Susan Stebbing
Susan Stebbing
Susan Stebbing
Susan Stebbing
Susan Stebbing
innovative work in these and other areas helped move analytic
philosophy from its early phase to its middle period.
SUSAN STEBBING
Frederique Janssen-Lauret
University of Manchester
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009026925 Published online by Cambridge University Press
Shaftesbury Road, Cambridge CB2 8EA, United Kingdom
One Liberty Plaza, 20th Floor, New York, NY 10006, USA
477 Williamstown Road, Port Melbourne, VIC 3207, Australia
314–321, 3rd Floor, Plot 3, Splendor Forum, Jasola District Centre,
New Delhi – 110025, India
103 Penang Road, #05–06/07, Visioncrest Commercial, Singapore 238467
www.cambridge.org
Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9781009013031
DOI: 10.1017/9781009026925
© Frederique Janssen-Lauret 2022
This publication is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception
and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements,
no reproduction of any part may take place without the written
permission of Cambridge University Press & Assessment.
First published 2022
A catalogue record for this publication is available from the British Library.
ISBN 978-1-009-01303-1 Paperback
ISSN 2634-4645 (online)
ISSN 2634-4637 (print)
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009026925 Published online by Cambridge University Press
Cambridge University Press & Assessment has no responsibility for the persistence or
accuracy of
URLs for external or third-party internet websites referred to in this publication
and does not guarantee that any content on such websites is, or will remain,
accurate or appropriate.
Susan Stebbing
DOI: 10.1017/9781009026925
First published online: November 2022
Frederique Janssen-Lauret
University of Manchester
2 Logic 13
3 Philosophy of Science 32
4 Metaphysics 45
6 Conclusion 60
References 63
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009026925 Published online by Cambridge University Press
Susan Stebbing 1
Her books were favourably reviewed and her papers well-received. She
was chosen for prestigious roles in academia in the UK and abroad. She
held a visiting professorship at Columbia, delivered the British Acad-
emy’s annual lecture, and served as President of the Aristotelian Society.
Nevertheless, she faced obstacles which her male counterparts did not
have to contend with. She was turned down for a professorial chair at
Cambridge because she was a woman at a time when Cambridge did not
allow women to be members of the University. As a lecturer at a women’s
college, she had a high teaching load which was spread across most areas
of philosophy. Women’s colleges being underfunded and understaffed,
her teaching load did not lessen after her promotion to Professor. Hav-
ing been raised as a girl with a disability in the Victorian era, Stebbing
had not received the rigorous training in classics and the exact sciences
which her male counterparts took for granted. She had to embark on
a self-education project in physics and its philosophy in her twenties
and thirties. Had she had access to the educational resources in science,
mathematics, and classics open to her colleagues G. E. Moore, Bertrand
Russell, A. N. Whitehead, and Ludwig Wittgenstein, her contributions to
logic and philosophy of science might have been greater still.
Despite her impressive achievements, Stebbing has also received lit-
tle attention to date from historians of analytic philosophy. History of
analytic philosophy, as we will discover shortly (Section 1.1), has often
focussed exclusively on those men it unironically calls the ‘founding
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009026925 Published online by Cambridge University Press
beyond what this short publication can cover but concentrates on Steb-
bing’s life and on connections between her thought and contemporary
thinking about ordinary language. By contrast, I will concentrate on giv-
ing a thorough yet accessible overview of Stebbing’s positive, original
contributions, including her views on the philosophy of logic (Section 2),
her anti-idealist interpretation of the new Einsteinian physics (Section 3),
her solution to the paradox of analysis (Section 4), and her pioneering
work on critical thinking (Section 5). Although accessible, my overview
of Stebbing’s work is not in the style of a textbook or encyclopaedia
piece. I defend original readings of Stebbing, take stances on interpretive
issues, and provide support for the view that analytic philosophy should
be regarded, not as the tradition of the followers and followers’ followers
of three or four Great Men but as a broad and varied movement with a
variety of female and male ancestors, loosely unified by a focus on tak-
ing the methods and deliverances of the sciences as an inspiration for
philosophy.
phase, where (at least in the UK) it was dominated by logical atomism,
towards a middle period typified by more focus on ordinary language and
a more holist approach. To view her primarily as a Moorean is problem-
atic because it denies her credit for originality, but also because it appears
to fall prey to what I have called the Great Men narrative of analytic
philosophy (Janssen-Lauret, in press-b). According to this historiograph-
ical narrative, analytic philosophy is the work of three or four particular
men, their followers, and their followers’ followers. Soames writes, ‘ana-
lytic philosophy . . . is a certain historical tradition in which the early
work of G. E. Moore, Bertrand Russell, and Ludwig Wittgenstein set
the agenda for later philosophers’ (Soames, 2003: xiii) and Beaney
describes analytic philosophy as ‘the tradition that originated in the work
of Gottlob Frege (1848–1925), Bertrand Russell (1872–1970), G. E.
Moore (1873–1958), and Ludwig Wittgenstein (1889–1951) and devel-
oped and ramified into the complex movement (or set of interconnected
subtraditions) that we know today’ (Beaney, 2013: 9).
Soames and Beaney’s characterisations of analytic philosophy are
formulated the way they are for a reason: to sidestep known issues
with attempted definitions of ‘analytic philosophy’ which define it too
narrowly, whether geographically as ‘Anglo-American’ philosophy, the-
matically as philosophy focussed on the analysis of language, or as
‘critical’ rather than speculative philosophy (Katzav & Vaesen, 2017).
All of those candidate definitions leave out major figures in the history of
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009026925 Published online by Cambridge University Press
to their rightful place is to give up the hero narrative of the Great Men
and embrace the ‘movement’ narrative of early analytic philosophy.
