The Gentle Civilizer of Nations - MARTTI KOSKENNIEMI
The Gentle Civilizer of Nations - MARTTI KOSKENNIEMI
The Gentle Civilizer of Nations - MARTTI KOSKENNIEMI
0 521 62311 1
Self-Determination of Peoples
A Legal Appraisal
0 521 63752 X
0 521 46311 4
.
State Immunity
0 521 46319 X
-
0 521 46324 6
The Gentle Civilizer
of Nations:
The Rise and Fall of International
Law 1870–1960
M A RT T I KO S K E N N I E M I
Contents
Preface
page xi
List of abbreviations
xiv
Introduction
1
1
“The legal conscience of the civilized world”
11
A manifesto
12
An old-fashioned tradition
19
24
An amateur science
28
A time of danger
35
39
A romanticprofession: Bluntschli
42
47
Method: enlightened inwardness
51
54
57
Limits of liberalism
67
Cultural consciousness
70
Culture as character
76
88
2
Sovereignty: a gift of civilization: international lawyers and
imperialism 1870–1914
98
Ambivalent attitudes
99
110
112
116
121
vii
Contents
132
Between universality and relativism: colonial treaties 136
143
149
152
155
166
3
International law as philosophy: Germany
1871–1933
179
182
194
206
209
210
213
228
Getting organized
231
249
261
4
International law as sociology: French “solidarism”
1871–1950
266
284
288
291
297
Meanwhile in Paris . . .
309
L’affaire Scelle
316
Solidarity with tradition: Louis Le Fur
317
viii
Contents
327
342
348
5
Lauterpacht: the Victorian tradition in
international law
353
Tradition in modernity
353
A complete system
361
369
A political commitment
376
388
399
A Grotian tradition?
406
Coda
411
6
Out of Europe: Carl Schmitt, Hans Morgenthau,
413
A 1950 retrospective
415
418
424
432
Another retrospective
437
455
465
Empire’s law
480
A culture of formalism?
494
Epilogue
510
Bibliography
518
Index
558
ix
Preface
The essays in this book are inspired by many sources and reflect
various conversations I have had with international lawyers in the
course of the past four years or so. The initiator of the idea of the
book was Professor Sir Elihu Lauterpacht, who kindly invited me to
give the Sir Hersch Lauterpacht Memorial Lectures at the University
of Cambridge in 1998, and in that connection pointed out that this
privilege also involved a commitment to prepare the lectures for
publication. Eli’s hospitality in Cambridge in 1997 and the discussions
I had with him also underlie my interpretation of his father’s work in
chapter 5. As always, I am indebted to Professor David Kennedy
from the Harvard Law School for innumerable conversations and
collaborative projects, Dighton weeks and weekends, shorter and
longer periods together and in wider company in the Boston area,
Helsinki and other places, at various stages of writing of these
essays. But the only person to have read the whole of this work, and
whose comments and criticisms are reflected on every page, as in
everything about its author, is Tiina Astola. This book would not exist
without them.
Many other friends and colleagues have been involved. The
comments and work of Dr. Outi Korhonen are reflected in the
description of the culture of late nineteenth-century internationalists.
The account of international lawyers and imperialism (chapter 2)
draws on the important work of Professors Antony Anghie and
Nathaniel Berman, and from discussions I have had with them over
the years. That section owes much to the invitation I received from
Dr. Surya Subedi to give the Josephine Onoh Memorial Lecture at the
University of Hull in February 1999. I also want to thank the
participants in the international legal history project under Professor
Michael Stolleis at the Max Planck xi
Preface
Institute for Legal History in Frankfurt for the debate on persons and
problems relating to my German story (chapter 3), among them
particularly Dr. Betsy Roeben, whose work on Bluntschli I have
plundered in chapter 1 and Dr. Ingo Hueck whose writings on the
institutional aspects of the German interwar scene underlies sections
of chapter 3. I am grateful for a number of French friends and
colleagues, too, among them in particular Professors Pierre Michel
Eisemann and Charles Leben, who directed me to primary and
secondary materials without which I could not have made sense of
the French story in chapter 4. I also thank Doyen Vedel for
correspondence on Louis Le Fur, Dr. Oliver Diggelmann for a
discussion and a copy of his unpublished dissertation on Max Huber
and Georges Scelle as well as Professor Geneviève Burdeau and Mr.
Pierre Bodeau for providing relevant materials or references. Chapter
6 on Carl Schmitt and Hans Morgenthau and the
I could not have written this book without one year’s leave of
absence from the University of Helsinki, made possible by a grant
received from the Finnish Academy (Suomen Akatemia).
Preface
Martti Koskenniemi,
xiii
Abbreviations
AFDI
AJIL
Annuaire IDI
ARWP
ASIL
BYIL
ICJ
IDI
ILA
PCIJ
RdC
RDI
RGDIP
ZaöRV
Zeitschrift für ausländisches öffentliches Recht und Völkerrecht xiv
Introduction
I
This book grew out of the Sir Hersch Lauterpacht Memorial Lectures
that I gave at the University of Cambridge in the fall of 1998. It is,
admittedly, quite a bit longer than those original lectures were, but it
is still informed by the same interest. This was to expand upon an
article I had written a year earlier on Hersch Lauterpacht himself for
the European Journal of International Law and in which I had
attempted to cover the same ground I had done in a book ten years
earlier, but from an altogether different perspective. In that book I
had described international law as a structure of argumentative
moves and positions, seeking to provide a complete – even
“totalising” – explanation for how international law in its various
practical and theoretical modes could simultaneously possess a high
degree of formal coherence as well as be substantively
indeterminate.1 The result was a formal–structural analysis of the
“conditions of possibility” of international law as an argumentative
practice – of the transformational rules that underlay international
law as a discourse – that relied much on binary oppositions between
arguments and positions and relationships between them. But as
perceptive critics pointed out, whatever merits that analysis had, its
image of the law remained rather static. Even if it laid the
groundwork for describing the production of arguments in a
professionally competent international law practice, it fell short of
explaining why individual lawyers had come to endorse particular
positions or arguments in distinct periods or places. Even if it
claimed that all legal practice was a 1 Martti Koskenniemi, From
Apology to Utopia: The Structure of International Legal Argument
(Helsinki, Lakimiesliiton kustannus, 1989).
The Lauterpacht essay – the only one of the chapters below that has
been previously published as such – chose another approach. It tried
to put in a historical frame the development of the ideas and
arguments of one of the twentieth century’s most influential
international lawyers.
in this book is, then, not a set of ideas – for many such ideas are
astonishingly alive today – nor of practices, but a sensibility that
connotes both ideas and practices but also involves broader aspects
of the political faith, image of self and society, as well as the
structural constraints within which international law professionals live
and work.
Like my earlier work, this book examines the rather surprising hold
that a small number of intellectual assumptions and emotional
dispositions have had on international law during its professional
period. This time, I have attempted to bring these assumptions and
dispositions together in the form of a series of narratives that traces
the emergence of a sensibility about matters international in the late
nineteenth century as an inextricable part of the liberal and
cosmopolitan movements of the day, and that dissolved together
with them some time during the second decade after the Second
World War. Like the liberal reformism which 2
Introduction
on Germany and France hope to make clear, the received image not
only fails to articulate the variety of approaches and positions that
lawyers took in their writings and practices, but is sometimes
completely mistaken. One of my desires is that the ensuing account
will finally do away with the image of late nineteenth-and early
twentieth-century lawyers as “positivists” who were enthusiastic
about “sovereignty.” If any generalization can be made in this
regard, it is rather that these men were centrists who tried to
balance their moderate nationalism with their liberal
internationalism. In Europe, they saw themselves as arguing against
the egoistic policies of States and in favor of integration, free trade,
and the international regulation of many aspects of domestic society,
including human rights. Their credo was less sovereignty than a
critique of sovereignty.
Introduction
Finally, the recounting of the story about the “rise” and “fall” of
international law seemed to me necessary not only because of what
it might tell us of the profession as it was then but what it could say
of it as it is now. I hope that these essays provide a historical
contrast to the state of the discipline today by highlighting the ways
in which international lawyers in the past forty years have failed to
use the imaginative opportunities that were available to them, and
open horizons beyond academic and political instrumentalization, in
favor of worn-out
So although this book covers quite a bit of the same ground as the
one I published ten years ago, the move from structure to history
makes this a completely different work. Or almost does. For the play
of apology and utopia is of course effective in the writings of the
lawyers I discuss below and continues to account for the fact that
they became highly regarded representatives of the profession. But I
have consciously tried to downplay that aspect of their work, and to
focus instead on the political and in some cases biographical context
in which they worked and on the professional and political projects
that they tried to advance through their 2 Cf. also Martti
Koskenniemi, “Between Commitment and Cynicism; Outline of a
Theory of International Law as Practice,” in Collection of Essays by
Legal Advisors of States, Legal Advisors of International
Organizations and Practitioners in the Field of International Law
(New York, United Nations, 1999), pp. 495–523.
practice, on the struggles for power and position in which they were
engaged, and on their defeats and victories.
III
The move from structure to history in the analysis of international
law is thus the first ambition of this book. But to refer to “history”
probably begs more questions than it answers. Lawyers – especially
those with an interdisciplinary interest – should bear in mind that the
grass is not necessarily any greener in the adjoining fields.
Historiography, like sociology or philosophy, is at least as much
riddled with methodological controversy, and uncertainty about
premises, as law is. What kind of history, then, do the following
chapters offer to the reader? Two alternatives had to be discounted
at the outset. One was the grand history that would paint a canvas
of “epochs” following each other under some metahistorical law
about the workings of “culture” or “power” on the destinies of
peoples or civilizations, patterns of creation, flourishing, and decline.
There already were such histories and little could be added to them
that would be new or interesting.3 Perhaps more importantly, they
implied philosophical, methodological, and political assumptions that
seemed hard to sustain. Already the identification of the relevant
“epochs,” not to say anything about the ways in which they reduced
a complex world into hierarchical blocs, following each other in a
more or less monotonous parade headed by laws of
interdependence, Great Power policies, or perhaps “progress,”
seemed burdened with contestable assumptions about what was
central and what peripheral, what valuable and what harmful in the
past, and failed to address the question 3 The standard English-
language introduction remains Arthur Nussbaum, A Concise History
of the Law of Nations (Revised edn., New York, Macmillan, 1954).
Like that work, most of the writing in the field has been undertaken
by Germans. See particularly Wilhelm Grewe, Epochen des
Völkerrechtsgeschichte (Baden-Baden, Nomos, 1984) recently
published as The Epochs of International Law (trans. and rev. by
Michael Byers, Berlin and New York, de Gruyter, 2000). Ernst
Reibstein, Völkerrecht. Eine Geschichte seiner Ideen in Lehre und
Praxis (2 vols., Freiburg and Munich, Alber, 1958 and 1963), is a
collection of citations, chronologically arranged to support the
author’s sometimes idiosyncratic theses. Shorter recent introductory
overviews are Karl-Heinz Ziegler, Völkerrechtsgeschichte. Ein
Studienbuch (Munich, Beck, 1994) and Antonio Truyol y Serra,
Histoire du droit international public (Paris, Economica, 1995). Still
impressive is Robert Redslob, Histoire des grands principes du droit
des gens depuis l’antiquité jusqu’à la veille de la grande guerre
(Paris, Rousseau, 1923). An extensive (though not exhaustive)
bibliography is Peter Macalister-Smith and Joachim Schwietzke,
“Literature and Documentary Sources relating to the History of
Public International Law: An Annotated Bibliographical Survey”
(1999), 1 Journal of the History of International Law, pp. 136–212.
Introduction
“international law” has been either this or that. Like any social
phenomenon, international law is a complex set of practices and
ideas, as well as interpretations of those practices and ideas, and the
way we engage in them or interpret them cannot be dissociated
from the larger professional, academic or political projects we have.
I wanted to articulate some of those projects, and thus to describe
the lawyers as actors in particular social dramas. International law is
also a terrain of fear and ambition, fantasy and desire, conflict and
utopia, and a host of other aspects of the phenomenological lives of
its practitioners. I also wanted to take a step in the direction of
describing it in terms of their occasionally brilliant insights and
(perhaps more frequently) astonishing blind-ness, the paradoxes of
their thought, their intellectual and emotional courage, betrayals and
self-betrayals.
the League because one was a pacifist, because that suited the
foreign policy of one’s patria, or in order to forestall attempts
towards a more intrusive federalism in Europe, or any mixture of
such reasons. In order to attain a credible description that accounted
for unity as well as variety one needed to understand each position
by reference to some sort of a contextual background from which it
arose.
Introduction
Thus the following essays are neither epochal nor biographical in the
various forms in which such histories are usually written. They form
a kind of experimentation in the writing about the disciplinary past in
6 Here I think especially of the new work by Antony Anghie, David
Bederman, Nathaniel Berman, Anthony Carty, David Kennedy, Karen
Knop, Outi Korhonen, Carl Landauer, and Annelise Riles.
which the constraints of any rigorous “method” have been set aside
in an effort to create intuitively plausible and politically engaged
narratives about the emergence and gradual transformation of a
profession that plays with the reader’s empathy. The essays do not
seek a neutral description of the past “as it actually was” – that sort
of knowledge is not open to us – but a description that hopes to
make our present situation clearer to us and to sharpen our own
ability to act in the professional contexts that are open to us as we
engage in our practices and projects.
In this sense, it is also a political act. I hope that it does not treat its
protagonists unjustly. But if it seems that it does, then I have
Goethe’s ironic response to fall back on, namely, that it is the one
who acts that is always unjust, and the one that merely observes,
that is just.
10
civilized world”
On the other hand, peace had been created and enforced through a
pact among five Great Powers, three of which (Austria, Prussia, and
Russia) were governed by absolutist monarchs whose main motive
for cooperation seemed to be their shared wish to curb any proposal
for representative government or increased franchise. If there was
indeed economic progress, its geographic scope was limited to the
West while much the largest part of Europe was untouched by the
benefits of industrialization or free trade. Progress, while undeniable,
had grown out of a peace that seemed both precarious – as had
been shown by the Crimean 11
13
Legislators and jurists needed to learn about the laws and legislative
projects of different countries so as to better appreciate the effects
of proposed domestic reforms and to reduce conflicts that might be
caused by differing laws. Today, the prospectus declared, nobody
who wanted to ameliorate social conditions could afford to neglect
the study of comparative law.8
In the manifesto that headed the first issue, Rolin inaugurated the
Revue as a professional forum for liberal legislative reform in Europe.
In the matter of personal status, the abolition not only of slavery but
of servitude; in civil matters the freedom of establishment; in penal
matters, the creation of a more just relationship between the crime
and the punishment and the application of the punishment in the
interests of the criminal as well as that of society; the suppression of
the criminalisation of usury, and of privileged corporations, the
liberation of the value of gold and silver, and the freedom of
association.12
14
In international law this opinion is really and rightly the queen and
legislator of the world. It is the voice of reason itself . . . And it is
finally also the progressive expression of that natural law which
Grotius had defined so well and so profoundly.15
But public opinion was not whatever uncultivated whim pleased the
masses. On the contrary:
We mean a public opinion that is serious and calm, that is based on
the application of certain principles of universal justice, with constant
elements, an 13 Rolin-Jaequemyns, “De l’étude de la législation
comparée et de droit international,”
p. 235.
p. 256.
pp. 225–226.
15
Formal State acts may be just or unjust, right or wrong. They could
therefore not be the fundamental source of the law of nations.
Whether they should be obeyed depends on whether they were
accepted by the civilized conscience of peoples:
p. 225. For the role of public opinion, cf. also Francis Lieber, On Civil
Liberty and Self-Government (Philadelphia, Lippincott, 1859), pp.
405–416.
p. 228.
18 Rolin-Jaequemyns, “De l’étude de la législation comparée et de
droit international,”
p. 225.
19 For biographical details, cf. the obituaries in (1902), 2/IV RDI, pp.
88–122 and Nys,
16
In fact, none of the men behind the Revue came from the tradition
of Grotius, or the school of “European Public Law” that had
dominated international legal writing from Vattel well into the mid-
nineteenth century. None was a lawyer–philosopher in the vein of
Suarez or a diplomat like Wheaton. Like Rolin, Asser was and
continued as a practic-ing lawyer in addition to holding a university
chair. In later years, he was instrumental in setting up the Hague
Conference on Private International Law and undertook a number of
activities in the field of unification of private law. He failed to get
elected to the Dutch Parliament but did secure the Nobel Peace Prize
in 1911. Westlake had practiced as a barrister since 1854 and, aside
from being a “thoroughly trained and competent equity lawyer”20
was also a “convinced and unflinching liberal.”21 After a brief period
in the House of Commons he was elected Whewell Professor of
International Law in Cambridge in 1887 but continued taking part in
various foreign policy activities including the British Government’s
Balkan Committee and the manifesto in favor of Finland.
213.
17
The Revue was born out of a sensibility that looked for social
progress, emphasized responsibility, and sought a via media
between individualism and collectivism, abstract speculation and
political action. It was democratic but fearful of the masses,
reformist but bourgeois. In psychoana-lytic language it might be
characterized in terms of the repression of extremism and a
sublimation of aggression into a more or less successful toleration of
variety, of different shades of grey.24 Its spirit was both nationalist
and internationalist – though opposed to “extreme” variants of both.
It was politically “progressive” inasmuch as it rejected monarchic
absolutism and “conservative” to the extent that it saw revolution 23
Aside from Rolin’s programmatic articles on private and public
international law, and the first of his series of chroniques, the first
issue contained an article on the abolition of corporal punishment in
France in 1867 together with a comparative review of corporal
punishment in various European States. Franz von Holtzendorff
(1829–1889) from Berlin reviewed recent publications on the prison
system, arguing against absurdly long sentences and in favor of
prison leave. Pradier-Fodéré (1827–1904), consultant to South
American governments, criticized the Western misuse of
capitulations in Turkey and argued in favor of their abolition. The
French essayist, poet, and historian Edouard Laboulaye (1811–
1883), Professor of Comparative Legislation at the Collège de France
and later a member of the French National Assembly, wrote a short
piece on the lack of historical perspective in Montesquieu’s Esprit des
lois while the Argentinian lawyer–diplomat Carlos Calvo (1824–
1906), reiterated the Calvo doctrine – that governments should not
be held responsible for damage caused by acts of domestic
insurgents.
18
An old-fashioned tradition
In his manifesto, Rolin made no reference to earlier continental
writing on international law – although he did dwell briefly on
humanitarian ideas and federalist proposals by Rousseau, Kant, and
others. He completely passed over the treatises that had come out
earlier in the century, particularly in Germany, written by experts in
public law, with an interest in international affairs often triggered by
consultant work to a sovereign. The founders of the Revue sought a
complete break from that tradition: its focus had been too narrow,
its ambition too limited. Indeed, it must have seemed more part of
the problem than an instrument for its resolution.
26 I have here used the 1864 edn. prepared by Vergé of the Précis
du droit des gens moderne de l’Europe.
28 Martens, Précis, I, p. 46 § 6.
19
The Gentle Civilizer of Nations
But it was a narrow and a distant law that looked like the complex
rules of some exotic variation of the game of chess. As such it was
completely alien to the espritd’internationalité that animated the
circle of Rolin and his friends.
29 Martens, Précis, I, p. 56 § 8.
20
21
22
dynasties and wars and their politics the conservative principle of the
balance of power. They provided no foothold for activism outside
governmental diplomacy, indeed any activism seemed a priori
suspect inasmuch as it tended to disturb the balance of power that
both associated (sometimes seemed to think identical) with the
maintenance of the States.48
23
24
Like von Martens and Klüber, Kaltenborn accepted that Europe was
naturally divided into sovereign States.63 Unlike them, however, he
saw these States also joined in a historical and cultural community to
which his new science would give reality. It would describe legal
subjects (States) in their relation to certain objects (territory,
commerce) and the legal forms (treaties, diplomacy) whereby these
were linked together. Such a rela-tional systematic was derived from
sovereignty (the older doctrine of absolute rights) but gave reality to
the principle of international legal community (the old doctrine’s
relative rights) as well.64 This enabled Kaltenborn to respond to the
“deniers” who had doubted whether international law was law in the
absence of legislation, adjudication, and enforcement through an
argument that was to become the profession’s 57 Kaltenborn, Kritik,
pp. 112–113, 175–185.
25
“reality.”67
13.
26
71 Vergé, “Le droit des gens avant et depuis 1789,” pp. i–lv.
75 Vergé, “Le droit des gens avant et depuis 1789,” pp. xxii–xxiii.
27
28
217–234.
29
Hence, until late in the second half of the century, international law
received no general academic treatment in France that would have
been separate from a discussion of natural law.88 In the 1868
edition of his great treatise on the rights and duties of neutrals in
maritime war Hautefeuille (1805–1875) had still this to say about the
basis and proper method of his science:
30
France in 1880, for example, the relevant position was Chair of Droit
de la nature et des gens.91 After the Chair of International Law in
Strasbourg was abolished in 1867 the only international law
professorship remained in Paris. This had been established in 1829
but the courses given by its holders – Royer-Collard (1830–1864)
and Charles Giraud (1864–1874)
– had been more about diplomatic history than positive law. Only in
1889 was international law introduced at French universities as a
compulsory subject with an examination.92 The situation was not
very different in other continental States. When in Holland a law of
1876
31
Not all German public lawyers shared von Mohl’s theory of the
representative State or, even if they did, drew as far-reaching
conclusions from it. For Adolf Lasson (1837–1917), for instance, the
Hegelian legal 96 Cf. G. W. F. Hegel, Philosophy of Right, trans. by S.
W. Doyle (London, Prometheus, 1996 [1896]), pp. 340–341.
32
After the reform of legal education in the mid-century, the first chairs
of international law proper were set up quite rapidly in Oxford in
1859 (the Chichele Chair with Montague Bernard [1820–1880] as its
first occupant) and in Cambridge in 1866 (the Whewell Chair with
William Harcourt [1827–1904]).104 The position held by the
eccentric Scotsman James Lorimer (1818–1890) in Edinburgh after
1862 continued to be a chair in the Law of Nature and of Nations, a
combination well reflected in Lorimer’s teaching.105 Sir Travers
Twiss (1809–1897) who was much used as Foreign Office consultant,
taught at King’s College London in 1852–1855, but moved from
there to hold the Regius chair of civil law in Oxford until 1870. In
addition, private grants enabled the teaching of international law at
other universities as well.
33
109 “Never in the entire history of the world has a single power
exercised a world hegemony like that of the British in the middle of
the nineteenth century . . . Never since then has any single power
succeeded in re-establishing a comparable hegemony . . .
for no power has since been able to claim the the exclusive status of
‘workshop of the world,’” Eric Hobsbawm, The Age of Revolution
(London, Abacus, 1997 [1962]), p.
365.
34
Peace would follow from the uniting of nations (and their working
classes) brought about by the natural development of free trade and
increasing popular enlightenment – or, as some assumed, of
impending revolution.112
35
116 Cf. Brian Bond, War and Society in Europe 1870–1970 (London,
Fontana, 1983), pp.
26–28.
117 Emile de Laveleye, Des causes actuelles de guerre en Europe et
de l’arbitrage (Brussels and Paris, Muquerdt and Guillaumin, 1873),
p. 11.
36
becomes attached to its rights and the law.118 This was part of a
new literature that turned away from materialism and rationalism
and sought to invoke struggle and the depths of feeling. It now
seemed that the
States were always full of fear of each other, and hungry for more
wealth, honor, Herrschaft. No rational explanation could change this
aspect of their nature – to fantasize to the contrary would leave only
bitter disappointment.121 States had no purposes outside
themselves: indeed could not have because their very definition lay
in the aim of advancing the nations that inhabited them. They could
not accept a law above themselves without self-mutilation. There
was no analogy with individuals in the natural state:122
this dream of a legal order over and between States is a confused
and mindless dream that is born of weakness and false
sentimentality and has received the appearance of realisability and
reasonableness only through the misuse of words and unclear
ideas.123
121 Lasson, Princip und Zukunft, pp. 31–32. Cf. also pp. 7–9.
124 The rules of international law are rules of prudence rather than
law while obedience to them is dictated only by clever egoism,
Lasson, Princip und Zukunft, pp. 42–55.
37
38
“No right without its duties, no duty without its rights” as theirs. For
biographical 39
who a few years earlier had given the “Anglican Race”: “the obvious
task
. . . among other proud and sacred tasks, to rear and spread civil
liberty over vast regions in every part of the earth, on continent and
isle.”132
provided publicity and political support for such efforts. As Rolin was
corresponding with his acquaintances in Europe, the American
pacifists Elihu Burritt (1810–1879) and James B. Miles (1823–1875)
took up the proposal for a conference to draw up a code of
international law that their compatriot, the legal reformist David
Dudley Field (1805–1894) had already made in 1866 at the British
Association for the Promotion of Social Sciences. Miles – who could
speak no foreign language – was despatched to Europe in January
1873 and having met with peace activists and lawyers in Britain,
France, Italy, Austria, and Germany conferred with Rolin in Ghent in
early March 1873. Despite initial enthusiasm for the American
proposals, Rolin and the Europeans soon decided that they went
much further than the scientific restatement they had had in mind.
The Americans were seeking to establish an open organization
whose composition, aims, and working methods were directed
towards political influence, especially the revival of the peace
conferences, and deviated from those of the limited scientific
organization that had been contemplated in Europe.134 They were
part of an Footnote 131 ( cont. )
detail, apart from the above book by Hartigan, cf. Frank Freidel,
Francis Lieber.
138 In the course of the discussion in Ghent it had been argued that
the provision was quite ambitious. Nonetheless, it was maintained
because: “on a pensé qu’il était essentiel d’affirmer, pour ainsi dire
en tête des statuts, le lien intime qui doit exister entre le science
véritable du droit international et les inspirations de la conscience
public du monde civilisé” (1873), V RDI, p. 683.
41
The language came from the pen of the Swiss lawyer, Johann Caspar
Bluntschli, then Professor of Political Science at the University of
Heidelberg, an accomplished publicist in civil and public law, a
moderate-liberal politician and a Protestant activist. Already in
November 1872
This had not been the first time Bluntschli had had recourse to the
idea of a Rechtsbewusstsein der civilisierten Welt. In 1867 he had
had published his Das moderne Völkerrecht der civilisierten Staaten
als Rechtsbuch dargestellt. This book – like the idea of the Institute
– was also credited to Lieber and followed Lieber’s example in taking
the form of a prepared codification.140 Bluntschli explained that he
had chosen this form as he had not wished to report merely the
contents of existing treaties or customs
– this would have been unnecessary (as many books already did
this) but also counter-productive as it would have frozen the law’s
development: I was rather seduced by the contemporary idea to
formulate international law in terms that were clear and correct and
to articulate the legal norms that were held necessary or useful by
the consciousness of the civilized world. In this way I hope to
contribute as much as possible to the development of international
law.141
For Bluntschli, the essence of the legal craft was neither the
reporting of treaties, negotiated by diplomats with an eye for
immediate benefit, nor 139 “Das internationale institut für
Völkerrecht (Institut de droit international) soll dem gemeinsamen
Rechtsbewusstsein der civilisierten Welt zum wissenschaftlichen
Organe dienen.” J. C. Bluntschli, Denkwürdiges aus meinem Leben,
auf veranlassung der Familie durchgesehen und veröffentlicht von
Dr. Rudolf Seyerlen (3 vols., Nördlingen, Beck, 1884), III, p. 331.
42
That all (positive) law was Volksrecht did not contradict the
possibility of a general human law: “What lives in a single people is
only the general human nature that expresses itself in an individual
way.”147 For example, Savigny constructed private international law
in a way diametrically 142 Johann Caspar Bluntschli, Das moderne
Völkerrecht der civilisierten Staaten als Rechtsbuch dargestellt (2nd
edn., Nördlingen, Beck, 1872), p. vi.
