The Problems of Philosophy
The Problems of Philosophy
CHAPTER VI
ON INDUCTION
IN almost all our previous discussions we have been concerned in the
attempt to get clear as to our data in the way of knowledge of existence.
What things are there in the universe whose existence is known to us
owing to our being acquainted with them? So far, our answer has been
that we are acquainted with our sense-data, and, probably, with
ourselves. These we know to exist. And past sense-data which are
remembered are known to have existed in the past. This knowledge
supplies our data.
The only reason for believing that the laws of motion remain in
operation is that they have operated hitherto, so far as our knowledge of
the past enables us to judge. It is true that we have a greater body of
evidence from the past in favour of the laws of motion than we have in
favour of the sunrise, because the sunrise is merely a particular case of
fulfilment of the laws of motion, and there are countless other particular
cases. But the real question is: Do any number of cases of a law being
fulfilled in the past afford evidence that it will be fulfilled in the future?
If not, it becomes plain that we have no ground whatever for expecting
the sun to rise to-morrow, or for expecting the bread we shall eat at our
next meal not to poison us, or for any of the other scarcely conscious
expectations that control our daily lives. It is to be observed that all such
expectations are only probable; thus we have not to seek for a proof that
they must be fulfilled, but only for some reason in favour of the view
that they are likely to be fulfilled.
The belief that the sun will rise to-morrow might be falsified if
the earth came suddenly into contact with a large body which destroyed
its rotation; but the laws of motion and the law of gravitation would not
be infringed by such an event. The business of science is to find
uniformities, such as the laws of motion and the law of gravitation, to
which, so far as our experience extends, there are no exceptions. In this
search science has been remarkably successful, and it may be conceded
that such uniformities have held hitherto. This brings us back to the
question: Have we any reason, assuming that they have always held in
the past, to suppose that they will hold in the future?
It has been argued that we have reason to know that the future
will resemble the past, because what was the future has constantly
become the past, and has always been found to resemble the past, so
that we really have experience of the future, namely of times which were
formerly future, which we may call past futures. But such an argument
really begs the very question at issue. We have experience of past
futures, but not of future futures, and the question is: Will future
futures resemble past futures? This question is not to be answered by an
argument which starts from past futures alone. We have therefore still
to seek for some principle which shall enable us to know that the future
will follow the same laws as the past.
It must be conceded, to begin with, that the fact that two things
have been found often together and never apart does not, by itself,
suffice to prove demonstratively that they will be found together in the
next case we examine. The most we can hope is that the oftener things
are found together, the more probable becomes that they will be found
together another time, and that, if they have been found together often
enough, the probability will amount almost to certainty. It can never
quite reach certainty, because we know that in spite of frequent
repetitions there sometimes is a failure at the last, as in the case of the
chicken whose neck is wrung. Thus probability is all we ought to seek.