What I take to be most distinctive about early analytic philosophy is
its quest to find a philosophy compatible with new developments in the
sciences, especially the natural sciences and pure mathematics. Most nar-
ratives of the emergence of analytic philosophy to date have focussed
more on early Russell and Moore’s opposition to idealism (e.g. Hyl-
ton, 1990; Candlish, 2007). But Frege, Russell, Whitehead, and other
early analytic philosophers were also driven by reflection on the math-
ematical revolution in rigour and general relativity. These results upset
traditional philosophical certainties about the infinite, parts and wholes –
for example, the intuition that no whole is the same size as any of
its proper parts – and the nature of space and time. Analytic philo-
sophers held that philosophy should accept these results as true, set out
to clarify and interpret them, and fit philosophical enquiry around them
(MacBride & Janssen-Lauret, 2015). For some lesser-known early or
proto-analytic philosophers, such as Welby, Stout, Ladd-Franklin, and
de Laguna, reflection on new findings in the emerging science of psych-
ology was also a major driving force. A further concern for many early
analytic philosophers was opposition to idealism, although later gener-
ations of analytic philosophers contained some idealists. Critical analysis
of linguistic meaning, reference, and truth became crucial items in the
analytic philosopher’s toolbox as she set out to investigate the logical
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009026925 Published online by Cambridge University Press
late Victorian and Edwardian culture did not classify all of mathemat-
ics as strongly masculine. Applied mathematics, used in the physical
sciences and engineering, fields associated with economic gain and the
public sphere, was highly male-coded. But those who didn’t wholly dis-
approve of women’s education often considered pure mathematics, such
as mathematical logic, algebra, and set theory, which did not draw on
worldly knowledge, suitable for a woman to study. For example, Grace
Chisholm’s mathematics lecturers advised her to leave the very applied
department in Cambridge to pursue her PhD in pure geometry in Ger-
many (Jones, 2000). Christine Ladd-Franklin was encouraged to give up
trying to persuade reluctant male physics professors to admit her to their
research laboratories and instead pursue pure mathematics, which she
could study at home (Janssen-Lauret, in press-a). Limited instruction in
10 Women in the History of Philosophy
the classics was another frequent obstacle for the early generations of
female academics. Educated parents immersed their sons in Greek and
Latin from early childhood but only rarely did the same for their daugh-
ters. Constance Jones recounted in her autobiography that the women of
her family learnt only enough Latin to teach their sons until the boys went
to school (Jones, 1922: 11). Even in the early 1940s, Mary Warnock and
her fellow female classics students found ‘what a struggle it was for girls
to keep their heads above water in Mods, an examination based on the
assumption that boys had been learning Latin and Greek almost as soon
as their education had started’ (Warnock, 2000: 39).
Towards the end of her history degree, Stebbing happened at random
upon Bradley’s Appearance and Reality while browsing in the library.
She was immediately gripped. Stebbing decided to stay at Girton for
another year to read for the Moral Sciences Tripos, as Cambridge called
its exams in philosophy. She studied philosophy with the logician W.
E. Johnson, who introduced her to Aristotelian logic. But Cambridge
did not allow women who passed their Tripos exams to graduate with
their degrees and would not begin to do so until 1948, after Stebbing’s
death. Stebbing accordingly moved to the University of London, which
did award degrees to women.
In London, she completed a master’s thesis on truth, pragmatism, and
the French voluntarism of Bergson, later published in the Girton series
by Cambridge University Press (Stebbing, 1914). After her move to Lon-
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009026925 Published online by Cambridge University Press
don in the early 1910s, Stebbing continued to teach for Girton on a casual
basis, as well as for Newnham, another Cambridge women’s college. She
also held visiting lectureships in London, at King’s College for Women,
and Homerton, a teacher training college. Stebbing regularly spoke at
the Aristotelian Society and published papers in its Proceedings. Several
of these earliest publications of hers were sympathetic to idealism. In
one meeting of the Society, Stebbing criticised Russell’s views on rela-
tions and, though also disinclined to follow Bradley all the way down the
road to monism, defended the idealist doctrine of concrete unity (Steb-
bing, 1916–17). Some twenty-five years later, Stebbing recounted that,
having presented her paper, she was confronted about the ‘muddles’ (a
favourite word of hers) inherent in her claims by a man she later dis-
covered to be G. E. Moore. Stebbing described feeling ‘alarmed’ at first
Susan Stebbing 11
Lodge, with her sister Helen and her friends Hilda Gavin and Vivian
Shepherd, as well as engaging in anti-war activism in the form of lec-
tures on behalf of the League of Nations Union, advocating disarmament
(Chapman, 2013: 37–8). In 1920, Stebbing finally secured one of the few
and far between academic posts open to women, a lectureship at Bedford
College, a women’s college in London. From 1924 to 1929, Stebbing
published a flurry of serious, original journal papers clearly belonging to
the tradition of analytic philosophy. But these were not works of Moorean
common-sense philosophy. Stebbing spent most of the 1920s publish-
ing extensively on philosophy of physics, a topic which had been of
interest to her since at least her master’s thesis, which includes detailed
discussions of the question of whether physical laws are necessary (Steb-
bing, 1914: 3, 28–35, 70–1). Her main interlocutors were the analytic
12 Women in the History of Philosophy
but used these periods of illness to read books in English, French, and
German, often publishing her thoughts as a book review. As a result of
her extensive reading and trilingualism, Stebbing was one of the first out-
side of continental Europe to see the significance of logical positivism.
She published a detailed study of the movement (Stebbing, 1933b) three
years before Ayer published his Language, Truth, and Logic. Stebbing’s
publications on logical positivism did much to introduce it to the British
philosophical scene. In the late 1930s, Stebbing, increasingly alarmed by
the rise of fascism and generally conscious that the general public would
benefit from the ability to detect and resist fallacious argumentation and
manipulative uses of language by those in authority, began to write on
the application of critical thinking to ethics and politics. She also worked
with Jewish refugees, work which she continued until her death in 1943.
Susan Stebbing 13
2 Logic
Susan Stebbing seems always to have loved logic and to have felt at
home within it. As a Girton undergraduate, she had studied Aristotel-
ian logic with W. E. Johnson, who would later write, with significant
help and support from Newnham philosophy student Naomi Bentwich
(Johnson, 1924: v), a three-volume magnum opus entitled Logic. The
mistress of Girton, E. E. Constance Jones, was herself a logician, then
author of three books (Jones, 1980, 1982, 1905). We know that Steb-
bing and Jones discussed logic together, too, because Jones thanked
Stebbing for helping her with the proofs of the second edition of her
Primer of Logic (Jones, 1913: i). Among Stebbing’s early publications,
before she became an analytic philosopher, is a defence of (Aristotelian)
logic against the charge that it is mostly useless in everyday reasoning
(Stebbing, 1915).
