order and
design. Goethe illustrates the contrast between the functionally oriented engineer
and the genius inspired by nature:
Eure Gebude stellen euch also Flchen dar, die, je weiter sie sich ausbreiten,
je khner sie gen Himmel steigen, mit desto unertrglicherer Einfrmigkeit
die Seele unterdrcken mssen! Wohl! wenn uns der Genius nicht zu Hlfe
kme, der Erwinen von Steinbach eingab: Vermannigfaltige die ungeheure
Mauer, die du gen Himmel fhren sollst, dass sie aufsteige gleich einem
hocherhabnen, weitverbreiteten Baume Gottes, der mit tausend sten,
Millionen Zweigen, und Blttern wie der Sand am Meer, rings um, der Gegend
verkndet, die Herrlichkeit des Herrn, seines Meisters. (113)
You conceive of your buildings as if they were just two-dimensional surfaces. The more they expand, the bolder they rise to the skies, the more they
have to oppress the soul! Well! If that genius who inspired Erwin von Steinbach
did not come to our aid: Multiply the immense wall that you have to raise
toward the skies so that it rises like a sublime, widely spread-out tree of God,
whose thousands of branches, millions of twigs and leaves like the sand on
the ocean announce everywhere the glory of its lord and master.
The engineer who derives the form of the building merely from its function is
accused of being oblivious to the psychic impact his building will have on its
beholders. The greater his technical accomplishmentsthe broader his walls, the
higher they extend toward the skiesthe more his building will oppress the soul
of its beholder. For Goethe, architecture must be understood as art rather than as
just a form of engineering and must aim for an entirely different effect on the
beholder: architecture-as-art must uplift and edify the soul.
Goethe is playing on the relationship between a literal building or edifice and
10
Grey Room 35
the spiritual meaning of edification, which derives from a New Testament image
describing the rebuilding of the soul in architectural terms.7 He continues in the
religious register by borrowing from devotional literature, comparing the architects tower to a tree of God that announce[s] everywhere the glory of its lord
and master. The change of register does not mean that Goethe assigns a religious
task to art. Although the architectonic work of art, like natural beauty, is to be an
object of devotional contemplation, Goethe radically secularizes this devotion,
because what reveals itself in the act of contemplation is not the divine creator but
the human genius of the artist. By thus making architecture the model object of art,
Goethe redefines the function of art: the function of art is not beautification, ornament, or decoration, nor is it in the realm of representation and mimesis; instead,
art is to present an occasion for a deeply moving encounter, a unique experience
which will leave a lasting impact on the beholder. Art, that is, is supposed to provide the occasion for an enduring, strengthening, and uplifting experience comparable to the kind of experience that used to be found in the religious domain.
Strasbourg Cathedral: Edification and Theophany
Few if any of the discussions interpret Goethes On German Architecture as a
systematic argument about the function of art, an interpretation that can be based
on an analysis of how this text stages its own argument.8 Goethe begins by thematizing, in great detail, the rhetorical situation of the text, thus addressing the pragmatic function of art in the introductory passage of the pamphlet. He presents the
text as the real-time, autobiographical commentary of a first-person speaker, a
pilgrim searching for the grave of Erwin von Steinbach. When the pilgrim doesnt
succeed in finding the grave, he decides to endow a memorial for the great architect
and artist. However, he quickly realizes that von Steinbach does not need a memorial because he has already memorialized himself through his own work, the great
tower of Strasbourg Cathedral. The pilgrim concludes this train of thought by carving the name of the architect, like the name of the beloved, into the stem of a slender
beech tree. He then remodels the tree into a primitive altar and, as a sacrifice to
von Steinbachs spirit, offers up some of the natural products he has collected during
the day.