144 Cf. Friedrich Carl von Savigny, Vom Beruf unserer Zeit für
Gesetzgebung und Rechtswissenschaft (Reprint of the 3rd edn.
[1840], Freiburg, Mohr, 1892).
145 “In dem gemeinsamen Bewusstsein des Volkes lebt das positive
Recht . . .,” Friedrich Carl von Savigny, System des heutigen
römischen Rechts (8 vols., Berlin, Veit, 1840), I, p. 14.
wing of the historical school against those who sought to replace the
study of classical Roman law by enquiries into the Germanistic ius
commune.151
The argument highlighted the position of the academic jurist. It was
the jurist’s task to bring, through a combination of historical and
“philosophical” study, the völkisch law into consciousness.
44
154 Wieacker, A History of Private Law, p. 311. Cf. also Carl Joachim
Friedrich, The Philosophy of Law in Historical Perspective (2nd edn.,
Chicago University Press, 1963), p. 140.
45
161 Cf. e.g. Peter von Oertzen, Die soziale Funktion des
staatrechtlichen Positivismus (Frankfurt, Suhrkamp, 1974), pp. 60–
71, 118–123, 154 et seq. Cf. also pp. 184–185 below.
162 His first publication in the field was Das moderne Kriegsrecht
der civilisierten Staaten (Nördlingen, Beck, 1866), a section of the
1867 work brought out in advance due to the Austro-Prussian war.
46
47
169 Maine, International Law, p. 49. Cf. also Collini, Public Moralists,
p. 303.
48
“The legal conscience of the civilized world”
book canvassed it – was born with classical Greece and Rome, was
consolidated at Westphalia, and now extended to native territories,
colonial government, and war. It consisted of European and
American States plus a few Christian nations elsewhere, such as “the
Hawaiian Islands, Liberia and the Orange Free State.”174 This was
not just some privileged political conglomerate but, in the words of
Francis Lieber “one family of advanced nations”175 whose “habits,
occupations and ideas . . .
[f]amily life and social life”176 – were the basis of international law:
The society of states, having European civilization, or the
international society, is the most comprehensive form of society
among men . . . The consent of the international society to the rules
prevailing in it is the consent of the men who are the ultimate
members of that society.
Bluntschli’s law was neither fixed on sovereign will nor drawn from
Roman law or moral theory but emerged spontaneously through the
lives of (European) peoples. Because spontaneous, this was a fragile
law 170 Maine, International Law, p. 51. Maine even held “that the
Law of Nations is essentially a moral and, to some extent, a religious
system,” p. 47.
172 Wheaton had already tackled the issue. Law of nations did not
have “laws” – for laws emanate from a political superior. If laws are
a necessary element of law, then international law is law only in a
metaphorical sense. But this had no effect on the tangible reality of
sovereigns everywhere aligning their behavior with certain rules of
conduct to which they had expressly or tacitly agreed. Cf. Henry
Wheaton, Histoire de progrès du droit des gens en Europe depuis la
paix de Westphalie jusqu’à nos jours (2 vols., 3rd edn., Leipzig,
Brockhaus, 1853), II, p. 370.
49
The organic position was a liberal position, not too far removed from
Rousseau’s views about national self-determination and radically
opposed to the conservative-monarchist tradition of early
nineteenth-century public law.179 As we have seen, already von
Mohl, Bluntschli’s predecessor in Heidelberg, had in 1860
constructed public law on the basis of a theory of representative
government, advocating a three-level analysis of international law as
relations between States, communities (or civil societies,
Gesellschaften), and individuals. This had led him to focus on
extradition law which emphasized the juxtaposition of statehood and
individual rights and allowed a terrain for a liberal politics in favor of
non-extradition for political offences.180 Bluntschli simply followed
up by arguing that sovereignty was always limited by the obligation
to guarantee the human rights of citizens and non-citizens alike.181
178 “Es hängt nicht von der Willkür eines Staates ab, das
Völkerrecht zu achten oder zu verwerfen,” Bluntschli, Das moderne
Völkerrecht, p. 58. On Rolin’s anti-voluntarism, cf.
50
The men of 1873 thought that to find out the law it did not suffice to
record what States had done or said. It was necessary to delve
deeper into the spirit and history of the community. But how does
the scholar do this? Where does one find international law, asks
Rolin, and responds: Not in express enactments which do not exist,
nor in precedents that may themselves be just or unjust, but in the
testimony of his conscience, illuminated and fortified by what the
wisest of men have decided in analogous cases. Thus the principles
posed by publicists in external law find their juridical and legislative
authority in their presumed conformity with human conscience.187
p. 226.
51
The law could be found only by looking inwards, into one’s own
normative intuitions whose authority lay in their being those of a
person educated in the canon of Western civilization. This was an
anti-formalist view: “International law increases in substance and
binding force in relation to the degree that the common conscience
of humanity increases in clarity and energy.”188 Bluntschli’s 1867
code, for instance, contained no separate treatment of formal legal
sources at all. Treaties appear only in paragraph 402 while the law in
the preceding 401 paragraphs emanated from a formless
Anerkennung or a consensus, extracted and justifiable partly
through history – that is to say custom – and partly through
philosophy – that is, the dictates of reason and ethics, including
52
In their legal theory, the men of 1873 turned inwards to look for a
law that they believed existed in their moral conscience, cultivated
by a humanitarian sensibility whose outward expression was their
alignment with the political liberalism of the day. The theory of the
text-writer as an organ of popular conscience–consciousness
legitimized the projection of that morality as an expression of what
was best in the cultural heritage of nineteenth-century Europe. The
microcosm of individual sensibilities and the macrocosm of public
law were experienced as aspects of one and the same reality.
Emphasis was less on the construction of rational systems – this was
an old-fashioned idea – than on the development and cultivation of
appropriate personal attitudes – on becoming “civilized,” in a word.
It is not by chance that most of the 194 Whether and to what extent
its precepts already applied outside its formal sphere of validity was
a problem that could be solved neither in a fully egoistic way nor
through some “pseudo-philanthropic Utopia.” Alphonse Rivier,
Lehrbuch des Völkerrechts (Stuttgart, Enke, 1889), pp. 3–5.
18–19, 59.
53
198 “Il est avant tout désirable que la bourgeoisie industrielle, les
agriculteurs et les autres classes sociales dont la commerce et la
division internationale du travail font la prospérité, aient une action
et une influence plus considérables dans l’administration de la
République. Ces classes forceront alors les représentants de la
nation à mettre les intérêts de l’humanité au-dessus de ces intérêts
factices et trompeurs, résultats de la politique étroite des
gouvernements,” Fiore, Le droit international codifié, p. 10.
54
“social necessities and the need to maintain the unity of the family”
required that the wife acquire the husband’s nationality, Fiore, Le
droit international codifié, p. 167.
55
56
215 Cf. Fiore, Le droit international codifié, pp. 84–85, 275–283. Cf.
also J. C. Bluntschli, Gesammelte kleine Schriften (2 vols.,
Nördlingen, Beck, 1879), II, pp. 279–312.
57
The great economic slump had started in Europe in the very year the
Institut was established. Apart from Britain, all European countries
returned to protective tariffs. The negative effects of industrialization
had become visible: pauperization of large populations was a reality
around many industrial centers – yet agriculture was the hardest hit
by the depression. As Bluntschli noted, in parts of civilized Europe
the condition of workers and peasants was worse than that of the
slaves of antiquity.220 While the tone of the economic debate
changed from optimism to pessimism, socialists could interpret the
turn to monopoly capitalism as the system’s last gasp before final
collapse.221
pp. 1–17.
137–168.
220 “Eigenthum,” in Gesammelte kleine Schriften, I, p. 221.
58
59
The Gentle Civilizer of Nations
One of the eleven founding members of the Institut was the Belgian
economist and Christian socialist Emile de Laveleye, who not only
participated actively in drafting its Statute but was the main author
of the Declaration that was intended to serve as the Institute’s
profession de foi.232
61
To make sure that the Institut would not appear to take sides in
political controversy, its early work concentrated on a pet theme of
Mancini’s and Asser’s, the drafting of international conventions on
private international law – particularly conflict of laws in civil,
commercial, and criminal matters. It also dealt with the procedures
of international arbitration and sought to codify the Washington
Rules that had been written into the Alabama compromis. When the
Institut did take a more activist line
62
p. 16.
63
1871. Bluntschli certainly never imagined that there was any conflict
between his nationalism and individual rights: each was defined in
terms of the other.246 The two also came together in his theory of
national self-determination: a law denying this, Bluntschli wrote,
would simply be an Unrecht. 247 For him as for Lieber, the defense
of individual liberty went hand in hand with a (moderate)
nationalism.248
Yet, all international lawyers espoused the cause of their State and
felt that its particular nationalism was of the beneficial variant. From
his seat in the first chamber of the Baden Parliament Bluntschli
became an active supporter of Bismarck’s “energetic” unification
policy.249 He even defended the integration of Schleswig-Holstein
into the German Confederation in 1863 on the basis of the national
idea – and not following the principle of dynastic succession as
provided in the London Treaty of 1852. He had no reservation about
the legitimacy of war to defend German honor if its just claims were
opposed: “We have to invest all, and thus we can accomplish all . . .
A nation of Germany’s greatness that defends its right and honor will
also emerge victorious from a difficult war.”250 Here nationalism
prevailed over individual rights; at least in Schleswig-Holstein it
sufficed that unification was “necessary,” even if the population
opposed it.251 Bluntschli also saw unification (at least under
Prussia) as a safeguard against French imperialism. But he was
critical both of German pride ( Hochmut) and French vanity (
Eitelheit) and ready to admit that French “femininity”
counterbalanced German
247 Bluntschli, “Die Entwickelung des Rechtes und die Recht der
Entwickelung,” in Gesammelte kleine Schriften, I, pp. 44–55.
251 “A part should not obstruct the whole,” Bluntschli, Das moderne
Völkerrecht, pp.
64
which most successfully compete in that fair field; but although that
may be the result it is not the object of the English ideal.”253
Westlake’s admiration of the “English ideal,” indissociable from his
admiration of liberalism, turned in this way into a nationalism that
provided no understanding for President Kruger’s position in the war.
Had the English Uitlanders been given a right to vote, Transvaal
would have ceased being independent. From Westlake’s perspective,
however, such independence had no real weight. He had no trouble
canvassing the eventual British annexation of Transvaal and the
Orange Free State.254
422.
65
By defining the relevant national link such a code would give effect
to the national character of the dispute wherever it was to be
decided.260
A few years later, Asser succeeded in mobilizing the Netherlands in a
massive effort for the development of rules of private international
law and the unification of law.261 His approach was entirely
pragmatic. He readily admitted that legal unification was not always
beneficial but sometimes required compromises on the part of
national legislatures that might violate the national sentiment.262
Care was to be taken so as not to direct international reform against
the autonomy of States or the powers of legislative organs.
Unification was to commence in the field of conflicts of laws where
reform seemed most urgent and least threatening to national
authorities.263
261 He shared the Prize in 1911 with the Austrian pacifist August
Fried. On the setting up of the Hague Conference on Private
International Law in 1894 cf. the report by Asser in (1894–1895), 13
Annuaire IDI, pp. 369–374.
66
This was not to deny the need for better worker protection or social
welfare schemes, he wrote, but to insist that how these should be
carried out was best left to national legislators.267 Alphonse Rivier,
Rolin’s friend from Brussels, wrote that the great dangers of the time
were racial hatred 264 Francis Lieber, Fragments of Political Science
on Nationalism and Internationalism (New York, Scribner, 1868), pp.
20–21.
67
68
Within the Institute, such views were not too extreme280 – even
Lieber associated socialism with despotism, “those fatal negations of
freedom,”
278 At its session of Geneva in 1892 the Institut did modify the
resolution of 1882 to the effect of exempting from non-extradition
crimes that were “directed against the basis of all social
organization, and not only against a determined State or a particular
form of government” (Art. 4). Règles internationales sur l’admission
et l’expulsion des étrangers, 9 September 1892 (1892–1894) 12
Annuaire IDI, p. 183.
280 Cf. also the remarks by Martens and Saripolos (1879–1880), 3–4
Annuaire IDI, pp.
265–276.
69
70
“anxious to see the law of the survival of the fittest and of natural
selec-tion adopted in human society.”287 Even as international
lawyers had no doubt about the superiority of European civilization
over “Orientals,”
they did stress that the civilizing mission needed to be carried out in
an orderly fashion, by providing good examples, and not through an
unregulated scramble.
The liberal jurists of 1873 could not fail to see the limitedness of
such concept of culture. Its mastery was hardly an adequate basis
for imagining oneself as the “organ” of a popular conscience–
consciousness. The old German textbooks gave much too much
weight to formal treaties 286 Lorimer, “La doctrine de
reconnaissance,” p. 335.
290 For the distinction, cf. e.g. Raymond Geuss, Morality, Culture,
and History. Essays on German Philosophy (Cambridge University
Press, 1999), pp. 33–44 and Terry Eagleton, The Idea of Culture
(Oxford, Blackwell, 2000), pp. 10–14.
71
Hence the early stress on comparative law and conflict of laws in the
Revue and the Institut.292 This created a practical problem,
however. It could hardly be expected that international lawyers
undertake ethnographic or sociological studies as a condition for
being able to say anything general about international law. Though
Bluntschli, for instance, argued that nations had different character
and that successful reform must be compatible with such
character,293 his 1867 code-book contained no character studies of
European nations. For the purposes of international law, he and his
colleagues assumed that whatever differences there existed between
European nations, they were sufficiently similar for there to be an
international law among them, and sufficiently different from non-
European peoples so as to preclude the extension of such law to the
latter.
72
295 This classification comes from Lorimer, Institutes, I, pp. 101 and
passim.
73
If international lawyers were truly for progress, then they could not
avoid also being preachers of the conversion of non-Europeans into
300 Cf. Bluntschli, “Der Stat ist der Mann,” in Gesammelte kleine
Schriften, I, pp. 278–283.
74
would hardly have been appreciated.307 It was left for his successor
in Oxford (after Pollock), Sir Paul Vinogradoff, much later to produce
an express theory of international law’s evolution through stages.308
As will be argued in more detail in chapter 2, when European
expansion 305 In fact, the materials for Maine’s magnum opus had
already been compiled and lectured on by him in the early 1850s. Cf.
Burrow, Evolution and Society, pp. 142–143.
75
reached its peak in the 1880s and 1890s, international lawyers made
only a superficial use of the theory of the degrees of civilization in
their attempt to grasp the legal aspects of the expansion.
Culture as character
The standard opposition of “civilization” to “barbarism” by Rolin and
his friends invoked a set of shared intuitions about what was
valuable and what was base in social life. If “barbarian” societies
were uncivilized, this meant they indulged in vice, lacked restraint
and moderation, that they were “fanatical,” untrustworthy, and
uneducated. Even at best, barbarians were, in the favourite
metaphor, like children who allowed their passions to rule their
behavior.309 If, as in Westlake, a more formal criterion such as
“absence of government” was invoked, it was done to draw attention
to the chaotic state of native life in which a “king or chief ” might
sign away anything simply because of being “such a drunkard as to
be subject to delirium tremens.”310 Westlake seems to have “found
the key to social problems in the development of individual
character.”311 He was a friend of Thomas Hughes, a later Principal
of the Working Men’s College of which Westlake was one of the
founders and the hugely popular theorist of Victorian character in
The Manliness of Christ.312 In his inaugural lecture at Cambridge
Westlake emphasized activism, charity and the sense of personal
responsibility, as central ideas around which international law was
constructed, over the narrow and technical definitions of the subject
as rules or principles formulated as mere abstractions.313 Moreover:
“No law national or international, will be durable unless it is fairly
well adapted to the character and circumstances of the men who are
to observe it.”314 Such and analogous statements focused on
personal virtue and especially on proper character as corner-stones
of a civilized morality, equally applicable in human lives as in the
lives of nations. But they were projections of what the men of 1873
411–412.
76
77
The Gentle Civilizer of Nations
Vitoria, Suarez and Las Casas were the favorites, perhaps as they
opposed Empires that had since collapsed – whose merit had been
their resolution against adversity. Grotius, too, was often portrayed
in this light and Bluntschli praised Pufendorff’s courage in his
separation of international law from Christian religion.322 In a way,
international legal history became a story of individual lawyers acting
like so many chivalrous knights, defending the oppressed against the
oppressors, peace against war, carrying the torch of civilization (from
Greece and Rome) through dark ages to the present. It was not
kings or diplomats but writers and scientists who finally woke up
“das schlummerende Rechtsbewusstsein der civilisierten Welt.”323
Twiss projected this ideal directly to the jurists of his day. The
international lawyer was “by his vocation placed senti-nel upon the
outworks of this system”:
78
more powerful, and to control the spirit of war and conquest, when
it attempts to overthrow the established doctrines of public law324
79
– the woman’s natural timidity made her unsuitable for politics. The
State must therefore obviously be a man: “Men form and lead the
State.
329 Bluntschli, “Die Einwirkung der nationalität auf die religion und
kirchlichen Dinge,”
80
For Rolin, the duty to keep the treaties was a matter of honesty and
of forthrightness; there was nothing more to it. External sanction,
for instance, was not a criterion of whether one was obligated or
not.335 The perspective of the Holmesian “bad man” is completely
absent from this image. Inasmuch as it sufficed to say ibi jus, ubi
societas to prove the existence of international law, the law’s basis
was set on a morality of sociableness. The system could work if
States were – or could be persuaded to become – reasonable and
moderate individuals whose main concern would be with the
protection of their freedoms (often seen as “fundamental rights”)
and the pursuit of material and spiritual progress through
cooperation.
332 “Die Entwickelung des Rechts und das Recht der Entwickelung,”
in Gesammelte kleine Schriften, I, pp. 53–55.
333 “Arische Völker,” pp. 74–75. A world State was impossible for
just this reason: “Denn die Völker und Nationen haben ihre
eigenthumliches Dasein. Ihr individuelle Character hat auch sein
Recht und seine Bedeutung. Sie sind zwar nur Gestaltungen
innerhalb des sie alle umfassenden Wesens der Menschheit, aber in
dieser ihrer Existenz unvertilgbar und nothwendig,” “Der Stat ist der
Mann,” p. 281.
81
One mark of the possession of the capacity for membership was the
possession of a municipal law “consonant with modern European
ideas,” p. 55.
82
“The legal conscience of the civilized world”
them joined
345 The general view was that war was a last resort for a State for
the vindication of its rights. Cf. e.g. Bonfils–Fauchille, Manuel, pp.
522–523. But note also Fiore, Le droit international codifié,
advocating collective war against the law-breaker, pp. 60–63.
346 “La guerre est donc un mal; mais, un mal inhérent à l’humanité
et indéracinable.”
83
84
352 Westlake, International Law, II, pp. 191, 192. Likewise, Fiore, Le
droit international codifié (“Sera considérée comme déloyale et
contraire au droit moderne la conduite de l’Etat qui commencerait les
hostilités sans déclaration de guerre préalable”), p. 306.
85
reflected for both Westlake and Maine the way in which it violated
the honorable conventions of the duel.354
The rules of such dueling, it goes almost without saying, apply only
in combat between the civilized. In colonial wars Westlake did not
find it difficult to imagine that a colonizer might need to take
“punitive expeditions” in cases of “inroads or other outrages
committed by savages of half civilised tribes.” In such cases “the
whole population must suffer for want of a government sufficiently
marked off from it.” Constraints in colonial war were, again, internal
to the belligerents’ virtue: “no humane officer will burn a village if he
has any means of striking a sufficient blow that will be felt only by
the fighting men.”355
Even in war, the social life of the members of the family of nations
was supposed to continue. No one was to be cast outside: the
complex norms regarding maritime neutrality (of the right of visit
and seizure, blockade, lists of contraband goods), for instance, were
disputed in detail between the British and the French – though
Harcourt’s criticism of Hautefeuille ironically shows just to what
extent national passions were involved.358 And when Bluntschli
advocated the almost complete leaving of private relations, including
commercial relations between the citizens 354 Maine, International
Law, pp. 148, 149. Cf. also Art. 88 on spies and 101 on deception in
war of the Lieber Code, Hartigan, Lieber’s Code, pp. 61, 63.
356 Cf. e.g. Art. 14–16 of the Lieber Code, Hartigan, Lieber’s Code,
p. 48.
86
of the belligerents, beyond the compass of war, this was quite logical
from the perspective of the effort to draw a rational limit between
the public and private realms – however much it went against earlier
teaching on the matter.359 But the very concept of such rules, and
their having a sensible objective, was never seriously questioned.
Indeed, the laws of war have perhaps never before nor since the
period between 1870 and 1914 been studied with as much
enthusiasm. Optimism in reason and the perfectibility of human
nature laid the groundwork for the view that men could be educated
to wage war in a civilized way. The “later Enlightenment consensus”
(an implicit agreement about the general rules: sparing civilians,
minimizing unnecessary harm, directing one’s acts at formal
enemies) mapped the mental terrain of civilized warfare.360
Where did this consensus come from? Until the Hague Conferences,
there were no general treaties on the laws of war.361 Grotius had
drawn from stories of chivalry, courage, and pity shown by fighting
men through history that reflected ideas of honor that were partly
constitutive of what he thought of as European civilization. That
such acts were cited in demonstration of natural law conceptualized
them within a framework of explanation with which cultured Europe
was familiar. The code proposed by Lieber and adopted by Lincoln in
1863 to govern the conduct of the armies of the Union was largely a
compilation of humanitarian principles taken from publicists from
Grotius onwards; it was animated by the need to define clearly the
distinction between public and private property; and it followed the
idea that war was a rational, public pursuit of limited objectives.
“Humanity” and “honor” were its guiding principles.362 The Martens
clause that became part of the 1899
87
This is why the men of 1873 did not possess a “theory of European
civilization” even as they stressed the need to find a historical and
cultural basis for law. Ubi societas ibi jus may have been a necessary
argument for a profession looking beyond naturalism and formalism,
but it did not ground a sociological program for the lawyers – as it
did for Marx, Durkheim, or Weber. But of course, none of these men
felt able to bank their reformism on the individual moralities of a
class of lawyers.
The elusive sensibility
The stories of the Revue and of the Institut are undoubtedly
narratives of (relative) failure. From its early association with broad
liberal–reformist 364 Hall, A Treatise, p. 411.
88
One set of reasons for such relative failure must be sought from the
general atmosphere of the period towards the turn of the century
which witnessed the general decline of European liberalism. The
1890s were a time of intellectual revolution in which the scientific
and political certainties of mid-century and of the 1880s – that
“stuffy decade” – were gradually brushed aside.368 Writing a
farewell address to his colleagues at the Institute on board a ship
that took him and his family to the Far East in September 1892,
Rolin expressed the wish that the Institute would not succumb to a
time of “the most extreme opinions” and his conviction that
moderation would prevail, “persuadé que la verité, comme la vertu,
se trouve au milieu.”369 Yet, such optimistic centrism was
increasingly viewed as shallow theory and unworkable practice. It
had failed to engage accumulating evidence that passion and desire
–
372 Cf. the obituaries of Westlake by Edouard Rolin (1913), XLV RDI,
pp. 265–270; T. E. Holland (1913), 26 Annuaire IDI, pp. 698–700;
Albéric Rolin (1913), 26 Annuaire IDI, pp. 701–712. Cf. also Fischer
Williams, “Introduction,” pp. 10–11, 13 as well as the essays on
Westlake’s life in Memories of Westlake generally.
90
91
The men of 1873 were not satisfied with the rationalism of the
successive editions and translations of von Martens and Klüber, nor
the passion for “system” in Kaltenborn’s 1847 treatise. These were
too abstract and cold for the tastes of men educated in the
teachings of the historical school and active politicians in the liberal
cause. The contribution of Grotius or Pufendorff had been valuable
in its time but incompatible with modern legal science, unable to see
law as a historically and 376 Oertzen, Die gesellschaftliche Funktion,
p. 119. Similarly, Georg Jellinek, “Johann Caspar Bluntschli,” in
Ausgewählte Schrifte und Reden (2 vols., Berlin, Häring, 1911), II,
pp.
289–291.
92
Yet they could not fully reject rationalism, either, for it was an aspect
of the culture they so appreciated. They needed it to oppose the fin-
de-siècle dangers of anarchism, nationalism, and war as well as to
create distance between their societies and what colonial
administrators encountered as they penetrated deeper into
“uncivilized” territory. So they theorized rationalism and natural law
into a default position, a last reservoir from which to grasp
arguments when other sources ran dry.
For them, the legal status of slavery or the slave trade could not be
inferred from cultural habits but directly from human nature: that
the slave trade had been agreed as illegal by treaty was a measure
of the moral conscience of European nations. But illegality could not
be dependent on such agreement – even if there might not always
exist positive guarantees to enforce it.385 The new generation
would not allow cultural arguments to encroach upon its liberal
conscience. That conscience might sometimes express itself through
a formal natural law argument, but more often it was simply taken
for granted that the equal freedom of human beings was applicable
everywhere and transgressed the limits of relativism justifying, for
instance, Christian intervention (as 382 For an early example, cf.
John Westlake, “Commercial Blockade (1862),” in Collected Papers,
pp. 312–361.
383 For a recent discussion of these cases, cf. Alfred B. Rubin, Ethics
and Authority in International Law (Cambridge University Press,
1997), pp. 101–108.
94
95
96
97
1870–1914
98
behavior in the colonies, the ground from which they argued for
humane treatment of the natives was an outdated concept of natural
law that had little intellectual credibility even in their own
professional milieu. Most of them agreed with Theodor Woolsey
(1801–1889), President of Yale and the author of a leading American
textbook of the period, that lawyers making use of natural principles
were in fact spinning the web of a system out of their own brains as
if they were legislators of the world.7 In their nostalgicreferences to
a universal natural law they were ignoring the extent to which even
the philosophes had wondered about the appropriateness of
applying identical precepts for the administration of all societies. The
ambivalence about the powers of natural reason was plainly evident
in Montesquieu whose Esprit des lois distinguished between “laws in
general” that were based on human reason and thus applicable to all
nations and laws in particular: “that should be in relation to the
nature and principle of each government . . . to the climate of each
country, to the quality of its soil, to its situation and extent . . .
itics for which colonies are not just ends in themselves, but also
pawns in global power games.” Jürgen Osterhammel, Colonialism. A
Theoretical Overview (trans. from German S. L. Frisch, Princeton,
Wiener, 1997), p. 21. In this chapter, imperialism appears as an
insistence on the extension of formal European sovereignty in the
colonies.
Neumann (New York and London, Hafner & Collier, 1949 [1748]), p.
6.
100
Europeans came into contact with societies and cultural forms that
seemed to share little of what they felt was the common core of
their civilized identity. How were they to think of such societies and
Europe’s relationship to them? In the eighteenth century, Europeans
had often either dismissed primitive societies on account of their not
partaking of the same kind of humanity as that enjoyed by the
Europeans, or idealized them into Noble Savages, representatives of
a Golden Age lost to Europe.9 Neither attitude had much by way of
reasoned background and they often emerged in connection with
stories intended to make a political point about present Europe
rather than to provide a basis for thinking about foreign cultures. In
the course of the first half of the nineteenth century, such attitudes
gave way to more historicized explanations such as the Comparative
Method that viewed primitive peoples as earlier stages of human
development in an overall law-like frame of progressive history.10 By
the 1870s the assumption of human development proceeding by
stages from the primitive to the civilized had come to form the
bedrock of social anthropology and evolutionary sociology that
provided much of the conceptual background for cultivated European
reflection about what Europeans often sweepingly termed the
Orient.11
183–196.
