Roger Scruton Hunting
Roger Scruton Hunting
Roger Scruton Hunting
Rights: All rights reserved. © The White Horse Press 1997. Except
for the quotation of short passages for the purpose of
criticism or review, no part of this article may be reprinted or
reproduced or utilised in any form or by any electronic,
mechanical or other means, including photocopying or
recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system,
without permission from the publishers. For further
information please see http://www.whpress.co.uk.
From a View to a Death: Culture, Nature and the
Huntsman’s Art
ROGER SCRUTON
ABSTRACT: The division between the natural and the artificial is itself
artificial. But we continue to yearn for a ‘homecoming’ to our natural state –
which means, to the identity with our environment which was the condition of
the hunter-gatherer. Totemism is the thought-process whereby the prey can be
simultaneously consecrated as a species, and pursued to the death as an
individual. This thought-process has an evident ecological function. The moral-
ity of hunting resides in the maintenance of this dual attitude. An anthropological
explanation is offered of the perceived rituals of hunting, and of ‘guiltless
killing’.
control. The experience of the sublime vanished at the moment when Burke and
Kant defined it: their descriptions were a kind of valediction, inspired by the
premonition of a world entirely subject to human mismanagement.
None of that alters the fact that the contrast between the natural and the
artificial is an immovable part of our worldview, and one of the cultural values
to which we cling. We need this contrast, because we need to see our actions in
terms of it. We need to distinguish those impulses which belong to mother nature,
from those which involve bids for freedom. And we need to relate to other
creatures for whom there is no such contrast: creatures whose behaviour stems
from nature alone. It matters to us that we should be in constant relation to
animals – and wild animals especially. For we seek an image of innocence, of the
world before our own depredations, the world without man, into which man
comes as an intruder. The burden of self-consciousness is lightened by this
image: it shows us that we walk on firm ground, where the burden may from time
to time be set down, and upon which we may rest from our guilt. All this is
beautifully captured in the opening pages of Genesis, and the vision of Paradise
– absurd though it may be from the Darwinian perspective – is the perfect symbol
of the natural world as it would be, had we been able to produce it unaided, and
without relying on the raw material of evolution.
The desire for a natural order is perhaps unknown to those who are truly part
of it. But it is an immovable given in the lives of all civilised beings, and even
if it cannot be satisfied, it will exert its power over our thinking, and make itself
known both in the life of the mind and in the life of the body. It burst upon us in
the writings of Rousseau, and his egregiously sentimental vision of the state of
nature has exerted its charm over many subsequent writers. But it appeared in a
more moderate and intriguing form in the writings of the German romantics,
three of whom – Schelling, Hegel and Hölderlin – helped to forge the picture of
our condition which has since proved most persuasive, and to which I pay tribute
in this article.
According to this picture, human history shares the structure of human
consciousness, and the individual life is a microcosm of the species, which is in
turn, for Hegel, a microcosm of the universal Geist. The human soul and human
society are both founded in a condition of innocence or ‘immediacy’, in which
they are at one with the world and with themselves. And each grows away from
this one-ness through a process of sundering and alienation, as it comes to
recognise the otherness by which it is surrounded and upon which it depends.
Finally each attains its redemption, as it is restored to the wholeness from which
it began, but at a higher plane – the plane of understanding. Just as the individual
self is realised by transcending its self-alienation and becoming fully and
completely known to itself, so is society fulfilled, when the primitive unity with
others is rediscovered, but in the form of a self-conscious and law-guided order.
The picture is dressed up by Hegel in the clothes of the dialectic; it is
transformed by Feuerbach into a kind of negative theology, and by Marx into a
473
FROM A VIEW TO A DEATH
theory of history. It survives into our century in many forms, and has some of the
Uralte resonance that it also tries to explain. You will find it in works as diverse
as Proust’s Remembrance of Things Past and T.S. Eliot’s Four Quartets. You
will find it buried in the obscure prose of Husserl and Heidegger, distorted in the
writings of the psychoanalysts or lifted into a brash light by Scheler. It would not
be an exaggeration to say that it is now the most important image of our condition,
and has a peculiar power to endure precisely in those people who have rejected
the religious vision – the vision of Paradise, the Fall and Redemption – from
which it originally sprang. Wherever we look in the modern world, we find this
image actively colonising people’s plans and projects. Almost everything that is
believed in, almost everything for which a real sacrifice is made, has the
character of a Heimkehr – a return from alienation, destruction and despair, to an
image of home. But not home in its innocence. Rather home transfigured,
become conscious of itself, and emancipated from the taint of bondage.