By framing his text in this way, Goethe casts his discussion of Strasbourg Cathedral
and his mise-en-scne of an exemplary experience of art in bold anthropological
and ethnographical terms. The functional approach to art, which Goethe rejects in
his critique of Laugier, is replaced by a ritual and symbolic approach to art, the
primitive hut by the poets improvised altar.9 The sequence of actions in the intro-
11
ductory passage, which is entirely in the present tense, is also a critical reflection
on the uses of certain place-bound religious and secular memorial practices. The
search for the gravestone recalls the Roman practice of pietas, the duty of the offspring to maintain the memory of the deceased, and contrasts with a more worldly
form of remembrance, fama, which maintains the memory of the deceased persons
glorious deeds and accomplishments.10 Whereas the religious practice depends on
the piety of the survivors, the glorious remembrance of a hero can be influenced
at least to a certain degreethrough clever public relations strategies. In either
case, fame needs a medium, which traditionally takes the form of epic poetry. The
speaker who presents himself in the role of the person who wants to memorialize
the great achievements of Erwin von Steinbach, who promises to endow a marble
monument in his memory, places himself in the position of the poet upon whose
achievement the heros fame ultimately depends.
However, the opening paragraph of Goethes pamphlet does not end by marking
the speakers position as the poet who would be charged with the memorialization
of the hero. Instead, the speaker realizes that his intention of creating a monument
to the memory of Erwin von Steinbach has already been rendered obsolete. The
hero has already made himself immortal by erecting the tower of Strasbourg
Cathedral, an achievement the would-be poet compares, with extraordinary boldness, to the building of the tower of Babel:
Wenigen ward es gegeben, einen Babelgedanken in der Seele zu zeugen,
ganz, gro, und bis in den kleinsten Theil notwendig schn, wie Bume Gottes;
wenigern, auf tausend bietende Hnde zu treffen, Felsengrund zu graben,
steile Hhen drauf zu zaubern, und dann sterbend ihren Shnen zu sagen:
ich bleibe bey euch, in den Werken meines Geistes, vollendet das begonnene
in die Wolken. (110)
Few had the gift to engender a babylonic thought in their soul, whole, great,
and necessarily beautiful down to its smallest part, like Gods trees; even
fewer had the gift of encountering thousands of hands, willing to dig into the
rock, and to magically build on that up to steep heights, and then while dying
say to their sons: I remain with you in the works of my spirit; complete what
I have begun in the clouds.
Already the neo-Platonic tradition of the Renaissance had rewritten the story of the
tower of Babel by no longer criticizing the hubris of the entire enterprise but
instead celebrating the superhuman achievement.11 What is new in the way Goethe
mobilizes the reference to the tower of Babel is that he celebrates the superhuman
12
Grey Room 35
achievement as the artists actual realization of his bold idea. Moreover, this tower
is both a quasi-divine creation that embodies complexity, infinite detail, and wholeness and an open-ended work that memorializes its creator by inviting its beholders
to complete it in his spirit.
By making the beholder accountable for completing the work of art in the spirit
of its creator, Goethe reconceptualizes the traditionally understood relationship
among artist, artwork, and beholder; in effect, he collapses the artist and beholder,
leaving only the two primary positions of artist-beholder and artwork. The beholder
is given a status almost equal to that of the bold artist hero, which also protects the
beholder from the intimidating, overwhelming impact of a work of genius. By
becoming an active participant in the completion of the work of art, the beholders
spirits are uplifted and he feels strengthened and edified by his aesthetic experience. The artwork takes on a dual aspect: on the one hand, it is open-ended, to be
completed in its contemplation by a beholder; on the other hand, it appears as an
independent, complete, autonomous presence. The insistence on the actual realization of the building, not just its conceptualization, emphasizes the actual presence
of the work, a presence that manages in a unique material reality to survive the
physical presence of the artist, which for generations may be recognized, remembered, and understood by those who are capable of matching the creative spirit of
the artist.
For Goethe, a work of art is a unique original insofar as it, like a shrine devoted
to a saint, guarantees the presence of the deceased; specifically, the artwork guarantees the presence of its creator. Such works of art do not fit within a semiotic system, they are not based on a model of representation but instead on the emphatic
endowment of presence, which Goethe describes as the experience of mutual
recognition between artwork and beholder. This kind of aesthetic experience
requires a specific disposition in the beholderthe wholeness of his soul, whose
integrity is reflected back to him.
Was brauchts dir Denkmal! und von mir! Wenn der Pbel heilige Namen ausspricht, ists Aberglaube oder Lsterung. Dem schwachen Geschmckler wirds
ewig schwindlen an deinem Kolo, und ganze Seelen werden dich erkennen
ohne Deuter. (110)
What do you need a monument for! And from me! If the common crowd
pronounces sacred names, it is superstition or blasphemy. The weak philistine will always be dizzy confronted with your colossal monument, and souls
of integrity will recognize you without help.