[1871]) and Primitive Culture (2 vols., New York, Harper, 1958). The
idea of a universal history as “the realization of a hidden plan of
nature to bring about an internally
101
“civilization” that now took the place of natural law as the universal
standard of evaluation and with the force of apparent natural
necessity called for European expansion. Law, wrote Bluntschli’s
successor in Heidelberg, August von Bulmerincq (1822–1890), was
the guardian of 12 For a good description of “pedigree history,” cf.
Raymond Geuss, Morality, Culture and History. Essays on German
Philosophy (Cambridge University Press, 1999), pp. 1–3.
102
expressed in the fact that although the man was the head of the
house-hold, his power over family members was not unlimited. The
right of property and especially of the ownership of land were
distinctly Aryan institutions, designed to give human beings “eine
feste Heimat.”19
Above all, the Aryans were State people, Bluntschli wrote, having 16
A. Bulmerincq, “La politique et le droit dans la vie des états” (1877),
IX RDI, p. 364.
103
104
105
106
107
Civilization is not a veneer; it must penetrate the very heart and core
of societies of men. Its true signs are thought for the poor and
suffering, chivalrous regard and respect for woman, the frank
recognition of human brotherhood irrespective of race or colour or
nation or religion, the narrowing of the domain of mere force as a
governing factor in the world, the love of ordered freedom,
abhorrence of what is mean and cruel and vile, ceaseless devotion to
the claims of justice.42
Westlake and Hall absented public law completely from the relations
of protecting and protected communities: the only international law
duties owed by the colonizer were towards other colonizers. Nor did
colonization bring any determinate administrative duties. The
situation in different protected territories differed so radically that
the colonizing State
“must be left to judge how far it can go at a given time, and through
what form of organisation it is best to work.”45
108
109
would have provided the Age of Empire with any better credentials.
After the Napoleonic wars, European expansion took place with little
sense of a conscious process. Europeans had expressed some
systematic interest in the exploration of non-European spaces in the
eighteenth century but the upheavals of century’s end made the
society turn inwards. Great Power diplomacy sought to reconstruct
the European equilibrium and with the exception of the Eastern
Question, the European Concert focused until 1884 exclusively on
European affairs.
Russia moved back and forth in the east and Austria was
preoccupied in the Balkans.
110
58 Cf. e.g. Gann and Duignan, The Burden of Empire, pp. 12–14,
18–19. As late as 1876, the capitalist and humanitarian William
Mackinnon aimed to conclude a treaty with the Sultan of Zanzibar
that would have given Mackinnon’s company sovereign rights over
the area between the East African coast and the Great Lakes.
Salisbury intervened out of fear of formal engagements that this
might have entailed. Five years later still, Gladstone politely refused
the Sultan’s request for the establishment of a British Protectorate
over this strategically placed island. Cf. Wesseling, Le partage de
l’Afrique, pp. 189–190.
111
112
On the other hand, however, von Martens and Klüber both felt they
needed to say something of the world beyond Europe. Both were
educated in the Aufklärungsideale of the eighteenth century and like
Montesquieu, Kant, or Rayneval held that natural law provided for
the equal worth of individuals, irrespective of race or religion. They
thus espoused quite a liberal conception of the right of native
ownership.
that was evident – but also in how secondary sources (the nature of
the thing, tacit agreement and analogy) presuppose a cultural
knowledge of the sphere in which it is to be applied. Friedrich
Saalfeld, Handbuch des positiven Völkerrechts (Tübingen, Ostander,
1833), pp. 4–5.
65 Saalfeld, Handbuch, p. 5.
113
Klüber and von Martens would probably have agreed. At any rate,
they took no exception to the famous construction of British title to
American territory by the argument crystallized in Chief Justice
Marshall’s 1823
decision that allowed the Indians a right of occupancy but gave the
Federal Government as possessor of sovereignty the power to
extinguish it.69 On the other hand, they were not dealing with
European publiclaw claims over vast stretches of territory. When
they wrote, the Orient was still principally an object of commerce,
travel, and proselytizing. The colonial encounter took place between
individual natives or native tribes on the one side and private
individuals, missionaries, humanitarian associations, and trade
companies on the other. Beyond appealing to humane behavior on
both sides, there was no need to envisage norms governing the
formal relations between European and non-European communities,
even less of jurisdictional boundaries between European States.
At the same time, lawyers were digesting the lesson of the historical
school, and emphasized the cultural limits of European diplomatic
law.
114
Sovereignty: a gift of civilization observed by that portion of the
human race in their mutual intercourse.”
Klüber and von Martens did not call their international law the Droit
public de l’Europe for nothing. For Wheaton, as for later professional
lawyers, Western consular jurisdiction as it existed in 1836 in Turkey,
the Barbary States, and other Islamic countries was but a logical
offshoot of the law’s cultural peculiarity: Europeans were to be
governed by European law; anything else would be arbitrariness.
115
116
75–83.
117
118
90 Cf. Robinson and Gallagher, with Denny, Africa and the Victorians,
pp. 193–202.
91 Cf. Robinson and Gallagher, with Denny, Africa and the Victorians,
pp. 290–294, 307–330; Wesseling, Le partage de l’Afrique, pp. 253–
264.
119
Two years later, Germany took over German East Africa as a formal
protectorate.92 By 1895 all German colonies in Africa (South West
Africa, Togo, Cameroons, German East Africa) had come under direct
imperial Schutzgewalt, as much parts of the Empire under
international law as departments or provinces.93 With the brutal
crushing of the Herero uprising in South West Africa in 1905 and the
“Maji-Maji”
It was impossible not to rule and yet insist on internal reform and
abolition of the slave trade.98 Even Gladstone’s liberal government
that had in 1880 come to power on a vocally anti-imperialist
platform two years 92 Cf. Wesseling, Le partage de l’Afrique, pp.
200–203, 221–222; Thomas Pakenham, The Scramble for Africa
1876–1912 (New York, Random House, 1991), pp. 346–349.
94 For the two wars, cf. e.g. Pakenham, Scramble for Africa, pp.
602–628.
120
121
The Gentle Civilizer of Nations
537–546.
122
109 Cf. e.g. Salomon, L’occupation, p. 96; Jèze, Etude théorique, pp.
32–36 and Jörg Fisch,
123
The rule was also limited in time and space: it was to apply only to
new acquisitions and only to acquisitions on the coasts – at a time
when there was practically no coast left to occupy. Significantly, the
Conference refused to apply it to the African interior because this
would have required an exact determination of the formal claims of
the powers and would have resulted “en fait à une partage de
l’Afrique” – something the Conference was desperate to avoid.111
5–7, and Fisch, “Africa as terra nullius,” pp. 358–360, 363–366. For a
positive assessment, cf. Sir Travers Twiss, “Le congrès de Vienne et
la conférence de Berlin” (1885), XVII RDI, p. 215.
124
119 “none of the thirty-eight clauses of the General Act had any
teeth. It had set no rules for dividing, let alone eating, the cake.”
Pakenham, Scramble for Africa, p. 254.
120 Cf. also G. N. Uzoigwe, “The Results of the Berlin West Africa
Conference: An Assessment,” in Förster, Mommsen, and Robinson,
Bismarck, Europe, and Africa, pp. 542–544.
125
of the General Act did not determine anything about the behavior of
European States, they both divested European expansion from some
of its potential burdens (by limiting “effectiveness” undefined) and
allowed private interest to parade as public interest – as well as
irreversibly excluding any pretensions to sovereignty that indigenous
communities might have entertained. Articles 34 and 35 treated
“sovereignty” as a quality that could attach only to a European
possession.121 Moreover, sovereignty was treated first and foremost
as an exclusivity, unaccompanied by clearly defined obligations.
Much of the drafting process was constituted of the watering down
of the duties of the colonizing power.
121 The proposal was made by the United States delegate Mr.
Kasson that the conference might also discuss the rights of
indigenous tribes, pointing out that international law: “suit
fermement une voie qui mène à la reconnaissance de droit des races
indigènes de disposer librement d’elles-mêmes et de leur sols
héréditaires,” and suggesting that his government would be
prepared to require that acquisition be based on free consent. To
this, the Chairman Mr. Busch observed that “M. Kasson touche à des
questions délicates sur lesquelles la Conférence ne saurait pas
éxprimer d’opinion,” “Le Conférence de Berlin,” de Martens, Nouveau
recueil, X, pp. 335–336.
122 Cf. the criticism in e.g. Jèze, Etude théorique, pp. 265–267.
126
It regulates, for the mutual benefit of the civilised states, the claims
which they make to sovereignty over the region and leaves the
treatment of the natives to the conscience of the state to which
sovereignty is awarded.”126
127
After all, even he held that the treatment of the natives was a
matter of Western conscience – a notion not bereft of legal
implications, as we saw in chapter 1. In a polemic of 1910
concerning the character of the relationship between the British
Government and the native States of India (that is to say, the
“territories outside British India [ruled by] Native Princes and Chiefs
under the suzerainty of the Crown”), Westlake emphatically rejected
the idea that such relations could ever come under international law.
They were relations of British constitutional law – yet this meant also
that “the same principles of natural justice which underlie
international law must be applied to their relations.”129
130 For a useful early review, cf. Mérignhac, Traité de droit public
international, II, pp.
430–435.
314–315.
128
At the other end of the spectrum were the critical articles and
interventions within the Institut by the Swiss lawyer Joseph
Hornung. He attacked not only Western brutality in the colonies but
also its double standards: if intervention in favor of oppressed
Christians in Turkey had been lawful throughout the century, it
should also have been possible to intervene in favor of Africans and
Asians living under tyrannical rule.
129
p. 245.
140 The two attitudes – full differentiation and full identification –
structured European attitudes towards the natives from the outset. A
classic discussion of the way that the logic of identification in a
Spanish “defender of the Indians” such as Bartolomé de Las Casas
and the logic of difference in the conquistador Hernando Cortés
betrayed
130
In the second place, this gives too much credit to the “universalism”
of earlier jurists such as Grotius or Vattel, or indeed Klüber and von
Martens. They used natural law because in the absence of large
numbers of treaties, arbitrations, or a profession of commentators
there was little else on which they could rely. More importantly, their
“universalism” was a projection of their Western humanism, a
secular variant of the Christian view of a single God. This may or
may not have been politically admirable (the Conquistadores, after
all, were also universalists). But in terms of dealing with otherness,
the historical school had at least recognized the hypocrisy that was
the flip side of universalism – the technique of including the non-
European into a universe of European concepts by doing away with
native identity (for instance, by excluding native ownership of land
through the imposition of a thoroughly European standard of
“cultivation of the soil” as condition of ownership).143
But if the distinction between the civilized and the uncivilized did
structure colonial international law at the end of the nineteenth
century, it did so accompanied by considerable doubt about its
adequacy. Even Lorimer’s threefold division between civilized,
barbarian (or half-civilized), and savage (uncivilized) nations seemed
too crude for application in special studies that increasingly drew
upon anthropological and sociological accounts such as Tylor’s 1871
study of primitive culture.144
143 Cf. Richard Tuck, The Rights of War and Peace. Political Thought
and the International Order from Grotius to Kant (Oxford University
Press, 1999), pp. 106–108 and 195–196.
131
149 A final question dealt with the possible need to adopt measures
to regulate the maritime transport of Chinese “coolies.” Cf. (1877), 1
Annuaire IDI, pp. 51, 141–142.
132
As to the latter, Twiss had become convinced that there was no such
difference between the ideas and faith of Christian and Oriental
nations or in their attitudes towards the pacta sunt servanda, that
the latter could not be admitted in the community of nations. The
difficulties lay not in theory but in practice, in enforcement. Many of
China’s and Turkey’s treaties, for instance, had been made after
defeat in war. Attitudes to implementation therefore remained
hostile. Were China, for instance, free to do so, it would immediately
repudiate the treaties of Tientsin and Peking (1858 and 1860) and
return to isolation.151 Religious views were generally tolerant –
although a special difficulty concerned Islamic attitudes towards
Christians. The experts agreed that the time for lifting the protective
veil of consular jurisdiction had not yet arrived, although it should be
better organized so as to avoid the injustices that often accompanied
it.152
154 Cf. e.g. Paternostro, “La revision des traités avec le Japon au
point de vue du droit international” (1891), XVIII RDI, pp. 10, 177–
182 and the report by de Martens in (1882), XIV RDI, pp. 324–328.
133
160 The powers, Salisbury pointed out in 1877, had granted Turkey’s
territorial integrity only on condition that it would not mistreat its
subjects. If it did so, in the eyes of the European powers, then that
grant was withdrawn. Gustave Rolin-Jaequemyns,
135
freely of their own accord, for themselves and their heirs and
successors for ever
As Stanley was still making provisions for the voyage, de Brazza was
advancing on the north bank of the river, formally as an agent of the
French national committee of the Association Internationale Africaine
that 163 The Comité was organized as a private company with an
initial budget of 1 million Belgian francs, provided by an international
group of financers, Pakenham, Scramble for Africa, p. 146. Léopold
wrote to Stanley at the end of 1881:”La Belgique ne désire aucun
territoire en Afrique, mais il est indispensable que vous achetiez pour
le Comité des études autant de terrain qu’il vous est possible de
obtenir, et que vous placiez successivement sous la souveraineté de
Comité, dès que possible et sans perdre une minute, tous les chefs,
depuis l’embouchure du Congo jusqu’aux chutes Stanley.” Letter
reproduced in Georges Henri Dumont, Léopold II (Paris, Fayard,
1990), p. 172.
136
During his time in King Léopold’s service Stanley alone was said to
have concluded at least as many as 257 such treaties.170 As
Salomon wrote,
“there was scarcely a modern traveller who would not have found
himself in the role of a diplomatic agent and would not have
attached to his collection of souvenirs some treaty of territorial
cession.”171
197–199, 207–208.
137
pointed out: “it must also be asked whether the acquisition conforms
to ideas of justice, whether the acquisition of certain territories does
not constitute, from a purely moral point of view, a reprehensible
act, in a word, whether the occupation, as manifestation of
acquisition, is legitimate.”172 Native consent given in a treaty of
cession seemed to constitute an irreproachable moral–legal basis for
European title and did away with the suspicion that Europeans were
merely following in the footsteps of the fifteenth-and sixteenth-
century empires. Clearly, it was a problematic practice. Despite the
(somewhat ambiguously formulated) proposal by the American
delegate at the Berlin Conference, Mr. Kasson, however, no
requirement of native consent was included in the Berlin Act –
although the conference did recommend that such consent be
normally secured. The problem was both conceptual and practical.
First, as the Martitz Report pointed out: “[a] treaty of cession cannot
be concluded by entities other than States that recognize
international law.”173
175 The treaties that Peters claimed as the basis of his annexations
in East Africa had been made in the German language.
177 Cf. also Rivier, Lehrbuch, p. 136; Nys, Le droit international, II,
pp. 111–116.
For such reasons, a second group insisted that native treaties were
indispensable ingredients or even the only legally valid basis of
European title.182 Though the Berlin Conference had not accepted
the American proposal to this effect, it had expressly recommended
it. And the practice was treated as serious by the powers
themselves. By the 1920s, attitudes had changed to the extent that
a leading authority on the issue held it to be a majority view that the
natives could dispose over their lands and that European sovereignty
should normally be based on 179 Cf. John Westlake, International
Law (2 vols., 2nd edn., Cambridge University Press, 1910), I, pp.
123–124; Chapters, pp. 144–155; Pasquale Fiore, “Du protectorat
colonial et de la sphère d’influence (hinterland)” (1907), XIV RGDIP,
pp. 150–151.
180 Later lawyers have sometimes associated this position with the
theory of legal positivism. This, however, is wrong as we have seen,
for neither Rolin nor Westlake was a positivist in any clear sense.
182 This position is in a very absolute form in Henri Bonfils and Paul
Fauchille, Manuel de droit international public (2nd edn., Paris,
Rousseau 1898), pp. 280–281. From the fact that the texts of the
treaties often referred to the local chief as sovereign entitled to
dispose of land rights, Alexandrowicz draws the doubtful conclusion
that they were actually so regarded. Alexandrowicz, The European–
African Confrontation, pp. 30–40, 118–122, 127–128.
139
321–325.
140
Engelhardt, for instance, held that the parties in Berlin had solved
this question by recommending that treaties (either of cession or of
protectorate) be always concluded with the non-European
community.
Whichever legal position one took was in the main compatible with
colonial interest, yet had its difficulties, too. European predominance
could be secured by granting the validity of colonial treaties as well
as dismissing them. When colonial enthusiasts such as the Belgian
professor and later Secretary-General of the Institut Baron
Descamps (1847–1933) insisted that indigenous chiefs were
perfectly capable of transferring sovereignty, they seemed to imply a
normative universe in which the Europeans and the Africans acted as
formal equals.192 Such universalism, however, had nothing to
foreclose the possibility or even likelihood of manipulation. To deal
with this problem, lawyers automatically retreated to paternalism:
the native was unable to understand his interests. To be a
universalist and yet to acknowledge cultural difference was 188
Frantz Despagnet, Essai sur les protectorats (Paris, Larose, 1896),
pp. 246–251; S.
190 “Der naturliche Billigkeit und der bona fides der zivilisierten
Staaten,” Heimburger, Erwerb, p. 114.
141
196 This remains invisible for such critics such as Alexandrowicz and
Gong who associate colonialism with positivism.
142
198 Dumont, Léopold II, p. 175. Cf. also Thomson, La Fondation, pp.
147–162.
144
145
(1890), XXII RDI, pp. 599–602. By 1895 all German colonies had
become formal parts of the Empire while only in New Guinea did
there remain a company to carry out some administrative tasks. Cf.
Von Stengel, “La constitution et l’administration des colonies
allemandes” (1895), III Revue de droit public et de la science
politique en France et à l’étranger, pp. 275–292.
146
Such events were a shock to those who had hoped that Western
civilization would be adopted by indigenous populations almost
automatically. Demands were made for a “strong hand” in guiding
the natives to the path of civilization. Liberia and Haiti were held by
the 1870s as
Rolin interpreted the crushing of the Abushiri rebellion and the full-
scale blockade of the East African coast as part of the struggle
against slave-trading Arabs.219 To achieve pacification, international
lawyers 214 Hyam, Britain’s Imperial Century, pp. 150–154.
216 Gann and Duignan, The Burden of Empire, pp. 128–129; Hyam,
Britain’s Imperial Century, pp. 159–161.
147
For such reasons, from the first clashes of colonial powers outside
Europe – in the Far East, in Africa, and in the Pacific Ocean in the
1870s
The law of occupation was seen as great progress from earlier ages.
234–235, 260.
148
227 For some such ambivalence, cf. Salomon, L’occupation, pp. 263–
273.
149
In his study for the Institut on the effects of the Berlin Act on the
law of colonial occupation, the German professor Martitz proposed
that it should always be possible to occupy a territory or set up a
protectorate over an area that did not already come under the
sovereignty or protectorate of one of the States members of the
international legal community (“des Etats qui forment la
communauté de droit des gens”). This proposal was rejected,
however, as many members held that the treatment of almost all
non-European territory as res nullius in this way went simply too far.
As no other proposal was adopted either, the conditions of
occupation (or protectorate) were left obscure.229 As far as the
resulting obligations were concerned, Martitz tried almost to reverse
the position attained in Berlin by suggesting that occupation and
protectorate (“occupation à titre de protectorat”) should both entail
at least some degree of formal rule.230 Occupation was to be
accompanied by the establishment of a responsible local government
with sufficient means to ensure the regular exercise of its authority.
The establishment of a protectorate would have required setting up
some system to protect acquired rights and to see to the education
of the natives. However, no formal occupation by Europeans would
have been required.231
229 For discussion, cf. Fisch, Die europäische Expansion, pp. 330–
332 and Despagnet, Essai, pp. 231–234.
150
151
240 The Mahdi, or Sheikh Muhammad Ahmad ‘Abd Allah, was the
leader of the Mahdist rebellion against the English and the de facto
ruler of the Sudan in 1885–1898.
152
July 1898.
The French had assumed that the rules of the scramble had been
laid out in Berlin and based sovereign rights on actual occupation (or
at least 242 Lewis, Fashoda, pp. 47–59; Pakenham, Scramble for
Africa, pp. 465–467.
243 For the end of the Fashoda crisis, cf. e.g. Lewis, Fashoda, pp.
206–230 and the graphic description in Pakenham, Scramble for
Africa, pp. 524–556. The quote is from Pakenham, p. 552.
153
247 Cf. e.g. Mérignhac, Traité de droit public international, II, pp.
444–447.
154
155
156
157
Finally the pressure on the King built up to the extent that he was
compelled to transfer the territory to Belgium in 1908 – though not
without 260 There is a wealth of writing on the system of
administration set up in the Congo in and after 1885. Cf. e.g. Roger
Anstey, King Leopold’s Legacy: The Congo under Belgian Rule 1908–
1960 (Oxford University Press, 1966), pp. 1–10. The facts were
revealed to Belgian audiences by Félicien Cattier, Etude sur la
situation de l’Etat indépendant du Congo (Brussels and Paris, Larcier
and Pedone, 1906). A more recent account is Hochschild, King
Leopold’s Ghost, pp. 115–181.
158
265 Cf. e.g. Bonfils–Fauchille, Manuel, pp. 81–82, 178; von Liszt,
Das Völkerrecht, pp. 40, 43–44 passim.
263–281.
159
160
Sovereignty: a gift of civilization considered vacant lands as State
property; all colonial powers used methods that were in use in the
Congo. How the State dealt with vacant lands was in any case not a
matter for international law but for the State’s own constitutional
and private law to resolve. “A State uses the territories that
constitute its private domain as it wishes; it sells them, it rents them
out, it attaches such conditions to the concessions it grants as it
sees warranted . . . in none of this does it owe an explanation to
other States.”272 No violation of the free trade provisions of the
Berlin Act was involved, Nys claimed. Neither State ownership of
vacant lands nor the granting of concessionary rights constituted a
monopoly under Article 5 which prohibited the parties only from
establishing “any kind of commercial monopoly or privilege”
(“monopole et privilège d’aucune sorte en matière commerciale”):
this concerned only the right to buy and sell, to import and to
export, and had nothing to do with property rights over natural
resources.273 In a lengthy, pedantic survey of the status of the
Congo State in light of the events of 1884–1885 Nys joined the other
Belgians in arguing that the recognitions did not possess constitutive
character and that in any case, neither they nor the obligations of
the Berlin Act conditioned the statehood of the Congo in any
way.274 He maintained that the Congo had carefully complied with
all the provisions of the Berlin Act, including those having to do with
the protection of the indigenous people: “The Independent State of
the Congo has not neglected any effort, has not spared itself any
sacrifice in order to realize the humanitarian wishes of the
Conference of Berlin of 1884 and 1885.”275
329–332.
161
162
163
288 Westlake continued publishing until his death in 1913 but none
of his (published) writings dealt with the humanitarian problem in
the Congo. For bibliography, cf.
164
165
One obvious paradox should have set alarm bells ringing that all was
not right. The argument about the civilizing mission was completely
unhelpful as discussion turned to disputes between the colonial
powers themselves. Reading through the first three decades of
Rolin’s Revue, one gets no sense that colonization was viewed as a
common European venture. Although all lawyers spoke in terms of a
homogeneous
166
299 The main critic being Jèze. Good reviews of the new French
attitudes towards colonization through commerce in the 1890s are to
be found in Coquery-Vidrovitch, Le Congo, pp. 25–30 and Pierre
Guillen, L’expansion (Politique étrangère de la France 1881–1898,
Paris, Imprimerie nationale, 1984), pp. 53–69. Despagnet draws
critical attention to this practice in the second edition of his Cours de
droit international public, pp. 429–432.
167
The Belgians, as we have seen, apart from Cattier (who was not an
inter-
168
169
170
At the end of the First World War, popular opinion had turned
decisively against formal empire. Territorial gains had also been
excluded from the Allied war aims. Thus the question arose what to
do with the former German colonies and the non-Turkish parts of the
Ottoman empire that had been handed over to the entente
powers.313 As one among his fourteen points, President Wilson
declared to the US Senate in early 1919 that the subject peoples’
interests should be at the same level as those of established powers
and that the “well-being of peoples not yet able to stand by
themselves . . . forms a sac red trust of civilization.” As is well
known, the result was limited League supervision of three classes of
former German and Turkish colonies: the “A” mandates (Syria and
Lebanon, Palestine and Transjordan, and Iraq), that received internal
self-government and were expected to become independent at a
future date, the “B” mandates (the Cameroons, Togoland,
Tanganyika, Rwanda-Urundi) for whose administration the
mandatory remained responsible, and the “C” mandates (South West
Africa and the Pacific Islands) that were to be administered as
integral parts of the Mandatory’s territory.314 It was unclear how the
system should be legally characterized. The involvement of the Allied
Supreme Council, the Mandatory powers, the League and individual
States (especially the United States) created a long-standing
controversy on where sovereignty over the mandated territories lay,
and how wide-ranging were the duties 311 Cf. The League of
Nations, The Mandates System; Origin – Principles – Applications
(League of Nations Publications, Geneva, 1945), pp. 7–13. Cf. also
Alexandrowicz, The European–African Confrontation, pp. 115–116.
313 The distribution was carried out within the Allied Supreme
Council in January 1919.
314 For the establishment of the mandates system, cf. e.g. Albert
Millot, Les mandats internationaux. Etude sur l’application de l’article
22 du Pacte de la Société des Nations (Paris, Larose, 1924), pp. 5–
86.
171
317 Cf. Henri Rolin, “Le système des mandats coloniaux” (1920),
III/1 RDI, pp.
329–363.
172
with
federalist
proposals.
Sir
John
Fischer
Williams
173
326 Cf. League of Nations, The Mandates System, pp. 46–51 and for
the conditions of independence under the mandates system, Annex,
pp. 118–120.
175
For those institutions do not carry the good society with themselves.
176
Here lies the difficulty. Institutions do not replace politics but enact
them.
178
1871–1933
“[T]he victorious war is the social ideal: the victorious war is the
ultimate means for every highest objective. In war the State
demonstrates its real being, it is the fullest proof of the special
quality of the State . . .
In the victorious war legal thought sets the ultimate norm which
decides which State has Right on its side . . . Who can, may also.”1
These are certainly among the most frequently quoted sentences
from Erich Kaufmann’s (1880–1972) 1911 book Das Wesen des
Völkerrechts und die Clausula rebus sic stantibus which expounded a
theory of the total State as Europe’s historical and spiritual reality.
For Kaufmann, a conservative legal theorist and a practitioner –
including being a legal adviser at the foreign ministry of the Federal
Republic in the 1950s – and a member of the Institut de droit
international, the view of international law as superior to the State
emerged from an unhistorical moral nihilism. Because the State –
and not the shallow and discontinuous realm of the cosmopolitan –
was the concrete enfolding of human spirituality, international law
could never aspire to a normativity higher than the State. Useful as a
mechanism of coordination, international law possessed no intrinsic
value, represented no world-historical process of enlightenment or
transcendence. No social ideal was embedded in it. Therefore, all
treaties bore an implicit reservation: they were valid only as far as
the conditions that were present at their conclusion did not change
so that the 1 Erich Kaufmann, Das Wesen des Völkerrechts und die
Clausula rebus sic stantibus (Tübingen, Mohr, 1911), pp. 146, 153.
The first sentence makes a hidden reference to Rudolf Stammler’s
Kantian view of a “community of persons of free will” as the social
ideal.
