Shawver 1996
Shawver 1996
Shawver 1996
4, 1996
W H A T P O S T M O D E R N I S M C A N D O FOR
PSYCHOANALYSIS: A GUIDE TO THE
POSTMODERN VISION
Lois Shawver
I will use the term "modern" to designate any science that legitimates itself...
making an explicit appeal to some grand narrative.., such as the emancipation
of the rational or working subject, or the creation of wealth. (Lyotard, 1993, p.
xxiii)
read a book on the topic. Who, after all, wants to read a theory that pro-
motes psychological pathology by a strange use of fictions and untruths?
But an examination of these criticisms will show that the critics have re-
defined the terms of postmodernism in ways that trade on figurative, ver-
nacular images of pathology.
The postmodern self seems . . . like the familiar self of the psychoanalytic con-
sulting room: a disjointed, decentered, and dislocated self seeking to ameliorate
this very condition . . . . In my view, a clinical diagnosis masquerades as a clinical
cure. (Lean/, 1994, pp. 454-455, emphasis added)
POSTMODERN PSYCHOANALYSIS 375
There is, however, nothing about the underlying postmodern insight that
requires us to use the metaphor of psychological fragmentation, a meta-
phor that colors the insight with a pathological imagery, or to think of
decentering as a kind of psychological imbalance. These pathologizing
metaphors revise the meaning of postmodern terms. If we cast the post-
modern vision in words more designed to characterize its insights, we may
find the postmodern's enthusiasm more understandable.
What modernists call "postmodern fragmentation" might be better called
the "dialogic character of our minds." This is our tendency to imagine an
audience for everything we say, to work out what the audience says and to
appreciate, at times, its power and be persuaded by it (Bakhtin, 1981;
Sampson, 1993; Hermans and Hermans-Jansen, 1995; Rothstein, 1993;
Watkins, 1990). The dialogic character of your mind manifests itself con-
cretely when you leave an argument with a friend and continue it in your
mind as you drive off. This is your ability to have a fantasy of two or more
people in a conversation while keeping straight what each person is say-
ing. Your mind creates both parts of the conversation, but separates the
thoughts as to whether they belong to you or the other person.
And so we can say that the inner conversation is composed of two kinds
of voices: the voice of the self, and the voices of others that are spoken of
collectively as the Other. Sometimes the Other may be the voice of a spe-
cific person such as one's mother (saying "button up your jacket"), but it
can be a vague voice such as the voice of the opposition in a political
dispute. Nevertheless, one knows these other voices so well that it is typ-
ically possible to reverse roles in a role-play and speak with them, saying,
perhaps, what one's political opponent might say. Sometimes the Other in
one's mind does not speak at all but simply provides an audience and a
context for one's private monologue. But what is most profound about the
concept of a dialogic mind is the realization that there is always a question
of identifying the owner of these voices. Suppose one hears oneself think-
ing critical thoughts of a person standing in the grocery line. Is this one's
own voice speaking? Or is one simply echoing the voice of someone who
says things one no longer endorses.~
The observation that the mind is dialogic is central to much psycho-
analytic theory. In psychoanalysis we might note that free-associating pa-
tients say what they do as a response to the imagined analyst who is the
subject of their transference. This imagined analyst is an important exam-
ple of an Other. Noting the importance of this dialogic character of the
mind, Lacan argued that the key to the Unconscious was to be found in
deciphering what the imagined Other was saying because the patient's re-
marks and associations were a response to this imagined Other. This imag-
376 SHAWVER
[lit is speech functioning to the full, for it includes the discourse of the other in
the secret of its decipher. It was by deciphering this speech that Freud redis-
covered the primary language of symbols, still living on in the suffering of civi-
lized man. (Lacan, 1977, p. 69)
In order to rediscover the effect of Freud's speech [we need to look not to his
words but to the principles behind them.] . . . [And when we do, we see that]
Freud's discovery was to demonstrate that this verifying process [in which we
learn who we are] authentically attains the subject by decentering him from the
consciousness-of-self. (Lacan, 1977, p. 80, emphasis added)
Any conflict within or without can vanish from sight and actually be (arti-
ficially) diminished if one aspect of it is suppressed and the other made predomi-
nant. Speaking in terms of two people or two groups with conflicting needs and
interests, the open conflict disappears when an individual or group is subdued.