13
The speaker concludes by reporting to Erwins spirit how he (the speaker) carves
Erwin von Steinbachs name into the beech tree and presents to him a sacrificial
offering. The speaker leaves some botanical finds he has gathered on his walks to
decay in honor of Erwins spirit. The emphatic aesthetic experience, the selfaffirming communication between a beholder of art and the spirit of the deceased
artist is analogized to the sacrificial offering at a saints shrine. Alongside the pilgrimage metaphor the narrator places a metaphor of secular love by implicitly
comparing Erwin von Steinbach to the beloved whose name is carved into the bark
of a tree. Thus the loving exchange between beholder and artwork is analogized to
the symmetric and reciprocal exchange that occurs during a mutual recognition of
lovers. The lack of an official sacerdotal presence or officially sanctioned altar
highlights the improvisational character of the scene. The fact that the botanical
finds are just handed over to decay rather than killed or burned places the ritual at
a far remove from the sacrificial rites of monotheistic religion, especially the central
blood sacrifice of Christianity.
The experience of art as an intensified communication and exchange between
the spirit of the artist and the beholder promises to grant the kind of satisfaction
and affirmation that is provided when lovers look into each others eyes or an
infant finds him- or herself reflected in its mothers loving gaze.12 The original
work of art can exercise this self-affirming mirroring function because, like the
beloved or the mother, its accessibility is exclusive. The original work of art admits
only a special kind of beholder, not the common crowd or the deformed connoisseur. Because the original work of art does not fit any preexisting schema of perception, its appreciation requires a beholder who is sufficiently artistically
talented. Instead of being frightened and turned away by the works uniqueness
and openness, the beholder must be able to understand its compositional logic in
order to complete it in his own thoughts. In this ability the beholder is affirmed as
another potential artist and creator, capable of transcendence.13
In On German Architecture Goethe does not only attribute an edifying function
to the work of art; he also stages this function in the detailed report of his encounter
with Strasbourg Cathedral. Although both passages begin as if presenting the narration of a unique experience that leads to the revision of his prejudice against the
Gothic, closer inspection reveals that Goethe is presenting not a unique realization
but a process of contemplation that claims a paradigmatic status by calling for
repetition and inviting the readers identification and imitation:
Ein ganzer, groer Eindruck fllte meine Seele, den, weil er aus tausend
harmonierenden Einzelheiten bestand, ich wohl schmecken und genieen,
14
Grey Room 35
keineswegs aber erkennen und erklren konnte. Sie sagen, dass es also mit
den Freuden des Himmels sei, und wie oft bin ich zurckgekehrt, diese
himmlisch-irdische Freude zu genieen, den Riesengeist unserer ltern Brder
in ihren Werken zu umfassen. Wie oft bin ich zurckgekehrt, von allen Seiten,
aus allen Entfernungen, in jedem Lichte des Tags zu schauen seine Wrde
und Herrlichkeit! Schwer ists dem Menschengeist, wenn seines Bruders
Werk so hoch erhaben ist, dass er nur beugen und anbeten mu. Wie oft hat
die Abenddmmerung mein durch forschendes Schauen ermattetes Aug mit
freundlicher Ruhe geletzt, wenn durch sie die unzhligen Teile zu ganzen
Massen schmolzen, und nun einfach und gro, vor meiner Seele standen, und
meine Kraft sich wonnevoll entfaltete, zugleich zu genieen und zu erkennen!
Da offenbarte sich mir, in leisen Ahndungen, der Genius des groen
Werkmeisters. Was staunst du? Lispelt er mir entgegen. Alle diese Massen
waren notwendig, und siehst du sie nicht an allen lteren Kirchen meiner
Stadt? (114)
A whole, great impression filled my soul. Because it consisted of a thousand harmonizing details I could very well taste and enjoy but I had no way
of cognitively grasping and explaining it. They say that it is the same with the
joys of heaven. How often did I return to partake in this heavenly-earthly joy,
to grasp the giant spirit of our older brothers through their works. How often
did I return from all sides, from all distances, in all kinds of daylight to view
his honor and glory. How hard it is for the human spirit if his brothers work
is so high above him that all he can do is bend down and adore. How often
did dusk bring friendly relief and rest to my exhausted eyes until it melted the
innumerable parts into one whole mass, which then would stand simple and
grand before my soul, and my entire force would unfold with great pleasure
to be able to enjoy while gaining insight at the same time! Then the genius of
the great master of this work would reveal itself to me in quiet anticipations.