179
3 Writing 50 years later, Kaufmann still held that this “youthful” work
contained the nucleus of all his later oeuvre. Erich Kaufmann,
Rechtsidee und Recht. Gesammelte Schriften ( GS ) (3 vols.,
Göttingen, Schwartz, 1960), III, p. xx.
180
The total State of 1911 and the “collective spirit” of 1935 both
articulate a transgression, an attempt to overcome the liberal
dichotomies of the individual and community, force and law, faith
and reason. What may have shifted in the years between was the
assumption of where that higher level lay, not the conviction that the
tangible worlds of the day’s law and politics failed to reflect it.
When Kaufmann wrote his 1911 book, Germany had become the
European State that had most reason to feel that formal
international relations had been superseded by a new constellation
of power. As an industrial economy and a military power it had no
rival on the continent.
181
and Hans Kelsen’s formalism half a century later may seem as wide
as international law itself. In a historical and political sense they are,
however, just a step apart, and sometimes merge into each other.
The history of international law in Germany during that period is a
narrative about philosophy as the founding discipline for reflecting
about statehood and what lies beyond. In this narrative “concrete
reality”
In the very year when the German empire was declared, Adolf
Lasson published his Princip und Zukunft des Völkerrechts, which
gave expression to the idea that sovereign States could not be
members of a legal community above them and that their natural
relations could only be those of envy, struggle, even hate. Treaties
between States reflected relations of power and could be maintained
only as long as those relations remained stable. Far from being
illegal, war remained a “means of negotiation”
in which the States sought to find out what the real power relations
between them were, and to conclude a peace treaty accordingly.7
182
183
of the State meant juridically, Gerber argued, was that it had “like all
law”
Authoritarianism arose from the organic view: State power was the
spiritual power of a people having become conscious of itself.12
Von Gerber did not think that State power knew no limits. On the
contrary, it became completely constrained by the objective of
advancing the common interest. Though these limits were difficult to
set in abstracto, von Gerber included a number of individual rights
and freedoms, as well as socio-cultural objectives, among them.13
The problem was, as Otto von Gierke (1841–1921) and other liberals
retorted, that the limits were determined from the inside of State
will, and not from the history or interests of autonomous
communities ( Genossenschaften) or an independent theory of
subjective rights.14 This debate brought to the surface the tension
between the authoritarian and individualist strands in the theory of
the State. On the one hand, the State appeared as a hierarchical
structure, and the citizen its passive object; on the other, the State
embodied the nation’s pursuit of self-determination without which
individual freedom would be nothing.15 Von Gerber dealt with this
tension by allowing the State’s organic justification to recede to the
background, and by concentrating on the State as a conglomerate of
(possible) acts of will, described through formal legal concepts that
claimed neutrality in regard to the authoritarian and individualist
views.16
184
160–161n1.
21 Laband, Das Staatsrecht, II, p. 153; Laband, Deutsches
Reichsstaatsrecht, p. 158.
185
international law, too, emerged from State will but existed as a set
of autonomous concepts and institutions, particularly in formal
treaties.
Before 1871 the organic theory had seen itself as the juridical
representation of the German Volk. After unification, that function
was given over to Reich legislation. The resulting Gesetzpositivismus
opened up the possibility of explaining international engagements as
binding on the 24 Carl Bergbohm, Staatsverträge und Gesetze als
Quellen des Völkerrechts (Dorpat, Mattiessen, 1876), pp. 19, 60–63.
27 One difficulty was that the juristic method focused on law as legal
enactments ( Gesetz) that were not available in the international
realm. Bergbohm accepted that this fact did not support codification,
but he did not believe it disqualified international law as law.
Accepting Laband’s distinction between the material and the formal
notion of Gesetz, Bergbohm noted that a (material) Gesetz included
two parts: the behavioral norm directed to the legal subjects and the
directive to the authorities to enact a reaction if the norm was
violated. Because most international law did not contain the latter, it
was law as will but not as Gesetz. The failure to make this distinction
had often
186
187
188
189
190
In the context of domestic society, this became covalent with the call
to obey positive law and laid the groundwork for the doctrine of the
Rechtsstaat – “Argue as much as you like, and about whatever you
like, but obey!”43 In the international realm, however, there was
little positive law available. Kant had considered the case of human
history – locating freedom at the level of individuals while redefining
the human species as the realm of nature. To make the two
compatible, Kant was compelled to assume that nature was
ultimately moral (nature as realization of freedom).44 In an
analogous way, internationalists thought that national freedom could
be realized only within the realm of necessity that international
relations was. An implicit morality was thus read into the facts of
interdependence towards which lawyers now turned – with the
simple argument that these facts could always be read as the
content of unde-clared (but rational) will. There may be differences
of opinion about what were the “necessary consequences drawn
from the common will of nations” (“nothwendigen, aus dem
Gemeinschaftswillen des Staaten zie-henden Schlussforderungen”) –
but this was normal and could be dealt 42 Cf. Immanuel Kant, “What
is Enlightenment?,” in Political Writings, pp. 54–60.
191
Human will might be the immediate motivation for action but how it
functioned was dependent on “deeper” social laws. Even Heilborn
acknowledged this. Having defined law as self-legislation, he inferred
its continued validity over “arbitrary” will from the same source: “But
if the creation of a legal order is a necessary implication of human
nature, then its negation is excluded by the same necessity. The
intrinsic consciousness of right and duty in human beings does not
allow law as arbitrary propositions [ willkürliche Satzung] but as the
just order of life.”46 The view of law as rational self-legislation gave
expression to the social ideal of autonomous, self-determining legal
subjects. It was a liberal idea. But it connected only with difficulty
with any concrete reality. Inasmuch as the theory was not presented
as one of revolution (which it was not), it tended to portray any
actual social order as intrinsically rational.47 If no importance was
given to the actual (however “dogmatic”) will, the argument
collapsed into a defense of the status quo. Now surely lawyers –
least of all German lawyers – could not just think that the present
order was law by its intrinsic force. What was the relationship of
psychological
46 Heilborn, Grundbegriffe, p. 6.
192
For Nippold, it was clear that treaties were the most important
source of international law. Like other liberals, he imagined State will
as the rational will to participate in increasing cooperation and even
in the harmonization of domestic laws. A natural Annäherung and
Ausgleichung were slowly leading to something like a world State.51
Despite his sociological language, however, Nippold saw most
progress in international law as a result of the work of
Wissenschaft.52 He proposed the establishment of an international
organization of jurists with a much larger membership than that of
the Institut as well as the setting up of an international training
school for international lawyers – a proposal that culminated in the
establishment of the Hague Academy of International Law in 1913.
His work did not contain a serious effort to analyze the social forces
that would determine the direction of future integration. It was an
armchair sociology he espoused, built on the assumption that States
would – when gently guided by men of science – come to
understand where their real interests lay, and agree on a world
federation.
193
194
But it was not obvious what the relevant “facts” were, in what the
law’s positivity consisted.
58 Stolleis, Geschichte, II, p. 435; Juha Tolonen, Stat och Rätt (Åbo
Akademi, 1986), p. 108.
60 Franz von Liszt, Das Völkerrecht (5th edn., Berlin, Häring, 1907),
p. 7.
195
Such theories were without illusion about the State. They were also
politically dangerous. Either they made the legitimacy of State power
suspect as an ideological facade, or they dismissed public policy as
altogether irrelevant in the determination of social order. Ludwig
Gumplowicz (1858–1909) a Staatslehrer from Graz of Polish origin,
for instance, insisted on the need to let go of the illusion of law as
an expression of common will. No such will existed; the State was an
aggregate of groups struggling against each other with the result
that some groups were always more powerful than others and the
minority invariably ruled over the majority. That science was to focus
on these naked facts might make the groups that benefited from this
state of affairs uncomfortable: “But it is not up to science to worry
over the momentary comfort of the ruling classes.”62 Quite
consistently, Gumplowicz – a denier of international law – closed the
1902 edition of his book on the social State-idea in an obituary for
the Rechtsstaat.63
221–222.
197
198
72 The Verein had been set up in 1872. Its leading members were
the economists Gustav Schmoller and Lujo Brentano who were
identified with the new “ethical direction,”
der
modernen
Völkerrechtswissenschaft
an
der
Viennaer
199
Although the main body of Jellinek’s work was in the field of public
law, and written into his Allgemeine Staatslehre of 1900, read widely
beyond Germany,74 its relevance for international law is direct and
has been lasting. The distinction between a sociological and a legal
perspective on the State made it possible to characterize diplomacy,
too, as both struggle for power and the administration of a legal
system. The thesis of the normative power of the factual created
space for a Kantian internationalism that built on self-legislation by a
will aware of the constraints under which it had to work.
3–4.
200
International law as philosophy: Germany 1871–1933
201
From these premises Jellinek developed his “two sides theory” of the
State – the State as a sociological and a juridical conception, a
distinction that mirrored the Kantian dichotomy between the world
as Sein and as Sollen. In the sociological realm, the State could be
portrayed as a set of relations of will that took the appearance of
Herrschaft, the use of power by some over others. Or it appeared as
a geographically based community
of
individuals
pursuing
determined
objectives.
202
This did not, however, exhaust the State’s being. No social institution
or event – and certainly not the State – could be reduced to one
single frame of explanation. From a juridical perspective, the State
could be conceived as a legal subject, in which case the sociological
community ( Verbandseinheit) appeared as a particular kind of
corporation ( Körperschaft).
203
only an act that comes from autonomous choice can have ethical
significance. An act produced by irresistible external force has no
moral value.
vols., Munich, Freiburg, 1963), II, pp. 40–41. Cf. also Léon Duguit,
Le droit social, le droit individuel, et la transformation de l’Etat
(Paris, Alcan, 1908), pp. 53–54 as well as Léon Duguit, L’Etat, le
droit objectif et la loi positive (2 vols., Paris, Fontemoing, 1901), I,
pp.
124–131.
95 “Was bis jetzt nur trotz der Souveränetät und gegen die
Souveränetät behauptet werden konnte, kann nun durch die
Souveränetät erklärt werden.” Jellinek, Die Lehre von den
Staatenbindungen, p. 36.
204
International law as philosophy: Germany 1871–1933
What exists becomes what should exist. This was no illegitimate leap
from facts to norms: the relationship was mediated by
consciousness.
The mind vested tradition with normative sense. But the mind, too,
countered its own conservatism by its tendency to rebel against
states of things that failed to meet expectations of justice. In both
directions, facts received normative meaning through the activity of
the mind, free and constrained simultaneously.100
102 Cf. also Jellinek, Die Lehre von den Staatenverbindungen, pp.
102–103.
205
– they are the concrete reality States have to take into account in
their interaction with each other.
107 Jellinek, Die Lehre von den Staatenverbindungen, pp. 95, 109–
113. Jellinek had used an analogous argument in his discussion of
the emergence of norms in primitive society in Die sozialethische
Bedeutung in 1878, pp. 16–22, 25. There he defended a social
conception of ethics against an individualist one in a way that
suggested a collective determination of the contents of voluntas, cf.
e.g. pp. 33–41. For a criticism of this as naturalism, cf. Triepel,
Völkerrecht und Landesrecht, pp. 80–81n.
206
207
77–100.
208
209
210
495–500.
211
Von Stengel’s appointment was widely criticized but his role in the
Hague remained small. His 1909 tract collected many conservative
themes about international politics under an assessment of the
Hague Conferences. It responded to ideas prevalent in Germany but
remained an isolated pamphlet within the international law
community. By contrast, Zorn became an active participant in the
Conferences and propagated their results with enthusiasm, publicly
commending Chancellor von Bülow’s change of attitude to arbitration
in 1899 (in which Zorn himself seems to have played an important
role) but criticizing Germany’s steadfast opposition to making it
compulsory in 1907.122 He was proud of the German contribution in
the drafting of the Statute of the Permanent Court of Arbitration and
agreed with Jellinek’s positive assessment of its importance.123 In
his Rectoral address he claimed that the initial German skepticism
had been caused by inflated expectations and used the occasion to
reiterate the pointlessness of its continued opposition to compulsory
arbitration. It had already been adopted in a German–British
arbitration treaty of 1904, and there was no reason why it could not
be generalized. Even without a specific reservation, it was obvious
that vital interests and national honor ( Ehrenklausel) would limit the
potential dangers.
Yet Zorn carefully distanced himself from the pacifists. Whether the
conferences were organs of an “international community,” as
Schücking had recently argued, was not a legal question: participant
States still 121 Cf. Karl von Stengel, Weltstaat und Friedensproblem
(Berlin, Reichl, 1909).
212
127 Robert Piloty, “Staaten als Mächte und Mächte als Staaten. Ein
Wort zu den Grundlagen des Völkerrechts” (1914), VIII Zeitschrift für
Völkerrecht, pp. 360–365.
128 Of the 28 articles classed under these items in the Archiv’s first
25 years, three were written by well-known international lawyers –
Heinrich Lammasch (1853–1920) from Vienna, whose contribution
dealt with nationality, Ferdinand von Martitz (1839–1922) from
Tübingen and Berlin who, though trained in legal history,
constitutional, and administrative law, was one of the German
members of the Institut, and whose long article on the suppression
of slavery and the slave trade in Africa 213
Chinese dispute. All three articles were published in the Archiv’s first
volume. In later years, most of the international law materials came
from established public lawyers such as von Stengel and Störk or
young doctors who edited their theses for the Archiv.
214
His optimism did not survive the war. In a joint editorial with Max
Fleischmann (1872–1943, the future editor of von Liszt’s
Völkerrecht) in 1916 Kohler declared that the international law of
agreements had come to an end. The war had demonstrated the
enormous differences in the legal consciousness of European
powers. The English total war ( Wirtschaftskrieg) struck at civilians
and was completely at odds with the German idea of war as struggle
between States. It was time for a German journal to bring forward
the German standpoint. It was time for a jurisprudence that would
not rest content with examining the day’s diplomacy: a new law
should arise from the depth of the histories, lives, and interests of
European societies. Dreams of peace had dispersed like soap
bubbles and the Peace Palace could now open its doors for other
worthy human goals. With undisguised bitterness Kohler admitted
having been himself prisoner of the illusion that other nations would
share his idealism; that they too would have enough to do at home.
All this was error: “Treaties with liars and traitors cannot form
sources of law; only peoples with a sharp moral sense may be
entitled to participate in law-creation.”132 Could the British and the
French be trusted, or be treated as brothers? “Nein und dreifach
nein.” Instead of treaties, a natural law was now needed, Kohler
wrote, that was progressively enveloped in culture as an idea
simultaneously historical and rational; not an abstract conceptual
jurisprudence but a science whose leading principles would emerge
from the observation of life itself. This would be a truly German
science and a legislator that would express necessary historical and
rational truths. The victorious war would inaugurate the Kaiser as
the guarantor of international law and justice.
215
Schücking came from a family of liberal traditions but did not engage
in politics until having received a chair at Marburg’s conservative law
faculty in 1902.133 The crises of the first years of the century and
his contacts with left–liberal politicians, his mentor Ludwig von Bar
from Marburg (1836–1913) and above all the Austrian pacifist Alfred
Fried (1864–1921), led him into a political jurisprudence and
alignment with the latter’s “organizational pacifism” that were
completely alien to German publiclaw.134 Like the Statute of the
Institut, Schücking saw the international jurist as an educator of the
people, a “Mentor des Volkes über alle Klasseninteressen.”135
Lawyers were not describers of but participants in international
politics and had a duty not only to report on existing law but to
further its development. Schücking blamed his colleagues for their
backward-looking orientation, their disregard of natural law and of
the socio-economic developments of the fin-de-siècle. Germany was
stuck with nationalism at a time when everyone else was becoming
internationalist.136 In a much-read pamphlet in 1909 he repeated
Bluntschli’s proposal for a European confederation with the long-
term objective of a World State.137 He later had several occasions
to develop his 133 For Schücking’s early years, cf. Detlev Acker,
Walther Schücking (Munster, Aschendorff, 1970), pp. 4–13.
216
139 Walther Schücking, Das Werk vom Haag, Erster Band: Die
Staatenverband der Haager Konferenzen (Munich and Leipzig,
Duncker & Humblot, 1912), p. 81. The book has been translated as
The International Union of the Hague Conferences (trans. G.
Fenwick, Oxford, Clarendon, 1918), in which the expression
“Weltstaatenbund” has been inappropriately translated as “World
Federation,” p. 86. Throughout the book, however, Schücking takes
pains to refrain from arguing that the Hague Convention of his
proposal would set up a supranational form of government.
217
219
152 For the text of the official German draft and a short comparative
introduction, cf.
114–116.
154 Cf. Walther Schücking and Hans Wehberg, Die Satzung des
Völkerbundes (Berlin, Vahlen, 1921), pp. 11–12.
220
Writing to his wife from Versailles in May 1919 while the German
delegation was waiting for Allied responses, Simons referred to
Schücking as “a great child, a pure heart and an incorrigible
idealist.”156 Though a rather stereotyped image of a pacifist –
especially from the pen of a diplomat – the description does point to
a real problem that lay in Schücking’s apparent denial of the
complexity of the political world, including his own position. He was
a nationalist who interpreted “real”
221
160 He was one of the founders of the Deutsche Liga für Völkerbund
in December 1918 as well as of the Deutsches Comité für
europäische Cooperation in 1928, both of which initially had
important public figures as members but failed to develop into mass
organizations. Cf. Acker, Walther Schücking, pp. 147–154, 181–186.
222
223
224
326–331.
225
226
International law as philosophy: Germany 1871–1933
178 Huber had been educated in Zürich, Lausanne, and Berlin where
at the age of 24
227
228
“old” law had been like, and, consequently, what was needed by way
of reform. Reading through the German wartime writings one is
struck not only by the force with which the old arguments between
“natural law”
and “positivism” are restated but also by the way politics and history
are as it were suspended for the moment of the academic struggle.
Nothing demonstrates the isolation and helplessness of the German
international law community better than its turn inwards, and
backwards, into nineteenth-century debates about the basis of the
law’s binding force.
229
showed, once again, why it was logically impossible to find the law’s
foundation in State will – there had to be a non-voluntary reason for
why will should be binding. Through a familiar dialectics, he
demonstrated how positivist lawyers constantly fell back on non-
positivist assumptions – and how ironicit was that it was they who
kept indicting natural law as a Hydra that always grew a new head
from an old wound.185 Fear of natural law was a fear of sin, a
justified fear that grew out of the secular exaggerations of Hobbes
and Rousseau first, and then from the collapse to a spiritually
impoverished positivism. Yet for all the radical conservatism of his
language – including his proposal to set the Pope as the
international appeals court – Cathrein’s natural law was empty of
reform. God still spoke through States and had enacted the right of
self-preservation and self-perfection at the top of the system.
Familiar ideas about good faith, just war, and suum quique tribuere
formed its substance: pacta sunt servanda was still tempered by the
rebus sic stantibus – and no indication was given about how (or by
whom) to measure the “fundamental” character of the change.
The exact opposite was preached on the modernist side that saw not
positivism but not enough positivism as the problem. Speaking in
occupied Bonn in 1918 at the centennial of the University, its Rector,
Ernst Zitelmann (1852–1923), the private international lawyer and
legal theorist, a kindred spirit of Bergbohm’s, argued that the war
had demonstrated how much of international law still remained the
pious wishes of writers of textbooks. The tendency to fill the gaps of
positive law with political opinions and principles of morality had
simply proven too great.
There was a great tiredness about the pamphlets and talks that
poured 185 Cathrein, Die Grundlage, p. 30.
230
231
international law since 1902 but from now on devoted at least half
its space to international law debates and documents. In the same
year its founder,
the
private
international
lawyer
Theodor
Niemeyer
232
196 However, despite the fact that Kaufmann was replaced by Carl
Schmitt in the Institute’s scientific council, it continued its activities
with relatively little interference and provided at least some room for
independent counseling. Hueck, “Die deutsche
Völkerrechtswissenschaft”; Stolleis, Geschichte, III, pp. 395–396.
233
Although the war had an effect on the themes dealt with, Niemeyer
was able to direct its activities to constructive objectives. The first
meeting in Heidelberg in October 1917 concentrated on an analysis
of the much-discussed contrast between the “German” and “English”
concepts of warfare, of which the latter was understood as –
unsurprisingly – illegal.
234
201 Cf. Kimmich, Germany and the League of Nations, pp. 6–18.
235
Some of the provisions of the draft found their way into the official
German proposal. Otherwise, however, it was lost in the general
stream of unofficial proposals on post-war organization. It had no
effect on the Allied draft which remained substantially unchanged
from February 1919. The Germans had been unrealistic if they had
expected that the Allies would see the negotiations as other than
implementation of German war guilt. The German Foreign Minister
Brockdorff-Rantzau’s theatrical appeal to the “law” of the fourteen
points, delivered sitting down at Versailles on May 7, 1919, did
nothing to assuage the Allies and created an atmosphere in which
the Germans were compelled to oppose the treaty by the fatal
strategy of trying to redeem their national past.205
110–117.
236
212 Karl Strupp, Das Werk von Locarno (Berlin and Leipzig, de
Gruyter, 1926), pp. 92–93, 113.
213 Cf. Kimmich, Germany and the League of Nations, pp. 82–91.
237
238
221 Kelsen, Das Problem der Souveränität, pp. 13–16, 37–40, 102–
103.
240
241
225 Rudolf Métall, Hans Kelsen. Leben und Werk (Vienna, Deutige,
1967), p. 11.
226 Kelsen, Der soziologische und der juristische Staatsbegriff, pp.
207–210.
233–248.
242
In other words, the State was neither a person nor a will that stood
against an independent law. The two were not distinct: stripped of
its ideological and metaphoric properties, the State was identical
with the domestic legal order.232 This view corresponded closely to
the political reality of the decaying Danube monarchy in which it was
developed.
“belonging.” But this merely posed the further question of what type
of psychical relationship was involved. An internal “feeling” was an
individual matter that did not ground a realm of collective statehood.
The assumption of a trans-individual unity of wills or parallelism of
psychological processes (common will, group feeling, common
consciousness) led into social psychology – and easily collapsed into
the metaphysical notion of a group soul. (Kelsen thinks Freud a
distinct progress from Le Bon: the masses have no soul, libido is an
individual matter, Der soziologische und der juristische Staatsbegriff,
pp. 21–22.) A State cannot be described as a “psychological mass” –
for it has a permanence that is inscribed in its institutions. The point
is that the members of a group mediate their relations through a
regulating order, that is to say, a system of norms, and come to
think of themselves as members of a State by reference to it. But in
such a case, the State’s existence is a matter by definition
independent of any “feeling of association”: it is a juridical notion
which then offers, through metaphor and Verdoppelung, a point of
identification for the group, Der soziologische und der juristische
Staatsbegriff, pp. 25–30.
243
This did away not only with the theory of the State as a subject of
international law but also with the view of State will as the single (or
most important) source of international law.237 As a social
technique, law came about in two ways: by conscious enactment
(treaties) or spontaneously (custom).238 There were, of course,
psychological motives and social and political causes behind both of
its sources. But law was not a science of motives or causality. From
the legal perspective, the 233 Cf. Métall, Hans Kelsen, p. 42. The
Emperor seems however not to have read Kelsen’s memorandum but
acted under his German advisors, Métall, Hans Kelsen, pp. 21–22,
29.
236 Kelsen, Introduction, pp. 42–46. In this way, all rights became
political inasmuch as their application was conditioned on “will.”
244
question about the “source” of law sought only to find out which
directives qualified as (legally) valid. And that question could be
answered only by examining the chain of validity. Whether law arose
from someone’s will or reflected a community’s consciousness were
like the question about its moral appropriateness: they were not
answerable in a legal way, and pointed to other scales of evaluation
than the legal (namely psychology, political theory, or ethics). This
did not mean that these questions were wrong, or nonsensical, only
that there was no legal response to them.239
The Pure Theory of Law exposes once and for all the attempt to use
the concept of sovereignty to lend a purely political argument –
which is always vulnerable to a comparable counter-argument – the
appearance of a logical argument, which would by its very nature be
irrefutable. And precisely by exposing the argument as political, the
Pure Theory of Law facilitates development that has been stunted by
mistaken notions, development in terms of legal policy –
facilitates such development, but does not justify or postulate it. For
that is a matter of complete indifference to the Pure Theory of Law
qua theory.240
In this extraordinary passage Kelsen not only quite correctly
assessed the political significance of the pure theory but also
revealed its limitation, a limitation that explains something of the
failure of his politics.
242 Most famously in his debate with Carl Schmitt about the
“guardian of the constitution.” For recent analysis, cf. David
Dyzenhaus, Legality and Legitimacy. Carl Schmitt, Hans Kelsen and
Hermann Heller in Weimar (Oxford, Clarendon, 1997), pp. 102–160.
245
246
247
248
whether one could keep the realms of objective law and subjective
politics distinct, as this required, and overrule the former by the
latter, put an impossible burden on the strength of the lawyer.
is false qua theory. This is not a simple task. The problems of the
pure theory do not lie in its internal coherence but in its relationship
to the surrounding world. Despite the critical bite of Kelsen’s
arguments, they still emanate from nineteenth-century German legal
thought: academic, system oriented, and neurotically concerned
over its status as Wissenschaft.
250
251
As the centre of social reality, the State united the dichotomies that
remained unresolved within formal thought. When, for example,
liberal rationalism created an irreducible (and destructive)
antagonism between the individual and the community, it failed to
see how the two interacted and constantly constructed each other. A
numerical Einzelheit turned into concrete Besonderheit through
social recognition.264 As a concrete and 258 Kaufmann, Das Wesen
des Völkerrechts, p. 136.
264 Kaufmann, Das Wesen des Völkerrechts, p. 145. Cf. also the
argument on the functioning of the Volksgeist in the individual in
“Zur problematik des Volkswillens” (1931), in GS, III, pp. 274–275.
252
This was the meaning of Hegel’s dictum about the State being the
reality of concrete freedom.
Judged against the concrete State, the international was weak and
superficial. The liberal imagination often projected it as a cosmopolis
of abstract, unconnected individuals – a “humanity” – whose
members enjoyed natural rights and belonged to their communities
out of free consent. But no individual was abstract or unconnected in
this way. All were products of history and parts of something
international only through their States. Failure to understand this
concrete reality was the reason for the failure of rationalism to
develop a credible concept of either the law or the State.265
Peace, for example, was a purely negative and formal idea that
implied no principle of distribution. A Weltstaat was a Utopia, and
not a beneficial 265 Kaufmann, Das Wesen des Völkerrechts, pp.
182–185.
253
254
“law,” they move in a circle: perhaps the law was enacted by the
Mafia!
255
256
257
258
Each looked towards the other and strove for Aufhebung: this and
the judicial techniques for avoiding contradiction were part of the
dialectic and the teleology embedded in law.296
259
260
261
262
life. Hence war as the social ideal: only war constituted proof of the
presence of a realm of objective value over the subjective wants of
individuals. Where the Kantian–Kelsenian perspective led to an
alienated moral agnosticism that was vulnerable to the critique of
technical reason, the Hegel–Kaufmann outlook prepared the ground
for a totalitarian State.
The effort to explain freedom and order not only as compatible but
defined by reference to each other lay at the heart of legal
formalism of the public law tradition. Among liberals, it articulated a
moderate concept of statehood directed to protection of individual
rights. Among conservatives it explained individual rights as an
acceptable ingredient of an authoritarian State. But the idea of
positive freedom involved was inherently unstable. If freedom is
nothing but the realization of and if 305 In this sense, e.g. Robert
Pippin, Modernity as a Philosophical Problem. On the Dissatisfactions
of European High Culture (2nd edn., Oxford, Blackwell, 1999), pp.
160–179.
306 Cf. e.g. Hans Sluga, Heidegger’s Crisis. Philosophy and Politics in
Nazi Germany (Cambridge, Harvard University Press, 1993), pp.