It is this image which dominates the thinking of the environmental move-
ments of our time, and also of the campaigners for animal rights who are so often
in conflict with them. Both are haunted by the idea of a primitive unity between
man and nature, in which other species have an equal weight to our own. Both
are appalled by the accelerating presumption which has alienated man from
nature, and set him at odds with the order upon which he nevertheless depends.
And both look forward to a restored unity with the natural world – a unity
achieved not by innocence but by understanding, and by the self-knowledge and
self-discipline which come from accepting our limitations.
Myths are necessary to human life, and part of the price that we pay for
consciousness. Moreover, even if they give a distorted view of history, they
frequently give insight into the human psyche. Deep down in all of us there are
psychic residues, inherited from our hunter-gatherer ancestors, which speak to
us of another and simpler world. It was a world in which we were at home, since
we were adapted to it by evolution. Our instincts, our spontaneous perceptions,
movements and social feelings, bear witness to that distant and
never-to-be-recovered condition in which the separation of man from nature had
yet to come about. And the strain of modern life would be unbearable, if we did
not rehearse the spontaneous psychic movements that were implanted in us by
the species, and which are as important for our proper functioning as it is
important to a dog that it should bark from time to time, or to a chicken that it
should lay an egg. This is the truth, I believe, in those myths of Paradise and Fall,
which have brought so much consolation to our species, and also – in their
secularised versions – so much needless destruction. Planted in us, too deep for
memory, and beneath the layers of civilisation, are the instincts of the hunter-
gatherer, who differs from his civilised descendants not only in making no
distinction between the natural and the artificial order, but also in relating to his
own and other species in a herd-like way. The hunter-gatherer is acutely aware
of the distinction between men and women; he quickly unites with his fellows
474
ROGER SCRUTON
remains one of the most penetrating works on the art of hunting with hounds.
Nevertheless, it is the beginning of a new relation to the natural world: the
relation which stems from our role as a dominant species, able to conscript other
species to our purposes, and to exploit their instincts.
The hunter now works side by side with animals whom he treats as
individuals, in hot pursuit of the prey whose individuality is lent to it only
temporarily, as it were, and because it has been singled out by the chase. The
horse beneath him is Sam or George, whose habits he knows, and with whom he
communicates directly; the hounds to whom he calls are Saviour, Sanguine and
Sawdust, and he addresses them by name, aware of their individual virtues and
vices, for which he makes constant allowance. But the fox – Charlie, the generic
being who appears equally in Aesop and Surtees, in La Fontaine and Stravinsky
– is merely incarnate in the hunted animal and will survive its death. For the brief
moment of the chase, Charlie is an individual, to be understood through the
beliefs and strategies, the vulpine strengths and weaknesses that distinguish this
particular instance. Once killed, however, Charlie returns to his archetypal
condition, reassuming his nature as The Fox, whom the huntsman knows and
loves, and whose eternal recurrence is his deep desire.
Thus it is that the huntsman who has shot the cunning little vixen in Janácek’s
beautiful opera also rejoices to rediscover her in her daughter. And, as the music
makes lucidly apparent, this rediscovery is not of the individual vixen, but of the
universal Vixen, and of the natural context which provides her life.
Although this return to a previous relation with the natural world is now rare,
it helps us to understand some of the longings and frustrations of those who seek
for it. In the civilised world, where food is not hunted or gathered but produced,
hunting and gathering become forms of recreation. But they awaken the old
instincts and desires, the old pieties and the old relations with our own and other
species. If your purpose in angling is to catch a fish, then how simply this could
be achieved with an electrode, which stuns the population of the river bank, and
brings it, afloat and unconscious, to the surface. But what angler would look on
this method with other than disgust? To catch fish in this way is to cross the
barrier between the natural and the artificial – it is to conquer another portion of
nature for the world of machinery. Yet the point of angling was to return, in
however well-protected a guise, to the natural world, the world unblemished by
our footsteps. And that is the experience so lyrically evoked by the great tradition
of writers, from Isaac Walton to Richard Jefferies, who have celebrated the sport
as a therapy for the anxious soul.
