Modern Philosophy Notes
Modern Philosophy Notes
Modern Philosophy Notes
This General Introduction highlights the concept of the Term 'Modern'; the nature and
growth of Modern Philosophy. The introduction ends with explaining philosophy during the
Renaissance.
Modern Philosophy
Key Words:
Introduction
This specific period has certain definite features which make it stand out clearly in the history of
Europe. This period has witnessed a diminishing authority of the Church and an increasing
authority of science. Europe had begun to define itself more on political and national lines rather
than religious lines and States have started replacing the Church as authority that controls
culture. The French and American revolutions which had very momentous impacts occurred
during this time and nations were in the path of democratization.
With the Barbarian invasion of the Roman Empire, an era of great ancient civilizations had come
to an end in Europe. By the 5th century, Christianity had become the official religion of the
Roman empire and the Church had become the most powerful organization in Europe [Lavine].
This has resulted in the complete domination of Christianity as an institution based on
unquestionable faith and rigid dogmas in the place of the free, rational, independent
philosophical thinking of the Greeks. Consequently, the Church had destroyed many writings
and works of art of the ancient civilization charging them for being pagan, un-Christian and
immoral and had given birth to a new civilization with redefined social, cultural, economic and
political domains all over the European continent.
The passage from the ancient Greek to Christian worldview was actually a retreat from the
rational to supernatural and from the logical to the revelational. This period had replaced critical
thinking with faith and loyalty to the doctrines of the Church. It therefore, replaced science by
superstition. Most of the philosophical contemplations of this age were confined to the problems
related to the rational justification of faith and God‟s existence.
Modern Philosophy
Bertrand Russell observes that the period of history which is commonly called "modern" has a
mental outlook which differs from that of the medieval period in many ways. Of these, two are
the most important: the diminishing authority of the Church, and the increasing authority of
science. [A History of Western Philosophy].
An important historical event that has happened during this period in European cultural life was
the advent of the Renaissance [the French word for rebirth]. It is generally accepted that the
modern outlook began in Italy with Renaissance. The Renaissance actually consist in the revival
of the ancient wisdom of the Greek and Roman civilization in the modern age. The intellectuals
and creative artists of this period have recognized that the ancient wisdom of the Greeks and the
Romans is the source of valuable insights that have the potential to change the course of human
life in a drastic manner.
The term Renaissance stands for a period in European history spanning from the middle of the
14th century to the beginning of the 17th century. By 15th century the original Greek works were
read and appreciated. Thinkers have also read critically appreciated and St. Thomas‟
interpretations of Aristotle. The recovery of the classical languages, literature, art, history and
philosophical insights resulted in the revival of the spirit of Greek humanism, which considered
the recognition of the dignity and worth of human beings as central. Humanism acknowledges
the power of human reason to know the truths of nature and conceives humans as having the
capacity to determine, express, and achieve what is good for us.
The Idea of the Good remained a core concern of the Greek civilization. The participation in the
life of the city-states and the social and the political life that existed during that period
determined the conception of the Good held by the Greeks. An entirely different conception of
the good was prevalent during the Middle Ages, where to live according to the dictums of the
Church was considered as primordial.
Renaissance, on the other hand, as we have seen above, consists in the revival of the ancient
wisdom and humanistic spirit. It aimed at restoring to man the capacities, strengths and powers
of the individual person which the middle ages had ignored. It has recognized the dignity of man
in terms of his individual achievements, and not necessarily in terms of his divine allegiance.
The Renaissance thus considered the culture of the ancient world as superior to the present one
and had looked ahead to a new mode of life.
This period was also marked with the rise of modern science. Copernicus, Kepler, Galileo and
Newton were the pre-eminent scientists of this era. Copernicus‟ heliocentric view of the universe
has overthrown existing paradigms and Kepler came up with mathematical interpretations of the
heliocentric view. Galileo developed the observation method with mathematical interpretations
to new heights and with the emergence of modern science, the belief/faith-based world views
were increasingly replaced by the reason-based scientific outlook. Copernicus and Galileo
brought together the two important elements of scientific method: the empirical method that
emphasizes on observation and experiment and the rational approach that uses the principle
behind the mathematical deductive reasoning.
Though Renaissance was a period that witnessed intense developments in many fields, it was not
a very rich period for philosophy. This period had witnessed a revived study of Plato, over
Aristotle. As Russell observes, Renaissance encouraged the habit of regarding intellectual
activity as a delightful social adventure, not a cloistered meditation aiming at the preservation of
a predetermined orthodoxy [A History of western Philosophy]
One major development happened during this period was the challenge Saint Thomas's
interpretation of Aristotle faced from different quarters. Aristotle was studied with more
emphasis on secular and scientific aspects, independent of the dominant Scholastic
interpretations. Platonism, Stoicism, Epicurianism and Skepticism were also reintroduced during
this period. The authority of both the Roman Catholic Church and the Holy Roman Empire
began to decline during this time and it encouraged having a new look at the philosophical
issues, ancient philosophy texts and approaches. As T.Z.Lavine observes:
With the coming of the Renaissance there occurs an expression of a humanistic faith in man, in
his power to direct his life and the life of his society toward freedom and justice, together with
the sense that this power, which had been a possession of the individual in the ancient Greek
world, had been lost in the world of medieval Christendom. [From Socrates to Sartre: The
Philosophical Quest.]
Cultural Impact
Art and literature played a crucial role in forming the cultural and intellectual environment of
this era. It was during this time both art and literature became independent of religious dogmas
and mythology and artists exhibited the courage in portraying human glory and not just suffering
and death as it used to be earlier. In other words, art and literature turned away from Christian
themes to nature as it is seen and perceived by man. Nature became an interesting object of study
and had been conceived not just as an expression of the supernatural. The human body has also
become an object of artistic imagination as a result of the overcoming of the body-negativism
that dominated European culture since the time of Plato and became strong during the middle
ages.
This was also an age of scientific and other discoveries that enabled man‟s understanding the
world with having better control over it. There were many new inventions and discoveries that
enabled men to dominate nature, which also include other people in far away continents. The
discovery of the New World by Columbus is an example. Along with such developments in the
scientific, economic and political realms, Europe also witnessed the rise and growth of the
Protestant reformation of Christian religion, sphereheaded by Martin Luther.
The philosophical temperament of this age was thus characterised by the scientific temper,
humanism and skepticism. It was predominantly concerned with epistemological questions,
which dealt with the sources, kinds and limits of human knowledge. In the ethical domain, it
sought to discover the criteria and the possibility of moral life without religious principles. The
modern age was thus characterised by an awakening of the reflective spirit and the critical
approaches that doubted and questioned all forms of authority particularly the authority of
tradition. It was visibly against absolutism and collectivism and asserted the importance of
freedom in thought, feeling and action.
In the political realm, states increasingly took the place of the Church and have moved more
towards constitutionalism and the creation of more and more democratic institutions. Another
important feature of this age was the emergence of individualism and an associated ideal of
liberalism. Modern philosophy has emerged in such a social and political environment.