214–219.
307 Cf. also Krieger, The German Idea of Freedom, pp. 458–470.
264
This was already anticipated in the moving last chapter of the 1934
Hague lectures by Karl Strupp who had been dismissed from his
position in Frankfurt in 1933, and had moved first to Istanbul and
then to France where he committed suicide on the eve of the
German occupation. For the positivist Strupp, the complete failure of
the Codification Conference of 1930 had been a grave
disappointment that left him only the avenue of natural law on which
to argue – and yet, he lamented, a natural law without the real,
substantive agreement of States would fall apart the moment it was
needed. Between non-existent positive law and an ineffective natural
law, all that was left was a hope that the ideals of natural law would
become the ideal of States, their own (positive) natural law. Such
oscillation between professionalism and faith by a lawyer deeply
aware that “the very foundations of the law of nations were shaking
by the force of attacks from outside” was vivid testimony of the
dead-end into which the divided tradition of German public law had
come.308 To hope for harmony was already to have given up hope.
581–586.
265
“solidarism” 1871–1950
266
and provides the true source of inspiration not only for that
commentary but for the whole of the oeuvre of this late follower of
solidarist radicalism. Not only do we find an international legislator,
administration, adjudication and police force, situated in this local,
yet cosmopolitan setting, the structure of the international society it
administers has been completely transformed. Its legislative body is
not composed of representatives of States, not even of geographical
constituencies, but of the professions – such professions having
become the centers around which members of the global electorate
now construct their identities. “The representation of peoples thus
became a representation by professionals, competent because
chosen from among technical experts, exempt from all tyranny
because the majority that would be formed over particular questions
would always vary; such majority uniting the representatives of
different professions in accordance with particular professional
interests.”2
267
for the actions of the social collectivity that encompass all aspects of
the 5 John Patrick Diggins, Max Weber. Politics and the Spirit of
Tragedy (New York, Basic Books, 1996), p. 67.
268
448–489.
269
270
International law as sociology: France 1871–1950
say that its internationalism would have been less than honest. On
the contrary, since the early nineteenth century French republicans
had identified the French nation through the universal principles of
the Revolution
271
272
– this was not only a tragedy for France but a blow to world
peace.28 The ambivalence of Despagnet’s characterization of French
policy at the Berlin Conference could be applied generally to the way
French internationalists saw the relations between France and the
world: “it is by advocating moral considerations at diplomatic
assemblies that the vanquished France could first reconquer the
position in the world that belongs to it.”29 This is to repeat the
Revolutionary ethos of 1789: 23 Despagnet, La diplomatie de la
troisième république, p. 128.
24 Had not France received a free hand from Salisbury three years
earlier but held back from taking action as Tunisia was, after all, an
independent country? Despagnet, La diplomatie de la troisième
république, p. 77.
273
“The idea of France” – in legal terms, this was certainly the Code
Civil.
274
Each State was free – just like each individual – to the extent that its
freedom did not violate that of other States. The rights of States at
sea were derived from natural law: the freedom of the seas, the
concept of 33 Cf. Paul Fauchille, “Nécrologie Louis Renault (1843–
1918)” (1918), XXV RGDIP, pp.
41 Renault, Introduction, p. 6.
276
43 Renault, Introduction, p. 8.
277
278
Paul Fauchille (1858–1926) was one of his two students that Renault
chose as editors of the Revue. He was a real flâneur who never
occupied a university or administrative position but worked at home
with a wide array of publishing projects in history and international
law as well as initiatives with the Institut. In 1919 Fauchille became
one of the founders and the first Secretary-General of the Institut
des hautes études internationales with the University of Paris. It was
Fauchille who declared that the purpose of the Revue was to defend
the rights and interests of France
– a declaration that has been benevolently but not incorrectly
interpreted as meaning that he associated French interest with the
universal interest.53 It was not by coincidence that Fauchille began
his 1911 report to the Institut de droit international on the
customary laws of naval warfare by the observation that the very
idea of drafting such rules on the basis of humanitarian ideas could
be traced back to Napoleon.54 Fauchille was a man of facts and
details and thus well suited to edit the Revue’s 51 The recurrent
anarchist attacks in Europe in the 1890s gave impetus for scholars to
publicize their views on the principles of extradition for politically
motivated crimes.
This, too, was law in the service of the sovereign: the domestic
anarchist was analogous to the colonial people – an outsider to the
established order, an object of discipline.
279
56 Bonfils–Fauchille, Manuel, p. 3.
58 Bonfils–Fauchille, Manuel, p. 7.
280
simply a reflection of the fact that they did not possess “un système
commun de morale, qui assure entre elles la réprocité des droits et
des devoirs.”59 There was only one fundamental right – the right to
existence. Every other right followed as a conceptual derivation from
it. If in some cases such rights were violated – the right of non-
intervention, for example, was constantly breached by the United
States and Britain
By the 1880s French lawyers had generally begun to depart from the
canons of exegesis. Absolute freedom of contract or unchallenged
right of property were unable to deal with the social ills of the Third
Republic and to check the advance of socialist ideals.61 The
emergence of a collectivist radical–liberalism in French politics was
paralleled in law schools by new anti-literalist, sociologically oriented
civil and public law teaching such as François Gény’s (1861–1959)
influential distinction between the juridical “donné” and “construit,” a
theory of the juridical science as a method for finding the law
embedded in actual social relations (“donné”) and a technique for
constructing normative principles out of the purposes of positive
law.62 But neither Gény’s hermeneutics nor the sociological or
institutionalist public law doctrines by Saleilles, Hauriou, or Duguit
produced an immediate effect on French international law. On the
other hand, the very emergence of international law in the facultés
in the 1880s had to do with the expansion of legal culture.63
RGDIP, pp. 66–89 (Part 1), 236–264 (Part 2), and (1899), VI RGDIP,
pp. 503–532
(Part 3).
67 Pillet, “Le droit international public,” pp. 13–18. For Pillet as for
others, non-European entities could not be treated in the same way
as European States because they did not possess this idea of State
functions, Pillet, “Le droit international public,”
282
283
284
285
85 Bourgeois, Pour la société des nations, pp. 23–26, 167. Cf. also
Bourgeois, “Discours à l’Institut de droit international” (1910), 23
Annuaire IDI, pp. 365–373 and e.g. Alfred Fouillée, L’Evolutionnisme
des idées-forces (Paris, Alcan, 1890).
286
Perhaps he was truly thinking that a sense of solidarity and good will
was 86 Quoted in Mérignhac, La Conférence internationale, p. 393.
287
95 Léon Bourgeois, Solidarité (7th edn., Paris, Colin, 1912), pp. 105–
106. Cf. also Borgetto, La notion de fraternité, pp. 345–350.
288
“the result of two forces that were for a long time hostile to each
other but have recently approached each other and been united in
all nations that have reached a superior level of evolution: the
scientific method and the moral idea.”100 Bourgeois now theorized
solidarism as simultaneously factual and normative in the way of
much natural law.101 Its factual side 196 J. E. S. Hayward describes
the history of the concept in three periods. Between 1792
344 et seq.
198 Cf. Arnaud, Les juristes, pp. 86–125. On the activist role of
French jurists, largely committed to liberalism in nineteenth-century
France, cf. also L. Karpik, “Builders of Liberal Society: French
Lawyers and Politics,” in T. C. Halliday and L. Karpik (eds.), Lawyers
and the Rise of Western Political Liberalism (Oxford, Clarendon,
1997), esp. pp.
108–123.
289
191–192.
290
The shock of the First World War – more than 1.5 million French
soldiers dead – destroyed many Frenchmen’s belief in traditional
diplomacy. The violation of Belgium’s neutrality as an automatic part
of the Schlieffen Plan and the widely publicized violations of the
Hague rules committed by German troops in occupied territory –
duly enumerated in Renault’s study of war crimes at an early stage
of the war110 – also 107 Bonfils–Fauchille, Manuel, pp. 4, 3–13.
110 Louis Renault, Les premières violations du droit des gens par
l’Allemagne. Luxembourg et Belgique (Paris, Tenin, 1917).
291
The lesson drawn by Pillet was that international law could not be
created by agreement between diplomats and statesmen or through
abstract discussions at conferences. It could emerge only when
people and nations had grown to accept it: a civilized people
behaved in a civilized way. In the absence of such – “civilized” –
culture treaties would remain a hypocrisy:111 “only the awareness
and practice of Christian morality may provide the laws of war the
support they need, and it is because they had forgotten this
elementary fact that nations are now witnessing with stupor the
unforeseen re-emergence of barbarism.”112 The Hague Conferences
failed because they worked on the conditions of peace in the
abstract, and not on the actual causes of war: the constitution of
Poland, the Finnish question, the extermination of the Armenians, or
the Balkan situation. Having avoided such “real” issues, the Hague
Conferences could end only in failure.
292
International law as sociology: France 1871–1950
293
the French Prime Minister and Foreign Minister Ribot had appointed
Bourgeois to head the French committee to consider the setting up
of a Société des Nations.118 By this move, the direction of French
interwar international law was set. It was only natural that he and
Larnaude became the French representatives on President Wilson’s
Committee on the League of Nations (“Crillon Committee”) within
which they advocated a standing military force (or at least a military
planning committee) in the service of the League.119 Later, as the
first French representative in the League Council and the Council’s
first President Bourgeois continued to defend collective security and
international sanctions and fully associated himself with the effort to
interpret the League as a first step towards universal federation.
The draft Covenant prepared by the French and submitted to Wilson
in June 1918 contained provisions for effective sanctions, supported
by an international army. It also provided for a Council of Great
Powers, mandated to make binding decisions e.g. on disarmament.
Legal disputes were directed to a tribunal and political ones to the
Council. The French had unshakeable faith that they would always
be on the side of peace-loving nations and that their predominance
coincided with the general interest.120 However, Wilson’s choice of
the Hurst–Miller draft as the basis for discussion made the result
inevitably “a triumph of Anglo-American diplomacy.”121 The British
had aimed at an organization for cooperation, the Americans
emphasized the territorial guarantee. The outcome was a
compromise negotiated in ten three-hour sessions during February
3–13, 1919. The French were almost methodologically sidelined and
their suggestion of the international army was rejected for political
and constitutional reasons. Accordingly, when the League came into
existence, on January 10, 1920, few Frenchmen had faith in its
capacity to deter aggression. Bourgeois attributed responsibility for
this state of affairs squarely to Wilson and took upon himself as the
first President of the Council to examine alternatives to fill the 118
The other two members of the committee were Admiral Lacaze and
Jules Cambon, former ambassador to Berlin.
119 Cf. Scelle, La Pacte des Nations, pp. 326–328; Léon Bourgeois,
L’oeuvre de la Société des nations, 1920–1923 (Paris, Payot, 1923),
pp. 52–53. On Bourgeois’ international activities, cf. Hayward, “The
Official Social Philosophy,” pp. 41–46.
121 F. S. Northedge, The League of Nations. Its Life and Times (New
York and London, Holmes & Meier, 1986), p. 41.
294
International law as sociology: France 1871–1950
gaps.122 Time for such proposals was, however, over. During its first
years the League saw itself frequently by-passed by Great Power
diplomacy carried out by the Inter-Allied Conference of
Ambassadors, a left-over from wartime coordination. Nonetheless,
the supporters did not lose faith. Bourgeois was involved in
practically all of the early activities of the League: “The edifice of
peace can be built on law, and law alone.”123
One of his early reports organized the Committee of Jurists that was
to set up the Statute of the Permanent Court of International
Justice.124
Bourgeois was awarded the Nobel Prize in 1920, largely for his
activism at the Peace Conferences. He and Larnaude (who set up
the Union juridique internationale for this purpose) became active
propagandists for the League, interpreting it as a tangible
manifestation of the union between universal humanitarianism and
the French idea. They saw it as not just a League of governments
but of peoples who were to be educated into internationalism
through it. For the essence of the French spirit – in contrast to
German – lay in:
the vocation of sacrifice for an ideal at the same time national and
human that had inspired the great movements of the French people,
from the crusades at the moment when Christianity fixed its eyes on
the whole of humanity to the immor-tal campaigns of the sons of
Revolution who ran to the frontiers to save the endangered Patrie
and carry far the flag to announce human rights to peoples.
124 For the report and commentary, cf. Bourgeois, L’oeuvre, pp.
159–208.
295
296
If treaties and formal diplomacy seemed only a thin façade over the
reality of Europe, many lawyers now turned to science, particularly
sociology, to reimagine an international order less amenable to the
kind of catastrophe the First World War had been. Particularly
promising seemed Durkheimian sociology, with its relentlessly anti-
individualist outlook and its emphasis on the conscience collective as
the fundamental social fact. To answer the question about what held
modern industrial society together, Durkheim had in 1893 provided a
theory of “organicsolidarity” that accounted for integration even in a
society where there was no universal resemblance between the
tasks or positions of individuals. The fact of division of labor was
only superficially disintegrating: the shoemaker, the civil servant, and
the factory owner might lead completely different lives; but that did
not mean they were not reciprocally dependent on the distinct
contribution each had to give. Even as individuals might experience
modernity differently, and pathological cases (such as anomie)
emerged, modern societies still cohered as functional wholes.
Organic solidarity depicted the paradox that the increase of the
autonomy of individuals carrying out diversified tasks deepened their
dependence on each other.
297
Well before the war, French public law had already used such
arguments to create a conception of the State diametrically opposed
to the German one. Building directly upon Durkheim’s concept of
solidarité sociale, Léon Duguit (1859–1928), Durkheim’s friend and
colleague at the University of Bordeaux, the most important theorist
of public law of the period, argued that law was not an effect of the
State but a transformation of the objective needs of
interdependence. The State and the popular will were both
“metaphysical fictions.” Instead, (objective) law emerged directly
from the fact of mutual dependence in conditions of division of
labor.134 It was distinguishable from other norms (i.e. those of
morality and economics) by the recognition of the need of a social
sanction; not the actual application of such sanction but the
recognition that it would be desirable.135 This was a monistic
concept of law that did not recognize doctrinal distinctions between
private and public or national and international law. All law
expressed “ultimately,” as an empirical matter, normative relations
between individuals.136
298
Here are the facts: Individuals with common needs and different
inclinations, who exchange services, who have always lived together
and have always exchanged services, who by virtue of physical
constitution cannot avoid living together and exchanging services,
individuals of whom some are stronger than others, and of whom
the strongest have always exercised constraint on the weaker ones,
individuals that act, and have consciousness of their actions. Here
are the facts. Beyond them, there is only fiction.137
140 Duguit, Le droit social, p. 71. The two notions were practically
interchangeable: “Dans la solidarité je ne vois que le fait
d’interdépendence unissant entre eux par la communauté des
besoins et la division du travail les membres de l’humanité et
particulièrement les membres d’un même groupe social.” Duguit, Le
droit social, p. 8.
299
Property, for instance, was a social function; its limits were not
determined by a given subjective right but by objective law, by what
kind of property regime the society needed. Administrative or
legislative acts, too, were facts. They were not binding because they
emanated from State will but to the extent that they provided a
faithful translation to what was socially necessary.141
Like Bourgeois and Pillet, Duguit saw the State as a kind of political
arm of social solidarity. Its functions were completely determined by
what solidarity required. The law binds only “if it formulates a rule of
[objective] law or puts it into effect, and only to the extent it does
so.”142
Legislation was not creative but declaratory. This is why laws were
binding on those who voted for them. There was no need to have
recourse to an ingenious (but false) theory of self-legislation.143
143 Duguit, Le droit social, pp. 52–54. There is the objection that
this creates anarchy: everyone can decide whether or not to obey.
Duguit does not have a good response to this. First, he says, a
number of laws are self-evident. Second, those that are not, need
not necessarily be opposed by violence or anarchy. The solution is to
set up a tribunal that consists of members of all classes that would
judge the law’s lawfulness, Duguit, Le droit social, pp. 55–58.
144 Cf. Brimo, Les grands courants, pp. 250–253 and Michel Miaille,
Une introduction critique au droit (Paris, Maspero, 1982), p. 332.
300
148 It is hard to see how Duguit could fully accept Durkheim’s two
concepts of solidarity and still hold individuals as the fundamental
social fact. He seems to have rejected Durkheim’s view of the
collective as a real entity while perhaps thinking that the content of
individual conscience could be socially determined, Lukes, Emile
Durkheim, p. 103. For the oscillation in Duguit, cf. Sfez, “Duguit,” pp.
122–123.
149 Le droit social is full of references to Comte, cf. e.g. pp. 12, 17,
24, 149.
301
State and thus rid society of “the false and dangerous political
system based on sovereignty and the personality of the State.”155
Happily, during the last few years a new school had developed in
France that was no longer prisoner to civil law and which examined
international law closely “following its transformations, their causes
and their results.” He credited Renault as the leader of the new
school and cited Bonfils–Fauchille (oddly) as its leading product.156
302
Already in 1912 Alvarez claimed that international law had fallen into
disrepute by failing to take account of the economic, technological,
and cultural changes, including peoples’ increasing desire for peace.
Despite its avowed positivism, it reflected the ideas of a by-gone
international society, “metaphysical or a priori” doctrines of
fundamental rights, independence and sovereignty.157 Like modern
domesticsociety, however, the international world was no longer
ruled by individualism but by
“the principle of solidarity that also takes into account the interests
of the social group, because individuals live in society and in a
situation of mutual dependence.”158 As a result, an international
“regime of solidarity” was being constructed through international
unions, legislative conferences, and legal cooperation.159 Most
lawyers had failed to see this.
303
304
pp. 5–9 .
305
For Politis, international law, like all law, emerged from social facts.
From this he drew the three consequences of solidarist doctrine: that
legislation (or codification) had only declaratory, and not
constitutive, effect; that all law dealt ultimately with individual
behavior; and that States possessed rights only to the extent that
was functionally necessary.
The use by a State of its freedom was illegal if such use was “[only]
to the detriment of the collectivity’s general interest.”171 Sovereignty
was to be replaced by “the solidarity of human relations [which] is
the great social phenomenon of today.”172 States were artificial
fictions and the individual the only “real” subject of international law,
situated in a historical continuum from family to tribe; tribe to
nation; nation to region; region to universal community. Many
lawyers, Politis claimed, such as Kelsen and Verdross, Schücking,
Krabbe, and Westlake, had already understood this. And while
official diplomacy was still being obstructive, it was “powerless
against the realities of life.”173 In 1927 Politis reviewed four
diplomatic developments that manifested the new realities:
increasing acknowledgement of the position of the individual; the
emergence of an international criminal law; creation of a compulsory
system of international justice; and codification. To carry the
changes through required both activism and prudence; for the most
part, Politis believed that the League was being successful, despite
occasional setbacks (such as the failure of the Geneva Protocol in
the drafting of which he was personally involved) or timidity
(concerning the choice of topics of codification).174
306
178 Cf. e.g. Politis, Les nouvelles tendences, pp. 49, 62.
307
In 1943, shortly before his death, Politis published his last book on
308
Meanwhile in Paris . . .
Funds for the Institute were received from the French government
and 184 Alvarez, La codification, p. 140.
187 Eugene Weber, The Hollow Years. France in the 1930’s (London,
Sinclair, 1995), p. 17.
309
145–152.
310
There were those like the diplomatic historian and lawyer, professor
at the Ecole libre des sciences politiques, Charles Dupuis (1863–
1939) who ridiculed the attempt to get rid of sovereignty by Duguit
and Politis – this would be to attempt to get rid of police,
administration, taxation, and welfare. Nobody wanted it. Instead,
internationalism and nationalism should be balanced against each
other. In the realist fashion, he criticized the Kellogg–Briand Pact as
being both indeterminate in content and based on a presumption
about the binding force of promises which, if it were true, would
make the pact unnecessary.192 He specifically attacked Politis’
concept of the abuse of right which to him smacked of an “abuse of
words.” Either one acted within one’s right or one did not. To say
that one was using rights in an “anti-social” and thus abusive fashion
injected a moral evaluation into what should be a legal
assessment.193 Dupuis shared the disappointment of Pillet and the
French right about the conditions of Versailles: The League, he
argued in 1920, had come about without taking account of the
lessons of history. Of the three conditions for international order –
renouncing absolute sovereignty, presence of international
organization, and a spirit of internationalism – the third (which he
seemed to equate with an internationalist public opinion) was a
precondition for the others and remained to be created. The Pact
was too abstract and unclear in a way that would not matter if the
League could rely on an esprit international. But there was no such
spirit, Dupuis argued.194 A real law needs to be backed up by force:
in the ideal world, the use of force would rely on public opinion. In
its absence, the drafters of the Covenant should have taken their
lesson from nineteenth-century diplomacy that showed that even if
the balance of power was eminently not a legal principle, it could still
be used to support law and 191 “Discours de M. de La Pradelle,” p.
12.
194 Charles Dupuis, Le droit des gens et les rapports des grandes
puissances avec les autres états avant la pacte de Société des
Nations (Paris, Plon, 1921), pp. 7–11, 477–532.
311
The Gentle Civilizer of Nations
196 The second chair was set up after the war. Other
internationalists taught at Paris as well. But Louis Le Fur had a
professorship “without a chair” and Gilbert Gidel’s position was in
constitutional law. Politis had been appointed “honorary professor”
at the faculty and teaching in international law (for instance, courses
at the Hague Academy) was given by the public and constitutional
lawyers Gaston Jèze and Joseph-Barthélemy. For the faculty in 1932,
cf. Berthélemy, L’école de droit, pp. 66–69.
312
him without the ambition to blow them up into a full legal system.
sweeping generalizations.
448, 462–486.
313
In the curriculum of the first year of the new Institut, there was also
a series of lectures by the new Professor of International Law at the
University of Strasbourg, Louis Le Fur (1870–1943), on the
“philosophy of international law,” which condemned materialism and
voluntarism as parts of the breakdown of tradition that Germany had
sought to accomplish. What was needed was a return to the “first
foundations of a universal morality and law; to what had been called
a philosophia perennis”
The French right and left agreed that the kind of diplomacy that had
prevailed in 1914 had been a major cause of the war. Both held that
a reformed international law was to give expression to forms of more
authentic community. But where the former preached moral and
religious revival, and obedience to authority, the latter sought
renewal from science, technology, and institutional cosmopolitanism.
Both used solidarist language to advance federalist ideas. The
federalism of tradition constituted a hierarchical structure of
communities whose purpose was to facilitate the renewal of Europe’s
spiritual energies. Modernist federalism sought to liberate the
professional classes to realize the progressive laws of social
interdependence. It is conventional to speak of the return of natural
law in juristic thinking after the First World War. This undermines the
degree to which at least French lawyers were looking both
backwards and sideways: into tradition and history – the Spanish
Scholastics, Grotius, and the teachings of the Catholic Church207 –
but also towards Rousseau and Durkheim and recent theories of
public law, sor on Poland and speculated about the need for a
coming Finnish–German alliance in the North, A. de Lapradelle, Le
marxisme tentaculaire. La formation, la tactique et l’action de la
diplomatie soviétique (Issidou, Editions internationales, 1942), pp.
310, 202–204, 229.
207 Cf. in this respect among the writings by the Révérend Père
Yves Leroy de la Brière (1877–1941), e.g. “Evolution de la doctrine
et de la pratique en matière de représsailles” (1928/II), 22 RdC, pp.
237–294; Le droit de juste guerre: Tradition théologique et
adaptations contemporaines (Paris, Pedone, 1938).
315
L’affaire Scelle
316
L’affaire Scelle was mainly about university politics, and the doctrinal
positions of the two protagonists did not play a visible part in it. On
the other hand, it did polarize the relationship between the rightist
majority in the Faculty of Law and the left-leaning jurists such as
Gaston Jèze, whom we met in chapter 2 criticizing commercial
colonization, the internationally well-known expert of the law of
public finance who had voted for Scelle and later himself became the
target of a similar series of protests for his involvement as
Abyssinia’s counsel against Italy in the League in 1935–1936. In
Paris, Scelle must have represented not only Herriot’s controversial
coalition but also a step towards the unknown –
317
318
Le Fur was no more an original thinker than Benda but, like the
latter, able to strike a responsive chord in his audience by finding the
main culprit for the destruction of the authority of tradition in
nineteenth-century German political and legal thought and Kultur.
He explained the shocking vulnerability of pre-war internationalism
as a story of sin and its wages, a loss of moral sense, and
uncontrolled fall into the abyss of violence. The message bore a
redemptive hope, of course, in the form of a moderate reform of the
international system towards a decentralized universal federation. It
is no surprise that Le Fur found himself a much-used speaker, a
three-time lecturer at the Hague Academy of International Law, a
member and vice-president of the Institut de droit international, and
in 1933 the President of the Institut international de philosophie du
droit et de sociologie juridique.
220 Louis Le Fur, “La paix perpetuelle et l’arbitrage international”
(1909), XVI RGDIP, pp. 447–448.
319
The critical program was outlined in a 1920 book on the just war
that was prefaced by the conservative nationalist Maurice Barrès
(1862–1923), describing the outcome of the war as a victory of the
“French idea of law” and equating justice with the return of Alsace–
Lorraine to France.224 The attack on tradition was a distinctly
German operation: “In the first rank of the systems destructive to
morality and law are those elaborated by Germans . . . Things have
come to the point where it is possible to say without exaggeration
that present Germany has lost the notion of law, at least law in the
traditional sense.”225 After Martin Luther, the largest part of the
responsibility for this state of affairs lay with Kant’s methodological
doubt about the human ability to know the good.226 This led to
subjective idealism – the world as a projection of human
consciousness – that romantic writers used for the adoration of
völkisch nationalism.227 The categorical imperative could only
appear as an irrational escape from skepticism. And it imposed too
great a demand for individuals. Breaking down under its own weight,
Kantian morality left its subjects in a void that was quickly filled
either by the Hegelian State as the Ersatz-center of moral lives or a
Nietzschean amoralism, the “paganism of passions.”228 “The idea of
liberty as a unique rule of action can only breed anarchy and in fact
consecrate the triumph of the strongest.”229 Under such conditions,
law was reduced to a contract to set up a sovereign to deter
individuals from destroying each other. Not differentiating between
good and bad laws, and seeing the State only as a system of
constraint, the Kantian view became “if not the theoretical
legitimation, at least the practical consolidation of despotism.”230 In
the 1930s Le Fur saw these dangers in the degeneration of
parliamentarism into a search for special advantages 223 Louis Le
Fur, Précis de droit international (3rd edn., Paris, Dalloz, 1937), pp.
308–309.
224 Louis Le Fur, Guerre juste et juste paix (Paris, Pedone, 1920),
Préface par Maurice Barrès, pp. v, vi.
320
The second way of German errors lay with positivist historicism and
racism. The former taught that there was no universal moral order.
But if the Volksgeist was not limited by something outside itself, it
became a name for majority rule whose only limit was popular
aspiration.238 The organic theory mistook a biological metaphor for
reality and ended up in the complete submission of individuals to the
State.239 Moreover, positivist nationalism led inescapably to racism,
reducing human beings to their physical characteristics, neglecting
their moral nature and opening the door for reproductive
manipulation.240
Throughout the 1920s and 1930s Le Fur wrote with passion, and a
sense of acute danger against the errors of German philosophy –
235 Louis Le Fur, Races, nationalités, états (Paris, Alcan 1922), pp.
68–77.
239 Le Fur took delight in the fact that German racism was itself
drawn from the writings of non-Germanic scholars such as Lamarck,
Darwin, and Gobineau.
240 Le Fur, Guerre juste, pp. 39–47 and Races, pp. 40–60.
321
The Gentle Civilizer of Nations
But Le Fur had no sympathy for the writings of Alvarez, either, that
for him seemed to glorify arbitrary consensus.244 Even the theories
of Duguit and Scelle were more acceptable as they were really,
despite themselves, moral doctrines in the garb of sociological
language.