What are you amazed at? He would whisper to me. All these masses were
necessary, and dont you see them in all of the older churches of my city?
The Strasbourg Cathedral passage can be read as the account of an experience
not only of the discovery of the beauty of the faade but of the discovery and revelation of a contemplative technique of the self. The first-person singular of the
experience, as well as of the description of the experience, is both an individualized I and an exemplary I inviting identification and imitation. The insight
into the harmony of the composition, the overview of the confusing multiplicity
of forms occurs only gradually after repeated contemplationhow oftenunder
15
16
Grey Room 35
17
himself as an autonomous self that creates himself anew as he creates his world.
The aesthetics of emphatic presence remained important even for the later Goethe,
although he increasingly distanced himself from the model of subjectivity derived
from pietist devotional literature. Instead he took up the experience of space,
thinking of it as an intense experience of embodiment. Also in his later years he
began to be interested in techniques of the self that aim at the control of involuntary bodily and physiological reactions such as disgust and vertigothat is, reactions that blur the clear distinction between an external, objective world of
perception and an interior world of vivid imagination.18
Architecture as Fiction
Architecture remained for Goethe an art form that allowed him to reflect on arts
ability to produce an emphatic presence, to enhance, transform, and transfigure a
beholders or audiences perception and sensibility. Yet, whereas the essay on
German architecture from 1771 makes its case by drawing on meditational techniques of contemplation and visualization, Goethes later essay on architecture no
longer draws on these religious techniques of the self. Instead, the later essay
works with two key concepts: character and fiction. Character, by then a category
in the discourse on architecture, dealt with the assessment of a particular buildings ability to relate form to function, be that in view of the buildings apt choice of
materials, proportions, and styles that would allow for the optimal use of the building, or in view of the buildings teleological transparency, its capacity to advertise
its use and function in semiotically transparent terms.19 Fiction, however, not a
common or conventional concept in architectural theory, becomes the counterpart
to character by which Goethe extricates architecture from functional and teleological determinism.
Whereas Goethes essay about Strasbourg Cathedral characterizes the experience of presence provided by the work of art as a gradual visualization of the compositional order of the almost infinite manifold, in the Architecture essay from
1795 the aesthetic experience of presence is cut off from the visual domain:
Man sollte denken, die Baukunst als schne Kunst arbeite allein frs Auge;
allein sie soll vorzglich, und worauf man am wenigsten acht hat, fr den
Sinn der mechanischen Bewegung des menschlichen Krpers arbeiten; wir
fhlen eine angenehme Empfindung, wenn wir uns im Tanze nach gewissen
Gesetzen bewegen; eine hnliche Empfindung sollten wir bei jemand erregen knnen, den wir mit verbundenen Augen durch ein wohl gebautes Haus
18
Grey Room 35
hindurch fhren. Hier tritt die schwere und komplizierte Lehre von den
Proportionen ein, wodurch der Charakter des Gebudes und seiner verschiedenen Teile mglich wird.20
One would think that architecture, as one of the fine arts, would primarily
engage our sense of sight; however, something that has hardly been noticed
is the fact that architecture engages primarily our sense of motor control. We
have a pleasant sensation when we move in a dance according to certain
rules. A similar sensation should be provoked in somebody who is led through
a well-built house blindfolded. This leads us to the difficult and complicated
doctrine of proportions, which determine the character of a building and its
diverse parts.