More important, however, is the fact that industrial fishing, of the kind
deprecated by the angler, is an offence to the totem. It aims indiscriminately at
the collective, and instead of sacrificing the individual trout for the sake of the
universal Trout, throws the universal itself onto the river bank. Like trawling and
drift-netting, it constitutes a threat to the hunted species – and the threat, as we
476
ROGER SCRUTON
relate to each other in a special way, through the give and take of practical reason,
and its associated concepts of justice, duty and right. Human beings are actual
or potential members of a moral community, in which each member enjoys
sovereignty over his own affairs, so long as he accords an equal sovereignty to
others. The concepts of right and duty regulate such a community, and ensure that
disputes are settled in the first instance by negotiation and not by force. And with
all this comes an immense burden of guilt. Morality and self-consciousness set
us in judgement over ourselves, so that we see our actions and characters
constantly from outside, judged by ourselves as we are by others. (It is part of the
function of moral dialogue, and the concepts of duty, right and justice, to
generate this external point of view.) We become cut off from our instincts, and
even the spontaneous joy of fellowship is diminished by the screen of judgement
through which it first must pass.
Animals rescue us from this predicament. Their lack of self-consciousness
neutralises our own, and their mute unembarrasability makes it possible to pour
out on them the pent up store of fellow feeling, without fear of judgement or
reproach. At the same time, we are acutely aware of their moral incompetence.
Their affection is too easily won, and based on nothing. However much a man
may be loved by his dog, this love brings warmth and security, but no release
from guilt. It is a love that implies no moral approval, and which leaves the
character of its object unassessed and unendorsed. For many people in the
conditions of civilised life, the relation with a pet is the best that can be achieved,
by way of satisfying the sedimented needs of the hunter-gatherer. But it is a
relation that is essentially one-sided, with one party speaking and acting for both.
The master smiles into the eyes of his dog as into a mirror, and finds there no
independent confirmation of his doubts and certainties.
The hunter-gatherer faces and overcomes the guilt of his condition more
easily than we do. Although Freud’s explanation of totemism, as the re-enactment
of an Oedipal murder, cannot be accepted, implying as it does that hunter-
gatherers are caught in the emotional web of fin-de-siècle Vienna, it contains a
profound truth. The willed identity between the hunter and his tribe, and between
the tribe and the universal prey, affirms, for the hunter, his primal innocence. Just
as there is no guilt attached to killing when lion kills goat, so are we released from
guilt when acting from the imperatives of the species. At the same time,
considered as species, the prey is identical with the tribe. Hence this guiltless
killing is also a purging of guilt – of the guilt that attaches to the murder of one’s
kind. The prey becomes a sacrificial victim: the individual who pays with his life
for the continuity of the tribe, by attracting the accumulated aggression between
the hunters which is the price of their mutual dependence. This pattern of thought
becomes explicit in the Jewish ritual of the scapegoat – a ritual, however, which
treats the victim far more harshly than the prey is treated by the hunter. In the
prey, therefore, a collective soul resides and the hunter confronts as he kills the
478
ROGER SCRUTON
man; the claim to territory and the animals who live in it; and the therapy for guilt
involved in guiltless killing.
But is it guiltless? Hunting, shooting and to a lesser extent angling have been
repeatedly condemned as immoral: not immoral per se, since they may well be
necessary if people are to feed themselves. But immoral in circumstances like
ours, when hunting is a recreation rather than a means to food and clothing. The
arguments here are involved and various, and there is no short answer to them.