243 Cf. e.g. Le Fur, Précis, pp. 190–198 and “Règles générales,” pp.
147–152.
322
323
43–44.
324
325
326
mental social fact but refrained from advocating either free trade or
protectionism. In sum, “tradition” here was less a material doctrine
about the way the world should be governed or organized than an
attitude of human nature, about authority and community. Here lay
its weakness: it was an attempt to renew the nineteenth-century
concept of virtuous conscience – moral sense and honesty278 – at a
time when the very idea of virtue had been undermined by the
developments against which it was stated. It saw the world in terms
of philosophical doctrines confronting each other; as if how people
behaved were determined by them. Le Fur was eclectic because
tradition was so; because that was a tradition born in another age
and for other kinds of problématique; a tradition that was silent
about how to resolve the problems of a non-traditional age.
and his 1906 dissertation in Paris dealt with the economic history of
Spanish imperialism.280 The social–historical method was
consciously 278 Cf. e.g. Le Fur, “Règles générales,” pp. 151–152,
159–160.
279 After his dissertation in 1906 Scelle for the first time took part in
the agrégation – unsuccessfully. Thereafter he attained practical
experience as the Secretary of the Brazilian delegation at the second
Hague Conference and to the US delegation in the Orinoco
Steamship Co. case. He was Professor of International Law at the
University of Sofia in Bulgaria in 1908–1910. After teaching in Lille
and Dijon, he passed his agrégation at the third try in 1912 and was
appointed to the University of Dijon. He was mobilized and ordered
to the front in August 1914, participating in combat duty and acting
as “officier jurisconsulte” to the French Eighth Army. He was
demobilized in November 1918, taking up again his appointment in
Dijon. During 1929–1933 he also taught at the University of Geneva
as well as the Graduate School of International Studies. In 1932
327
328
41–80.
329
supporter of the idea (though not always the practice) of the League
of Nations.290
His developed views were for the first time clearly laid down in a
1923
There was nothing particular about them: they, too, were only a
means to realize individuals’ solidarity.
Most of Scelle’s mature ideas were present in this early sketch and
further elaborated in his general course at the Hague Academy of
1933, in the two-volume Précis that came out in 1932 and 1934 and
in an extensive report to the Institut international de droit public of
1935.294 Many of those ideas – monism, the significance of traités-
lois, and the role of the dédoublement fonctionnel – are quite well
known but it may be convenient to summarize them in four points.
This led into monism: like social reality, law, too, was one.
Distinctions between State law and international law, private and
public law were perhaps useful for exposition but without normative
difference. The bonds of solidarity (solidarity as fact, not as a
“feeling” or a moral principle) formed innumerable groups or
societies, within and between which different needs give basis to
different laws. Such societies were hierarchically related so that the
more inclusive ones overrode the less inclusive ones. For example,
treaties automatically overrode conflicting national law (although
their reception had a practical value in that it status as well as
providing for a judicial function. For analysis and criticism, cf.
297 This did not mean that anyone who disapproved of particular
legislation could ignore it. Legislation enjoyed the presumption of
being in accordance with the objective law ( hypothèse de bien
légiféré), cf. Scelle, Précis, II, pp. 297–299.
331
332
210–234.
333
For Scelle, international law was about learning the scientific truth
about how society was to be administered so as to best secure the
attainment of social utility. The view had no limit: the international
milieu was merely one and a rather arbitrarily limited aspect of a
monistic world.
Disagreement about the law appeared as truth and error about
(social and biological) facts; not as struggle over interests or values.
It is not difficult to see how such theory might seem appealing to
deal with international conflict. Already formulating the problem
provided a solution: there was no irreducible antagonism between
interests; every conflict demonstrated error on somebody’s part and
it was the point of juridical technique to find out on whose part. War,
for example, could only be lawful or not; neither a matter of
privilege nor of formal definition, war was either anti-social violence
or enforcement, tertium non datur.322 Law and politics turned into
sociology with a normative task, just as 318 Scelle, Précis, I, pp.
143–145. For Scelle’s arguments about the need to open China and
Japan for foreign trade – forcibly if necessary, cf. Leonetti, “Georges
Scelle,” pp.
314–315.
335
By contrast, for Scelle treaties did not create the law but only
declared it.324 This appeared to make the problem of revision
disappear: a change of necessity would automatically transform the
legal situation as well.
336
327 In France, for instance, the revolution of 1848 had been needed
to start the development that led to the institution of labor law and
finally the act on accidents of 1898
that set aside the individualist principles that had governed the
subject under the Code Civil, and enacted the revolutionary principle
of responsibility for risk. It is the same internationally. If
governments persist in upholding obsolete law, the ultimate means
of change is unilateral repudiation that may involve war, Scelle,
Théorie juridique de la révision, p. 50.
337
– that is, against the social meaning (“sens social nécessaire”) of the
Covenant – that the Assembly’s view could be lawfully overridden.
But only a future supranational legislation would do away with the
danger of war as a last recourse. The future international legislator
should be entitled to directly modify national law, thus spelling the
end of sovereignty.
With a veiled reference to the Nazi regime Scelle concluded his 1936
book with the wish that tyranny and violence would be eradicated
from society by legislation. Today, however, everything still hung on
the presumption of the binding force of present, formally valid law –
a presumption that fatally weakened Scelle’s objectivism, making it
appear just another politics of reform, among others.
338
348–352.
339
340 Georges Scelle, “La guerre civile espagnole et le droit des gens,”
1 (1938), XLV
341 Georges Scelle, “La guerre civile espagnole et le droit des gens,”
3 (1939), XLVI RGDIP, p. 197.
342 Le Fur, “La guerre,” 2, pp. 62–63.
340
348 It was clear for Le Fur, for instance, that the Franco government
was more respectful of international obligations (it had showed its
willingness to restore foreign property that had been subjected to
nationalizations) and to carry out a policy of national and
international reconciliation, Le Fur, “La guerre,” 1, pp. 81, 84–87.
341
342
343
The Gentle Civilizer of Nations
267–270.
361 Cf. Le Fur, Précis, pp. 308–309 and especially Le Fur, “Le
développement historique du droit international de l’anarchie
international à une communauté internationale organisée”
(1932/III), 41 RdC, pp. 548–556.
344
345
– that legal problems were really resolved outside the law, namely in
sociology and in the various technical and functional disciplines
Scelle advocated. Like Comte, Scelle had no argument to explain
why lawyers might have something useful to do in the scientifically
administered bureaucracy that was the logical outcome of his views.
346
Once and for all, I ceased to believe that history automatically obeys
the dictates of reason and the desires of men of good will.”370 In an
ironic twist, the teaching of the “men of good will” and pessimists
converged in that neither was able to find much for international
lawyers to achieve.
The rationalists took their lesson from Comte and Durkheim and saw
federation as a scientific necessity: only technical administration
would remain – politicians, soldiers, and lawyers were recast as
survivals from feudal or theological ages. Pessimists such as Aron
would look towards Weber and the irreducibility of power and
interest and lay their stakes with a statesmanship of prudence –
such as Monnet’s – as the only alternative to tragedy.
371 For the dynamism written into the plan, cf. Paul Reuter, “Le plan
Schuman”
347
host city of his federal utopia. It was not for nothing that René-Jean
Dupuy (1918–1997) characterized the High Authority of the Coal and
Steel Community in 1957 as “le premier exemple historique de
l’avène-ment internationale des technocrates” and linked its origins
to the suggestions by Saint-Simon and Proudhon to employ technical
experts to advance corporate interests overriding those of States.372
The new spirit was also visible in the establishment of the Annuaire
français de droit international in 1955 for the purpose of following
and commenting upon the events of international relations on an
annual basis with the stated purpose of “avoiding the construction of
useless and dangerous systems, detached from the realities of
international life.”
42, 52–53.
348
349
– only that those efforts had no success whatsoever. The two articles
in the 1950s Revue générale that engaged in doctrinal abstraction
both attacked sociology as the founding discipline of international
law, repeating the point about the impossibility of drawing norms out
of social facts. Truyol y Serra and Smyrniadis (was it a coincidence
that both were foreigners?) decried the spiritual poverty of
positivism and advocated a turn to metaphysics and morality – yet
failing to answer the pragmatist’s objection about the arbitrary or
non-consequential nature of what one came up with as one’s
fundamental principles.380 When the latter claimed that this
morality was “anchored in the conscience of human beings” he
seemed to be echoing Marcel Sibert’s (1884–1957) 1951 textbook
which based the necessity of international law on the fact that “[l]a
conscience des peuples honnêtes la proclame.” Sibert at least was
able to translate his moral generalizations into a theory of ordre
public that had some technical–professional meaning for lawyers;
whereas Smyrniadis’ “international morality” was left floating in a
conceptual 378 His originally anonymous analyses and appeals
having been collected in Lapradelle, La paix moderne, pp. 141, 136–
138.
350
revealed aspects of both. On the one hand, there was the ease with
which solidarity as an abstract doctrine could be turned to buttress
381 Marcel Sibert, Traité de droit international de la paix (2 vols.,
Paris, Dalloz, 1951), II, pp.
8, 14–18.
382 Roberto Ago, “Droit positif et droit international” (1957), III
AFDI, pp. 14–62.
351
“real.”383
352
international law
Tradition in modernity
Less than two months after the capitulation at Munich, on November
16, 1938, Hersch Lauterpacht delivered an address to the League of
Nations Union of his new academic home, Cambridge University, on
the general subject of the League. He started the address by
confiding to his audience that this was a topic on which he felt so
strongly as to be unable to trust the “freely spoken word” and that in
order to maintain restraint and deliberation, he would read from a
manuscript, as was not his custom.1 Nonetheless, the address
departs from Lauterpacht’s customary, detached and complicated,
somewhat dry English at several points, most notably when, slightly
after the middle, he switches over to the first person plural. The
address opens with the argument that the events of the 1930s – the
Manchurian and Abyssinian Wars, the Munich accords – and the
attitudes taken by key League members have meant that the
Covenant’s collective security provisions, the territorial guarantee
(Art. 10) and the obligation of collective response (Arts 15 and 16),
have fallen into desuetude. In the fulfillment of its principal
objective, the League has failed. All that remains is the hope –
asserted without conviction – “that the true spirit of man will assert
itself in the long run.”
353
over stable and balanced growth, and the rise of dictatorships “on a
scale unprecedented in history.”3 There is little doubt about the
principles which identified Lauterpacht’s Cambridge audience as a
community. To invoke those principles Lauterpacht chooses to look
into the past – like Grotius once did in seeking authority from the
customs of the Romans,
354
8 For the modernist view, cf. Paul Fussell, The Great War and
Modern Memory (Oxford University Press, 1975). For the
traditionalist interpretation, cf. Jay Winter, Sites of Memory, Sites of
Mourning. The Great War in European Cultural History (Cambridge
University Press, 1995).
355
356
357
103–111.
358
374, 375.
359
360
361
115–129.
27 Sir Alfred Zimmern, The League of Nations and the Rule of Law
1918–1935 (London, Macmillan, 1935), p. 98.
362
363
215–296.
41 Lauterpacht, Private Law Sources, pp. 91–104.
364
365
366
But he goes further, arguing that the completeness of the rule of law
ties to decide cases. Legal argument is always able to fill the gap in
the end.66 Even “spurious gaps” may be filled: an unsatisfactory
single rule may be by-passed to give effect to a major principle of
law, the intention of the parties, or the purposes of the legal system
as a whole. In this way, even legal change is regulated by the law.67
145–153.
367
Arguments about the clash between law, on the one hand, and
justice or peace, on the other, are equally vacuous.71 Critics mistake
complexity for conflict. Problems of the unjust rule may always be
tempered by reference to the larger purposes of the law, rebus sic
stantibus, abuse of rights or equity.72 The needs of realism are
incorporated in the State’s undoubted right to determine the
conditions of self-defense and in the exception to the vitiating effect
of duress in the law of treaties.73
368
369
During the war, Lauterpacht stayed at his father’s timber mill that
had been requisitioned by the Austrian Government as part of the
war effort.
370
The argument for the completeness and unity of the law must have
seemed important enough to enable Lauterpacht to establish himself
in Britain and to overcome possible suspicions British lawyers might
have had against him. Hence in 1931, still working with The Function
of Law, he sought to refute the widely held British view that a
fundamental difference existed between the Anglo-American and
Continental schools of legal thought. Lauterpacht finds no such
fundamental divide.92 More importantly, assuming its existence
would be undesirable from a humanitarian point of view and
“question that ultimate uniformity of the sense of right and justice
which is the foundation of the legal ordering of the relations
between states.” It will hinder the (inevitable) development of
international law into a “common law of mankind.”93
372
373
198 This is the vote of February 1933 taken among members of the
Oxford Union, the University’s prestigious debating society.
374
106 For the drafting history, cf. Alfred Verdross, “Les principes
généraux du droit dans la jurisprudence internationale” (1935/II), 52
RdC, pp. 207 et seq; Géza Herzcegh, General Principles of Law and
the International Legal Order (Budapest, Akadémiai Kiadó, 1969),
pp. 11–33.
375
The Gentle Civilizer of Nations
Private Law Sources and The Function of Law. Here there were now
all the materials from which international lawyers could construct a
working system to resemble the domestic legal order: cases,
commentary and a doctrinal forum, henceforth available in most
major libraries and (in the case of Oppenheim) even on the shelves
of Foreign Offices.
A political commitment
By 1927 Lauterpacht had settled in Britain. He was married (since
1923), his son was born and he had received a lectureship at the
London School of Economics (recommended by Harold Laski, Arnold
McNair, and N. C. Gutteridge). His relations with his early supervisor
McNair had developed into a friendship. In 1931 he was naturalized
as a British subject. The following year he became Reader in Public
International Law at the University of London and was called to the
Bar by Gray’s Inn in 1936. Lauterpacht was now relatively free to
express his view on various aspects of international and British
policy. And because, according to the argument in The Function of
Law, every event of international policy was amenable to legal
analysis, it seems logical that he should think it important to
undertake public analyses of contemporary international events from
a legal perspective.
This view led Lauterpacht to deny that the League was merely a
coordinative body of diplomatic conciliation and to emphasize the
provisions on collective security whose importance both
contemporary critics and enthusiasts often belittled as a
consequence of their “realism” or in their effort to combat it by
focusing on the League’s functional activities.110
107 Hersch Lauterpacht, “Japan and the Covenant” (1932), 3
Political Quarterly, p. 175.
109 Lauterpacht, “The Covenant as the Higher Law” pp. 63–64, 60.
376
What, for example, was the significance of the claim made by the
principal signatories to the 1928 Kellogg–Briand Pact that they
themselves remained the sole judges of the application of the right
of self-defense? In a language familiar from The Function of Law,
and later from his period at the Court, Lauterpacht wrote: “An
interpretation which leaves to the interested States the right to
decide finally and conclusively whether they have observed the
Treaty probably deprives the Pact of the essential vinculum juris and
renders it legally meaningless.”112 The
112 Hersch Lauterpacht, “The Pact of Paris and the Budapest Articles
of Interpretation” (1934), 20 Transactions of the Grotius Society, p.
198.
377
378
379
pp. 191–197.
p. 146.
380
Lauterpacht: the Victorian tradition in international law was not a
conflict where a State could remain neutral for it was fought for “the
purpose of vindicating the rule of law among nations.”134 Nor did
there exist any place for neutrality in the Allied-conceived future
legal order. To the contrary, there would be a legal duty on “all
mankind” to make war upon the aggressor.135 The principles of
collective security and the indivisibility of peace would be parts of
the new law.
381
“make clear to all the world exactly where the Great Britain
stands”139
382
383
384
“State,” then there is little point in insisting that the status still exists.
however, it goes too far in the opposite direction. From the existence
of a gap between “facts” and their cognition it draws the
consequence that 151 Lauterpacht, Recognition, pp. 45–51.
385
the two are wholly independent from each other, that recognition is
an act of pure, unconstrained political will. But in fact nobody treats
it as such. If statehood is a matter of fulfilling some antecedent
criteria, then surely recognition must comply with such criteria – and
that it is so regarded is evident, for example, in the generally
accepted view that holds premature recognition as a violation of the
law154 and that tests governmental authority by reference to its
effectiveness; to hold otherwise would allow intervention in the
internal affairs of the State.155
The only open question that remains is what the legal criteria of
attaining the relevant status are, and how they are to be interpreted.
Here there is, of course, much debate and discretion. On the one
hand, a legal view is incompatible with politically loaded criteria,
such as legitimacy of origin, religion, political orientation, or even the
willingness to abide by international law.156 On the other hand,
such criteria cannot be purely factual, without violating the principle
of ex injuria non jus oritur.
386
of the interwar years. Its legal utopia relied not only on diplomats’
willingness to understand their job accordingly but – much more
crucially 161 Lauterpacht, Recognition, pp. 329 et seq.
166 Cf. Harold Temperley, The Victorian Age in Politics, War and
Diplomacy (Cambridge University Press, 1928), pp. 14–21.
387
Lauterpacht’s whole family, his parents, his brother and sister and
their children, with the exception of one niece, were murdered in the
Holocaust, presumably as early as 1940. It is not clear when he
learned of the fate of his family. Nothing is visible of this tragedy in
his writings
388
169 These themes – the advocacy for a War Crimes tribunal, the
elaboration of the basis of its jurisdiction, as well as the law
applicable and a discussion of a neutral State’s duty to extradite
suspects – are also dealt with in “The Law of Nations and the
Punishment of War Crimes” (1944), XI BYIL, pp. 58–95 (an article
based on a Memorandum Lauterpacht prepared for a Committee set
up by the Department of Criminal Science at Cambridge University).
389
175 These ideas were not generally shared among the British
international law community. Professor Brierly, for instance, took a
very critical view of the proposals – especially of the implied aim of
forcing democracy as the internal form of government
390
In his view, the situation was worse now than it had been in 1919.
The interwar years had been a period of regression to which the
peace of 1945 had brought no significant relief. Modernity had failed
him. He attributed this to four rather different causes: lawlessness in
the conduct of warfare, the suppression of normal conditions by the
Allies in occupied Italy and Germany, the prevailing atmosphere of
admiration of power, and the requirement of unanimity of the
permanent members of the Security Council.181 Even recent
progress in some areas (the growth of international organization, the
acceptance of the principles of enforcement and human rights) “has
been obscured by the tangible and menacing reality of the division
of the world into two opposing groups of States.”182
182 “International Law after World War II,” p. 167. Cf. also “The
Grotian Tradition in International Law,” p. 1 n 2.
391
392
393
Just as in the “political” writings of the 1930s, it turns out that the
substance of the rights is less important than the procedures, the
key problem being “what shall be the international machinery for
securing the rights after they have been recognized.”198
Lauterpacht was disappointed by the early jurisdictional decision by
the Commission on Human Rights not to take action on individual
petitions and responded by the argument that human rights were
not merely an incidental decoration but an underlying theme of the
Charter. It would therefore have been possible for the Commission in
accordance with the principle of effectiveness to examine individual
complaints.199 He urged as the essential part of the future
International Bill of Rights – what became the two 195 Lauterpacht,
International Law and Human Rights, pp. 27–47.
394
202 Letter to the Times, July 26, 1947, Collected Papers, 3, pp. 408–
409.
395
The point here is that the relationship between the tradition and the
institutional proposals is more complex than Lauterpacht is willing to
acknowledge. Tradition (natural law) and modernity (institutional
experience) refuse to lie comfortably in the same bed. A reliance on
the former may sometimes support statehood, sometimes
federalism.
396
397
398
To carry out this task it did not suffice to remain in the university.
399
the Corfu Channel case, he wrote a letter in May 1949 to the British
Legal Adviser, expressing an interest “in advising private clients and
foreign governments . . . mainly for the reason that it brings [him] in
touch with the practical side of international law.”214 And he
affirmed his loyalty by expressing his readiness to exclude cases that
would interfere with his teaching or be “clearly contrary” to the
views of the British Government
216 The two reports supplement each other and have been edited
and reprinted in Collected Papers, 4, pp. 101–388.
218 Cf. e.g. Draft Art. 11(5) and 15, Collected Papers, 4, pp. 257,
296.
400
Lauterpacht: the Victorian tradition in international law had arisen
before the ratification of the declaration was of a “highly subjective
character” – for when is a dispute not related to anterior facts,
sometimes to facts quite far away in time?219 During his brief period
at the Court (1955–1960), his most memorable statements related
precisely to the self-judging reservations made by States to their
declarations of acceptance of the Court’s jurisdiction that enabled
them arbitrarily to foreclose the Court’s involvement. Unlike the
majority of the judges, Lauterpacht felt that such a reservation made
the whole declaration invalid abinitio: no compulsory jurisdiction was
in fact created at all.220
220 Cf. ICJ, Norwegian Loans case, Reports 1957, p. 34; Interhandel
case, Reports 1959, p. 95.
221 The notes Lauterpacht had prepared during 1958–1960 for the
second edition of the book show that his view remained unchanged.
There still appeared no reason to make a distinction between
justiciable and non-justiciable disputes – although, Lauterpacht now
was prepared to concede, the faculty to decide every case did not
necessarily mean that judges could settle every dispute. The political
usefulness of the law was a question to which there could be no
properly legal answer. This was a matter of faith. Cf. fragments of
additions that were to be inserted in a planned second edition of
Function of Law, manuscript for a new paragraph 11a, Lauterpacht
Archives, to be published in Collected Papers, 5 (part IX.3). Cf. also
“Some Observations on the Prohibition of ‘Non Liquet’,” pp. 200–201.
401
article on the law applicable to the continental shelf. Here there was
a question in which a number of States had resorted to unilateral
acts to influence their legal position. Many argued that this was
permissible because no rule had crystallized and the Lotus principle
– the presumption of liberty of action – would therefore have to be
applied. However, consistent with the teaching in The Function of
Law, Lauterpacht discarded the possibility of non liquet and instead
constructed the applicable law by the relevant legal principles
available. There were two such opposing principles: geographical
contiguity and effective occupation.
Both were too extreme, however, and could not be used to dictate
particular solutions. To the contrary: “the conceptions of effective
occupation and contiguity, being relative, are but a starting point. It
is within the legitimate province of the judicial function – and of
statesmanship
– to use them with such discretion as the equitites of the case and
considerations of stability require.”228 Everything hinged on the
“decisive 225 Lauterpacht, “Règles,” p. 383.
227 For example, applying the laws passed by the Allied occupation
authority in Germany after the war, French courts had restored the
German nationality of Jewish stateless persons whose nationality
had been illegally removed by the Nazi regime.
402
403
The three reasons for judicial caution that he discusses are reasons
of conjecture, linked to the present, temporary, and intrinsically
unsatisfactory character of international society. According to
Lauterpacht, judges should not legislate because they would then
lose the confidence of the governments; there would then be no
cases submitted to them; 235 Lauterpacht, Development of
International Law, pp. 158–165.
237 E.g. by expanding the scope of legal subjects or basing the rule
on the vitiating effect of duress on the outlawry of war. Lauterpacht,
Development of International Law, pp.
173–185.
405
“[I]n the sphere of action, ideas may not be more potent than the
individual human beings called upon to realize them.”249 The image
of progress is no longer (as in the interwar “political” period) that of
diplomats arguing about collective security in Geneva, nor (as it was
after the Second World War) that of UN bodies administering human
rights.
A Grotian tradition?
406
407
The Gentle Civilizer of Nations
261 Cf. e.g. “Règles,” pp. 302–304; “Book Review. Karl Lowenstein,
Political Reconstruction” (1946), XXIII BYIL, pp. 510–511.
408
Kelsen did not deny the place of values in law (and for legal study)
but insisted on the need for openness in “value-choices” – e.g. the
choice between dualism and monism.268 Such relativism was not
part of Lauterpacht’s world: the Eternal Verities could not be
subjected to
268 Hans Kelsen, Das Problem der Souveränität und die Theorie des
Völkerrechts (2nd edn., Tübingen, Mohr, 1928), pp. 257–266.
409
410
411
412
“international relations”
OAS
that
the
adherence
of
any
of
its
members
to
1 Quoted in Max Harrelson, Fires all around the Horizon. The UN’s
Uphill Battle to Preserve the Peace (New York, Praeger, 1989), p.
182.
413
414
Carl Schmitt, Hans Morgenthau and “international relations”
a parallel between his critique and that made by Julien Benda in the
Trahison des Clercs forty years earlier, concluding the article by the
observation that “Freedom is today threatened from many sides. It
has never survived the abandonment of intellectual independence.”6
7 Carl Schmitt, Der Nomos der Erde im Völkerrecht des Jus Publicum
Europaeum (Berlin, Duncker & Humblot, 1950).
Telos, pp. 105–127 and Rafael Gross, “‘Jewish Law and Christian
Grace’ – Carl Schmitt’s Critique of Hans Kelsen,” in Dan Diner and
Michel Stolleis (eds.), Hans Kelsen and Karl Schmitt. A Juxtaposition
(Gerlingen, Bleicher, 1999), pp. 105–107. For a useful summary of
Schmitt’s antisemitism cf. Heinrich Meier, The Lesson of Carl Schmitt.
415
416
Carl Schmitt, Hans Morgenthau and “international relations”
24–31.
417
418
22 Cf. e.g. “Das neue Vae Neutris” (1938), in Schmitt, Positionen und
Begriffe, pp. 251–255.
419
for the coming global order.26 One was a universal empire under
one great power – the United States. This, of course, he saw as a
tragedy, a final victory of the dominance of economy and technology
(and those possessing them) over the rest of the world. A second
alternative was for the United States to take over England’s place in
the old territorial equilibrium as the “balancer,” the external
guarantor of Europe’s internal peace, accompanied by unquestioned
primacy in the Western Hemisphere. The third alternative – clearly
preferred by Schmitt and perhaps seen by him as the one most likely
to emerge – was a structure of territorial division between a limited
number of large blocks ( Grossräume) that mutually recognized each
other and excluded external intervention: the image of Spengler and
Orwell, and the focus of Friedmann’s anxiety in 1965.
420
Carl Schmitt, Hans Morgenthau and “international relations”
had drawn from Roman law and whose last great name had been
Savigny. Since 1848 this jurisprudence had been gradually
instrumentalized in the service of national legislatures and parties. It
had become part of “an untrammelled technicism which uses state
law as a tool” and lost its role as the “last refuge of legal
consciousness.”29 A quarter of a century later he had no reason to
change this assessment. That the forces for European unity were no
match to an economically and technologically driven globalization
paralleled the inequality of strength between a doctrinal–technical
Europäisches Gemeinschaftsrecht and what he called
“ideologies of progress.”30
p. 85.
421
422
(2nd edn., with a new introd., New York, Greenwood, 1989). Both of
these contain relatively positive assessments that are now countered
by the very polemical study by William E. Scheuerman, Carl Schmitt:
The End of Law (Lanham, Boulder, New York and Oxford, Rowman &
Littlefield, 1999). The best English-language study, however, is Gopal
Balakrishnan, The Enemy: An Intellectual Portrait of Carl Schmitt
(London, Verso, 2000). Renato Cristi, Carl Schmitt and Authoritarian
Liberalism (Cardiff, University of Wales Press, 1998), makes the
useful point about Schmitt being a liberal in the sense of advocating
a liberal economy outside a strong State. Two collections of essays
shed light on the various aspects of Schmitt’s work in the English
language, Chantal Mouffe (ed.), The Challenge of Carl Schmitt
(London, Verso, 1999), and David Dyzenhaus (ed.), Law as Politics.
Carl Schmitt’s Critique of Liberalism (Duke University Press, 1998).