Twenty-first-century Western readers may feel a sense of surprise at
seeing several logicians among the first and second generations of UK
and US women to enter higher education and specialise in philosophy.
The contemporary stereotype is that women in philosophy, who remain
a small minority within the field, prefer moral or political philosophy
to logic. In our late twentieth- and early twenty-first-century Western
cultural context, logic is associated with masculinity. But this associ-
ation of male thinkers with logic and female thinkers with normative
philosophy, I will show, is a relatively recent invention, not common
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009026925 Published online by Cambridge University Press
in the days of early analytic philosophy. All women who held aca-
demic jobs in philosophy in the United States or the UK, and many on
the European continent, prior to the 1940s of whom I’m aware were
experts either on logic broadly conceived or on history of philosophy.
Some also published on normative philosophy; some did not. Besides
Jones and Stebbing, in the 1890s–1910s Christine Ladd-Franklin, Sophie
Bryant, Mary Everest Boole, Constance Naden, Margaret Floy Wash-
burn, Mary Whiton Calkins, Beatrice Edgell, Augusta Klein, Grace de
Laguna, and Helen Dendy also published regularly in mainstream phil-
osophy journals on formal logic, philosophical logic, and the application
of logic to other fields such as psychology. Notable female historians
of philosophy include Elizabeth Haldane, the Descartes scholar and
translator, and M. J. Levett, the celebrated translator of the Theaetetus.
14 Women in the History of Philosophy
associated with moral virtues of peacefulness, piety, and purity (Laslett &
Brenner, 1989: 387). Men ruled the public sphere, which included higher
education as well as politics and the marketplace, a sphere decidedly
less shot through with moral virtue and imbued with the kind of worldly
knowledge from which women were shielded. Although I shall concen-
trate on Stebbing’s largely white and upper/middle-class British context,
I note that cultural variations existed. In particular, some ethnic minority
groups within Western societies, such as African American communi-
ties, largely adhered to Victorian ideals of domesticity but highly prized
women’s education (Carlson, 1992: 61–2), and working-class commu-
nities of all ethnic groups valued women’s paid work outside the home,
which they did not view as being at odds with domesticity (Laslett &
Brenner, 1989: 389).
Politics, academic and practical, was described as an essentially mas-
culine enterprise, especially by opponents of women’s suffrage. Anti-
suffragists seized upon the doctrine of separate spheres to argue that
involvement in politics would erode women’s pure, instinctive virtue.
They justified their opposition to women’s suffrage on the grounds that
women were not suited to politics because emotion, not reason, informed
women’s morality. Anti-feminists argued that while feminine, instinct-
ive morality was well-suited to child-rearing and the domestic sphere,
it had no role to play in the cold, calculating world of politics, where
women would invariably ‘consider personalities above principles’ when
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009026925 Published online by Cambridge University Press
they cast their votes or became involved in governing (Hopkins, 1913: 8).
According to the doctrine of separate spheres, women’s moral superiority
did not issue from rational reflection or knowledge of ethical theory. It
flowed from motherly love, self-sacrifice, and domesticity. Western Vic-
torian and Edwardian cultural mores mostly did not encourage women to
study or teach moral theory in colleges or universities. And they viewed
women as outright incompetent in the realm of politics, a competitive
field drawing upon quite unfeminine worldly knowledge. Logic, by con-
trast, whether Aristotelian or mathematical, could be studied from home
or entirely within the safe walls of a women’s college. As a result, it
was considered, by those who approved of women’s higher education
but upheld separate spheres, as a safe subject for a woman to study.
16 Women in the History of Philosophy
(Whitehead, 1898: 116). Venn highly praised the 1883 published ver-
sion of her PhD (Venn, 1883: 595–601). Constance Jones made a major
advance in philosophical logic when she queried the third of the trad-
itional Aristotelian Laws of Thought, the Law of Identity. Jones denied
that subject-predicate statements in general express identities, as most
are not of the logical form ‘A is A’. According to Jones, their logical
form is, rather, one which states ‘an identity of denomination in diver-
sity of attribution’ (Jones, 1890: 46), that is, they attribute to the same
referent two different properties, using phrases with different ‘signifi-
cations’ (Jones, 1892: 20). Jones, then, proposed with what she called
her ‘New Law of Thought’ or ‘analysis of categoricals’, a version of
what we now know as the sense-reference distinction and was described
as such by her contemporaries: ‘a theory expressed first by Miss
Susan Stebbing 17
Constance Jones as long ago as 1890, and, a little later, by Prof. Frege’
(Klein, 1911: 521).
configuration there are in the world in case the sentence is true (see
Section 4).
To appreciate the novelty of Stebbing’s contributions, we need a brief
sketch of the historical backdrop, beginning with how Stebbing’s prede-
cessors, especially Moore and Russell but also Constance Jones, reacted
to those authors whom Stebbing labelled the ‘traditional logicians’. Steb-
bing’s ‘traditional logicians’ included the idealists Bosanquet and Brad-
ley, whose logic was Aristotelian but, by Stebbing’s lights, had lost sight
of the most positive features of Aristotle’s thought, the formalism which
Aristotle shared with mathematical logic (Stebbing, 1930: x–xii) by mis-
takenly setting ‘form’ in opposition to ‘Reality’ and proposing instead a
‘metaphysical logic’ governed by the principle of ‘identity-in-diversity’.
Russell and Moore’s first venture into anti-idealism, the New Phil-
osophy, had rebelled against idealism, with Bradley as their main foil.
