In 1975, researchers at Stanford invited a group of undergraduates to take part in a study about suicide. They were presented with pairs of suicide notes. In each pair, one note had been composed by a random individual, the other by a person who had subsequently taken his own life. The students were then asked to distinguish between the genuine notes and the fake ones.
Some students discovered that they had a genius for the task. Out of twenty-five pairs of notes, they correctly identified the real one twenty-four times. Others discovered that they were hopeless. They identified the real note in only ten instances.
As is often the case with psychological studies, the whole setup was a put-on. Though half the notes were indeed genuineâtheyâd been obtained from the Los Angeles County coronerâs officeâthe scores were fictitious. The students whoâd been told they were almost always right were, on average, no more discerning than those who had been told they were mostly wrong.
In the second phase of the study, the deception was revealed. The students were told that the real point of the experiment was to gauge their responses to thinking they were right or wrong. (This, it turned out, was also a deception.) Finally, the students were asked to estimate how many suicide notes they had actually categorized correctly, and how many they thought an average student would get right. At this point, something curious happened. The students in the high-score group said that they thought they had, in fact, done quite wellâsignificantly better than the average studentâeven though, as theyâd just been told, they had zero grounds for believing this. Conversely, those whoâd been assigned to the low-score group said that they thought they had done significantly worse than the average studentâa conclusion that was equally unfounded.
âOnce formed,â the researchers observed dryly, âimpressions are remarkably perseverant.â
A few years later, a new set of Stanford students was recruited for a related study. The students were handed packets of information about a pair of firefighters, Frank K. and George H. Frankâs bio noted that, among other things, he had a baby daughter and he liked to scuba dive. George had a small son and played golf. The packets also included the menâs responses on what the researchers called the Risky-Conservative Choice Test. According to one version of the packet, Frank was a successful firefighter who, on the test, almost always went with the safest option. In the other version, Frank also chose the safest option, but he was a lousy firefighter whoâd been put âon reportâ by his supervisors several times. Once again, midway through the study, the students were informed that theyâd been misled, and that the information theyâd received was entirely fictitious. The students were then asked to describe their own beliefs. What sort of attitude toward risk did they think a successful firefighter would have? The students whoâd received the first packet thought that he would avoid it. The students in the second group thought heâd embrace it.
Even after the evidence âfor their beliefs has been totally refuted, people fail to make appropriate revisions in those beliefs,â the researchers noted. In this case, the failure was âparticularly impressive,â since two data points would never have been enough information to generalize from.
The Stanford studies became famous. Coming from a group of academics in the nineteen-seventies, the contention that people canât think straight was shocking. It isnât any longer. Thousands of subsequent experiments have confirmed (and elaborated on) this finding. As everyone whoâs followed the researchâor even occasionally picked up a copy of Psychology Todayâknows, any graduate student with a clipboard can demonstrate that reasonable-seeming people are often totally irrational. Rarely has this insight seemed more relevant than it does right now. Still, an essential puzzle remains: How did we come to be this way?
In a new book, âThe Enigma of Reasonâ (Harvard), the cognitive scientists Hugo Mercier and Dan Sperber take a stab at answering this question. Mercier, who works at a French research institute in Lyon, and Sperber, now based at the Central European University, in Budapest, point out that reason is an evolved trait, like bipedalism or three-color vision. It emerged on the savannas of Africa, and has to be understood in that context.
Stripped of a lot of what might be called cognitive-science-ese, Mercier and Sperberâs argument runs, more or less, as follows: Humansâ biggest advantage over other species is our ability to coöperate. Coöperation is difficult to establish and almost as difficult to sustain. For any individual, freeloading is always the best course of action. Reason developed not to enable us to solve abstract, logical problems or even to help us draw conclusions from unfamiliar data; rather, it developed to resolve the problems posed by living in collaborative groups.
âReason is an adaptation to the hypersocial niche humans have evolved for themselves,â Mercier and Sperber write. Habits of mind that seem weird or goofy or just plain dumb from an âintellectualistâ point of view prove shrewd when seen from a social âinteractionistâ perspective.
Consider whatâs become known as âconfirmation bias,â the tendency people have to embrace information that supports their beliefs and reject information that contradicts them. Of the many forms of faulty thinking that have been identified, confirmation bias is among the best catalogued; itâs the subject of entire textbooksâ worth of experiments. One of the most famous of these was conducted, again, at Stanford. For this experiment, researchers rounded up a group of students who had opposing opinions about capital punishment. Half the students were in favor of it and thought that it deterred crime; the other half were against it and thought that it had no effect on crime.