Modern Philosophy
The most important feature of modern philosophy is the emergence of reason as the sole arbiter
in matters of knowledge and life. It becomes the only authority in philosophy and science and
consequently the concept of truth was associated with the notion of scientific observation. Truth
needs to be achieved through free and impartial inquiry and in this context theology, which
considers revealed knowledge as paramount lost its importance. This age emphasized the
practical applicability of knowledge.
In many respects, modern philosophy resembles ancient Greek thought. Like the latter modern
philosophy too emphasized on an independent search for truth and was thoroughly rationalistic,
as it considered human reason is the highest authority. It was naturalistic, as it attempted
explaining the inner and outer nature without supernatural presuppositions. It was scientific, as it
has very close ties with the new sciences that were emerging [Frank Thilly]
Modern Philosophy has also witnessed the emergence of two important epistemological schools
of thought—rationalism and Empiricism—as independent and opposing schools of philosophy.
The impact of modern scientific understanding on philosophy was quite visible, as both these
schools were preoccupied with the question of rational genuine knowledge. With these two
schools, philosophy regained its lost status as a foundational discipline. They have conceived and
equated philosophy with epistemology.
With its focus shifting to epistemology, philosophy's objectives too had changed. It now no
longer deals with the question of ultimate reality, as the ancient and medieval thinkers were
doing. According to these thinkers, philosophy deals with knowledge in a peculiar manner.
While scientific disciplines are concerned with knowledge of a particular aspect or domain of the
universe, philosophy deals with knowledge as such. Hence it is concerned with the nature, kinds,
limitations and sources of knowledge.
Empiricism, on the other hand, considers sense perception as the fundamental source of all
knowledge, they intend to show that there are no inborn or innate truths and there are no
propositions that yield necessary or absolute knowledge. John Locke (1632-1704), for instance,
who is the founder of the British empiricist school, vehemently opposes the conception of innate
ideas and asserts that all knowledge starts with experience. He claims that the human mind is a
tabula rasa or an empty cabinet in the beginning and it is experience that will start writing on it.
Both rationalism and empiricism affirm that reason is a faculty of the mind through which truths
about reality are known. With regard to the question of the source of knowledge they disagree.
But neither of them affirms that all knowledge comes from sense experience. Even the
empiricists acknowledge that there is some knowledge that does not derive from experience.
Though the dominant philosophical schools in the modern age were rationalism and empiricism,
other tendencies were also prevalent during this age. With the radical empiricist philosophy
of David Hume, skepticism became prominent. Mysticism was another trend which dominated
this age. The Catholic scholars preserved the Scholastic philosophy.
It will be interesting to have an account of the development of philosophy from the Greek golden
age to the modern period. The decline of the Greek-Roman civilization was actually a decline of
freethinking. As we have seen in a previous chapter, the emergence of the Christian Church as
the highest authority that controls culture happened during the middle ages which are also called
the dark ages.
Books
1. Copleston, Frederick, A History of Philosophy, vol.1: Greece and Rome, New York, Image
Books, 1993.
2. Durant, Will, A Story of Philosophy: The Lives and Opinions of the Greater Philosophers of
the Western World, Pocket Books, 1991.
3. Rogers, Arthur Keyon, A Student‟s History of Philosophy, New York, The Macmillan
Company, 1935.
6. Zeller, Eduard, A History of Greek Philosophy, London, Longmans, green and Co., 1881.
Web Resources
1. http://wps.ablongman.com/long_stearns_wc_4/17/4389/1123706.cw/index.html
2. http://www.historyofmacedonia.org/AncientMacedonia/greeklie4.html
3. http://www.utm.edu/staff/jfieser/class/110/7-rationalism.htm
Contents
1.0. Introduction
2.0. Intended Learning Outcomes (ILOs)
3.5. Ethics
4.0. Conclusion
5.0. Summary
2.0 Introduction
on a firm foundation led him into creating a problem of dualism. In this unit, we
shall consider Benedict Spinoza, another rationalist, and how he solved the problem
of dualism that was started by Descartes as well as his idea on the source and nature
of knowledge.
4. Discus his metaphysics vis-à-vis the notion of substance and God as different
from Descartes
Baruch Spinoza (or Espinosa) was born in Amsterdam in 1632. He was among
expulsion from the Synagogue of Amsterdam for his unorthodox views. His refusal
to accept the chair of philosophy at Heidelberg was further evidence of his desire to
preserve his freedom to pursue his ideas wherever the search for truth might lead
him. Though he was content to live in simplicity, to earn a modest living grinding
lenses, his fame as a thinker spread abroad and inspired both admiration and
Jews who had fled from persecution in Spain. He was trained in the study of the Old
Testament and the Talmud and was familiar with the writings of the Jewish
where he carried on his literary career, of which his Ethics is the crowning work.
In other words, Spinoza believes that the fabric of the universe is woven from the
warp and woof of logical necessity. “In Nature there is nothing contingent, but all
things are determined from the necessity of the divine nature to exist and act in a
certain manner” (Lawhead, 2015: 265). Why, then, do some events seem contingent
to us? Spinoza replies that “a thing cannot be called contingent unless with reference
to a deficiency in our knowledge.” When we fail to see that everything is necessary,
it is “because the order of causes is concealed from us” (qtd in Lawhead 2005: 265).
Hence, while we can deduce some truths apriori, only someone with the exhaustive
knowledge of the divine mind could deduce the existence and behavior of any
particular thing. The important point is that all truths are capable of demonstration,
Spinoza holds that all human ideas fall into three categories, which range from
the most inadequate and confused to the highest possible level of human knowledge.
1. Opinion or imagination: This is the source of inadequate ideas and false beliefs.
The most inadequate form of information is mere secondhand opinion (for example,
my belief that I was born on such and such a day). It also includes perception arising
from signs, such as the ideas and images I get from hearing or reading certain words.
The most common form of this low-grade cognition is what I receive from vague
experience.
2. Reason: This is the second level of cognition. Reason goes beyond fleeting sense
experience and searches out the underlying chain of reasons or causes that make
something what it is. it is of the nature of reason to perceive things under a certain
form of eternity
3. Intuition: The third and highest level of knowledge is intuition. Spinoza is not as
clear about this as we would like, for he describes its beneficial effects more than he
does its nature. It is best seen as an integrated vision of the whole that arises out of
the level of reason (Lawhead, 2015: 264-265).
Spinoza‟s metaphysics revolves around his position that there is only one
substance, "God or Nature" (Russell, 1945: 571). Spinoza offered a strikingly unique
conception of God, in which he identified God with the whole cosmos, a view that
we now call pantheism. His famous formula was "God or Nature" (Deus sive Natura),
as if to say that these two words are interchangeable (Stumpf and Fieser, 2012: 216).