Between a bullying father and subdued child there is no visible conflict. The
same holds true for inner conflicts. We may have a sharp conflict between our
POSTMODERN PSYCHOANALYSIS 377
hostility toward people and our need to be liked. But if we suppress the hostil-
i t y - o r the need to be liked--our relations tend to become streamlined. (Homey,
1991, pp. 177-178)
A few passages later she describes the "real self" as a self composed of a
complex of voices, a postmodern self. In fact, she seems to be thinking of
what postmoderns call a modern self, a streamlined and simplified self, as
what should be described as "fragmented" and pathological. She says,
[The neurotic] may have [a] . . . strong interest in not perceiving contradictory
values coexisting in him. (Homey, 1991, p. 180)
[T]he tensions are kept in a low key because no conflict emerges and he can
maintain a deceptive feeling of unity. (Homey, 1991, p. 180)
In this context Horney is making the same point that postmoderns make
when they say we have multiple voices inside us that allow us to identify
with more than one point of view. When we try to suppress these voices,
we do not eradicate them. We merely alienate ourselves from a part of
ourselves and increase our experience of fragmentation. The task of be-
coming integrated psychologically is to learn to incorporate these different
voices in a sense of self that can live with and even celebrate the mental
complexity that results from the dialogical character of our minds. A post-
modern psychoanalysis facilitates our appreciation of the different voices
within us, voices from our childhood dramas, voices that argue with us, or
appreciate us. It helps us know these voices as part of who we are. It
might, for example, help a patient recognize the self in a dream that ap-
pears to be about another person.
But psychoanalysis is not always postmodern. Whenever psychoanalysts
pathologize the dialogic character of the patient's mind, assisting the effort
to suppress the alternative point of view, psychoanalysis abandons its post-
modernist stance and becomes modernist. This situation can be seen as
pathogenic for people can be made anxious by the modernist belief that
the inner self should have homogeneous desires and impulses when they
recognize that they personally experience conflicting desires. This mani-
fests itself in the modernist obsession with the question of how one really
is. An alternative impulse, say a homosexual feeling, causes such a person
to doubt a lifetime of heterosexual pleasure. A gentle person is imagined
378 SHAWVER
never to have a violent thought. The modernist patient searches for a sim-
ple pigeonhole to climb into. This desire to be completely simple, without
any texture of mixed feeling, is, so the postmodern holds, the pathology of
modernity (Levin, 1987).
Psychoanalysis is sometimes modern, but the roots of psychoanalysis are
largely postmodern (Barratt, 1993). Psychoanalysis is postmodern when it
helps patients hear themselves as speaking with censored voices. These
voices speak through dreams and fantasies in the imagined guise of other
people. The patient says, "1 think people want me to run away," and the
postmodern analyst helps the patient hear this statement as an expression
of a censored voice. The postmodern analyst might say, "Perhaps you
sometimes think that you should run away." The analyst helps patients own
some of their censored voices.
The critics may call the postmodern voices "fragments," but fragments
are pieces that do not relate. The shattered cup on the floor has been
broken into fragments that no longer relate to each other. In contrast, the
voices of others in our minds are our ties with other minds to which we
relate. These voices represent our concept of what other people want to
say. We carry that concept inside us as a voice that articulates their point of
view even when we disagree, even when we challenge their truth and
despise their content.
The successful postmodern identity emerges not in shattered, meaning-
less fragments but as a chorus of these many voices, as a continuous own-
ing and disowning of the voices in our dreams, visions, and desires that we
find within us. And the point of a postmodern psychoanalysis is not to
shatter the mind into uncommunicating segments, but to help people learn
to hear the underlying harmony and counterpoint among the voices in
their dialogic minds.
Jacques Derrida introduced the term deconstruction into our current lit-
erature when he popularized a little used term of Martin Heidegger's. What
it means is this: If naming something gives it being (in the sense that nam-
384 SHAWVER
in 8 the "bi 8 dipper" gave the bi 8 dipper being), then deconstruction shows
us a glimpse of the world that has not yet been given this particular being.
We begin to notice the big dipper is made of stars and that it was a kind of
illusion that they belonged together in the unity of a "thing" (Derrida,
1976, 1981, 1985). "The word [deconstruction has] signified a certain at-
tention to [conceptual] structures . . . . Structures were to be undone, de-
composed, desedimented" (Derrida, 1988, p. 2).