Architecture as a fine art is thus no longer aligned with visual perception but with
the embodied sense of motor control. In addition, the spatial perception of a work
of architecture is compared to the temporally structured aesthetic experience of
ones own body while dancing. Goethe is suggesting that the proportions of a
specific building should be enjoyed in the way a dancer, rather than a passive audience member, enjoys a specific choreography. However, as in the earlier essay on
Strasbourg Cathedral, Goethe demands an active beholder. In the earlier essay the
beholder becomes a partner in dialogue with the artist who completes in his active
imagination the work of art. In the later work the beholder is not on an equal footing with the artist. Instead, the beholder enjoys himself as he is led through the
well-proportioned building. Goethes assertion that dance provides pleasure equivalent to that of a well-proportioned building allows him to redirect the discourse
on proportions and harmony; in effect, it is no longer grounded in the disembodied
discourse of mathematics, music, and the cosmic harmony of the spheres together
with all of its allegorical and emblematic dimensions. In its place is a dedicated
focus on the embodied individual.
Unlike the earlier essay on Strasbourg Cathedral, On Architecture does not
focus on one particular building. However, Goethe raises the issue of how we
should think about the individuality and specificity of a building, and from his
answer to this question he derives his decisive contribution to aesthetic theory. In
the essay on Strasbourg Cathedral the individuality of the work of art was depicted
as an issue of the artistic achievement of the individual artists genius, his ability to
present a manifold that appeared to dissolve into infinite detail within an ultimately
harmonious order. In the later essay Goethe pursues the question of a buildings
individuality under the rubric of character. Where the earlier essay included
Goethes critique of Laugiers reception of Vitruvius, the later essay refers directly
19
to Vitruvius when articulating the distinction between mere buildings and architecture as art:
Soll aber das Baugeschft den Namen einer Kunst verdienen, so mu es neben
dem Notwendigen und Ntzlichen auch sinnlich-harmonische Gegenstnde
hervorbringen. Dieses Sinnlich-Harmonische ist in jeder Kunst von eigner
Art und bedingt; es kann nur innerhalb seiner Bedingung beurteilt werden.
Diese Bedingungen entspringen aus dem Material, aus dem Zweck und aus
der Natur des Sinns, fr welchen das Ganze harmonisch sein soll. (368)
If building is to deserve the name of art, it has to be not merely necessary
and useful but also sensuously harmonious. Each art has its own sense of
what is sensuously harmonious; it can only be judged on its own terms. Those
terms can be derived from the combination of the buildings conditions, from
the material, the purpose, and meaning of the building with which the whole
building has to be in harmony.
This formulation appears to be an echo of Vitruviuss demand that architecture, in
order to be beautiful, has to respect the function it serves and the materials that are
used. But Goethe is actually making a decisive departure from Vitruviuss functionalism. In contrast to the cathedral essay, however, considerations of function
are not just set aside. They take on the role of just one relativizing element in the
evaluation of the overall appropriateness and proportions of the individual elements. One specific purpose of a buildingfor instance, its intended use as a
princely residence or as a cathedraldoes play a certain role in the evaluation of
the use of certain architectural elements. The building is to be evaluated on its own
terms, which do not exclude a consideration of its purpose and the materials that
have been used. And yet, as Goethe continues to argue, evaluations of the specific
character of a building or attempts to come to terms with what makes a building
unique, must be addressed through exactly those aspects through which the building transcends its mere satisfaction of functionalist principles as well as the merely
appropriate use of materials.
Whereas Goethe initially severs the perception of architecture from visuality and
relates it instead to a spatial perception coupled with a sense of gross motor and
body controla step in his argument that seems to keep an architectural paradigm
at the appropriate distance from a paradigm of art as mimesis or representation
the introduction of the term character and the ensuing argument appear to take
back that separation of art from considerations of mimesis. Goethe even introduces
the term fiction, although what he means by this term is not at all self-evident.
20
Grey Room 35
21
whether what he does is truly appropriate, it is as difficult for the connoisseur to evaluate the appropriateness of the decision.
The principles of the architects creative process have been clearly severed from
merely functionalist considerations. Goethe is proposing an even more exceptional
kind of architecture, the architecture of genius, which somehow goes beyond all
architectural goals and appeals to the educated intellect of its beholder, amazes
and dazzles him in a way that seems to involve all of his faculties. Far beyond
a mere pleasant sensation, what is at stake here is the conscious perception of
appearance and semblance; for example, an allusion to a certain building material
that then might not be used. This kind of architecture would appeal to a critical
observer, a beholder who evaluates the architects conscious choices and his departure from established conventions. But why should this kind of an aesthetic experience, this coming together of sense perception, a certain bodily awareness of
space, and the conscious reflection on types of illusion assume an almost ecstatic
quality of wonder? And why is it that Goethe claims that the highest purpose of
architecture lies in the production of this reaction as an effect of fiction?