The clue to Spinoza's unique conception of God is found in his definition: God I
attributes, each of which expresses eternal and infinite essence (Stumpf and Fieser,
2012: 216). Spinoza's special thoughts revolve around the ideas of substance and its
attributes and for him, there is only one single substance with infinite attributes.
attributes, God thus possesses an infinite number of aspects to his essence. However,
as we examine God from our limited human perspective, we can comprehend only
two attributes of God's substance: thought and extension, that is, God's mind and
God's body. Descartes thought that these two attributes showed the existence of two
distinct substances, thereby leading him to affirm the dualism of mind and body.
Spinoza, though, saw these two attributes as different ways of expressing the activity
infinite extension. Being infinite, God contains everything (Stumpf and Fieser,2012:
which is in itself and is conceived through itself: I mean that the conception of which
does not depend on the conception of another thing from which it must be formed."
There is no such thing as free will in the mental sphere or chance in the physical
is logically impossible that events should be other than they are (Russell, 1945: 571).
If God is infinite, Spinoza reasoned, it must follow that there cannot be anything that
is not God. If you discover something in the universe that is not God, then God can‟t
be infinite, because God could have in principle been that thing as well as everything
else. We are all parts of God, but so are stones, ants, blades of grass, and windows.
All of it. It all fits together into an incredibly complex whole, but ultimately
everything that exists is part of this one thing: God (Warburton, 1962: 78).
3.5. Ethics
integral part of nature. His point is that human behavior can be explained just as
phenomenon. Spinoza argued for the unity of all Nature, with people as an intrinsic
part of it, he develops a naturalistic ethics whereby all human actions, both mental
and physical, are said to be determined by prior causes. All people possess as a part
of their nature the drive to continue or persist in their own being, and this drive
Spinoza calls conatus, that is, innate striving. When this conatus refers to the mind
and body; it is called appetite, and insofar as appetite is conscious, it is called desire.
As we become conscious of higher degrees of self-preservation and perfection, we
Our ideas of good and evil are related to our conceptions of pleasure and pain. He
cautions that we must study not only our emotions but the whole order of Nature,
for is only from the perspective of eternity that we can really understand our own
particular lives, for then we see all events through the idea of God as cause ((Stumpf
and Fieser, 2012: 220-221). According to him, Passions enslave us only when we
lack knowledge.
Contrary to Descartes‟s dualism, Spinoza replies that “the mind and the body
are one and the same thing, conceived at one time under the attribute of thought, and
at another under that of extension (Lawhead, 2015: 269). Spinoza‟s solution to the
problem of mind and body is ingenious, though complex to assimilate. The mind and
the body are one and the same thing, which is conceived now under the attribute of
thought, now under the attribute of extension.‟ The theory of the attributes implies
not only that the one substance can be known in two ways, but that the same two
4.0 Conclusion
In this unit, we have discussed that Spinoza accepted pantheism where he sees
God and nature as opposites sides of the same coin. For him, everything is a
manifestation of God, hence, all things are determined from the necessity of the
divine nature to exist and act in a certain manner. We have also noticed in his thought,
2. There are three levels of cognition and the highest level is intuition.
3. All things are determined from the necessity of the divine nature to exist and
4. The mind and the body and one and the same thing.
Self-Assessment Exercise
How would Spinoza respond to Descartes‟s view that the mind and body are
completely separate?
1.0. Introduction
4.0. Conclusion
5.0. Summary
1.0 Introduction
Dissatisfied with the thoughts of Descartes and Spinoza, Leibniz came up with his
theory of deterministic monism. In this unit, we shall discuss his notion of substance
his solution to the mind-body dichotomy of Descartes and also his theory of
knowledge.
Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz was born in 1646 in Leipzig, Germany. His father
considered an intellectual genius. As a young boy, he learned to read the Greek and
Latin classics in their original languages. At the age fifteen, Leibniz was admitted
into the University of Leipzig and graduated at age seventeen. After a brief stint at
law. However, academic politics intervened and a committee of faculty and students
voted against giving him a doctorate, a situation which been attributed to his young
age. This painful experience drove him to the University of Altdorf, near Nuremberg,
where he was readily accepted (Lawhead, 2015: 277-278). At the completion of his
dissertation there, he not only received his doctoral degree in law at twenty-one years
of age, but was also offered a professorship. Although Leibniz had enjoyed a fruitful
public life, his popularity declined at the end of his life and he died in obscurity in
1716 at the age of seventy (Minimah, 2016: 104). His major works are Discourse on
Leibniz was not satisfied with Descartes and Spinoza‟s description of the
nature of substance, because for him, their view of substance affects our
understanding of human nature, the nature of freedom, and God. He considered the
explanations inadequate and sets out to offer a more useful explanation. Whether he
succeeded or not is a case for philosophical ratiocination. But first, what does he
think of substance?
extended in space and is not divisible into something more primary. For Spinoza,
substances called monads (Essien, 2011: 205). Monads are simple substances, but
unlike the atoms of Democritus and Epicurus which were inert and only derive their
dynamic force capable of action. Every individual monad is different from the others,
and possesses its own force which is the principle of action. For Leibniz, substance
monads interacts in nature. For him, the fact that underlies the appearance of
universal interaction between finite substances is that the total state of each monad
at each moment is infinitely complex and each different factor in it represents the
contemporary total state of a different one of the remaining monads (Essien, 2011:
216). In other words, every organism possesses a „dominant monad‟, distinct by the
clarity of its perceptions of all the others; and this dominant monad is the source of
the unity within the organism (Scruton, 1984: 73). This means that the universe is
knowledge. Leibniz believes that some ideas (such as those we find in logic and
mathematics) could not be derived from the senses. He argues for the weakness of
sense experience to lead us to truths that are certain and necessary. Leibniz claims
that if some items of our knowledge possess these qualities of necessity and certainty,
then they must be innate ideas that the mind discovers within itself (Lawhead, 2015:
279).
Leibniz distinguished between truths of reason and truths of fact. According to him,
truths of reasoning are necessary and their opposite is impossible. Because they are
knowable only by reason, Leibniz says that they are necessary, analytic and selfevident
When truth is necessary, the reason for it can be found by analysis, that is by
resolving it into simpler ideas and truths until the primary ones are reached. It
is in this way that mathematics, speculative theorems and practical canons are
Truths of reason, therefore are tautologies such that they cannot be denied
without one getting into self-contradiction. These truths need no empirical proof.
For instance, the assertion “A bachelor is an unmarried man” is a truth of reason and
truth of reason, therefore, is a necessary truth because the very meaning of the terms
used and the type of human understanding require that certain things be true (Stumpf
and Fieser, 2012: 228). If the truth of reason are necessary truths, truths of facts,
therefore, are contingent truth and can be denied without one engaging in self85
contradiction. Truth of facts are not known apriori but aposteriori, and unlike the
two ways by which we derive knowledge from facts. These are perception and
consciousness or the internal workings of the mind on the data. Through this
reflective acts, the principal objects of our reasoning is being furnished (Copleston,
1994: 312). To derive knowledge from truth of fact, therefore, calls for our synthetic
faculty.