Deconstruction is possible because our psychological worlds are struc-
tured with differance. That is, there is always a hidden depth interpretation
we have not yet seen. "Deconstruction does not consist in passing from
one concept to another, but in overturning and displacing a conceptual
order" (Derrida, 1982b, p. 329). Deconstruction lifts us out of the domi-
nant paradigm , the dominant metaphor or poetry, and invites us to dance a
different dance. It simultaneously defers this dominant perspective while it
recovers the imagery that had been hidden in the conceptual shadows of
deferred attention.
In more Wittgensteinian terms, deconstruction is the philosophical prac-
tice that "consists in assembling reminders for a particular purpose" (Witt-
8enstein, 1965, sec. 127). These reminders serve to demystify us about our
presumption that the way we happen to have poetized the world is the
only way it could be poetized. Our effort to demystify ourselves like this
involves us in "a battle against the bewitchment of our intelligence by
means of a language" (Wittgenstein, 1965, sec. 109). Deconstruction de-
mystifies us, then, by reminding us of things we already know at a point in
our inquiry that we are inclined to forget or to defer them.
How are we mystified by language? We are mystified by the poetic im-
agery implicit in our language, or, our tendency to confuse the way we talk
in one context (a more literal context) with that in another. (Wittgenstein
called this a confusion of language games.) Our language practices mislead
us into expecting the world to be more precisely what the imagery in our
language suggests it is. "A simile that has been absorbed into the forms of
our language produces a false appearance" (Wittgenstein , 1965, sec. 112).
For example, our language expresses the imagery of fault on the model
of owning an object. Just as we say, "Whose book is that?" we say, "Whose
fault is that?" and this tells us that the ownership of the fault belongs to a
particular person, just as the ownership of a book belongs to a particular
person. And so we want to place the blame on an individual even though a
little deconstruction shows us that things are never that simple. Our lan-
guage deludes us into thinking that people are simple causes when even a
little investigation beneath the surface shows us that the person we
"blame" is not the whole cause, that that person was part of a chain of
POSTMODERN PSYCHOANALYSIS 385
You are sitting in your office reading this journal. Your body feels the chair
around you, the floor beneath your feet, your hands at the edge of the book. You
feel this. This is the real. All the same, you recall for a moment the image of your
386 SHAWVER
hand scribbling with a Crayola when you were a child. The moment that you
recall "used to be," but it is no longer the real. Somehow your mind has made a
copy of the real that used to be and stored it for your occasional recollection, but
this reality of you as a child has passed. Make your mind return, now, to the real,
to the present that surrounds you. Today your memory of your childhood scrib-
bling lives only in your mind. Nevertheless, your memory provides you with a
copy, a kind of corpse of a reality that once existed but is no longer. This journal,
the room that surrounds you now, this is the real now.
Imagine a culture that treasures a group of old clay tablets containing legible
marks. These tablets, so legend has it, were inscribed by the ancestors who gave
this tribe life and continue to give life with the joy of each new child. One must
study hard at the foot of a master to learn to read these tablets, but those who do
so have the privilege of decipherin 8 the magic of many precious messages. So
precious are the messages that each day a group of eager readers gather with
their lanterns in the dark damp caves to read them with rapt attention. As they
mouth the words, they learn of a land of lush romantic beauty. The odd carvings
on these stones fill their minds with images of flowing brooks, huge gaudy
flowers, chirping birds that would actually sit on your shoulder with their lon 8
soft plume-like tails hanging like draping rainbows down to your knees. And
there, kneeling in the flickering light, these readers learn of secret answers to the
mysteries of their lives. They learn of birth and death, and what it means, of how
to live, of how to hunt and fish, of how to cook their food, of how to dig a grave.
Nothing seems possible without these words. One passage provides an incanta-
tion to purify the water, another turns boys into men, and the recitation of an-
other unites men and women in matrimony. Every action that their minds imag-
ine, that they care about, is guided by the sacred words on these old stones.
Wisdom to the members of this tribe comes by committing these precious words
to memory, copying the words and images into their heads so they may be recol-
lected as guidance and reassurance in times of need. For such a tribe, at least,
the past is surely real. Their present consists only in a daily struggle to make their
lives fill with images from the past and to conform to the guidance of the past.