According to Bradley’s (and Bosanquet’s) identity-in-diversity view,
what we think of as ordinary identity claims or subject-predicate state-
ments never represent reality correctly. Bradley and Bosanquet claimed
that true identity between subject and predicate could not be asserted
due to the ‘difference in meaning’ (Bradley, 1883: 28), that we ‘cannot
speak of the coincident part as the same, except by an ideal synthesis
which identifies it first with one of the two outlines and then with the
other’ (Bosanquet, 1888: 358). Bradley maintained that our thoughts and
language must always radically misrepresent reality, because reality is
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009026925 Published online by Cambridge University Press
to them to be intuitively true. But intuition proved no fit guide for math-
ematicians exploring novel systems, like Cantor’s theory of transfinite
numbers, and the new theory of classes, which introduced higher and
lower levels of infinity. Mathematicians’ only guide was adherence to
clearly laid-out proof methods. Instead of relying on syllogistic forms,
where each premise or conclusion has just one quantifier, rigorous new
treatments of arithmetic and geometry also needed statements with mul-
tiple quantifiers, such as ‘for each number, there is another number which
is its successor’ or ‘in between any two points on a line, there is another
point’. They needed a polyadic (that is, multiple-quantifier) logic, like
Frege’s Begriffsschrift (1879). Frege thought of his quantifiers as higher-
order properties: to say that so-and-sos exist is to say that the so-and-so
property has instances. Russell put such quantifiers to work in accounting
20 Women in the History of Philosophy
not directly. The Queen is, to them, a logical construct, or, as Russell
sometimes said, a logical fiction, someone whose existence and nature
we know of through descriptive knowledge of her properties. Russell’s
mature view at this time preserved the assumption, so central to his and
Moore’s first venture into anti-idealism, that our minds can reach out and
grasp, and name, constituents of reality directly.
Complete symbols or proper names, encoding in language a sign of
immediate acquaintance with something in the world, remained. Russell
stressed that we need them, as they are where analysis terminates: ‘Every
proposition which we can understand must be composed wholly of con-
stituents with which we are acquainted’ (Russell, 1910–11: 117). On
Russell’s view, analysis terminates in ‘sense-data’. Although sense-data
are now generally thought of as mental states, such an account of them is
not necessary. Moore considered an interpretation on which sense-data
are identical with the surfaces of objects (Moore, 1925: 59). Russell at
times admitted acquaintance with universals and the self, not merely with
mental states.
Stebbing enthusiastically embraced incomplete symbol theory for its
potential to account for negative existentials. Stebbing considered it
‘plain common sense’ that ‘negative existential propositions are true
if there is no individual in the actual world to which the descriptive
phrase applies’ (Stebbing, 1930: 56). She also mentioned negative exis-
tentials as playing an important role in science. She contrasted the planet
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009026925 Published online by Cambridge University Press
we need not pay attention to, whose only job is to stand for something
outside itself. In Principia, an occurrence of a term is called ‘referen-
tially transparent’ iff nothing is said of it but by means of it something
is said of something else (Whitehead & Russell, 1964 [1910]: appendix
C). Stebbing was among the first to stress the importance of context in
interpreting occurrences of expressions, as Quine was also to do in his
development of referential transparency (Quine, 1953: 124). But neither
of them was the first to do so. Russell admitted that he had first seen a
rebuttal of the transparency of language in ‘Lady Welby’s work on the
subject, but failed to take it seriously’ (Russell, 1926: 118).
Stebbing argued that Russell’s claim that ‘the proposition “a is the so-
and-so” means that a has the property so-and-so, and nothing else has’ is
not independent of context because some sentences of the form ‘a is the
so-and-so’ do not contain definite descriptions. For example, ‘the whale
is a mammal’ is usually used to express a taxonomical claim about whales
and has the form of a universal generalisation, equivalent to ‘all whales
are mammals’. A sentence such as ‘the dog is fond of peanut butter’ is
ambiguous. It can be used to make a generalisation about all dogs, in
which case it is a universal generalisation, or to make a statement about a
particular dog, identified by context (I might say it about my dog Daphne;
Stebbing might have said it about her dog Smoodger), in which case it
contains an incomplete symbol. Stebbing thus recommended a refined
account of incomplete symbols, which she credited to Moore in corres-
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009026925 Published online by Cambridge University Press
1 See Janssen-Lauret (in press-c) for a case that Stebbing’s argument here resembles
that of Constance Jones and may have been influenced by Jones; see also Janssen-
Lauret (2017) for a case that she may also have been influenced by Bradley.
Susan Stebbing 25
Beaney and Chapman (2021: §2) state that Stebbing’s book covers
‘traditional, Aristotelian logic’, Stebbing herself sharply distinguished
between Aristotle’s logic and that of those she called ‘Traditional Logi-
cians’, certainly including the idealists Bosanquet and Bradley. Among
Stebbing’s original views on logic is the doctrine that Aristotle’s logic
shares with the symbolic logic of Frege, Peano, Russell, and Whitehead,
but not with the thought of traditional logicians, a focus on formality.
Early modern logicians and their successors argued over whether logic
was an art, the ‘art of thinking’ – as in the title of the 1662 Port Royal
Logic, La logique ou l’art de penser (Stebbing, 1930: 163) – or a science,
and whether logic was psychologistic, that is, descriptive of reasoning, or
normative, prescribing to us how we ought to think and argue. Stebbing’s
college principal Jones caused much controversy with her bold, anti-
psychologistic stance that logic was the science of the relations between
propositions (Jones, 1890).