Nevertheless, it is not a sufficient justification for recreational hunting that it puts
us in touch with needed emotions, or that it maintains the boundaries which fence
off the ‘natural’ world. Even if it could be shown that hunting (in one or other of
its many forms) is the best that we over-civilised beings can hope for, by way of
a homecoming to our natural state, and the best proof against the tribal
aggressions which otherwise beset us, this would carry little weight in modern
times. It may or may not be significant that the first politician to ban hunting
(Adolf Hitler) also created a society remorselessly bent on hunting down the
‘enemy within’. But people believe that all such examples belong to the
irretrievable (and mercifully irretrievable) past. Many people are also sceptical
of the romantic Heimkehr. The best hope for our future, they believe, is to live
with our alienation, to cease to look for some simulacrum, however sublimated
and self-conscious, of the old tribal emotions and to look on the world as a vast
suburban garden, an artificial and third-rate paradise, which we must maintain
as kindly and responsibly as we can. This means taking the interests of all
creatures into account, and refraining from pursuits which cause needless
suffering, lest the spectacle of suffering should cease to trouble us. The
comparative toleration of modern people towards angling stems from the fact
that fish are so very different from us, in their appearance, habitat and behaviour,
that it is no sign of a hard heart to look on their sufferings unmoved. The hare,
the stag and the fox, by contrast, are near to us. Whatever the difference between
our thoughts and theirs, we share the circumstances of our pains, our terrors and
our death, and to inflict these things on such an animal is to act with a callous
disregard.
There is something right in that argument. But it also overlooks the crucial
fact from which I began this paper, and which is now at the back of all our minds,
including the minds of those opposed to hunting. The natural world can no longer
look after itself. We are guardians and keepers of the natural order, which owes
its character to us. We could turn our backs on it, and cease to interfere. But the
result would not be better, either for the animals who live in it, or for us, who
depend on the natural world for our sense of what we are. If deer were never
culled, Exmoor would contain nothing else, besides suburban houses, and the
highlands of Scotland would be treeless crags. If foxes were never killed, lambs,
ducks and chickens would be reared indoors, in conditions that no decent person
should tolerate. If angling ceased, our waterways would never be maintained,
481
FROM A VIEW TO A DEATH
and mink, coot and moorhen would drive all their rivals to extinction. In so far
as ‘bio-diversity’ is a wished-for part of our third-rate paradise, culling and
pest-control will remain incumbent on us. And it seems to me that the truly
callous way of doing these things, is the way that merely attacks the species – as
when poisoned bait is laid for rats and foxes, or electric shocks are used to free
some waterway of pike. Such practices involve a failure to achieve the ‘incarna-
tion’ of the species in the individual, and so to renew our respect for it. The true
graciousness of hunting occurs when the species is controlled through the
arduous pursuit of its individual members, and so impresses upon us its real and
eternal claim to our respect and sympathy. This does not mean that hunting can
be pursued in any way we choose. A rifle, in the hands of a well-trained stalker,
may be a permissible way to bring death to a stag; but it does not follow that the
very same stag might as well be killed by a grenade, a noose or a handgun. An
animal like the fox, which can be cleanly killed only in the open, and which is
never more quickly despatched than by a pack of hounds, requires great labour
and the cooperation of three species if he is to be hunted in this way. If he is to
be hunted at all, however, this is how it should be done.
The example is controversial, and those who believe in the rights of animals
will dismiss what I have said as quite irrelevant. On the other hand, I believe not
only that the concept of animal rights is based on a confusion, but that a true
understanding of the nature of moral judgement will find no conclusive argu-
ment against properly conducted hunting.2 Indeed, I incline to Plato’s view,
defended in The Laws,3 that hunting with hounds is the noblest form of hunting.
And this because it is the form in which our kindred nature with the animals is
most vividly present to our feelings. The pleasure that we feel in this kind of
hunting is borrowed from the animals who are really doing it – the hounds who
pursue, and the horses who excitedly follow them. The residual moral doubts are
ours, not theirs, and they must be answered by us – by ensuring that the fox or
stag has the best chance of saving himself, and the quickest death should he be
caught.
NOTES
1
S. Freud, Totem and Taboo, tr. J. Strachey, London 1950. There is another function
performed by totemism, which parallels the one to which I refer. By worshipping his prey,
the hunter also identifies with its spirit, learns to incarnate its spirit in himself, and so sees
the world as the prey sees it. In this way he learns to understand the motives and behaviour
of his quarry, and is able to track it more effectively. Totemism, on this view, is a kind of
inverse anthropomorphism, and has a similar function. The theory is elevated into a
functional explanation by Steve Mithen, in The Prehistory of the Mind, London 1996.
2
See Roger Scruton, Animal Rights and Wrongs, Demos 1996.
3
Book 7, concluding pages.