The reason for this exalted reaction seems to be that this kind of aesthetic experience provides an insight into human creativity. Herethat is, when fiction is at
stake and when an architectural work of genius is perceived as suchthe human
imagination can be intuited as a form of creativity that, unfettered by context,
need, function, or stylistic conventions, knows how to address, take up, and transform these very fetters. This is how architecture becomes the medium of an emphatically humanist approach to art.22
With this humanist approach to architecture Goethe departs from contemporary trends in architectural theory. Toward the end of the eighteenth century, architecture was typically associated with a symbolic function that could be articulated
in one of several ways: for example, to mean that specific buildings were to indicate in the design of their faade or their shape a specific function; or that they
were to serve as symbols of a specific collectivity or nation.23 Goethes notion of
fiction in architecture does not imply either notion of architectures symbolic function. For Goethe, the architecture of genius, in its ability to engage and enhance the
human imagination, represents the human imagination as a productive rather than
merely reproductive faculty. The architecture of genius invites the educated beholder
to admire in a work of architecture not its reference to something else but the specific choices and the creative selectivity of its artist.
The educated beholder evaluates a building by paying attention to the specific
22
Grey Room 35
character of the individual building. His or her evaluation, the attempt to do justice
to the way individual elements in a building come together as a unique totality, is
distinct from both mere reaction to specific stylistic features and the more mechanical evaluation of certain proportions, evaluations that do not necessarily require
an on-site visit but can also be based on engravings, etchings, and other merely
graphic reproductions of the building. How should works of architecture be evaluated according to Goethe? On the one hand, he insists that any evaluation
requires a visit to and inspection of the actual building. Only exposure to the original, he believes, provides the beholder with the unique experience of how a building organizes the space through which the beholder moves. On the other hand, the
beholder must bring into play his knowledge of architecture, of alternative options
and choices the architect would have had at his disposal, in order to grasp the
unique achievement of any one building as the realization of a work of genius. By
emphasizing the embodied aspect of the architectural experience, Goethe distinguishes the emphatic aesthetic experience from a mere visual, cognitive, and imaginative experience mediated by the architectural discourse of the journals,
pamphlets, and architectural prints that were being widely circulated by the end
of the eighteenth century. To the extent that the mature Goethe requires of the
architectural work of genius that it entail an element of fiction, he demands that art
insist on the ability to transcend what is given, what is required, what is necessary
and predictable and to present its beholder with an anthropologically crucial dimension of the human imaginationnamely, its capacity to appropriate and transform
dominant teleologies.
23
Notes
24
Grey Room 35
gen und zu frchten hat, greift der Halbgott, wirksam in seiner Ruhe, umher nach Stoff ihm seinen
Geist einzuhauchen. Und so modelt der Wilde mit abenteuerlichen Zgen, grlichen Gestalten,
hohen Farben, seine Cocos, seine Federn, und seinen Kper. Und lat diese Bildnerei aus den willkrlichsten Formen bestehn, sie wird ohne Gestaltsverhltnis zusammmenstimmen, denn Eine
Empfindung schuf sie zum charkeristischen Ganzen (116117). (Art is creative long before it is
beautiful. And yet, such art is true and great, perhaps truer and greater than when it becomes beautiful. For in man there is a creative force which becomes active as soon as his existence is secure.
When he is free from worry and fear, this demigod, restless in tranquility, begins to cast about for
matter to inspire with his spirit. And thus savages decorate their coconut-fiber mats, their feathers,
their bodies, with bizarre patterns, ghastly forms and gaudy colors. And even if this creative activity produces the most arbitrary shapes and designs, they will harmonize despite the apparent lack
of proportion. For a single feeling created them as a characteristic whole. Johann Wolfgang von
Goethe, On German Architecture, in Essays on Art and Literature, trans. Ellen von Nardroff and
Ernest H. von Nardroff [Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1994], 8.)
14. Johann Arnd[t], Vier Bcher vom wahren Christentum . . . , ed. Joachim Langen (Berlin, 1712),
1144.