Mathematical logic, which Stebbing called ‘symbolic logic’, cast new
light on the question of the distinctive characteristics and subject mat-
ter of logic, the question now generally called ‘logicality’. Previously,
logicians and mathematicians had been content to build their systems up
from principles which appeared to them to be intuitively true, or self-
evident. But late nineteenth-century mathematicians had begun to find
that coherent proof systems remained when some allegedly self-evident
principles were given up. Non-Euclidean geometries, for example, no
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009026925 Published online by Cambridge University Press
Stebbing held that the success of modern symbolic logic, which places
no reliance on intuitive self-evidence, gives us good reason to dispense
with self-evidence as a condition of logicality. It also places limits on the
role played by modal notions in logic: ‘We cannot answer that an axiom is
a proposition that is necessarily true, for we do not know what necessarily
true means’ (Stebbing, 1930: 175). According to Stebbing, what is neces-
sarily true is at best a relative notion given in terms of what is implied by
what (Stebbing, 1930: 176). She also argued that we cannot rely on the
notion of ‘logical priority’. To speak of one truth being ‘logically prior’
to another is obscure and adds an inappropriate dose of metaphysics to
our logic (Stebbing, 1930: 175). Stebbing concluded that ‘no deductive
system can be regarded as demonstrating necessarily true propositions by
means of necessary primitive propositions or axioms’ (Stebbing, 1930:
176–7) because truth cannot be established by proof in the sense of dem-
onstration; to find out what is true we must turn to the empirical. What
we can do is, in a given system, to take certain notions as undefined, and
some statements as not for present purposes standing in need of proof,
without their being taken to be absolutely indefinable or indemonstrable.
These are called ‘primitives’ after Peano (Stebbing, 1930: 175). But
what is the property that makes a system logic? Stebbing’s answer was
‘formality’, not in the sense of involving only proof without invoking
truth but in the sense of universal applicability.
If we reject the view that there are different logics, then I think we can
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009026925 Published online by Cambridge University Press
q just in case either p is false or q is true (Stebbing, 1930: 223). She quer-
ied Russell’s view that material implication is a plausible candidate for
logical consequence. She cast doubt on that view by arguing that in ordin-
ary language we say that, if q follows from p, then q can be deduced from
p. Material implication, Stebbing countered, can hold between statements
which cannot be deduced from one another. She expressed a preference
for an alternative account of logical consequence, based on a relation
which C. I. Lewis called ‘strict implication’ and Moore called ‘entail-
ment’ (Stebbing, 1930: 222; see also Douglas & Nassim, 2021). The
relation of entailment holds, for example, between statements like ‘this
is red’ and ‘this is coloured’, that is, it covers what is now often called
‘material consequence’. Entailment is not definable in psychological
terms (Stebbing, 1930: 223). Although we would now categorise this
kind of entailment as modal, Stebbing, in 1930, resisted this characterisa-
tion, arguing that ‘impossible’ is less clear than ‘entails’ (Stebbing, 1930:
222 n.1). Both implication and entailment are in turn distinct from infer-
ence, which Stebbing described as ‘a mental process’ (Stebbing, 1930:
210), and, although of interest to logic, different from validity. Inference
is psychological, but not validity (Stebbing, 1930: 211).
These views of Stebbing’s in turn affected her answers to the questions
of extensionalism in logic and the relationship of logic to philosophy
of science. The new mathematical logic’s need to overcome intuition
as a guide to logical truth, and replace it as far as possible with rules
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009026925 Published online by Cambridge University Press
its formality. Logic has no distinctive set of facts of its own; it traces
the general forms of reality (Stebbing, 1930: 474). Nevertheless, Steb-
bing never lost sight of logic’s connection to thinking and reasoning.
She consistently described thinking as an activity. Logical reasoning she
described as goal-directed, purposive thinking, separate not from action-
linked thinking but from free association of thoughts or idle reverie.
When giving examples of reasoning, she liked to give practical examples:
a man uses his knowledge of natural laws to trace a safe path off a cliff
in high tide (Stebbing, 1930: 1–2); a woman thinks through why it is
unwise to wear a given dress to the beach, as the chemically unstable dye
fades in sea air (Stebbing, 1930: 8); a man locked out of his flat devises
hypotheses which he can test in order to determine whether the flat has
been burgled (Stebbing, 1930: 234). Stebbing viewed logical reasoning
as an activity of people, people who interact in communities and whose
views are informed by the ‘intellectual climate’ (Stebbing, 1930: 294) in
which they live.
Lastly, a central aspect of Stebbing’s outlook was her view of logic
as continuous with philosophy of science and scientific methodology.
Stebbing did not favour a split of logic into an inductive and a deductive
branch, since she believed that science must deploy both inductive and
deductive reasoning (Stebbing, 1930: 245, 344). What is true in a nat-
ural science, unlike in a purely deductive science such as mathematics,
‘depends upon what there actually is in the world’ (Stebbing, 1930: 231)
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009026925 Published online by Cambridge University Press
‘in certain respects other others called by the same name . . . properties
belonging to all the instances of crows constitute the total positive ana-
logy’ (Stebbing, 1930: 250). Stebbing considered argument by metaphor
in the scientific context especially pernicious because she regarded a
metaphor as an especially weak analogy, connoting only one shared
property (Stebbing, 1930: 253). What sort of a system is a scientific
theory? Stebbing was sympathetic to the then fashionable view that
science does not explain (that is, it does not answer why-questions)
but instead describes; it answers how-questions. Yet she pointed out
that science does not merely describe in the sense of listing proposi-
tions which recount all the scientific facts, such as exact descriptions of
which motions occurred or which particles were present in which loca-
tion at which time. Such descriptions are neither feasible nor useful.
Susan Stebbing 31
laid the groundwork for her later metaphysics, and made room for a more
holist approach within analytic philosophy.
3 Philosophy of Science
Much of Susan Stebbing’s published work focussed on the philosophy of
science and especially on the philosophy of physics. But it is only very
recently that she has been given credit for holding original views on phil-
osophy of science (West, 2022; Janssen-Lauret, 2022a). To date, little has
been written about the half-dozen philosophy of science papers Stebbing
published between 1924 and 1929, where she set out her view, which
she termed ‘realism’, on the importance of observations to philosophy of
science (Stebbing, 1924, 1924–5, 1926, 1927, 1928, 1929). As we saw
in Section 2.1, Stebbing’s Modern Introduction to Logic had much to
say on the relationship between logic and scientific methodology. Yet,
to date, it has not seen much engagement from historians of analytic
philosophy. Her book Philosophy and the Physicists (Stebbing, 1937)
investigated and meticulously rebutted the idealistic interpretation of
Einsteinian physics and quantum mechanics then popular with some
physicists. Stebbing’s contemporaries described the book as having a
wholly negative project (Broad, 1938; Paul, 1938). But current schol-
arship has begun to argue that Stebbing put her original ideas to good use
in Philosophy and the Physicists, such as directional analysis (Janssen-
Lauret, 2022a; see also Section 4 in this Element) as well as novel views
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009026925 Published online by Cambridge University Press
which imply that we can no longer assume that it is necessarily true that
parallel lines never meet, or that wholes are always greater in size than
their proper parts, simply because they seem intuitively self-evident. It
was not merely that assuming the falsity of such apparently intuitive prin-
ciples led to perfectly coherent proof systems. Such proof systems, of
non-Euclidean geometry and set theories which allowed for denumerable
and non-denumerable infinities, were also fruitfully applied to model
the space–time of Einstein’s theory of general relativity. So, what had
appeared to be self-evident necessary truths about parallel lines never
meeting and wholes always being greater than their proper parts now
seemed to be actual falsehoods, not true of the physical world in their
complete generality. Stebbing saw the need for a properly worked-out
philosophy to fit around the deliverances of the new natural sciences.