Brief accounts of Schmitt’s biography are also contained in the
English translations of his major works.
423
The Gentle Civilizer of Nations
But they fail to undermine the force of many of his insights about
law and the new political order. To deal with Schmitt is necessary, as
many have argued, to understand the complex relationship between
political utopias and struggles; and international lawyers do owe an
explanation for the fact that while there has never been as much
talk about international law and morality as in the twentieth century,
never have atrocities on such wide scale been committed in the
name of political utopias.
Before the war Schmitt had found the academic articulation for the
end of the ius publicum Europaeum as well as the contours of its
successor in the writings of Georges Scelle and Hersch Lauterpacht,
two lawyers whose separate lines of argument converged in the view
of international law as the law of a “communauté universelle.”39 In
Scelle’s Droit des gens Schmitt saw the so far most consistent
application of radical liberal–democratic ideas to the international
system. Employing the French concept of the legislative State,
Scelle’s federalism may have oscillated insecurely between
individualism and collectivism, but relegated formal State law
definitely into the realm of the metaphysical and the unscientific.
Where Scelle was expressly dismissive of the lex lata/lex ferenda
distinction, Lauterpacht developed a more limited common law
analysis of international cases 39 Carl Schmitt, Die Wendung zum
diskriminierenden Kriegsbegriff (Berlin, Duncker & Humblot, 1988
[1938]), pp. 1–8. The pamphlet is based on a paper given to the
Association of German Jurists in October 1937, as Schmitt had been
expelled from political positions and feared for his safety. But he did
not turn his back on Nazi policy and remained supported by Göring
and Hans Frank. Nonetheless, the paper may be seen as an attempt
to move to a less politically contentious realm and to participate in a
wider European scholarly debate. In this, he had little success.
Foreign Minister Ribbentrop congratulated him for expressing so well
the German position.
424
There can be no neutrality between the policeman and the thief. The
concept of collective action, Schmitt held, was a key to the emerging
nomos. 42
426
Since then, liberalism had reduced all problems either into the realm
of a romantic aestheticism or chosen to treat them as exclusively
economic and technological.45 The end of European public law at
the end of the nineteenth century came about as a result of the
blurring of the notion of politics that had been a “presupposition”
behind the concept of the state.46
427
State law was like the law of nature: all-pervading, omnipotent, and
without an exception.
There could hardly have been a more striking gap between this kind
of liberal jurisprudence and the struggle against political collapse
that was the reality of Weimar. The situation itself seemed to prove
that order did not emerge from the spontaneous love of one’s
neighbors but had to be created by the political system. In a famous
debate between Kelsen and Schmitt about who is the “guardian” of
the constitution, Kelsen pointed to the supreme federal court while
Schmitt observed that this might be so as long as things stay
normal, but not if there is an extreme emergency – defined as the
inability of the regular legal process to control the situation. Here
Schmitt expounded his radical definition of the sovereign as “he who
decides on the exception,” that is to say, on “whether there is an
extreme emergency as well as what should be done to counter it.”50
The state of exception performed in politics the same task that
miracle did in theology: it reaffirmed and proved the authority of the
normal. How this was done cannot be legally circumscribed; no law
can foresee the exception and the conditions for suspending itself.
And more: every normality owes its existence to a pouvoir
constituant that once formed an exception: “The exception is more
interesting than the rule. The rule proves nothing; the exception
proves everything: It confirms not only the rule but also its
existence, which derives only from the exception.”51 Legal normality
hid political conflict from sight but did not make it disappear.
Conflict re-emerged every time the law was to be applied. “In every
transformation there is present an auctoritatis interpositio.”52 The
legal system relied on decisions by those in authoritative positions:
Kelsen had been able to construct a depoliticized law only by
emptying it of its content and ignoring implementation, the all-
important question Quis judicabit?
428
429
430
160–165.
431
The Gentle Civilizer of Nations
Otherwise, the State will cease to exist. What is left may be a set of
collective economic or cultural pursuits – sooner or later to dissolve
in civil war or by the force of external aggression.66
It had been the great merit of the ius publicum Europaeum that it
had limited war into a public law duel between formal States. As we
have seen, in Schmitt’s view, it was being replaced by a universalistic
“moralism” that far from doing away with conflict lifted all restraint
on how it would be waged. In the first place, it became outright
impossible to distinguish between conflict and its opposite. As war
ceased to be a formal status, what came in its stead was an
amorphous status mixtus, a grey zone of informal control and
pressure by those who had the means. This, Schmitt argued in the
1920s, had happened in the protectorates outside Europe that fell
short of formal annexation but guaranteed full control, as well as in
the innumerable forms of supervision, occupation, and investigation
over European (particularly German) territory established 64
Schmitt, The Concept of the Political, p. 45.
432
Secondly, and far more dangerously, moralism lifted all limits from
international violence. The renunciation of war as a matter of
“national policy” in the 1928 Kellogg–Briand Pact was deeply
deceptive: “The solemn declaration of outlawing war does not
abolish the friend–enemy distinction, but, on the contrary, opens
new possibilities for giving an international hostis declaration new
content and new vigor.”69 In practice, the declaration was
accompanied by specific reservations concerning war in self-defense
– reservations that were, Schmitt correctly observed, no mere
exceptions to the norm of peacefulness but “gave the norm its
concrete content . . . in dubious cases.” As sovereignty meant the
right to determine whether the enemy had attacked (or would attack
unless deterred), and what was needed to counter the foreseeable
attack, no change occurred in political reality. It was still the friend–
enemy distinction, and the ability to draw the extreme consequences
from it, that determined the political identity of States.70
433
The League was not “humanity” – it did not abolish war. On the
contrary: “It introduces new possibilities for wars, permits wars to
take place, sanctions coalition wars, and by legitimizing and
sanctioning certain wars it sweeps away many obstacles to war . . .
this establishment is not a league, but possibly an alliance.”73 The
humanitarian war becomes a war of annihilation (
Vernichtungskrieg), a global civil war where the enemy does not
have the dignity of a State and resistance will appear as “the illegal
and immoral resistance of a few delinquents, troublemak-ers, pirates
and gangsters.”74
Nothing of this had changed for Schmitt in fifty years. In 1978
434
It was against all this that Schmitt devised his concept of the
Grossraum in 1939 and in 1950: as a space of politics to replace the
obsolete neutralism of formal States and as a restraining instrument
against the appropriation of the language of humanity by the clercs
of a single, industrially based nomos. Cuius industria, eius regio. In a
world-scale economy, this would mean not Landnahme but
Weltraumnahme.76 Because this process was conceptually identical
with the demise of the ius publicum Europaeum, it seems natural
that Schmitt did not see international law as an effective restraint on
it. From his Weimar writings as well as from his “testament” of
1943–1944, however, it is possible to extract a sense about what he
thought of the law’s role in the struggle between single empire and
Grossräume. Two types of legal thought were responsible for the
erosion of the European jurisprudence since the nineteenth century.
435
The Gentle Civilizer of Nations
In the second (and third) editions, the political stood out, however,
from such delimitations so as to potentially encompass all of them.
Now politics had no intrinsic limit: every aspect of life could manifest
the friend–enemy opposition and thus transform itself into political
struggle. Politics had no substance, it described the “intensity of
association or dissociation of human beings.”80 This increased the
need to ensure that the State had the ability to prevent that struggle
from leading into an all-out civil war or indeed an all-out
international war – something it could do only through a
concentration of overwhelming power in the hands of a “guardian.”
Now this idea of politics as an intensity concept did not exist in the
earlier edition of the book. By contrast, it was centrally present in
the 1929 doctoral dissertation to the Faculty of Law at the University
of Frankfurt by the 25-year-old Hans Morgenthau, titled Die
internationale Rechtspflege. Ihr Wesen und ihre Grenzen (The
International Judicial Function. Its Nature and Limits). Morgenthau
had specifically taken issue with Schmitt’s influential 1927 work by
reference to which he developed his own notion of the political as a
quality and not a substance, capable of penetrating every realm of
international life. This was the reason, the young Morgenthau
claimed, that international law had been such a weak structure.
Morgenthau sent his dissertation to Schmitt and received in
exchange a complimentary letter. When the second edition of
Schmitt’s Der Begriff des Politischen came out in 1932, it included
the new definition of the political as an intensity concept – without
due acknowledgment, as Morgenthau later bitterly remarked.81
436
fully plain. A political change had led to “the end of the state system
which has existed since the sixteenth century in the Western world.”
437
The Cold War was the final stage in the dismantling of what Schmitt
had called the ius publicum Europaeum, its place taken by two
crusading superpowers, assisted by proxies in Europe and Asia.
Bolshevism and US
foreign policy were both crafted into a moralistic frame they had
inherited from the Second World War as a war against the absolute
evil that must be compelled to unconditional surrender.87
438
“[W]ithin the limits of their power.” This was Schmitt’s nomos, the
concrete order. Morgenthau’s 1951 book indicted American
utopianism, sentimentalism, legalism, and neo-isolationism as fatal
disregard of the need to determine clearly the (US) national interest
and to keep focus on it while one was acting. The “real issue” in the
cold war, for instance, was not an ideological confrontation but a
desire for power that transformed the revolutionary rhetoricof the
Soviet State into an instrument of Russian imperialism.89
Morgenthau agreed with Schmitt in his critique of US utopianism. It
led either into a completely unrealistic expectation that one’s political
contenders would feel bound by agreements concluded – the shock
at Soviet dismissal of the Yalta agreement on East European
democracy90 – or it resulted in the understanding of war as moral
struggle by “peace-loving nations” against the forces of evil; the
branding of the enemy as a “war criminal” having committed an “act
of aggression”
439
Law, if needed, would come later: to uphold the status quo.96 The
concrete order – balance of power – had first to be set up. And this
was an irreducibly political task.
440
127–128.
441
The “legal” and the “political” are not at all an adequate pair of
concepts that could enter into a determinate contrast. The
conceptual counterpart of the concept of political is formed by the
concept of the non-political but not by the concept of “legal
question” which, for its part, can be both political or non-
political.102
But those rights and duties are overwhelmed by the intensity of the
feelings of the participant States about them or about the context of
which they were a part. For example, there was no doubt that the
Versailles settlement constituted positive law. But its being so was
completely overshadowed by the intensity of the feelings (especially
in Germany) concerning its injustice. The controversy between the
Allied and Associated powers on the one hand and Germany on the
other could never be resolved by a tribunal. The “tension” was not
about what positive law said but whether and how it should be
changed.
442
443
444
– had been “in its original spiritual and political function alien to the
German nature.”117 By securing Germany’s membership in the
League Stresemann had been able to transform the organization in
accordance with the new European situation and to end Germany’s
spiritual isolation through means that did not involve the use of
violence, indeed were opposed to it
Hans Morgenthau,
445
446
stand the world in its naked reality, and not though the superficial
(religious, ethical, political) ideas through which it publicly justified
itself. For this purpose, science seemed a necessary instrument – not
just any science but one that would provide direct access to the
existential condition of social life. Already Morgenthau’s school
essays manifest this determination.122 It prompted him to study
philosophy for his first semester at the University of Frankfurt in
1923; but he left it after half a year, disappointed with the
superficially rationalist scientism en vogue there. Turning to law was
hardly a better choice in that respect, but at least it provided the
basis for a future livelihood.
It was not until after graduation in 1927, when he had taken the
position of assistant to the notable socialist lawyer Hugo Sinzheimer
(1875–1945), a former participant in the Weimar Assembly, the
owner of a law firm specializing in labor law, and through him had
come to know some of the most important legal and political
thinkers in Germany, that Morgenthau was introduced into an
intellectual milieu in which he felt that matters of existential and
political significance were being discussed.123 Among a
predominantly socialist group of lawyers and philosophers,
Morgenthau remained, however, a conservative.
447
127 “Über die Herkunft des Politischen aus dem Wesen des
Menschen” (Morgenthau Archive, Library of Congress, HJM-B-151,
copy on file with author).
448
“What was decisive was not the merits of legal interpretation, but
the 130 Morgenthau, “Über die Herkunft des Politischen,” p. 17.
131 Morgenthau, “Über die Herkunft des Politischen,” pp. 31–35, 43.
450
Morgenthau’s lengthy quotations from Jünger align his text with the
latter’s powerful expressionism. The attempt to come to terms with
the irrational by embracing it with full force was not too alien to
what Morgenthau saw himself doing. To create distance from Jünger,
Morgenthau espoused a rationalism that was at odds with the rest of
the article but surfaced constantly in his later writings, too, creating
the sense of contradiction that has so puzzled later commentators.
He agreed with Jünger that the official justifications for war were
really nothing; war was sought for the inner experience it provided,
the experience of energy, danger, “life” in an authentic non-
bourgeois sense. Where Jünger’s vitalism failed, Morgenthau
claimed, was in providing no explanation for why it still contradicted
human conscience. By not treating that contradiction, but dismissing
it, Jünger was pushed into extreme subjectivism.
139 Morgenthau, “Der Selbstmord mit guten Gewissen,” pp. 23, 30.
452
454
214–216.
455
The Struggle for Power and Peace (New York, Knopf, 1948) the
same theme is discussed in connection with sovereignty. Here
Morgenthau moves from a Kelsenian conception of “sovereignty” as
“supreme legal authority” (p. 248, italics mine) to a Schmittian
notion under which such supremacy is a function of struggle
between contending forces that lies normally dormant but asserts
itself “in times of crisis” (p. 261).
456
457
458
AJIL, p. 283.
459
First, for both, an era – the European era – had come to an end. A
political, technological, and moral revolution had undermined the
balance of power that had dominated Victorian normality. Interwar
formalism had collapsed in face of the realities of “power.” The
informal opposition between the blocs now set the absolute
conditions for international cooperation, diplomacy and law. It also
provided an atmosphere of crisis that threatened to collapse into a
full-scale nuclear destruction. The liberals had conceived technology
as an instrument of peace. Schmitt and Morgenthau saw it as a
means for political control, total war, and world domination.177
Legal normality was formed by reference to the extreme situation –
the nuclear catastrophe – that dictated the conditions under which
lawyers could work.178
177 Morgenthau, Politics among Nations, pp. 292–305. Cf. also Hans
Morgenthau, “The National Socialist Doctrine on World Organization”
(1943), Proceedings of the Seventh Conference of Teachers of
International Law and Related Subjects, Washington DC, April 23–
25, 1941, p. 107.
460
461
187 Hans Morgenthau, A New Foreign Policy for the United States
(New York, Washington, and London, Praeger, 1969), pp. 111 et seq.
113, 128.
189 “The moral duty to spare the wounded, the sick, the
surrendering and unarmed enemy, and to respect him as a human
being an enemy only by virtue of being found on the other side of
the fence, is superseded by the moral duty to punish and to wipe off
the face of the earth the professors and practitioners of evil,”
Morgenthau, Politics among Nations, pp. 182–183. Cf. also Greg
Russell, Hans J. Morgenthau and the Ethics of American Statecraft
(Baton Rouge, Louisiana State University Press, 1990), pp.
207–209.
462
Carl Schmitt, Hans Morgenthau and “international relations”
463
464
“the founder of the discipline”200 and who was listed (with Hannah
Arendt, Leo Strauss, and Herbert Marcuse) among “the four most
influential of [the] refugee intellectuals” in the development of
political theory in the United States.201 Morgenthau’s influence as
the founder of international relations follows from his conscious
departure from (legal) formalism on the one hand, but, crucially, of
his steadfast refusal to collapse the field into mainstream sociology
or ethics, on the other. He did not found the discipline despite the
contradiction between realism and idealism in Politics among
Nations. He founded it on that contradiction.
Before the war, the study of international relations in the United 199
Cf. Alfons Söllner, “Vom Völkerrecht zum science of international
relations. Vier typische Vertreter des politikwissenschaftlichen
Emigration,” in Ilja Srubar (ed.), Exil, Wissenschaft, Identität. Die
Emigration deutscher Sozialwissenschaftler 1933–1945
465
466
209 Cf. Jürgen Gebhardt, “Leo Strauss: The Quest for Truth in Times
of Perplexity,” in Kielmansegg, Mewes, and Glaser-Schmidt, Hannah
Arendt (linking this attitude to the general outlook of the German
academic elite – including the émigrés in the United States), pp. 84–
89.
467
468
Here lay the affinity between Morgenthau’s academic work and the
political realism of diplomats such as George Kennan or Henry
Kissinger. Morgenthau never supported the role of an international
and passim.
469
470
However, Herz and Morgenthau also reserved a limited role for law in
situations where the balance of power or common interests were
working. Both conserved a traditional court and case oriented image
of law. Legal rules and institutions were sometimes useful as
instruments for 221 This is accepted by Morgenthau as he writes
with undiguised nostalgia about the virtues of the aristocratic
internationalism of the nineteenth century. Cf.
471
472
Carl Schmitt, Hans Morgenthau and “international relations”
473
233 On this “pluralism,” cf. e.g. Richard Little, “The English School’s
Contribution to the Study of International Relations” (2000), 6
European Journal of International Relations, pp. 395–422.
474
McDougal’s and Harold Lasswell’s Yale School was only the most
visible but perhaps among the least influential of the new
approaches that grew up in the United States in the 1950s and
1960s. During those years, American international lawyers were
faced with three responses to the decline of interwar formalism.237
First, legal realism was overwhelming domestic academic law and
cultivated an image of the lawyer as a policy-maker relatively free to
choose the direction of legal advice.
475
476
answer the question “is this law or not?,” the usefulness of their
proposals appeared doubtful (and certainly not worth the trouble it
took to learn their language) to lawyers whose lay colleagues
persisted in asking precisely that question.
school that had been the leading successor to legal realism in the
1950s and had accepted much of the realists’ emphasis on discretion
but sought control by focusing on negotiating behavior, competence,
and 245 Wolfgang Friedmann, The Changing Structure of
International Law (New York, Columbia University Press, 1964), esp.
pp. 60–71, 82–95.
246 Charles G. Fenwick, “International Law: The Old and the New”
(1966), 60 AJIL, pp. 481–483.
477
250 Abram Chayes, The Cuban Missile Crisis (New York, Oxford
University Press, 1974).
Cf. also Abram Chayes, International Legal Process. Materials for an
Introductory Course (Boston, Little, Brown, 1968–1969).
251 Cf. Louis Henkin, How Nations Behave. Law and Foreign Policy
(2nd edn., New Haven, Columbia University Press, 1979).
478
tional law scholarship after the realist challenge was its deformalized
concept of law. Whatever political differences there were between
McDougal and Columbia scholars, they agreed that international law
was not merely formal diplomacy or cases from the International
Court of Justice but that – if it were to be relevant – it had to be
conceived in terms of broader political processes or techniques that
aimed towards policy “objectives.” A relevant law would be
enmeshed in the social context and studied through the best
techniques of neighboring disciplines.254 This would mean a shift of
emphasis from formal obligations to informal understandings and
“regimes,” with the acknowledgement that violations could be of
different degrees. Such policy pragmatism received support from the
negotiations leading up to the defusing of the Cuban missile crisis
and the period of détente that followed. What now seemed needed
was “avoiding all temptation to the adoption of single, high-level
code of the law of Soviet–Western relations” and “any Western
insistence on a postulated ‘World Rule of Law’” in favor of an
“essentially modest, low-level, empirically-based, step-by-step
approach.”255 Policy pragmatism to the core.
Empire’s law
259 This, I guess, is the flip side of Oppenheim’s dictum that respect
for international law has been greatest in balance-of-power systems.
If such balance is lacking, legal formalism gives way to the
enforcement of the hegemon’s morality. Cf. Stanley Hoffmann,
“International Systems and International Law,” in Hoffmann, Janus
and Minerva, pp. 157–164.
260 Cf. Carl Schmitt, “Die Ordnung der Welt nach dem Zweiten
Weltkrieg” (1962), in Staat, Grossraum, Nomos, pp. 600–607
(identifying the developing–developed States opposition as “die
wirkliche Verfassung der Erde,” p. 605).
480
article. Unlike most other American lawyers who were arguing about
the lawfulness of the intervention in one way or the other, he
refrained from taking sides on the legal controversy and especially
from following Schmitt or McDougal, for whom the events were part
of a process whereby a legal order was being created and
reaffirmed.
482
483
275 Cf. Dinah Shelton (ed.), Commitment and Compliance. The Role
of Non-Binding Norms in the International Legal System (Oxford
University Press, 2000).
485
way sociology has always done: transforming the debate about the
ends of action to the means of action, from normative praxis to
instrumental techne. It was this aspect of instrumentalism and the
turn to “science” to which Morgenthau and Schmitt drew attention in
their critiques of the liberal depoliticization and neutralization of
political choices.276
An instrumentalist culture, however, creates the danger of
administrative abuse. If law is only about what works, and pays no
attention to the objectives for which it is used, then it will become
only a smokescreen for effective power. Moreover, as Weber has
shown, recourse to deformalized standards (such as “democratic” or
“equitable”) transforms law into an instrument for the power that
has control over the executive.
277 Ernst Bloch, Natural Law and Human Dignity (trans. Dennis J.
Schmidt, Cambridge, Mass., MIT Press, 1987), pp. 132, 149–152.
486
In other words, if the “dual agenda” were only about what works, it
would achieve a thoroughly function-dependent, non-autonomous
law, an ingenious justification for a world Leviathan. Aside from
sociology, ethics is needed. This was precisely what McDougal and
his associates tried to attain by reference to their “goal values” of
“human dignity.”
But that kind of naturalism could not sustain the critiques of ethics
that had become part of the agnostic modernity of the profession.
The lawyers on the left fared no better. Institutionalism and legal
process relied on assumptions about interdependence and rational
behavior that had been effectively discarded by the Realists. They
were of course right to think that decision-makers in international
institutions shared a basiccommitment to liberal internationalism that
would by and large reflect the preferences of American
internationalists as well. But the scarcity of resources and conflicts of
interest between States imposed choices upon institutions that were
difficult to justify by the argument about long-term harmony of
interests. Such choices made these institutions – the United Nations
especially – vulnerable to the charge of political partiality. A
moderate internationalism proved just as little controlling in the
debates in the 1970s and 1980s on a new international economic
order, or on how to decide between environmental and economic
preferences in the 1990s, as it had been able to produce collective
security in the 1930s.
487
107–116.
193, 183–197.
488
from the kinds of sociology and ethics that are being advocated. The
suggested sociology is always already normatively loaded, and
loaded so as to underwrite the constellation already produced
through power.
283 For a reformulation, cf. John Rawls, The Law of Peoples: with
the “Idea of Public Reason”
489
It follows that a person, group, or a State that does not share them
is not only of another opinion (or preference) but has made a
mistake about something that that person, group, or State should
think rational for itself, too. Universalizability in theory leads
automatically to expansion as practice. If my principle is valid
because it is universal, then I not only may but perhaps must try to
make others accept it as well. In any case, I can rest confident that I
know what principles apply not only to me and my group but to any
person or any group. If I engage in contacts with them, I need not
face them as equals. I need not be open to their preferences
because I already know that mine are universally valid, for me as
well as for them, too. I may (or perhaps must) be kind towards and
patient with them, but the object of my encounter can only be the
transformation of the way they see the world, having them accept
my principles, too (because they are not really “mine” but universally
good).284
286 Michael Walzer, for instance, argues plausibly against the use of
invented moral principles to apply to the lives of situated persons: a
minimal morality such as offered by the hypothetical choice will be
unresponsive to the concerns and aspirations of any actual (“dense”)
culture with a sense of belonging “there.” Cf. Michael Walzer,
Interpretation and Moral Criticism (Cambridge, Mass., Harvard
University Press, 1987), pp. 11–18.
490
First case is the one where the decision-maker (State, legal adviser)
believes that his preferences fulfill the criteria postulated by the
theory about universal (rational) norms. In such a case, every
deviating position will appear as irrational, or at least partial,
subjective, historically conditioned, political bias. It may be taken
into account, of course, if that leads to the most effective overall
realization of the decision-maker’s own non-contextually valid
preference. But it enjoys no independent normative validity vis-à-vis
the decision-maker. It may be treated as an atavisticresidue from
political, religious, ethnic, or other such particular moralities. In due
course, with increasing enlightenment (defined as gradual
acceptance of the non-contextual position), it would be given up or
at least loosen its obsessive hold on those who still cling to it. In a
deep sense, having such preference either demonstrates ignorance
and error when measured against the norms or policies that are
accepted as universally valid, or results from the evil manipulations
of the leaders of that other community. These positions might be
called rational imperialism.287
491
They do not compete on their merits, but are overruled at the outset
as lacking some special character (non-contextuality) of the norms
the decision-maker holds. They are not just different but at a
different level of seriousness or justifiability altogether: “irrational”
where the decision-maker’s is “rational,” “subjective” or “passionate,”
against his
“objective” or “reasonable” position.289 Because they are so, there
never 288 In Tzvetan Todorov’s classic study, the distinction between
rational and cynical is expressed in the opposition of Las Casas and
Cortès, the former being a colonialist out of love, the latter using the
language of love in search of private gain. The Conquest of America.
The Question of the Other (trans. Richard Howard, New York,
HarperCollins, 1984), pp. 174–176. Moral universalism as a
psychological trap imposing excessive demands on its proponents –
and thus eventually leading to brutalization and cynicism – is a
consistent theme in critiques of Kant. For a controversial argument
about morality as “the last refuge of Eurocentrism,” cf. Hans Magnus
Enzensberger, Civil War (London, Granta, 1994), pp. 59, 61. This is
not too far from Schmitt’s arguments against universalism. The
defense is taken up by Jürgen Habermas: if moralization is mediated
through a legal order, no brutalization will occur. This is, as
Habermas readily admits, a liberal response that assumes the
presence of “an authority that judges impartially and fulfills the
conditions of neutral criminal punishment.” Jürgen Habermas, “Kant’s
Idea of Perpetual Peace, with the Benefit of Two Hundred Years’
Hindsight,” in James Bohman and Matthias Lutz-Bachmann (eds.),
Perpetual Peace. Essays in Kant’s Cosmopolitan Ideal (Cambridge,
Mass., MIT Press, 1997), p. 147. But this seems to assume what was
to be proved, namely the existence of a determining positive law or
procedure that could mediate between moral beliefs and public
enforcement. But if the critiques of legal formality are right, then this
presumption cannot be upheld. Habermas, too, accepts that a
“deception”
Only that individual can rise above hypocrisy or cynicism who can
accept the tragedy of life as struggle between incompatible but
equally valid (because equally arbitrary) preferences.
493
A culture of formalism?
494
And there may be a time for revolution and the throwing off of valid
law (and the profession that sustains it) altogether. But none of this
detracts from the need to know about valid law – indeed is premised
upon our ability to know it. And that need cannot be satisfied by
seeking to answer the causal or the moral question. On the contrary,
these latter questions can be meaningfully asked only once we share
an image of law as something that is – for want of a better word –
“valid.” The absence of this image is a product of the Weimar
heritage in American international relations theory.
“in fact” a question about what works, or what is good) and the
profession that was tasked to answer it. Yet we know, of course,
that questions of valid law do not admit of a single right answer.
Even if there may be agreement on a form, that often vanishes
when we seek to establish its meaning: States may undoubtedly not
cause harm to each other. But when asked what is “harm”? we are
led to interminable interpretative arguments, juxtapositions of rules
with exceptions, principles with counter-principles. All this does little
to facilitate sociological analyses about effectiveness, implementation
and compliance. But that is not the lawyer’s problem – unless the
lawyer has internalized the self-image of the political decision-
maker’s little helper.
495
294 Cf. Schmitt, Gesetz und Urteil, pp. 108–119; Hans Kelsen,
Introduction to Problems of Legal Theory. A Translation of the First
Edition of the Reine Rechtslehre or Pure Theory of Law (trans.