The students were asked to respond to two studies. One provided data in support of the deterrence argument, and the other provided data that called it into question. Both studiesâyou guessed itâwere made up, and had been designed to present what were, objectively speaking, equally compelling statistics. The students who had originally supported capital punishment rated the pro-deterrence data highly credible and the anti-deterrence data unconvincing; the students whoâd originally opposed capital punishment did the reverse. At the end of the experiment, the students were asked once again about their views. Those whoâd started out pro-capital punishment were now even more in favor of it; those whoâd opposed it were even more hostile.
If reason is designed to generate sound judgments, then itâs hard to conceive of a more serious design flaw than confirmation bias. Imagine, Mercier and Sperber suggest, a mouse that thinks the way we do. Such a mouse, âbent on confirming its belief that there are no cats around,â would soon be dinner. To the extent that confirmation bias leads people to dismiss evidence of new or underappreciated threatsâthe human equivalent of the cat around the cornerâitâs a trait that should have been selected against. The fact that both we and it survive, Mercier and Sperber argue, proves that it must have some adaptive function, and that function, they maintain, is related to our âhypersociability.â
Mercier and Sperber prefer the term âmyside bias.â Humans, they point out, arenât randomly credulous. Presented with someone elseâs argument, weâre quite adept at spotting the weaknesses. Almost invariably, the positions weâre blind about are our own.
A recent experiment performed by Mercier and some European colleagues neatly demonstrates this asymmetry. Participants were asked to answer a series of simple reasoning problems. They were then asked to explain their responses, and were given a chance to modify them if they identified mistakes. The majority were satisfied with their original choices; fewer than fifteen per cent changed their minds in step two.
In step three, participants were shown one of the same problems, along with their answer and the answer of another participant, whoâd come to a different conclusion. Once again, they were given the chance to change their responses. But a trick had been played: the answers presented to them as someone elseâs were actually their own, and vice versa. About half the participants realized what was going on. Among the other half, suddenly people became a lot more critical. Nearly sixty per cent now rejected the responses that theyâd earlier been satisfied with.
This lopsidedness, according to Mercier and Sperber, reflects the task that reason evolved to perform, which is to prevent us from getting screwed by the other members of our group. Living in small bands of hunter-gatherers, our ancestors were primarily concerned with their social standing, and with making sure that they werenât the ones risking their lives on the hunt while others loafed around in the cave. There was little advantage in reasoning clearly, while much was to be gained from winning arguments.
Among the many, many issues our forebears didnât worry about were the deterrent effects of capital punishment and the ideal attributes of a firefighter. Nor did they have to contend with fabricated studies, or fake news, or Twitter. Itâs no wonder, then, that today reason often seems to fail us. As Mercier and Sperber write, âThis is one of many cases in which the environment changed too quickly for natural selection to catch up.â
Steven Sloman, a professor at Brown, and Philip Fernbach, a professor at the University of Colorado, are also cognitive scientists. They, too, believe sociability is the key to how the human mind functions or, perhaps more pertinently, malfunctions. They begin their book, âThe Knowledge Illusion: Why We Never Think Aloneâ (Riverhead), with a look at toilets.
Virtually everyone in the United States, and indeed throughout the developed world, is familiar with toilets. A typical flush toilet has a ceramic bowl filled with water. When the handle is depressed, or the button pushed, the waterâand everything thatâs been deposited in itâgets sucked into a pipe and from there into the sewage system. But how does this actually happen?
In a study conducted at Yale, graduate students were asked to rate their understanding of everyday devices, including toilets, zippers, and cylinder locks. They were then asked to write detailed, step-by-step explanations of how the devices work, and to rate their understanding again. Apparently, the effort revealed to the students their own ignorance, because their self-assessments dropped. (Toilets, it turns out, are more complicated than they appear.)
Sloman and Fernbach see this effect, which they call the âillusion of explanatory depth,â just about everywhere. People believe that they know way more than they actually do. What allows us to persist in this belief is other people. In the case of my toilet, someone else designed it so that I can operate it easily. This is something humans are very good at. Weâve been relying on one anotherâs expertise ever since we figured out how to hunt together, which was probably a key development in our evolutionary history. So well do we collaborate, Sloman and Fernbach argue, that we can hardly tell where our own understanding ends and othersâ begins.
âOne implication of the naturalness with which we divide cognitive labor,â they write, is that thereâs âno sharp boundary between one personâs ideas and knowledgeâ and âthose of other membersâ of the group.
This borderlessness, or, if you prefer, confusion, is also crucial to what we consider progress. As people invented new tools for new ways of living, they simultaneously created new realms of ignorance; if everyone had insisted on, say, mastering the principles of metalworking before picking up a knife, the Bronze Age wouldnât have amounted to much. When it comes to new technologies, incomplete understanding is empowering.