In her work on logic, as we have seen, she argued that we may explain
‘how the exact and tidy world of the physicist is connected with the
fragmentary and untidy world of common sense [if we] demonstrate
the applicability of abstract deductive systems to the world given in
sense-experience’ (Stebbing, 1930: 452) and that we should turn to
Whiteheadian extensive abstraction to carry out this project.
As we saw in Section 1, the prevailing narrative of Stebbing’s devel-
opment has it that she was ‘converted’ to Moorean analytic philosophy
as a result of a philosophical exchange with Moore in 1917–18 (e.g.
Beaney & Chapman, 2021: §3). Although Stebbing herself was to an
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009026925 Published online by Cambridge University Press
between the primary qualities an object really has, such as its size, shape,
and motion, and the secondary qualities which are mental additions, such
as colour, sound, and smell. All these qualities are to be found in Nature.
All are to an extent abstractions from the panoply of events which it
comprises, as is the mind itself (Stebbing, 1924: 292).
Stebbing agreed that the Bifurcation of Nature must be abandoned, but
took a more moderate view than Whitehead. From early on, she expressed
a preference for an ontology of particulars and universals – though
one which included relational universals, not merely properties – which
together combine into facts, instead of Whitehead’s event ontology. Yet
she admitted that the nature of the particular-universal distinction was far
from obvious and must be carefully revisited in view of the difficulties
with its application to physics. She explicitly took issue with Moore’s
36 Women in the History of Philosophy
5. That piece of blotting paper was on the table before I saw it.
6. Other people besides myself have seen that piece of blotting paper.
(Stebbing, 1929: 147)
The view that (1)–(6) above are true and known to be true Stebbing called
‘realism’. Her ‘realism’ was clearly distinct from Moore’s ‘Common-
Sense View’, often described as one according to which ‘our ordinary
common-sense view of the world is largely correct’ (Baldwin, 2004:
§6), even though there are some similarities. Stebbing’s range of truths
was narrower, and more perception-focussed, than Moore’s. Stebbing
also emphasised that she saw both philosophy and physics as start-
ing from the same range of truths about perceptual observations, the
relationship of the observer to her perceptions, and her relationship to
Susan Stebbing 37
between knowing a truth and knowing its analysis, and Stebbing cited
his 1925 ‘Defence of Common Sense’ here for that insight. Neverthe-
less, Stebbing’s view had already moved beyond Moore’s at this point.
According to Stebbing, modern physical theory was in tension with naïve
realism, but not with her realism, and by itself neither compelled nor ruled
out an idealist interpretation of physics.
2 Eddington’s view is now often called ‘panpsychism’, but Stebbing did not use that term.
Susan Stebbing 39
that Moore at times seemed to incline towards the position that such a
view is paradoxical. Stebbing, by contrast, did not. She was very clear
that Eddington’s purported analysis, ‘the plank is material but its ultimate
micro-constituents are the stuff of consciousness’, is no more internally
contradictory than ‘the plank is solid but its component atoms are mostly
empty space’. Stebbing’s objection to Eddington’s idealist conclusion
was not that it was internally contradictory or at odds with common sense.
She simply found that it did not follow from his premises.
By Stebbing’s lights, Eddington’s project went wrong early on not just
by committing the fallacy of conflating macro-objects’ properties with
those of their constituents but by raising the question ‘how is percep-
tion possible?’, a question which Stebbing (for Whiteheadian reasons)
already considered ‘devoid of sense’ (Stebbing, 1937: 52), and by look-
ing to physics for an answer to it. Stebbing, of course, held that physics
itself must rest on facts about perception and observation, and relation-
ships between observers, and although she did not cite her 1929 account
of ‘perceptual science’ in Philosophy and the Physicists I will show that
she made use of it. What’s more, Stebbing objected to the Bifurcation
of Nature inherent in Eddington’s view that physics constructs a ‘sym-
bolic world’. Eddington’s ‘symbolic world’ duplicates the familiar world
in which, for example, Susan Stebbing stepped into her study and took
pleasure in seeing and smelling ‘a crimson and scented rose’ from a
bowl on her desk. On Eddington’s account, the world of physics con-
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009026925 Published online by Cambridge University Press
tains ‘duplicates’ of the desk, the bowl, the rose, etcetera. It contains
no duplicate of crimson but merely ‘its scientific equivalent electro-
magnetic wavelength . . . the wave is the reality . . . the colour is mere
mind-spinning’ (Eddington, 1928: 88). Stebbing felt that Eddington was
correct to deny that the wave itself is coloured, for we must not ‘in one
and the same sentence . . . mix up language used appropriately for the
furniture of earth and our daily dealings with it with language used for
the purpose of philosophical and scientific discussion’ (Stebbing, 1937:
42).3 Nevertheless, the wave not being coloured cannot be used as a
premise to support the conclusion that the rose is not really coloured
3 See Chapman (2013) for an interpretation of Philosophy and the Physicists which
emphasises the difference between ordinary language and the language of physics.