For them, the present is but a faulty copy of the past.
POSTMODERN PSYCHOANALYSIS 387
Writing in the common [Enlightenment] sense is the dead letter, it is the carrier of
death. It exhausts life. On the other hand, on the other face of the same proposi-
tion, writing in the metaphoric sense, natural, divine, and living writing, is vene-
rated; it is equal in dignity to the origin of value, to the voice of conscience as
divine law, to the heart, to sentiment, and so forth. (Derrida, 1976, p. 17)
Which is really the copy? The past or the present? Whenever we claim
that only one is the real, we defer to differance the other possible way of
seein 8 the world. Each contains a metaphysics, so postmodernism tells us,
that brings with it a way of life.
Each metaphysics slips in through the implicit imagery in the way we
speak. When language is being used effectively, we do not notice this im-
agery, but it is there in all but the most artificial and mathematical kinds of
languages. Moreover, we can study it and sometimes deconstruct its imag-
ery if we look closely. Saying the memory of your childish scribbling was a
record or a copy of a time that used to be and was no longer made the past
seem no longer rooted in the real. Saying that the tribesmen mouthed the
words on sacred tablets and had their minds animated with the ancient
imagery made the present consciousness seem but a copy of the past.
But whether we say the past is a copy of the present, or the present is a
copy of the past, these are only metaphorical images. There are no copies
388 SHAWVER
here in the sense that a Xerox is a copy. We are simply noticin 8 that both
memory and consciousness are like copies. According to one metaphysics,
the past is a corpse and the present is the real. According to the other, the
past is the living real that animates the present that is only a theater in
which the past is forever replayed.
Neither metaphysics is more correct than the other. They are just two
different ways humans have of poetizing time. Two sides of the same coin.
One must always be deferred. One side is always deferred on the other
side of differance where it exists as a trace, as something, Derrida would
say, we put under "erasure." "Under [this erasure] the presence of [a reality
beyond our words] is effaced while still remaining legible" (Derrida, 1976,
p. 23). Differance keeps within itself the mark of the past and the future
(Derrida, 1982a, p. 13). It works this way because of the limits of our
language to capture the unspoken reality as it is. It is the nature of our
language to highlight something of that reality only by deferring something
else, pushing something into awareness in the very act of pushing some-
thing else out.
But if language only gives us a unidimensional picture of the three-di-
mensional world, several pictures together can sometimes be embraced to
create a sense of a three-dimensional world. We cannot look at the back-
side of reality while we are staring at the front, but knowing it has a back-
side helps us gather a sense of the way things fit together. The point of
deconstruction is not to overthrow the Enlightenment perspective, but to
enrich our understanding by helping us decenter and see other points of
view. We do not need to honor the real as what was written in the tablets
of our culture over the present that is liberated from the past. "[N]othing
would be more ridiculously mystifyin 8 than such an ethical or axiological
reversal, returnin 8 a prerogative to some elder's right to writing" (Derrida,
1981, p. 13). Deconstruction is merely the demystification of the assump-
tions built into our language and this can enhance our ability to see past
those assumptions and to gain a clearer picture of the world beyond our
words.
But it seems that the Enlightenment metaphysics mesmerized our culture
with a poetry that taught us to see only the present as the real. In this
context, classical psychoanalysis has power because psychoanalysis is cul-
turally out of step with the Enlightenment. Psychoanalysis deconstructs the
metaphysics of presence by showing the patient how the present is an
enactment of past dramas, how the present is a copy of the past, and what
we feel to be a response to a present context can be seen as a response to a
historical one. Psychoanalysis not only deconstructs the metaphysics of
presence but it elaborates a metaphysics of history, provides us with a set
of images that shed light on the way in which our lives are dominated by
POSTMODERN PSYCHOANALYSIS 389
our histories. And, in a world that seems to consist only of what is present,
this deconstruction of presence provides our lives with a sense of en-
hanced meaning and depth.