4.0 Conclusion
Our investigation into Descartes, Spinoza and Leibniz (the rationalists) reveal
that knowledge is based on the rational capacity of human minds to arrive at certain
systems of truths which are innate in them. Though they all believe in reason as the
source of knowledge, they however, differ as to what constitute the nature of reality.
For Leibniz, reality consists of just one substance. This means that among the
5.0 Summary
monads.
Every individual monad is different from the others, and possesses its own force
Self-Assessment Exercise
Lulu press.
Hackett publishing.
Thomas Hobbes
Contents
1.0. Introduction
3.3. Metaphysics
3.4. Ethics
4.0. Conclusion
5.0. Summary
1.0. Introduction
546). He belongs to the empiricist tradition. However, unlike other empiricists like
more relevant in his political philosophy important ideas which, of course, is the
centerpiece of his philosophical endeavor. In this unit, you shall be learning about
some of his important ideas, not limited to his view on empiricism as a method, but
theory.
was brought up by his uncle when the father finally lost his job. Hobbes acquired a
good knowledge of classics at a tender age, and at just fourteen, he translated the
ancient classic of Euripides, The Medea, into Latin. Hobbes attended Oxford
university at age fifteen. He would later confess that he profited little in his years at
Oxford, in 1610, aged twenty-two years old, he became a personal tutor to Lord
him into the philosophical and scientific circles. In 1636, Hobbes travelled to Italy
Following the build-up to the Civil War in England in 1640, Hobbes feared
that his safety was not guaranteed in England because of his royalist convictions, so
he travelled to Paris. While in France, he served as the tutor to the Prince of Wales
was in exile. He returned to England after the Restoration and made peace with the
commonwealth in 1652. Hobbes died in the winter of 1679 aged Ninety-one years.
His major works are, The Elements of Law, Natural and politic (1640), Leviathan
In the introduction, you learnt that Hobbes belongs to the empiricist, but he
admired the way of mathematics. Thomas Hobbes assumed that empirical facts
correspond to geometric axioms, or that the axioms that the mind formulates
195). As an empiricist, Hobbes begins his philosophy with the given, with senseimpressions
Hobbes divided knowledge into two kinds. The first is knowledge of facts and
the second is the knowledge of consequence. Knowledge of fact is when one sees
effects, example, if A is true, then B will be true. Hobbes maintained that knowledge
who maintains that philosophy only takes account of bodies. For him, authentic
3.3. Metaphysics
causes. But what does Hobbes mean by causes? A cause, for him, is the sum or
And by causal explanation, Hobbes has in mind, an account of the generative process
by which some effect comes into being (Coplestone, 1994: 5). This implies that
whatever that fails to come into existence through generative process cannot be part
For him, therefore, metaphysics is concerned with the causes and properties
of bodies. However, all motions, according to him, is determined, which also follows
that human actions and behaviours are determined. But how does Hobbes account
for our internal actions? He accounts for it by maintaining that motions are of two
kinds; vital and voluntary motions. Vital motions are such automatic activities as the
circulation of blood, breathing, digestion etc. while voluntary motions are the aspects
of our behaviours that show freewill (Lawhead, 2002: 220). Voluntary motions
begin with our individual endeavours such as desire or aversion. Hobbes‟ vital
motions have no problems at all, but the problem rests on the voluntary motions. He
maintains that voluntary motions correlate with our experiences either as pleasurable
or painful. However, if we take Hobbes materialism too far, the result will be the
3.4. Ethics
Hobbes‟ moral philosophy is enshrined in his theory of motion and also in his
political philosophy. According to Asukwo (2016: 39), his moral and ethical
political society; it is also in line with the law of nature, which is the natural law.
Hobbes conceived of the goal of morality as justice in the society. Justice for him,
anything destructive to our life and consequently a law of nature” (Hobbes, 1988:
374).
Hobbes contended that the society rules are ordered by natural law, the law of
reason, which also governs the state. He ascribed “good” to the object of desire,
whereas evil is the object of aversion. Hence, like the Epicureans, he conceived of
good and evil as terms derived from pleasure and pain (Lawhead, 2002: 220).
However, since good and evil are subjective, Hobbes believes that we are guided by
and psychological egoism. On the critical perspective, Hobbes sees good as what
gives an individual pleasure. The implication of this is that morality. But how can
we can control people‟s pleasure in the face of subjectivity? This became the central
task of his political thought which we shall explore in the next section.
3.5. Socio-Political Philosophy
following the civil war of 1642. From this experience, he came to the conclusion
that chaos is inevitable where there is no stable government to prevent it. He also
believes that for any government to control chaos, it must possess an absolute power.
With these conclusions, Hobbes set out to solve the problem of political society
where, as exemplified in his moral theory, he presents the political states also as
moving bodies.
Thomas Hobbes political theory is also his theory of social contract. Hobbes
began with a hypothetical position of men before the formation of the civil state.
According to him, people had lived in a natural state or state of nature prior to the
formation of a civil state. The word, right, in the bare state of nature is a person's
freedom "to do what he would, and against whom he thought fit, and to possess, use
and enjoy all that he would, or could get." The driving force in a person is the will
to survive, and the psychological attitude pervading all people is fear—the fear of
death, and particularly violent death. In the state of nature all people are relentlessly
pursuing whatever acts they think will secure their safety. The picture we get of this
state of nature is of people moving against each other, bodies in motion, or the
anarchic condition Hobbes called the war of all against all (Stumpf and Fieser, 2012:
200).
twofold drive, namely; appetite and aversion. These two drives account for our
motions to and from other people or objects, and they have the same meanings as
the words love and hate. People are attracted to what they think will help them
survive, and they hate whatever they judge to be a threat to them. The words good
and evil have whatever meaning each individual gives them, and people call good
whatever they love and evil whatever they hate, there being nothing simply and
with our own survival, and we identify goodness with our own appetites. It would
appear; therefore, that in the state of nature there is no obligation for people to
respect others and there is no morality in the traditional sense of goodness and justice
In the state of nature, there was no government and no laws to guide the
activities of people. However, there was a law of nature or the natural law which
directed man to choose between good and evil. Recall that in his moral theory
Hobbes had suggested that we are guided by subjective pursuit of pleasure. Because
of this, there was bound to be crises in the state of nature. Hence, he presents the
state of nature as a state of chaos. Because of this, the condition life in the state of
nature was poor, solitary, nasty, brutish and short. People became wolves unto
themselves and everyone lived in a state of perpetual fear because even the strongest
However, the natural law, which is the law of reason suggested to people that
they should create for themselves a fearful being (The Leviathan) and hand over all
their power to it. This being will then control the people, wielding all the powers to
punish, protect and adjudicate laws. This is how the civil state came into existence.