Where it gets us into trouble, according to Sloman and Fernbach, is in the political domain. Itâs one thing for me to flush a toilet without knowing how it operates, and another for me to favor (or oppose) an immigration ban without knowing what Iâm talking about. Sloman and Fernbach cite a survey conducted in 2014, not long after Russia annexed the Ukrainian territory of Crimea. Respondents were asked how they thought the U.S. should react, and also whether they could identify Ukraine on a map. The farther off base they were about the geography, the more likely they were to favor military intervention. (Respondents were so unsure of Ukraineâs location that the median guess was wrong by eighteen hundred miles, roughly the distance from Kiev to Madrid.)
Surveys on many other issues have yielded similarly dismaying results. âAs a rule, strong feelings about issues do not emerge from deep understanding,â Sloman and Fernbach write. And here our dependence on other minds reinforces the problem. If your position on, say, the Affordable Care Act is baseless and I rely on it, then my opinion is also baseless. When I talk to Tom and he decides he agrees with me, his opinion is also baseless, but now that the three of us concur we feel that much more smug about our views. If we all now dismiss as unconvincing any information that contradicts our opinion, you get, well, the Trump Administration.
âThis is how a community of knowledge can become dangerous,â Sloman and Fernbach observe. The two have performed their own version of the toilet experiment, substituting public policy for household gadgets. In a study conducted in 2012, they asked people for their stance on questions like: Should there be a single-payer health-care system? Or merit-based pay for teachers? Participants were asked to rate their positions depending on how strongly they agreed or disagreed with the proposals. Next, they were instructed to explain, in as much detail as they could, the impacts of implementing each one. Most people at this point ran into trouble. Asked once again to rate their views, they ratcheted down the intensity, so that they either agreed or disagreed less vehemently.
Sloman and Fernbach see in this result a little candle for a dark world. If weâor our friends or the pundits on CNNâspent less time pontificating and more trying to work through the implications of policy proposals, weâd realize how clueless we are and moderate our views. This, they write, âmay be the only form of thinking that will shatter the illusion of explanatory depth and change peopleâs attitudes.â
One way to look at science is as a system that corrects for peopleâs natural inclinations. In a well-run laboratory, thereâs no room for myside bias; the results have to be reproducible in other laboratories, by researchers who have no motive to confirm them. And this, it could be argued, is why the system has proved so successful. At any given moment, a field may be dominated by squabbles, but, in the end, the methodology prevails. Science moves forward, even as we remain stuck in place.
In âDenying to the Grave: Why We Ignore the Facts That Will Save Usâ (Oxford), Jack Gorman, a psychiatrist, and his daughter, Sara Gorman, a public-health specialist, probe the gap between what science tells us and what we tell ourselves. Their concern is with those persistent beliefs which are not just demonstrably false but also potentially deadly, like the conviction that vaccines are hazardous. Of course, whatâs hazardous is not being vaccinated; thatâs why vaccines were created in the first place. âImmunization is one of the triumphs of modern medicine,â the Gormans note. But no matter how many scientific studies conclude that vaccines are safe, and that thereâs no link between immunizations and autism, anti-vaxxers remain unmoved. (They can now count on their sideâsort ofâDonald Trump, who has said that, although he and his wife had their son, Barron, vaccinated, they refused to do so on the timetable recommended by pediatricians.)
The Gormans, too, argue that ways of thinking that now seem self-destructive must at some point have been adaptive. And they, too, dedicate many pages to confirmation bias, which, they claim, has a physiological component. They cite research suggesting that people experience genuine pleasureâa rush of dopamineâwhen processing information that supports their beliefs. âIt feels good to âstick to our gunsâ even if we are wrong,â they observe.
The Gormans donât just want to catalogue the ways we go wrong; they want to correct for them. There must be some way, they maintain, to convince people that vaccines are good for kids, and handguns are dangerous. (Another widespread but statistically insupportable belief theyâd like to discredit is that owning a gun makes you safer.) But here they encounter the very problems they have enumerated. Providing people with accurate information doesnât seem to help; they simply discount it. Appealing to their emotions may work better, but doing so is obviously antithetical to the goal of promoting sound science. âThe challenge that remains,â they write toward the end of their book, âis to figure out how to address the tendencies that lead to false scientific belief.â
âThe Enigma of Reason,â âThe Knowledge Illusion,â and âDenying to the Graveâ were all written before the November election. And yet they anticipate Kellyanne Conway and the rise of âalternative facts.â These days, it can feel as if the entire country has been given over to a vast psychological experiment being run either by no one or by Steve Bannon. Rational agents would be able to think their way to a solution. But, on this matter, the literature is not reassuring. â¦