Susan Stebbing 41
Two tables! Yes, there are duplicates of every object about me . . . One
of them has been familiar to me from earliest years . . . it has exten-
sion, it is comparatively permanent; it is coloured; above all, it is
substantial . . . Table No. 2 is my scientific table . . . There is noth-
ing substantial about my second table. It is nearly all empty space.
(Eddington, 1928: xi–xii)
of two tables alongside each other was simply a mistake. The familiar
table is a logical construct. We all understand, at the level of ordinary
language, what it means to say that it is solid, coloured, and substantial.
The atoms which are mostly empty space and the fields which oscil-
late to produce electromagnetic waves are resultants of analysis. They
reside at the level of the most basic facts of physics. These basic facts
are composed of elements which, as far as we know, are simple. What
can correctly be predicated of them cannot be predicated of the table.
At least, we cannot make such predications without careful qualifica-
tion; we may be able to say, ‘at the subatomic level, the table consists
mostly of empty space’. This statement sounds counter-intuitive but may
constitute a summary of an appropriate, physical analysis of the ordin-
ary, solid table. The new mathematics taught us that we cannot deny that
42 Women in the History of Philosophy
infinite sets have proper parts the same size as them just because it sounds
counter-intuitive. The same is true of the analysis of the table in terms of
atoms which are themselves mostly empty space. Its counter-intuitive
appearance is not grounds to declare it false. Nor does it give us reason
to posit two tables, one solid and one tenuous.
Eddington’s reduplications further forced a strong and, according to
Stebbing, unhelpful Bifurcation of Nature into mind and body. She
described the way Eddington compared the human mind to a newspaper
office providing a ‘free translation’ of ‘messages’ from the outside world.
These messages we, or rather ‘the editor’ in our mind, that is, ‘the per-
ceiving part of our mind’ (Stebbing, 1937: 84), ‘dress’ with colour, space,
and substance which are not really there (Stebbing, 1937: 82). Stebbing
objected that Eddington relied on the metaphor of the newspaper editor
not as an illustration of something further to be explained but as an argu-
ment by analogy. Eddington offered up this argument in support of the
conclusions that our belief in the external world is ‘a remote inference’
(Stebbing, 1937: 85), that we know the world only because ‘its fibres
stretch into our consciousness’, and that yet we have grounds to identify it
with what is in common between many consciousnesses (Stebbing, 1937:
87). We have seen in Section 2.1 that Stebbing generally deplored the
use of metaphor as argument in philosophy of science because she cat-
egorised metaphors, in that context, as reasoning from weak analogy
(Stebbing, 1930: 253–4). The ‘editor’ metaphor is no different; the ana-
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009026925 Published online by Cambridge University Press
logy between the perceiving part of our mind and a newspaper editor
soon breaks down. Stebbing, then, saw no reason to revise her views
on the basis of Eddington’s argument from analogy. She maintained her
Whiteheadian view that the external world is not inferred from percep-
tions but directly apprehended: ‘there is equally no doubt that we are able,
as a result of our past experience, immediately to perceive that this is a
so-and-so. In such immediate recognition no inference is involved’ (Steb-
bing, 1930: 211). She reiterated the same conclusion for which she had
found support in her 1929 ‘perceptual science’ view that physics need
not justify other minds because they are inevitably presupposed by its
method: ‘Physics as a science results from the conjoint labour of many
minds or persons’ (Stebbing, 1937: 108). Stebbing wondered whether
Eddington’s mention of ‘fibres’ of consciousness constituted a further
Susan Stebbing 43
metaphor and was inclined to think not (Stebbing, 1937: 85); Eddington
derived the conclusion that we really only know our own consciousness
and that nerve impulses do not resemble the external world ‘in intrinsic
nature’ (Stebbing, 1937: 86).
Stebbing was sympathetic to part of Eddington’s case, in particular
to his suggestion that physics does not tell us the intrinsic nature of
things. After all, physics abstracts away from the macro-individuals, with
their absolutely determinate qualities which we are in touch with, in
favour of a constructed system of generalities which details their rela-
tions to each other: their extrinsic connections. Stebbing wrote, “‘the
world of physics” is nothing but a constructed system stated in terms
of imperceptibles, the system being such that it permits, under cer-
tain conditions, of interpretation by reference to perceptual elements’
(Stebbing, 1933–4: 9). She could sympathise with some of Eddington’s
structuralist assumptions, familiar to her from Russell and Carnap (Steb-
bing 1934b), including the suggestion that the information physics gives
us allows for multiple interpretations as long as those interpretations
share the structure of the information provided: ‘A constructed system
may be capable of interpretation in terms of a given set of facts. It may
then be adequate to this set, but it could never be exhaustive . . . physics
is abstract’ (Stebbing, 1933–4: 25).
Stebbing’s view, dating back to her 1920s papers, that modern physics
is in itself compatible with either an idealist or a materialist interpret-
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009026925 Published online by Cambridge University Press
ation also provides support for the conclusion that physics does not
reveal the intrinsic natures of things. She criticised the overconfidence
of nineteenth-century materialist physicists who felt very sure that they
knew the intrinsic nature of matter and atoms (Stebbing, 1937: 96). Yet
Eddington (unlike Stebbing) assumed that there nevertheless is some
intrinsic nature to be known and that we have reason to assume that it
is conscious. He began by arguing that there are ‘(a) a mental image,
which is in our minds and not in the external world; (b) some kind of
counterpart in the external world, which is of inscrutable nature; (c) a set
of pointer-readings, which exact science can study’ (Eddington, 1928:
254). He then added the premises that the schedule of pointer-readers
must be ‘attached to some unknown background’ and that ‘for pointer-
readers of my own brain I have an insight which is not limited to the
44 Women in the History of Philosophy
it seems to me quite clear that the new physics does not imply
idealism. Neither, however, does it imply materialism . . . There are
problems in plenty to be dealt with concerning the inter-connexions
of mental and bodily activity, but none of these problems are in any
way affected by developments in physics. To pursue this topic further
it would be necessary to consider in detail the various abstractions by
means of which we are able to divide ‘the sciences’ up, assigning some
problems to physicists, some to chemists, some to biochemists, some
to physiologists, and some to psychologists. (Stebbing, 1942–3, 184)
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009026925 Published online by Cambridge University Press
4 Metaphysics
Stebbing’s metaphysics, especially her distinction between metaphysical
and grammatical analysis, is the part of her oeuvre which has so far
received the most attention from historians of analytic philosophy. Older
texts which mention Stebbing (e.g. Urmson, 1956; Passmore, 1966)
focus on her views on metaphysical analysis. Many recent commenta-
tors (Beaney, 2003; Milkov, 2003; Beaney, 2016) do the same but tend to
describe her view repeatedly as ‘Moorean’ (see also Section 1).4 Milkov
even applies Moore’s name to a position which Stebbing claimed as
her own, giving the name ‘Moore’s directional analysis’ (Milkov, 2003:
358) to what Stebbing herself describes (in a paper about Moore) as ‘an
analysis I once called “directional analysis” ’(Stebbing, 1942: 527). Of
course, Stebbing acknowledged a debt to Moore in her work on analysis.