For Locke, the state is more powerful than the individual and exist to control the
affairs of people. For the state to be able to perform its function, Hobbes advocates
for an absolute state. Hence, the objective morality of the state supersedes the
4.0. Conclusion
In the introduction, you learnt that Thomas Hobbes belong to the empiricist
that empirical facts correspond to geometric axioms, or that the axioms that the mind
(Essien, 2011: 195). As an empiricist, Hobbes began his philosophy with the given,
5.0. Summary
1. Hobbes begins his philosophy with the given, with sense-impressions made
2. He divided knowledge into two kinds. The first is knowledge of facts and the
books. Pp 289-303
Lulu press.
Answer: Knowledge of fact is when one sees something done or remember seeing
be true.
Thomas Hobbes
Contents
1.0. Introduction
3.3. Metaphysics
3.4. Ethics
4.0. Conclusion
5.0. Summary
1.0. Introduction
546). He belongs to the empiricist tradition. However, unlike other empiricists like
more relevant in his political philosophy important ideas which, of course, is the
centerpiece of his philosophical endeavor. In this unit, you shall be learning about
some of his important ideas, not limited to his view on empiricism as a method, but
theory.
was brought up by his uncle when the father finally lost his job. Hobbes acquired a
good knowledge of classics at a tender age, and at just fourteen, he translated the
ancient classic of Euripides, The Medea, into Latin. Hobbes attended Oxford
university at age fifteen. He would later confess that he profited little in his years at
Oxford, in 1610, aged twenty-two years old, he became a personal tutor to Lord
him into the philosophical and scientific circles. In 1636, Hobbes travelled to Italy
Following the build-up to the Civil War in England in 1640, Hobbes feared
that his safety was not guaranteed in England because of his royalist convictions, so
he travelled to Paris. While in France, he served as the tutor to the Prince of Wales
was in exile. He returned to England after the Restoration and made peace with the
commonwealth in 1652. Hobbes died in the winter of 1679 aged Ninety-one years.
His major works are, The Elements of Law, Natural and politic (1640), Leviathan
(1651), Form and power of Commonwealth (1651), De Corpore (1655), De Homine
In the introduction, you learnt that Hobbes belongs to the empiricist, but he
admired the way of mathematics. Thomas Hobbes assumed that empirical facts
correspond to geometric axioms, or that the axioms that the mind formulates
195). As an empiricist, Hobbes begins his philosophy with the given, with senseimpressions
Hobbes divided knowledge into two kinds. The first is knowledge of facts and
the second is the knowledge of consequence. Knowledge of fact is when one sees
effects, example, if A is true, then B will be true. Hobbes maintained that knowledge
a philosopher, who, according to him, only pretends to reason (Coplestone, 1994: 4).
who maintains that philosophy only takes account of bodies. For him, authentic
3.3. Metaphysics
causes. But what does Hobbes mean by causes? A cause, for him, is the sum or
And by causal explanation, Hobbes has in mind, an account of the generative process
by which some effect comes into being (Coplestone, 1994: 5). This implies that
whatever that fails to come into existence through generative process cannot be part
For him, therefore, metaphysics is concerned with the causes and properties
of bodies. However, all motions, according to him, is determined, which also follows
that human actions and behaviours are determined. But how does Hobbes account
for our internal actions? He accounts for it by maintaining that motions are of two
kinds; vital and voluntary motions. Vital motions are such automatic activities as the
circulation of blood, breathing, digestion etc. while voluntary motions are the aspects
of our behaviours that show freewill (Lawhead, 2002: 220). Voluntary motions
begin with our individual endeavours such as desire or aversion. Hobbes‟ vital
motions have no problems at all, but the problem rests on the voluntary motions. He
maintains that voluntary motions correlate with our experiences either as pleasurable
or painful. However, if we take Hobbes materialism too far, the result will be the
mechanical outcome of forces acting on every reality.
3.4. Ethics
Hobbes‟ moral philosophy is enshrined in his theory of motion and also in his
political philosophy. According to Asukwo (2016: 39), his moral and ethical
political society; it is also in line with the law of nature, which is the natural law.
Hobbes conceived of the goal of morality as justice in the society. Justice for him,
anything destructive to our life and consequently a law of nature” (Hobbes, 1988:
374).
Hobbes contended that the society rules are ordered by natural law, the law of
reason, which also governs the state. He ascribed “good” to the object of desire,
whereas evil is the object of aversion. Hence, like the Epicureans, he conceived of
good and evil as terms derived from pleasure and pain (Lawhead, 2002: 220).
However, since good and evil are subjective, Hobbes believes that we are guided by
and psychological egoism. On the critical perspective, Hobbes sees good as what
gives an individual pleasure. The implication of this is that morality. But how can
we can control people‟s pleasure in the face of subjectivity? This became the central
task of his political thought which we shall explore in the next section.
following the civil war of 1642. From this experience, he came to the conclusion
that chaos is inevitable where there is no stable government to prevent it. He also
believes that for any government to control chaos, it must possess an absolute power.
With these conclusions, Hobbes set out to solve the problem of political society
where, as exemplified in his moral theory, he presents the political states also as
moving bodies.
Thomas Hobbes political theory is also his theory of social contract. Hobbes
began with a hypothetical position of men before the formation of the civil state.
According to him, people had lived in a natural state or state of nature prior to the
formation of a civil state. The word, right, in the bare state of nature is a person's
freedom "to do what he would, and against whom he thought fit, and to possess, use
and enjoy all that he would, or could get." The driving force in a person is the will
to survive, and the psychological attitude pervading all people is fear—the fear of
death, and particularly violent death. In the state of nature all people are relentlessly
pursuing whatever acts they think will secure their safety. The picture we get of this
state of nature is of people moving against each other, bodies in motion, or the
anarchic condition Hobbes called the war of all against all (Stumpf and Fieser, 2012:
200).
twofold drive, namely; appetite and aversion. These two drives account for our
motions to and from other people or objects, and they have the same meanings as
the words love and hate. People are attracted to what they think will help them
survive, and they hate whatever they judge to be a threat to them. The words good
and evil have whatever meaning each individual gives them, and people call good
whatever they love and evil whatever they hate, there being nothing simply and
with our own survival, and we identify goodness with our own appetites. It would
appear; therefore, that in the state of nature there is no obligation for people to
respect others and there is no morality in the traditional sense of goodness and justice
In the state of nature, there was no government and no laws to guide the
activities of people. However, there was a law of nature or the natural law which
directed man to choose between good and evil. Recall that in his moral theory
Hobbes had suggested that we are guided by subjective pursuit of pleasure. Because
of this, there was bound to be crises in the state of nature. Hence, he presents the
state of nature as a state of chaos. Because of this, the condition life in the state of
nature was poor, solitary, nasty, brutish and short. People became wolves unto
themselves and everyone lived in a state of perpetual fear because even the strongest
However, the natural law, which is the law of reason suggested to people that
they should create for themselves a fearful being (The Leviathan) and hand over all
their power to it. This being will then control the people, wielding all the powers to
punish, protect and adjudicate laws. This is how the civil state came into existence.