Professor Thomas held that “under basic legal theory . . . a legal rule
can never be explained in terms of itself without reference to its
purpose.”
497
case in the world was thrown out of court because his lawyers had
forgotten to put in the right words of art.’ I suggest that we cannot
leave the rights of peoples, the safety of nations, to that kind of
technical-ity.”298 In other words, as if in an afterthought, perhaps as
an intuitive reflection of the awkwardness of the more formal – yet
completely deformalized – reasoning, the proponents of the
intervention sought to discard the relevance of the legal arguments
altogether. Not without impatience, Berle took the floor, making it
clear that the legal debate was somehow altogether beside the
point: “We here deal seriously with international affairs, where life
and death are at stake and not with interminable Byzantine
legalistics without point or outcome.”299 Later on he added the
rhetorical question, reminiscent of what Schmitt and Morgenthau
had written: “in international crises, do you want action, or do you
want merely words? We can have all manner of delay and debate.
We can have all kinds of reference from this body to that body, to
the Security Council, to the Powers having veto and back again. Is
that international law or international mockery?”300
“We all know that many legal situations are open and subject to
different interpretations, but law is ultimately a matter of black and
white, or we should have no business to sit here and profess to be
lawyers . . . I submit we must find an answer in terms of right and
wrong.”301 To the argument made by Mr Berle to think in terms of
action, not words, Friedmann responded: “I think that as a legal
argument this is perilous, because whether we like it or not, law is
based on words, words formulated in statutes, in treaties, in
conventions, in customary law.”302
498
499
I suggest that the opposition between Thomas and Berle on the one
hand, and Friedmann on the other, was not about “deformalized
standards” and “formal rules,” but about two cultures: the culture of
dynamism and what could be called a culture of formalism. Even if
formalism may no longer be open as a jurisprudential doctrine of the
black and white of legal validity (a position perhaps never
represented by anyone), nothing has undermined formalism as a
culture of resistance to power, a social practice of accountability,
openness, and equality whose status cannot be reduced to the
political positions of any one of the parties whose claims are treated
within it. As such, it makes a claim for universality that may be able
to resist the pull towards imperialism. To be sure, we often think of
formalism in terms of Kantian ideas about a (universal) reason – and
in so doing fall into the trap of generalizing a European
particularism: this is the stuff of the civilizing mission. The important
task is to avoid that kind of imperialism while at the same time
continuing the search for something beyond particular interests and
identity politics, or the irreducibility of difference. This is what the
culture of formalism hopes to achieve, and what was at issue in the
debate in New York on May 2, 1966.
victory but it has no claim as against their material views and may
be discarded as soon as victory by other means has been assured.
Something like that was part of the political faith of the men of 1873
I do not think so. There is room for a culture of formalism even after
the critique of rules has done its work. It is precisely because the
critique is correct that formalism cannot be permanently associated
with any of the substantive outcomes it may have coexisted with. Of
course, formalism may occasionally have supported good,
occasionally evil policies. It cannot replace political commitment or
responsibility. Formalists may sometimes have claimed that their
policies were “good” or “legitimate” because they were produced or
supported by formalism. In such cases they made a monster of it.
Such defenders ignore the critique of rules, and the fact that they
could have acted otherwise, too. To assess the culture of formalism
by reference to its substantive alignments is, as Kelsen well knew, to
mix up categories that should be held distinct. A bad policy is (and
should be criticized as) bad as policy and not because of whether or
not it was supported by impeccable legal arguments. The
emancipatory core, and the universalism of the culture of formalism,
503
351–361.
504
20–35, 48–51.
505
506
507
508
509
Epilogue
The father had to quit his welfare activities, partly because they
seemed to have no effect on his clients who were either joining
extremist causes or sinking deeper into apathy, partly because they
threatened his own livelihood. In an increasingly difficult economic
situation, he retired a poor man. The sons loved their father dearly
but reacted in opposite ways to his misfortune. One promised him
that he would bring the father’s project to a conclusion. The good
son shared the father’s ideals and would teach himself to avoid his
mistakes so that he could one day come home with proof that the
father had been right all along. Then they would sit down and
everything would be well, as it had been. The 510
Epilogue
rebel son loved his father equally. But because it broke his heart to
think how unjustly the world had treated his father, he reacted by
rejection.
Both sons had successful, even very successful careers, and many
people admired them and tried to learn from them although what
they taught were the exact opposites. But it often seemed that they
were followed less because of the depth of their teaching than their
ability to give powerful expression to something that many people
felt intuitively right though somehow always only partially
convincing. As they were saying the opposite things, well, then
perhaps it was not so tragic that the listeners were believing those
incompatible things as well. In the end, it was not what the two
said, but the strength of their commitment that mattered most to
their acolytes: how few people nowadays really say that in the end
all that matters is either love and charity or the lust for power!
“Now we of course know that it is both love and power because the
world is a dreadfully complex place – but isn’t it nice to know that
there are some who still commit their lives to a religion of love or a
religion of power as if there still existed clear alternatives to choose
from?”
At that time, the profession did not yet feel the implications of this
fact. Many of the last representatives of international law’s heroic
period left the scene (Kaufmann retired in 1958, Alvarez and
Lauterpacht died in 1960, Scelle in 1961, Morgenthau had already
quit writing about international law in 1940) but their presence was
still concretely felt.
512
Epilogue
reignty did not do away with conflict in the Third World, though it
may have localized much of it as civil war. The end of the Cold War
did bring about a significant expansion of the electoral process. Yet,
today’s democratic melancholy suggests that progressive
transformation requires more than the export of a determined set of
public institutions – but just what this might require and what role
international law might play in the future remains obscure. Whatever
globalization may mean, it has certainly not strengthened
international public policy. Nothing may have undermined the need
for a middle ground between the Empire and the tribe, capitalism
and identity politics. But whether it is possible to articulate and
uphold such a space, without repeating the tired antics of statehood,
the Rule of Law, and a State-centered international system remains
an open question.
Like Henri Rolin, they would call forth a change of vocabulary in this
respect, but at the same time reaffirm their faith in the public law
institutions that provided the context of their professional activity. It
is much less clear whether such faith can be sustained today. The
acceptance by the developed States of a legal obligation to eradicate
poverty in the Third World is no longer seriously expected. Indeed,
the very idea that economic injustice might be usefully dealt with by
States, and public law, may now seem altogether old-fashioned, and
politically ambivalent.
From the outside, little may have changed between 1960 and 2000.
Choosing international law at law school may still seem more than a
513
514
Epilogue
but it also implies an imperial logic of identity: I will accept you, but
only on the condition that I may think of you as I think of myself.
But recognition of particularity may be an act of condescension, and
at worst a prelude for rejection. Between the arrogance of
universality and the indifference of particularity, what else is there
apart from the civilized manners of gentle spirits?
Second Avenues, around 45th and 50th street, New York, and
compelled to negotiate with other tribes in a terrain that remains a
no-man’s land.
But precisely at this moment it has lost the ability to articulate its
politics: when everything is politics, Schmitt wrote, nothing is.
Without the ability to articulate political visions and critiques,
international law becomes pragmatism all the way down, an all-
encompassing internaliza-tion, symbol, and reaffirmation of power.
But maybe the time of synthesis is not yet here. Maybe it is now a
time to listen, and to learn. And in the process one could do worse
than remember that however one imagines what one is doing, and
how that relates to other people’s being, history has put the
international lawyer in a tradition that has thought of itself as the
“organ of the legal conscience of the civilized world.” I still think
international law cannot be reconceived all the time, and that doing
it is at least as important as thinking about doing it. But I agree that
there must be a standpoint for critique that is not just an
idiosyncratic “decision” by the occasional Weberian jurist but can be
articulated by reference to the ideal of universal emancipation,
peace, and social progress. It is not enough to isolate these as
“regulative ideals” – an all-too-convenient justification for
complacency. International law’s energy and hope lies in its ability to
516
Epilogue
517
Bibliography
Abbott, Kenneth and Duncan Snidal, “Why States Act through Formal
International Organizations” (1998), 42 Journal of Conflict
Resolution, pp. 3–32
518
Bibliography
Anstey, Roger, King Leopold’s Legacy: The Congo under Belgian Rule
1908–1960
Les juristes face à la société du XIXe siècle à nos jours (Paris, PUF,
1975) Arnold, Matthew, “Culture and Anarchy,” in Culture and
Anarchy and Other Writings, Stefan Collini (ed.) (Cambridge
University Press, 1993 [1859]), pp. 53–211
519
Bibliography
97–129
520
Bibliography
“Der Staat ist der Mann,” in Gesammelte kleine Schriften, I, pp. 260–
286
521
Bibliography
Brinkley, Douglas and Clifford Hackett (eds.), Jean Monnet: The Path
to European Unity (London, Macmillan, 1991)
Die Systematik des Völkerrechts von Hugo Grotius bis auf die
Gegenwart (Dorpat, Karow, 1858)
Carr, E. H., The Romantic Exiles (Serif, London, 1998 [1933]) The
Twenty-Years’ Crisis 1919–1939 (2nd edn., London, Macmillan, 1981
[1946])
522
Bibliography
Clark, Grenville and Louis Sohn, World Peace Through World Law
(2nd edn., Cambridge, Mass., Harvard University Press, 1960)
Craig, Gordon A., “The British Foreign Office from Grey to Austen
Chamberlain,” in Craig and Gilbert, The Diplomats 1919–1939, pp.
15–48
523
Bibliography
Davidson, Basil, The Black Man’s Burden. Africa and the Curse of the
Nation-State (New York, Times, 1992)
Delpech, Joseph and Antoine Marcaggi, “Le transfert à la Belgique
de l’Etat indépendent du Congo” (1911), XVIII Revue générale de
droit international public, pp. 105–163
859–883
17–42
Diggelmann, Oliver, “Anfänge der Völkerrechtssoziologie. Die
Völkerrechtskonzeptionen von Max Huber und Georges Scelle im
Vergleich,” unpublished PhD. thesis (Zurich, 1998, on file with
author) Diggins, John Patrick, Max Weber. Politics and the Spirit of
Tragedy (New York, Basic Books, 1996)
Diner, Dan and Michael Stolleis (eds.), Hans Kelsen and Karl Schmitt.
A Juxtaposition (Gerlingen, Bleicher, 1999)
Bibliography
(ed.), Recrafting the Rule of Law: The Limits of the Legal Order
(Oxford, Hart, 1999) Eagleton, Terry, The Idea of Culture (Oxford,
Blackwell, 2000) Eksteins, Modris, Rites of Spring. The Great War
and the Birth of the Modern Age (New York, etc., Anchor, 1989)
349–383
525
Bibliography
437–476
526
Bibliography
527
Bibliography
528
Bibliography
Harrelson, Max, Fires all around the Horizon. The UN’s Uphill Battle
to Preserve the Peace (New York, Praeger, 1989)
Hartigan, Richard Shelly, Lieber’s Code and the Law of War (Chicago,
Precedent, 1983)
Bibliography
Henkin, Louis, How Nations Behave. Law and Foreign Policy (2nd
edn., New Haven, Columbia University Press, 1979)
Herf, Jeffrey, Reactionary Modernism. Technology, Culture, and
Politics in Weimar and the Third Reich (Cambridge University Press,
1984) Hertslet, Edward, The Map of Africa by Treaty (3rd edn., 3
vols., London, HMSO, 1909)
149–177
Hold-Ferneck,
Alexander,
50–82
II–IV], 1885)
530
Bibliography
[1910])
531
Bibliography
542–558
108–123
Bibliography
Das Wesen des Völkerrechts und die Clausula rebus sic stantibus
(Tübingen, Mohr, 1911)
272–284
233–329
841–988
533
Bibliography
197–213
412–449
Bibliography
the Field of International Law (New York, United Nations, 1999), pp.
495–523
535
Bibliography
Lasson, Adolf, Das Culturideal und der Krieg (Berlin, Hertz, 1868)
Princip und Zukunft des Völkerrechts (Berlin, Hertz, 1871) Lasson,
Georg, “Adolf Lasson” (1918–1919), XII Archiv für Rechts und
Wirtschaftsphilosophie, pp. 1–10
221–240
229–230
536
Bibliography
137–172
“The Covenant as the Higher Law” (1936), XVII British Year Book of
International Law, pp. 54–65, Collected Papers, 4, pp. 326–336
393–446
145–158
“The Law of Nations and the Punishment of War Crimes” (1944), XXI
British Year Book of International Law, pp. 58–95
“Memorandum on the Draft of the Peace Act” (LA, copy on file with
author)
Bibliography
135–168
67–91
251–278
538
Bibliography
242–244
53–100
539
Bibliography
333–359
540
Bibliography
Lukes, Steven, Emile Durkheim. His Life and Work. A Historical and
Critical Study (Stanford University Press, 1973)
“Literature and
Bibliography
371–385
Neumann (New York and London, Hafner & Collier, 1949 [1748]) 542
Bibliography
63–68
A New Foreign Policy for the United States (New York, Washington,
and London, Praeger, 1969)
Politics among Nations. The Struggle for Power and Peace (New
York, Knopf, 1948)
“Der Selbstmord mit guten Gewissen. Zur Kritik des pazifismus und
der neuen deutschen Kriegsphilosophie” (Morgenthau Archive,
Library of Congress, HJM-B-96, copy on file with author)
“Über die Herkunft des politischen aus dem Wesen des Menschen”
543
Bibliography
Mutua, Makau Wa, “Why Redraw the Map of Africa? A Moral and
Legal Inquiry” (1995), 16 Michigan Journal of International Law, pp.
1113–1176
544
Bibliography
105–127
5–29, 176–192
545
Bibliography
Piloty, Robert, “Staaten als Mächte und Mächte als Staaten. Ein Wort
zu den Grundlagen des Völkerrechts” (1914), VIII Zeitschrift für
Völkerrecht, pp.
360–365
546
Bibliography
Reeves, Jesse S., “The Origin of the Congo Free State, Considered
from the Standpoint of International Law” (1909), 3 American
Journal of International Law, pp. 99–118
3–24
547
Bibliography
Bibliography
126–135
116–142
“La guerre civile espagnole et le droit des gens,” Part 1 (1938), XLV
Revue générale de droit international public, pp. 265–301; part 2
(1938), XLV Revue générale de droit international public, pp. 649–
657, part 3 (1939), XLVI Revue générale de droit international
public, pp. 197–228
“Une instance en revision devant la cour de la Haye: L’Affaire de la
Orinoco Steamship Company” (1911), XVIII Revue générale de droit
international public, pp. 164–202
Bibliography
Schmitt, Carl, The Concept of the Political, trans. from Das Begriff
der Politischen [2nd edn. 1934] and with an introd. George Schwab,
with a new foreword by Tracy B. Strong (Cambridge, Mass. and
London, MIT Press, 1996) The Crisis of Parliamentary Democracy,
trans. from Die geistesgeschichtliche Lage des heutigen
Parlamentarismus [1923/1926] Ellen Kennedy (Cambridge, Mass.
295–302
35–70
550
Bibliography
Legalität und Legitimität (1932, 4th edn., Berlin, Duncker & Humblot,
1988) Nationalsozialismus und Völkerrecht (Berlin, Dünnhaupt,
1934)
“Der neue Nomos der Erde” (1955), in Staat, Grossraum, Nomos, pp.
513–518
“Der Status Quo und der Friede” (1925), in Positionen und Begriffe,
pp. 33–42
146–157
551
Bibliography
Das Werk vom Haag, Erster Band: Die Staatenverband der Haager
Konferenzen (Munich and Leipzig, Duncker & Humblot, 1912)
Bibliography
“The Real New World Order” (1997), 76 Foreign Affairs, pp. 183–197
Slaughter,
Anne-Marie,
Andrew S.
Tulumello,
1–37
Srubar,
Ilja (ed.),
Exil,
Wissenschaft,
Identität.
275–292
Bibliography
32–115
193–249
287–400
554
Bibliography
Tolonen, Juha, Stat och Rätt (Åbo Akademi, 1986) Torres Campos,
M., “L’Espagne en Afrique” (1892), XXIV Revue de droit international
et de législation comparée, pp. 441–475
Triepel, Heinrich, “Ferdinand von Martitz. Ein Bild seines Lebens und
seines Wirkens” (1922), 30 Zeitschrift für internationales Recht, pp.
155–172
Völkerrecht und Landesrecht (Leipzig, Hirschfield 1899) Truyol,
Antonio, “Doctrines contemporaines du droit des gens” (1950), LIV
Kaarlo,
555
Bibliography
195–251
Bibliography
Wood, Frances, No Dogs and Not Many Chinese. Treaty Port Life in
China 1843–1943
557
Bibliography
“‘Moderne
Legitimisten’”
(1908–9),
II
Archiv
für
Rechts
und
Index
Arnold, Matthew, 88
Aryan law, 59
(German), 218
145
sociales, 12
anarchism, 69
Annam, 117
annexation
Bechuanaland, 125
482–489, 508
Bentham, Jeremy, 14
in Alvarez, 304–305
559
Index
Bernard, Montague, 33
Bildung, 85
and nationalism, 64
as politician, 90–91
Clausewitz, Karl, 83
Cobden, Richard, 83
collectivism, 69
Belgian 168
Science, 59, 72
146
British South Africa Company (BSAC), 120
Italian 168
comparative law, 13
Burritt, Elihu, 40
concrete
Calvo, Carlos, 40
Canon law, 22
conflict of laws, 66
Congo
capitalism, 60
conquest, 137
560
Index
511
Kaufmann’s, 249–261
161–163, 286
Le Fur’s, 317–327
234–235, 237
Kelsen’s, 246–249
Dominican Republic
Lauterpacht’s, 406–412
Scelle’s, 331–336
empiricism, 299
295–296
culture
esprit d’internationalité, 13, 20, 27, 57, 69, 92, as character, 75–88
of formalism, 500–509
Eurocentrism, 9, 305
Institut), 132–133
European Coal and Steel Community
cynicism, 491–492
561
Index
evolutionism, 74–76, 99, 100, 101–110, 142, 308
195
Lauterpacht’s, 376–379
German East Africa Company ( Deutsche
Le Fur’s, 324–327
Schücking’s, 216–222
208–213
500–509
435, 480
392
84, 182–183
freedom
480, 497–501
405, 411
fundamental
336–338
Hinterland, 151
379
562
Index
Hughes, Thomas, 76
332, 338
371–372, 513–516
262–263
interpretation
257–260
385–387, 400–401
(IBEAC), 119
Anglo-American, 238
German, 207–208
407
438
410
in Kelsen, 244
in Lauterpacht, 357
in Le Fur, 324–325
317, 329
511
233
563
Index
31, 92
on colonialism, 359–360
on neutrality, 379–381
on recognition, 382–388
Katchenowski, D. I., 40
361–369
156, 170
316–317
426
legal system
401–404
internationaux, 453–455
156–162
240
Belgian, 16, 90
Lieber, Francis, 39, 42, 49, 59, 67, 68, 69, 77,
87, 96
231
as practitioner, 399–401
Lithuania, 328–329
as Zionist, 370–372
in Nuremberg, 388–390
459
564
Index
437–440
482, 487–488
100
Manchuria,
378–379
170
native
materialism, 37,
citizenship, 128
sovereignty, 113–114
476–477
Nazism, 261–262
neo-colonialism, 175
471, 419
499–500
489, 493
465–468
565
Index
Oppenheim, Lassa, 8, 92
organic
512
theory, 31–32, 43, 44, 45, 46, 49, 50, 63, 91,
497
particularism, 504–509
Pufendorff, Samuel, 73
322–323
275, 286
Phillimore, Robert, 34
489–490
349
as “functionalist,” 282–284
legal, 475–476
political
479
reasonableness, 402–403
452–455, 468
rebus sic stantibus, 363, 368, 442 ( see also disputes, 367–368,
440–445
fundamental change)
Rechtsstaat, 20, 32, 191, 196, 197, 198–208, Political Theology. Four
Concepts on the Concept of 247, 249, 268, 502
Lauterpacht on 384–386
Politics among Nations. The Struggle for Power and Lorimer’s theory
of, 70–71
for Peace, 437
393–394, 407
reform
566
Index
453–454
288–291, 346
on humanitarianism, 434–436
on Lauterpacht, 424–426
278–279, 362
306, 450
160, 223
science
447, 476
scientism, 468
328, 334
Royer-Collard, Pierre Paul, 31
208, 321
Sibert, M, 350
Sidgwick, Henry, 74
slave trade, 94
Smith, Adam, 60
471, 511
334–335
in Scelle, 331–338
on democracy, 429
567
Index
sovereignty ( cont. )
338–342
universal
spying, 85–86
322
state theory
131
244–245, 252–253
Verne, Jules, 41
219–221, 236
structuralism, 5, 6
445
Vinogradoff, Paul, 75
36–38
virtue, 80
Suarez, Francisco, 78
Volksgeist, 32, 43
“subjectivism,” 320
296
Walker, T. A., 155
tradition
in Le Fur 317–327
331–332
143, 280
568
Index
372–373
Zanzibar, 125
Cover
Half-title
Series-title
Title
Copyright
Dedication
Contents
Preface
Abbreviations
Introduction
I
II
III
1 “The legal conscience of the civilized world ”
A manifesto
An old-fashioned tradition
A transitional critic: Kaltenborn von Stachau
An amateur science
A time of danger
A meeting in Ghent, 1873
A romantic profession: Bluntschli
A social conception of law
Method: enlightened inwardness
Towards a culture of human rights: Fiore
Advancing the liberal project
Limits of liberalism
Cultural consciousness
Culture as character
The elusive sensibility
2 Sovereignty: a gift of civilization – international lawyers and
imperialism, 1870–1914
Ambivalent attitudes
Informal empire 1815–1870: hic sunt leones
The lawyers 1815–1870
The demise of informal empire in Africa
The Berlin Conference 1884–1885
The myth of civilization: a logic of exclusion–inclusion
Looking for a standard
Between universality and relativism: colonial treaties
The myth of sovereignty: a beneficent empire
The limits of sovereignty: civilization betrayed
Occupation is nothing – Fashoda
Sovereignty as terror – the Congo
From sovereignty to internationalization
3 International law as philosophy: Germany 1871–1933
1871: law as the science of the legal form
From form to substance: the doctrine of the rational will
Between the dangerous and the illusory State
Rechtsstaat – domestic and international: Georg Jellinek
Rationalism and politics: a dificulty
Drawing lines in the profession
Public law and the Hague Treaties
A pacifist profession? Kohler, Schücking, and the First World
War
The internationalists: between sociology and formalism
1914
Getting organized
Beyond Versailles: the end of German internationalism
Ways of escape – I: Hans Kelsen and liberalism as science
Ways of escape – II: Erich Kaufmann and the conservative
reaction
Break: the end of philosophy
4 International law as sociology: French “solidarism” 1871–1950
Internationalism as nationalism: the idea of France
From civilists to functionalists 1874–1918: Renault to Pillet
Solidarity at the Hague: Léon Bourgeois
The theory of solidarism
The war of 1914–1918 and solidarism
Scientific solidarism: Durkheim and Duguit
International solidarity ...almost: Alvarez and Politis
Meanwhile in Paris ...
L’affaire Scelle
Solidarity with tradition: Louis Le Fur
The solidarity of fact: Georges Scelle
Which solidarity? Whose tradition? The Spanish Civil War
The European Union
The twilight of the idea of France: between politics and
pragmatism
5 Lauterpacht: the Victorian tradition in international law
Tradition in modernity
A complete system
Between Zionism and assimilation
A political commitment
Nuremberg and human rights
The birth of pragmatism
A Grotian tradition?
Coda
6 Out of Europe: Carl Schmitt, Hans Morgenthau, and the turn
to “international relations”
A 1950 retrospective
Vision of a new order
The ambivalences of a Katechon (restrainer)
A discipline transforms itself: Schmitt on Scelle and
Lauterpacht
Against liberal neutralizations and depoliticizations
“Whoever invokes humanity wants to cheat”
Schmitt and Morgenthau: the primacy of the political
Another retrospective
International law and politics: an asymmetrical relationship
The formation of a German thinker: between law and desire
The guardian of international law: sanctions
Schmitt and Morgenthau: the pedigree of anti-formalism
From international law to international relations
The heritage of realism in American international law
Empire’s law
A culture of formalism?
Epilogue
Bibliography
Index
Table of Contents
Cover
Half-title
Series-title
Title
Copyright
Dedication
Contents
Preface
Abbreviations
Introduction
I
II
III
1 “The legal conscience of the civilized world ”
A manifesto
An old-fashioned tradition
A transitional critic: Kaltenborn von Stachau
An amateur science
A time of danger
A meeting in Ghent, 1873
A romantic profession: Bluntschli
A social conception of law
Method: enlightened inwardness
Towards a culture of human rights: Fiore
Advancing the liberal project
Limits of liberalism
Cultural consciousness
Culture as character
The elusive sensibility
2 Sovereignty: a gift of civilization – international lawyers and
imperialism, 1870–1914
Ambivalent attitudes
Informal empire 1815–1870: hic sunt leones
The lawyers 1815–1870
The demise of informal empire in Africa
The Berlin Conference 1884–1885
The myth of civilization: a logic of exclusion–inclusion
Looking for a standard
Between universality and relativism: colonial treaties
The myth of sovereignty: a beneficent empire
The limits of sovereignty: civilization betrayed
Occupation is nothing – Fashoda
Sovereignty as terror – the Congo
From sovereignty to internationalization
3 International law as philosophy: Germany 1871–1933
1871: law as the science of the legal form
From form to substance: the doctrine of the rational will
Between the dangerous and the illusory State
Rechtsstaat – domestic and international: Georg Jellinek
Rationalism and politics: a dificulty
Drawing lines in the profession
Public law and the Hague Treaties
A pacifist profession? Kohler, Schücking, and the First World War
The internationalists: between sociology and formalism
1914
Getting organized
Beyond Versailles: the end of German internationalism
Ways of escape – I: Hans Kelsen and liberalism as science
Ways of escape – II: Erich Kaufmann and the conservative
reaction
Break: the end of philosophy
4 International law as sociology: French “solidarism” 1871–1950
Internationalism as nationalism: the idea of France
From civilists to functionalists 1874–1918: Renault to Pillet
Solidarity at the Hague: Léon Bourgeois
The theory of solidarism
The war of 1914–1918 and solidarism
Scientific solidarism: Durkheim and Duguit
International solidarity ...almost: Alvarez and Politis
Meanwhile in Paris ...
L’affaire Scelle
Solidarity with tradition: Louis Le Fur
The solidarity of fact: Georges Scelle
Which solidarity? Whose tradition? The Spanish Civil War
The European Union
The twilight of the idea of France: between politics and
pragmatism
5 Lauterpacht: the Victorian tradition in international law
Tradition in modernity
A complete system
Between Zionism and assimilation
A political commitment
Nuremberg and human rights
The birth of pragmatism
A Grotian tradition?
Coda
6 Out of Europe: Carl Schmitt, Hans Morgenthau, and the turn to
“international relations”
A 1950 retrospective
Vision of a new order
The ambivalences of a Katechon (restrainer)
A discipline transforms itself: Schmitt on Scelle and Lauterpacht
Against liberal neutralizations and depoliticizations
“Whoever invokes humanity wants to cheat”
Schmitt and Morgenthau: the primacy of the political
Another retrospective
International law and politics: an asymmetrical relationship
The formation of a German thinker: between law and desire
The guardian of international law: sanctions
Schmitt and Morgenthau: the pedigree of anti-formalism
From international law to international relations
The heritage of realism in American international law
Empire’s law
A culture of formalism?
Epilogue
Bibliography
Index