Critics of deconstructionism often fail to appreciate the meaning of the
"deconstruction of the metaphysics of presence." Leary (1994, p. 438), for
example, dismisses the "metaphysics of presence" as a synonym for the
word real. She says, "Derrida argued that philosophy has been led astray
by the search for referents and the desire to claim the 'real,' what he called
the 'metaphysics of presence.'" In her interpretation of things, deconstruct-
ing this metaphysics leaves us without a past. She says, "In key respects,
postmodernism purges the analytic situation of the need to grapple with
history, with things that once were and had an effect . . . . [P]atient and
a n a l y s t . . , are wedded to a constantly unfolding present" (Leary, 1994, p.
457). Actually, the deconstruction of presence can result in a greater sense
of the past. And although it is true that postmodern psychoanalysts such as
Hoffman (e.g., 1991) may focus treatment so that it highlights the present,
others such as Schafer (1992) teach how to retell the narrative of our lives
so as to animate the present with a sense of past.
CONCLUSIONS
The critics of postmodern psychoanalysis hide the power of this new
vision by replacin 8 its technical concepts with homonyms, that is, with
ordinary language terms that sound the same but have different meanings.
Translated in this way, postmodernism sounds foolish, but it is rather like
trying to understand ego psychology by interpreting "ego" as meaning
something like "arrogant." For example, the critics seem to think of "de-
centered" in terms of the vernacular concept of being "unbalanced," but
the postmodern term decentered means something more like "putting one-
self in the other person's shoes" or "looking at the world, empathically, as
if from the other person's consciousness." The critics of postmodern psy-
choanalysis, therefore, have simply reduced postmodernism to a straw man
theory that no one should endorse.
Even so, there is something inconsistent in their critique. Their major
complaint seems to be that postmodernism is insufficiently objective. We
might take this to mean that they believe it is too metaphorical, too prone
to create imaginative pictures, too little anchored in hard facts and a belief
in hard facts. If this is their main criticism, it is paradoxical that a critic
such as Leary makes her major arguments against postmodernism in the
language of rhetorical metaphors.
For example, Leary says that postmodern authors "all disavow the notion
that human beings have any essential or unitary core" (1994, p. 441). But
390 SHAWVER
Leary, surely, does not hold that the self has a core in the straightforward
way that an apple has a core. The notion that the self has a unitary core is
just her metaphorical way of describing the ineffable self as solid, durable,
and real.
And, Leary says that the postmodern self is "revealed to be e m p t y . . , far
from being liberated, [it] is instead enslaved" (1994, p. 454). But the post-
modern self is not empty in the simple concrete sense that a kettle on the
stove can be "empty," and it is not "enslaved" in the simple concrete sense
that Americans once enslaved Africans. Leary is again just creating meta-
phorical pictures as she tries to say somethin 8 that, presumably, she finds
difficult to say in more objective language.
And, Leary complains that, "Deconstructionism delinks language from
the world it is purported to describe" (1994, p. 438)~ But she does not
believe that there are concrete links between language and reality, as there
are links that tie the dog to the tree. This, too, is just a metaphorical way of
portraying her understandin 8 of postmodernism.
But her colorful metaphors portray postmodernism in a misleading way.
Postmodernism believes in a reality beyond words; it just believes that the
world beyond words is understood differently depending on how we agree
to describe it. It gives new emphasis to the importance of looking at the
way we talk about the world.
In fact, postmodernism might be summarized like this: Language matters,
and it matters far more than people have imagined. It does not simply label
reality in an accurate or inaccurate way. It creates metaphorical images of
reality that take us into different kinds of experience. Having different ex-
periences causes us to do things differently, to create different kinds of
institutions and cultures, and lead different kinds of lives. Psychoanalysis
cannot ignore this process without subverting its own clinical purposes. It
cannot become more objective by pretending its theories are not couched
in metaphorical relics that constitute our language.
What does postmodernism have to offer psychoanalysis? It invites an-
alysts to use a new set of concepts to study and observe the psychoanalytic
process. For example, it invites us to consider the way implicit metaphori-
cal imagery weaves its way through our patient's thoughts, to notice the
way patients structure their identities by claiming and rejecting impulses,
and to notice, too, the way a sense of one's history is minimized by the
patient's implicit endorsement of a metaphysics of presence.