For Locke, the state is more powerful than the individual and exist to control the
affairs of people. For the state to be able to perform its function, Hobbes advocates
for an absolute state. Hence, the objective morality of the state supersedes the
4.0. Conclusion
In the introduction, you learnt that Thomas Hobbes belong to the empiricist
that empirical facts correspond to geometric axioms, or that the axioms that the mind
(Essien, 2011: 195). As an empiricist, Hobbes began his philosophy with the given,
5.0. Summary
1. Hobbes begins his philosophy with the given, with sense-impressions made
2. He divided knowledge into two kinds. The first is knowledge of facts and the
Self-Assessment Exercise
books. Pp 289-303
Lulu press.
Answer: Knowledge of fact is when one sees something done or remember seeing
be true.
George Berkeley
Contents
1.0. Introduction
4.0. Conclusion
5.0. Summary
1.0. Introduction
In unit 3, you learnt about the empiricism of Locke and how he limits the data
of knowledge to ideas. Locke sees substance as the objects of our ideas. In this unit,
you shall be introduced into the thought of George Berkeley and how it led to
idealism. You shall also learn about his conception of matter and substance and the
2. Discuss his notion matter and substance and how it differs from that of Locke.
philosophy. He became a Fellow of the College a few years after he earned his B.A.
degree and was also ordained a clergyman in the Church of England, becoming a
bishop in 1734. George Berkeley died in 1753 and was buried in Christ Church
Chapel in Oxford. His major works includes, Essay Towards a New Theory of
him, "to be is to be perceived." Clearly, this would mean that if something were not
combinations of 'sensations or ideas' and draws the conclusion that they 'cannot exist
otherwise than in a mind perceiving them'. In his New Theory of Vision, he argues
that all our knowledge depends on actual vision and other sensory experiences. In
particular, he argues that we never sense space or magnitude; we only have different
According to him, all that we ever see are the qualities of an object that our faculty
of vision is capable of sensing (Stumpf and Fieser, 240). We do not see the closeness
from it. The more Berkeley considered the workings of his own mind and wondered
how his ideas were related to objects outside of his mind, the more certain he was
that he could never discover any object independent of his ideas (Stumpf and Fieser,
240).
Berkeley denies the independent existence of things other than that which is
sensible thing or body that it exists is to say that it is perceived or perceivable: in his
opinion, there is nothing else that it can mean. This analysis, he maintains, does not
affect the reality of things. 'Existence is percipi or percipere (Coplestone, 1994: 219).
If, then, I try to describe or interpret reality in terms of my experience, I first come
to the conclusion that there are other people like myself who have minds. From this
it can be assumed that, just as I have ideas, other people likewise have ideas.
Apart from my finite mind and the finite minds of others, there is a greater
Mind analogous to mine, and this is God's Mind (Stumpf and Fieser, 2012: 243).
God's ideas constitute the regular order of nature. The ideas that exist in our minds
are God's ideas, which he communicates to us so that the objects or things that we
perceive in daily experience are caused not by matter or substance but by God. It is
God, too, who coordinates all experiences of finite minds, assuring regularity and
to the finite minds or spirits of people, with allowance made for the differences in
competence between the divine and finite minds. The ultimate reality, then, is
spiritual (God) and not material, and the continued existence of objects when we are
not perceiving them is explained by God's continuous perception of them (Stumpf
Berkeley claims that every individual mind exist exterior to other minds. And
so also, human minds are diverted from things. There is therefore some other mind
wherein they exist, during the intervals between the time of our perceiving them.
And because all human minds are intermittently diverted from things, "there is an
omnipresent eternal Mind, which knows and comprehends all things, and exhibits
them to our view in such a manner and according to such rules as he himself has
ordained, and are by us termed the Laws of Nature" (Stumpf and Fieser, 2012: 243).
Berkeley, therefore, concluded that the existence of things depends on the existence
4.0. Conclusion
is either an idea in the mind or perceiving mind. This is an idealist position, which
5.0. Summary
Self-Assessment Exercise
Answer: Berkeley's argument for the existence of God is that all human minds are
which knows and comprehends all things, and exhibits them to our view in such a
manner and according to such rules as he himself has ordained, and are by us termed
the Laws of Nature. The existence of things, therefore, depends on the existence of
Contents
1.0. Introduction
3.5. Ethics
4.0. Conclusion
5.0. Summary
1.0. Introduction
Locke and Berkeley, purged them from the lingering metaphysics in their thought,
and gave empiricism its clearest and most rigorous formulation. In fact, he has been
described as the most consistent of the British empiricists. In his skepticism, Hume
denied the idea of substance and causality for lack of impressions producing them.
In this unit, therefore, you shall be learning about the skepticism of Hume. We shall
discuss his theory of knowledge, view on causality and also his denial of
metaphysical realities.
2.0. Intended Learning Outcomes (ILOs)
David Hume was born in 1711 in Edinburgh, Scotland, into a Calvinist family
assistant to the English ambassador. His reputation as a historian and man of letters
preceded him, and his three years in France were spent living the life of a celebrity
and being the idol of all the leading social circles. He lived out the last years of his
life in his hometown of Edinburgh where he was the leading light in Scottish
intellectual and literary circles. Hume died in 1776. His major works are, A Treatise
Knowledge
According to Hume, the difference between an impression and an idea is only the
see, feel, love, hate, desire, or will. These impressions are "lively” and clear when
we have them. When we reflect on these impressions, we have ideas of them, and
those ideas are less lively versions of the original impressions. To feel pain is an
impressions and their corresponding ideas are alike, differing only in their degree of
vividness with which they strike upon the mind and make their way into our thoughts
simply a copy of an impression, it means for every idea there must be a prior
corresponding impression, for instance when we talk about a flying horse or a golden
mountain even though we have ideas of them. But Hume explains such ideas as
Hume argues that it is not by mere chance that our ideas are related to each
other. There must be, Hume says, some bond of union, some associating quality; by
which one idea naturally introduces another. His explanation was that, whenever
there are certain qualities in ideas, these ideas are associated with each other (Stumpf
and Fieser 247). These qualities are, resemblance, contiguity in time or place, and
cause and effect. As resemblance, Hume says that when we see a picture, our
attention is often drawn to the original. Contiguity with time or place has to do with
an idea that a part indicates a whole, like when we mention a room and someone
thinks about other parts and the building as a whole. Finally, the quality of cause and
effects has to do with succession of events, where when one event is preceded by
another.
3.4. On Causality
Hume's most original and influential ideas deal with the problem of causality
(Stumpf and Fieser, 2012: 247). For Hume the very idea of causality cannot be
proven. But Hume intend to investigate it a little, so he asked "What is the origin of
the idea of causality?" Since ideas are copies of impressions, Hume asks what
impression gives us the idea of causality. His answer is that there is no impression
corresponding to this idea. How, then, does the idea of causality arise in the mind?