15. Seventeenth-century edification texts are characterized by an exemplary I, on the one hand,
and by a situational description related to a specific personal experience, on the other. This combination invokes both a total identification with the narrated I and an imaginary realization of the
speech situation. See Wolfgang Brckner, Thesen zur literarischen Struktur des sogenannten
Erbaulichen, in Volkskunde als historische Kulturwissenschaft 11 (1985): 209218.
16. Contesting the Sacred: The Anthropology of Christian Pilgrimage, ed. John Eade and Michael
J. Sallnow (New York: Routledge, 1991).
17. Johann Gottfried Herder, Sculpture: Some Observations on Shape and Form from Pygmalions
Creative Dream (1778), ed. and trans. Jason Gaiger (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2002).
18. In his autobiography, On Poetry and Truth, Goethe reports how he painfully trained himself to
sustain the view from the tower of Strasbourg Cathedral without succumbing to vertigo, a procedure
similar to that which he used when learning to tolerate the dissection of human corpses in anatomy
theaters.
19. See Vittoria di Palma, Architecture, Environment, and Emotion: Quatremre de Quincy and
the Concept of Character, AA Files 47 (Summer 2002): 4556.
20. Goethe, Baukunst, in sthetische Schriften I, 368.
21. See also Jens Bisky, who argues that Goethe uses the concept of fiction to direct our attention
to the aspect of mediation and artificiality of all beautiful architecture, to make us aware of the growing distance of architectural forms from their primitive beginnings, to make us see architectural
history instead of quasi-natural archetypes. See Jens Bisky, Die Fiktion der Baukunst, in Poesie der
Baukunst, 75.
22. In ber Wahrheit und Wahrscheinlichkeit der Kunstwerke, Goethe also defends the purposeful use of illusion in art and advocates for an art that resolutely insists on its artificiality, taken
neither as nature itself nor as a reference to it. Because a successful work of art still appears as nature
to its viewer, Goethe has his advocate of art explain, Ein vollkommenes Kunstwerk ist ein Werk des
25
menschlichen Geistes, und in diesem Sinne auch ein Werk der Natur. Aber indem die zerstreuten
Gegenstnde in eins gefat und selbst die gemeinsten in ihrer Bedeutung und Wrde aufgenommen
werden, so ist es ber die Natur. Es will durch einen Geist, der harmonisch entsprungen und gebildet
ist, aufgefat sein, und dieser findet das Frtreffliche, das in sich vollendete auch seiner Natur
gem. Davon hat der gemeine Liebhaber keinen Begriff. . . . [A]ber der wahre Liebhaber sieht nicht
nur die Wahrheit des Nachgeahmten, sondern auch die Vorzge des Ausgewhlten, das Geistreiche
der Zusammenstellung, das berirdische der kleinen Kunstwelt; er fhlt, da er sich zum Knstler
erheben msse, um das Werk zu genieen, er fhlt, da er sich aus seinem zestreuten Leben sammeln, mit dem Kunstwerke wohnen, es wiederholt anschauen und sich selbst damit eine hhere
Existenz geben msse (506). (A great work of art is a work of the human mind, and thus also a work
of nature. But because the work of art treats its diverse subject matter as a unified whole and reveals
the significance and dignity of even the most ordinary subjects, it goes beyond nature. A work of art
can only be comprehended by a mind that has been formed and developed harmoniously, because
only such a mind can relate to what is excellent and complete within itself. The savage art lover has
no concept of that. . . . But the true connoisseur sees not only the realism of what is imitated but also
the excellence in the selection of subject matter, the imaginativeness in composition, and the supranatural spirit of this micro-world of art. He feels that he must rise to the level of the artist in order to
enjoy the work, that he must focus his scattered energies on the work of art, that he must live with
it, must see it again and again, and thus achieve a higher level of awareness. Johann Wolfgang von
Goethe, On Realism in Art, in Essays on Art and Literature, trans. Nardroff and Nardroff, 7778.)
23. On this, see Wittman, The Hut and the Altar. See also Anthony Vidler, The Writing of the
Walls: Architectural Theory in the Late Enlightenment (Princeton: Princeton Architectural Press,
1987).
26
Grey Room 35
27