Chapter 4
Chapter 4
Chapter 4
Chapter 4
Inductive Reasoning in Law
“When you steal from one author, it’s plagiarism; if you steal from many, it’s
research.” – Wilson Mizner
Inductive Generalizations
There are many types of inductive reasoning, and the simplest and
most common of these types is called “inductive generalization.” An
inductive generalization is “an argument that relies on characteristics of a
sample population to make a claim about the population as a whole.” This
claim is a general claim that makes a statement about all, most, or some
members of a class, group, or set. The following are some example of
general claims:
Although the style of each of these four claims differ, all are general
claims. Since the first two use the words “all” and “every”, we can recognize
without much trouble that they refer to all members of a class, group, or
set. The first refers to all members of the group law students; the second
refers to all members of the group performance-enhancing drugs. Even
though the third claim does not use the words every or all, it too is general
claim. Further, this claim is no less general just because it tells us what
hearsays are not rather than what they are. The final example specifically
mentions most congressmen, but it should be understood to refer to the
entire class of congressmen because it claims that most are against the
legalization of divorce and implies that the remainder are not against it.
As a rule of thumb, the more examples you find, the stronger your
argument becomes. In O’Conner v. Commonwealth Edison Co., a federal
judge in Illinois lambasted an expert witness for attempting to formulate a
universal medical rule based on his observation of only five patients. Based
on th five patients (Dr. Scheribel) has observed with cataracts induced by
radiation therapy, he developed his “binding universal rule” that he applied
to O’Conner, thus committing the logical fallacy known as Converse
Accident (hasty generalization). It occurs when a person erroneously
creates a general rule from observing too few cases. Dr. Scheribel has
illogically created a “binding universal rule” based upon insufficient date.
Suppose we have three hundred students for our sample, will that
make the conclusion of our generalization acceptable? Not necessarily,
although the sample is definitely large enough, there is another factor we
need in evaluating the strength of inductive generalization. Thus, we need
to ask another question.
Although there were three hundred students who were interviewed for
the survey, the generalization may be weak if the three hundred students
only represent a particular portion of the whole student population.
Suppose these three hundred students are all members of Christ Youth in
Action (CYA), a Catholic organization of young people, they may not
actually represent the whole student population if a significant number of
students in that college is not a member of that organization. This will make
our conclusion questionable since such membership to that organization
greatly influences one’s view on death penalty for the Catholic Church
strongly opposes such kind of punishment. We call that kind of sample a
biased sample.
This has been the problem in the classic polling blunder that
happened in the United States. In 1936, Literary Digest magazine
conducted a massive polling effort to predict the outcome of the
Presidential election between Alf Landon and Franklin Roosevelt. The
Digest polled well over two million people, and the vast majority indicated
they would vote for Landon (keep in mind that modern news organizations
base their polls on the responses of 1,000 people). In the actual election,
however, Roosevelt won 523 electoral votes and Landon received only
eight. How did Literary Digest get it so wrong when it had crafted its rule
from a massive number of particular examples? The problem was the
Digest composed its polling list from telephone directories. In 1936, only
about 40% of households owned a telephone, usually those who are in the
upper class. This, even if they used random sampling in picking the
individuals to call and ask for their presidential preference, the sample
population is an unrepresentative group of the American public at that time.
The argument would be strong. Given our premise, the conclusion is more
likely to be true if its claim is more limited, restricting itself to many rather
than most Malaysians. Other phrases that could soften the conclusion are
possible, probably, and likely. Remember that inductive generalizations
should not overstate their conclusions. Let us take another example:
None of the ten teachers I met in this school knows how to speak Spanish.
Analogical Arguments
Suppose you are to defend a legal claim that the use of marijuana
should be allowed by the state. The issue pertaining to this matter is hinged
on two opposing legal opinions – one that asserts marijuana is a healing
herb and the other that claims marijuana is a dangerous drug. Which of
these two positions is to be followed? Without a clear universal rule or past
cases on point, deductive logic and inductive generalizations are of little
help. Instead, you must rely on the power of analogy to convince the court
that marijuana is to be treated as a healing herb. To defend your stand, you
must assert that marijuana, like other herbs that are not prohibited by law,
is non-toxic. It does not contain substances that kill brain cells or increase
risks of cancer. There have been no deaths associated with marijuana use.
On the contrary, like legal herbs, marijuana provides more health benefits
than risks. It helps in curing rheumatoid arthritis, diabetes, PTSD, epilepsy,
antibiotic-resistant infections and neurological disorders. The process of
drawing these comparisons and explaining why they are important is the
heart of reasoning by analogy. The idea is to find enough similarities
between the case at hand and existing rules or precedents to convince a
court that the treatment or judgment must be the same.
Let us put a twist regarding the issue of the bicycle owner’s attempt to
recover this property.
In the previous cases, the legal battle was between the innocent
owner and the wrongdoer (the thief or the defrauder). But in the present
case, the battle is between two innocent persons – it is between the
innocent owner and the innocent buyer. That is a relevant difference that
can justify the buyer’s ownership of the bicycle.
The relevant difference was how the bicycle was acquired from the
original owner – theft and fraudulent inducement. In the case of theft
(Cases 1 and 4), the original owner never intended to transfer the title to
Roger; the property was taken without Sonny’s knowledge and without his
intent to pass the title. That means that no title ever passed, and Roger
acquired no title.
In the case of fraudulent inducement (Cases 2 and 3), Mike did intend
and act to transfer the title, although the owner was misled by Giovanni’s
fraudulent inducement. So, Giovanni did acquire the title, though it was a
“voidable” (as opposed to “void”) title. This means that Mike can still
recover the bicycle if he acted quickly while Giovanni still had the item
because he could still “avoid the title.”
But if, before Mike acted to avoid the title, Giovanni sold it to an
innocent buyer who paid full value (a Bona Fide Purchaser), the title that he
had transferred to the BFP became a good title. It no longer could be
“avoided.”
Upon the expiration of lease, PCSO may purchase the equipment for
P25 million. The following month, a petition was filed to declare the
agreement invalid because it is violative of PCSO’s charter and the law
regarding public bidding. More importantly, it violates Sec. 2(2) of Art. 9-D
of the 1987 Constitution and that standing can no longer be questioned
because it has become the law of the case.
The High Court held in the negative declaring that stare decisis
cannot apply. The previous ruling sustaining the standing of the petitioners
is a departure from the settled rulings on real parties in interest because no
constitutional issues were actually involved.
Moreover, the law of the case cannot also apply since the present
case is not the same one litigated by the parties before in Kilosbayan vs.
Guingona – the ruling cannot be in any sense be regarded as the law of
this case. The parties are the same but the cases are not. Thus, the Rule
on Conclusiveness cannot still apply.
But the rule does not apply to issues of law at least when
substantially unrelated claims are involved. When the second proceeding
involved an instrument or transaction identical with, but in a form separable
from the one dealt with in the first proceeding, the Court is free in the
second proceeding to make an independent examination of the legal
matters at issue.