His response is that the idea of causality is a wrong idea that has no corresponding
impressions but only arises in the mind when we experience certain relations
between objects. For him, when we speak of cause and effect, we mean to say that
A Causes B. But what kind of a relation does this show between A and B? in his
response, Hume claims that in our experience, we are being furnished by two
relations, namely, (1) contiguity, for A and B are always close together, and (2)
priority in time, where event A (cause) always precedes B, the effect. But how do
we tell if at very point A happens that B will follow? Hume argued that there is no
contiguity in space and priority in time, we do not have any impression of necessary
connection. Thus, causality is not a quality in the objects we observe but is rather a
Hume denied that substance in any form exists or has any coherent meaning.
If what is meant by the self is some form of substance, Hume argued that no such
substance can be derived from our impressions of sensation (Stumpf and Fieser, 249).
Hume, therefore, submit that notions like substance, reality, mind, matter, etc, are
metaphysicians seek to answer, like what is the nature of reality, what is the cause
of the world, what is the relationship between matter and mind, etc, are all
terms of our empirical meaning criteria, these questions dissolve into nothingness
(Essien, 2011: 231). For him, any material containing metaphysical knowledge of
When we run over libraries, persuaded of these principles, what havoc must
for instance; let us ask: "Does it contain any abstract reasoning concerning quantity
and number? No. Does it contain any experimental reasoning concerning matters of
fact and existence? No. Commit it then to flames, for it can contain nothing but
Sophistry and illusion (Hume, 1748: 132)
Hume also denied the existence of self. He questions if we have any one
impression that is invariably associated with our idea of self. Finding none, he argues
that the human mind is a kind of theatre where several perceptions successively make
their appearance and then disappear. Hume denies the existence of a continuous selfidentity
perceptions.
Hume emphasizes that the order of the universe is simply an empirical fact
and that we cannot infer from it the existence of God. He points out that from a finite
effect you cannot conclude an infinite cause (Lawhead, 2015: 349). However, this is
4.0. Conclusion
remains unchallenged for; little wonder that his skepticism awoke Kant from his
dogmatic slumber, who responded with his critical philosophy as we shall see later
5.0. Summary
3. He denied causality.
Self-Assessment Exercise
What are the three ways in which one idea becomes associated with another
idea?
Lulu press.
Immanuel Kant
Contents
1.0. Introduction
3.5. Ethics
4.0. Conclusion
5.0. Summary
1.0 Introduction
The debate between the empiricists and the rationalists and their response to
the nature and source of human knowledge provided the ground through which the
thought of Kant flourished. While the empiricists rooted for experience as the nature
and source of human knowledge, the rationalists were of the claim that knowledge
comes from reason and that the human mind is crowned with ideas that are innate to
reconciliation between these two opposing traditions. This gave birth to a revolution
in epistemology in the same manner that Copernicus did in Astronomy. In this unit,
you will learn about Kant‟s attempt at synthesizing rationalism and empiricism.
Immanuel Kant was born in Konigsberg, East Prussia, on April 22, 1724. His
parents were Pietists, a sect of Protestants who lived severe, puritanical lives and
emphasized faith and religious feelings over reason and theological doctrines
(Lawhead, 2015: 355). Although Kant‟s later religious thought was hardly orthodox,
he was always sensitive to the longings of the heart that cannot be met by the cold
ended up becoming a professor there himself. Kant retired from public life and
lecturing in 1797. He died on February 12, 1804 after a period of illness. His major
works are, Critique of Pure Reason (1781), Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics
and rationalism. His epistemological quest, therefore, became the quest for a kind of
knowledge that is synthetic-apriori. He was able to locate synthetic or aposteriori
Therefore, to have a clear knowledge, he thought it was necessary to begin with the
“all bachelors are unmarried” is a true analytic judgment because the contradiction
of this statement is necessarily false. We can confirm the truth of this judgment not
by going out and gathering facts but merely by analyzing the meaning of the terms.
Furthermore, because the truth of this judgment is independent of any particular facts,
it does not give us any new knowledge about the world. Synthetic judgments,
however, do give us new information about the world. For example, “All the
bachelors in this class are six feet tall” is a synthetic judgment. Judgments of this
sort synthesize or bring together the subject (“bachelors in this class”) with the
predicate (“six feet tall”). It would not be a logical contradiction to deny this
Kant makes a further distinction, this time between judgments that are apriori
and judgments that are aposteriori. According to him, all analytic judgments are
apriori: Their meaning does not depend on our experience of any particular cases or
events since they are independent of any observations, as in the case of mathematics.
Synthetic judgments, on the other hand, are for the most part aposteriori, that is, they
occur after an experience of observation ((Stumpf and Fieser 276). Besides the
In the first line of the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant asserts that, “There can
be no doubt that all our knowledge begins with experience…but though all our
knowledge begins with experience, it does not follow that it all arises out of
experience.” From this position, it is evidenced that in the first part of the statement,
Kant supported empiricism, but in the second part, we also cite with the rationalists.
synthesis between these two opposing epistemological schools. Taking clue from
revolution” in epistemology. The empiricists thought that the mind is passive when
confronting the world and simply records impressions. In this picture, knowledge
picture asks us to consider the possibility that objects conform to our knowledge
(Kant, CPR Bxvi). In other words, for sense data to be experienced as objects by us,
the mind must impose a certain rational structure on them (Lawhead, 2015: 258).
This means that in the process of acquiring knowledge, it is not the human mind that
conforms to objects, instead, it is rather the objects that conform to the structure of
the human mind so that we can only know things as they appear to us. This new
Kant claims that there are two nature of reality; reality as they are in
themselves and as they appear to us. Things are they are in themselves are called
noumena while things as they appear to us are called phenomena. Kant maintain that
the noumena are beyond the scope of human knowledge while the phenomena are
the product of the human mind (Omoregbe, 1998:13). The conclusion of this is that
for Kant, we cannot know reality as they are in themselves, but only the way they
appear.
Kant maintains that there are certain aspects of reality that human
understanding could not access. Therefore, any attempt to explore these areas by our
experience” and this is certainly a misleading attempt. In other word, all objects of
understanding which are beyond the possible experience, are impossible; at least
with regard to our available abilities (Abdullah, 2008). This is due to the fact that
the noumenal world, including the concept of substance, force, action etc., has
3.4. Ethics
world, or even out of it, which can be called „good‟ without qualification, except a
good will” (Kant, 2008: 12). This implies is that, for Kant, the seat of moral worth
is in the will, and the good will is one that acts out of a sense of duty. Popkin and
Stroll (1996: 41), notes that the main question which Kant‟s moral theory was
designed to answer is: „What is the nature of morality?‟ This question, they reason,
can also be put in different ways such as: „What is a moral action as contrasted with
a non-moral one?‟ or again, „What is the difference between a person who acts
morally and one who does not? For Kant, a person is acting morally only when he
suppresses his/her feelings and inclinations, and does that which he/she is obliged to
do. Kant stresses that the essence of morality is to be found in the Will from which
the act is done. All those Wills reduced to one that a person is moral when he acts
It tells you what you ought, should, or must do, but it does not depend on any prior
(Lawhead, 2015: 372). A major test of a morally good act is, therefore, whether its
principle can be applied to all rational beings and applied consistently. Moral
philosophy is the quest for these principles that apply to all rational beings and that
lead to behavior that we call good (Stumpf and Fieser, 2012: 287).