And in doing all of this, postmodernism legitimates psychoanalytic dis-
course without requiring it to lay its foundation in the Enlightenment meta-
physics of an empirical science. It invites psychoanalysis to look at what it
is doing successfully without requiring that it reify the Unconscious or any
of its metaphorical concepts. Postmodernism shows psychoanalysis that it
POSTMODERN PSYCHOANALYSIS 391
has become the discipline best equipped to forestall the loss of meaning
from the glare of a metaphysics of presence by inspiring us with the pros-
pect of understanding our present in the light of our nostalgic memory.
But postmodernism awaits the creative work of psychoanalysis to synthe-
size this new thought within a clinical process. There are many paths be-
coming visible here. We are only beginning to explore this new terrain. We
are only just now learning to talk about it. To join in this movement one
need not accept every postmodern statement, or take every path any self-
identified postmodern would suggest. Postmodernism is less an ideology
than a vocabulary with associated insights. You do not lose your mind or
your agency in postmodernity. All you need to do to become a part of the
postmodern venture is learn to speak the language, to notice what it will
point out to you and to share in a conversation we are having about how
to utilize postmodern insights within a psychoanalytic frame.
Of course, those of us beginning on this journey may not convince the
wary to leave their favorite metaphors behind and come along with us, but
we will send back messages like this one, now and then, to reassure the
cautious that our venture into the postmodern wilderness has not resulted
in our falling off the edge of the world.
REFERENCES
Lakoff, G., and Johnson, M. (1980). Metaphors We Live By. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Layton, L. (1995). Trauma, gender identity and sexuality: Discourses of fragmenta-
tion. American Imago 52:107-125.
Leary, D. (1990). Metaphors in the History of Psychology. New York: Cambridge
University Press.
Leary, K. (1994). Psychoanalytic "problems" and postmodern "solutions." Psycho-
analytic Quarterly 68: 433-465.
Levi-Strauss, C. (1966). The Savage Mind. Chicago: The University of Chicago
Press.
Levin, D. (1987). Pathologies of the Modern Self. New York: New York University Press.
Lyon, D. (1994). Concepts in Social Thought. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
Press.
Lyotard, J. F. (1984). The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge. Min-
neapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Madison, G. B. (1992). Coping with Nietzsche's legacy: Rorty, Derrida, Gadamer.
Philosophy 36: 3-20.
Morawski, S. (1992). On the subject of and in postmodernism. British Journal of
Aesthetics 32: 50-59.
Passmore, J. (1985). Recent Philosophers. La Salle, IL: Open Court Publishing Com-
pany.
Rivera, M. (1989). Linking the psychological and the social: Feminism, poststruc-
turalism, and multiple personality. Dissociation 2: 24-31.
Rosenau, P. M. (1992). Post-modernism and the Social Sciences: Insights, Inroads,
and Intrusions. Princeton, N J: Princeton University Press.
Rothstein, S. W. (1993). The Voice of the Other: Language as Illusion in the Forma-
tion of the Self. Westpoint, CT: Praeger.
Sampson, E. E. (1985). The decentralization of identity: Toward a revised concept of
personal and social order. American Psychologist 40:1203-1211.
Sarbin, T. (1990). Metaphors of unwanted conduct: A historical sketch. In D. Leary
(ed.), Metaphors in the History of Psychology (pp. 300-332). Cambridge: Cam-
bridge University Press.
Sarup, M. (1989). An Introductory Guide to Post-structuralism and Postmodernism.
Athens: University of Georgia Press.
Sass, L. A., and Woolfolk, R. L. (1988). Psychoanalysis and the hermeneutic turn: A
critique of narrative truth and historical truth. Journal of the American Psycho-
analytic Association 36: 429-454.
Schafer, R. (1992). Retelling a Life: Narration and Dialogue in Psychoanalysis. New
York: Basic Books.
Shawver, L. (1977). Research variables in psychology and the logic of their creation.
Psychiatry 40:1-16.
Shawver, L. (1983). Harnessing the power of interpretive language. Psychotherapy:
Theory, Research and Practice 20:3-11.
Sherwood, S. J. (1994). Narrating the social: Postmodernism and the drama of de-
mocracy. Journal of Narrative and Life History 1 & 2: 69-88.
Soccio, D. (1992). Archetypes of Wisdom: An Introduction to Philosophy. Belmont,
CA: Wadworth Publishing Co.
Watkins, M. (1990). The Development of Imaginal Dialogues. Boston: Sigo Press.
Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical Investigations. New York: The Macmillan Co.
394 SHAWVER