3.5. Space and Time
A discussion on the doctrine of space and time is the most important part of
Kant‟s Critique of Pure Reason (Russell, 1945: 712). His thesis in the discourse is
that space and time are not mysterious sorts of “things” within experience but are
fundamental frames of reference in terms of which objects, which he calls the “forms
form of all appearance of outer sense. It is the necessary condition of all outer objects
as they appear to us but does not necessary underlie things as they are in themselves
(Essien, 2011: 241). Time, on the other hand is closely related to space. However,
the difference is that time is a form of intuition or perception of ourselves and our
Following from his critical remarks, Kant claims that we cannot demonstrate God's
existence, neither can we demonstrate that God does not exist by pure reason alone.
If, therefore, the existence of God cannot be effectively dealt with by the theoretical
reason, then some other aspect of reason must be considered as the source of the idea
of God (Stumpf and Fieser, 2012: 283). Kant's argument for the existence of God,
4.0 Conclusion
Kant attempted to put to rest, the struggle between rationalism and empiricism
on the source and nature of human knowledge. His thought has even been described
by some scholars as the last of man struggle with skepticism. However, it is not
without criticism. As a matter of fact, it has been argued that Kant was not successful
5.0 Summary
2. There are two natures of reality which are the noumena and the phenomena.
are unknowable
Self-Assessment Exercise
Popkin, R H. and Stroll, A. (1996). Philosophy. Third edition. Made simple books.
Lulu press
Wilder Publications.
Answer: In Kant's ethics, the essence of morality is to be found in the motive from
which the act is done. All those motives reduced to one that a person is moral when
German Idealism
German Idealism German Idealism is a philosophical movement centered in Germany during the
Age of Enlightenment of the late 18th and early 19th Century. It developed out of the work of
Immanuel Kant and is closely linked with the Romanticism movement. It is sometimes referred
to as Kantianism (although that more correctly also involves acceptance of Kant's ethical and
epistemological views). Other than Kant himself, the main contributors (who all had their own
versions of Kant's theory, some close in nature and some quite distinct) were Johann Gottlieb
Fichte, Friedrich Schelling, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel and (arguably) Arthur
Schopenhauer, and additionally Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi (1743 - 1819), Gottlob Ernst Schulze
(1761 - 1833), Karl Leonhard Reinhold (1757 - 1823) and Friedrich Schleiermacher (1768 -
1834). Although essentially a German movement, the Swiss-French writer and philosopher
Madame de Staël (1766 - 1817) introduced (in her famous book "De l'Allemagne") the works of
Kant and the German Idealists to French thinkers, who were still largely under the influence
of John Locke at that time. In general terms, Idealism is the theory that fundamental reality is
made up of ideas or thoughts. It holds that the only thing actually knowable is consciousness (or
mental entities), and that we can never really be sure that matter or anything in the outside world
actually exists. The concept of Idealism arguably dates back to Plato, and reached a peak with
the pure Idealism of Bishop George Berkeley in the early 18th Century. See the section on the
doctrine of Idealism for more details. The German Idealists, however, were dissatisfied with
Berkeley's rather naive formulation. In the 1780s and 1790s, Immanuel Kant tried to bridge the
two dominant philosophical schools of the 18th Century: Rationalism (which held that
knowledge could be attained by reason alone, a priori), and Empiricism (which held that
knowledge could be arrived at only through the senses, a posteriori). Kant's Transcendental
Idealism claims that we know more than Berkeley's ideas in our minds, in that we also directly
know of at least the possibility of "noumena"("things-in-themselves"), which are both
empirically and transcendentally real even if they cannot be directly and immediately known.
The actual "phenomena" which we perceive and which we think we know are really just the way
things appear to us and not necessarily real. Other German philosophers of the time used Kant's
work as a starting point, adding in their own interpretations and biases. As a movement, it was
not one of agreement (although there was some common ground), and each successive
contributor rejected at least some of the theories of their predecessors. Many of the German
Idealists who followed Kant, effectively tried to reverse Kant's refutation of all speculative
theology and reinstate notions of faith and belief in their explanations of what exists beyond
experience, a trend which was continued later in the 19th Century by the American
Transcendentalists. Jacobi, although in agreement with Kant that the objective thing-in-itself
cannot be directly known, tried to legitimized belief and its theological associations by
presenting the external world as an object of faith, even if logically unproven. Schulze tried to
use Kant's's own reasoning to disprove the existence of the "thing-in-itself", arguing that it
cannot be the cause of an idea or image of a thing in the mind. Following from Schulze's
criticism of the notion of a "thing-in-itself", Fichte asserted that there is no external thing-in-
itself that produces the ideas, but our representations, ideas or mental images are merely the
productions of our ego, or "knowing subject". Schelling's view was that the ideas or mental
images in the mind are identical to the extended objects which are external to the mind
("absolute identity"), so that there is no difference between the subjective and the objective.
Schleiermacher's variation was that the ideal and the real do not have a productive or causal
effect on each other, but are united and manifested in the transcendental entity which is God.
Another German Idealist, G. W. F. Hegel, claimed that pure abstract thought (as in Kant's
formulations) is limited and leads to unsolvable contradictions. In order to overcome these
shortcomings, Hegel introduced the integral importance of history and of the "Other" person in
the awakening of self-consciousness. In the process, he established a whole new movement of
Hegelianism, which in turn was hugely influential in the later development of Continental
Philosophy, Marxism and (by virtue of its opposition to Hegel) Analytic Philosophy.
Schopenhauer claimed that Kant's noumenon is the same as Will, or at least that Will is the most
immediate manifestation of the noumenon that we can experience. He saw the "will-to-life" (a
fundamental drive intertwined with desire) as the driving force of the world, prior to thought and
even prior to being. Schopenhauer's criticisms of the later German Idealists is seen by some as a
sort of "back to Kant" movement, giving impetus to a Neo-Kantianism movement in the mid-
19th and into the 20th Century, which yielded the Kantian analyses of such German philosophers
as Kuno Fischer (1824 - 1907), Friedrich Lange (1828 - 1875), Hermann Cohen (1842 - 1918),
Paul Natorp (1854 - 1924), Nicolai Hartmann (1882 - 1950), Ernst Cassirer (1874 - 1945),
Wilhelm Windelband(1848 - 1915), Heinrich Rickert (1863 - 1936) and Ernst Troeltsch (1865 -
1923). Also in the mid-19th Century to the early 20th Century, a movement which became
known as British Idealism revived interest in the works of Kant and Hegel. The leading figures
in the movement were T. H. Green (1836 - 1882), F. H. Bradley(1846 - 1924), Bernard
Bosanquet (1848 - 1923), J. M. E. McTaggart (1866 - 1925), H. H. Joachim (1868 - 1938) and J.
H. Muirhead (1855 - 1940).