But, in my view, it can be shown that Stebbing’s directional analysis in
fact made a key advance on Moore. She succeeded in solving at least one
key problem which baffled Moore in his ‘Defence of Common Sense’,
as we will see in this section. Stebbing made interesting contributions to
several other areas of metaphysics, too, such as the metaphysics of lan-
guage, causation, and mereology. But due to limitations of space, I will
discuss the former only in passing and hope to cover the latter two in
future work.
Stebbing’s distinction between metaphysical and grammatical analysis
constituted progress in philosophy. In effect, we may think of her dis-
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009026925 Published online by Cambridge University Press
tinction and the use she put it to as having already solved the paradox
of analysis ten years before Langford formulated it (Langford, 1942).
Langford presented the paradox as a conundrum for Moore’s views on
analysis, in the form of a dilemma. Do the common-sense propositions
which Moore calls ‘truisms’ (Moore, 1925: 32) and their analyses have
the same meaning? If the answer is ‘yes’, then the analysis conveys no
more than the original truism; then analysis is pointless and trivial. But if
the answer is ‘no’, the two do not have the same meaning; then the ana-
lysis is false. Langford wrote, ‘One is tempted to say that there must be
some appropriate sense of ‘meaning’ in which the two verbal expressions
do have the same meaning and some other appropriate sense in which
they do not’ (Langford, 1942: 323).
Stebbing had provided an explication of these two different senses
of ‘meaning’ in 1932. Unlike Moore, Stebbing had, from at least 1930,
insisted that the philosopher analyses not propositions but sentences or
sub-sentential expressions (Stebbing, 1930: 155, 441). She also clari-
fied that definitions do not define objects, or concepts, but expressions
(Stebbing, 1930: 439–41). Two years later, she made use of this view
to dispel the conflation between different kinds of ‘meaning’ which
Langford would complain about ten years afterwards. Stebbing wrote,
‘For my purpose it is sufficient to consider only two kinds of intellec-
tual analysis, namely, grammatical analysis and metaphysical analysis.
In grammatical analysis the elements of a sentence, viz., words, are
detected. . . . Grammatical analysis is analysis at what might be called the
same level’ (Stebbing, 1932–33: 77–8). She then sharply distinguished
grammatical analysis from metaphysical analysis: ‘The metaphysician is
concerned with what the words refer to, i.e., with the constituents there
must be in the world if the sentence is so used as to say what is true’
(Stebbing, 1932–33: 78).
Grammatical, or same-level, analysis explains a sentence in terms
of another stretch of language. Such analysis, if it consists in defi-
nition, or conceptual analysis, may well be a priori, or analytically
true. By contrast, metaphysical analyses are never analytic or a priori.
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009026925 Published online by Cambridge University Press
atoms which are, at the sub-atomic level, mostly empty space’ has an air
of paradox about it and is nevertheless true according to our best theory
of physics. We do not throw out paradoxical-sounding analyses offered
up by physics. We learn to live with them and distinguish them from the
truisms of the language of common sense. At the level of ordinary lan-
guage, ‘This table is solid’ does imply statements like, ‘This table does
not have large holes’, ‘This table is robust’, and ‘This table will bear
the weight of my books’. But none of that contradicts its being mostly
empty space at the subatomic level. This is a kind of directional analysis,
which we rely on both in physics and in metaphysics. We do not neces-
sarily take directional analyses to have failed if they sound paradoxical.
A paradoxical-sounding definition, or a paradoxical-sounding attempt at
conceptual analysis, would be problematic because those are kinds of
Susan Stebbing 49
point’ are not self-contradictory. Towards the end of her paper, Stebbing
concluded, ‘When we have made explicit what is entailed by directional
analysis, we find we must make assumptions which so far from being
certainly justified, are not even very plausible’ (Stebbing, 1932–33: 91–
2). That there are simple, unconfigured elements which enter into basic
facts is a major metaphysical assumption about the nature and structure
of the world. It is not a logical truth; it may be false.
The further epistemological claim that the basic facts are also know-
able by us is, similarly, at best an a posteriori truth. It is not only not
necessarily true but it may easily be actually false. The logical atomist
who also endorses Russell’s statement that ‘Every proposition which we
can understand must be composed wholly of constituents with which we
are acquainted’ (Russell, 1910–11: 117) makes an even stronger claim
than the above. Such a logical atomist makes the claim that simples are
not just knowable by us but known by acquaintance, directly, without
intermediary. This last claim is the one Stebbing seems to have regarded
as the least plausible.
Stebbing explained that ‘Russell . . . sought to discover a simple fact,
which he could regard as an indubitable datum’ (Stebbing, 1933b: 503).
This turned out to be ‘the sense-datum . . . with regard to [which] doubt
is impossible . . . sense-data are to be regarded as data in simple facts’
(Stebbing, 1933b: 503). But Stebbing did not think that philosophy and
physics should take sense-data as a point of departure. As we saw in Sec-
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009026925 Published online by Cambridge University Press
tion 3.1, Stebbing thought that both the philosopher and the physicist had
to start from a basis of ‘perceptual science’, which included not just ‘(1)
I am now seeing a red patch’ but also ‘(2) I am now perceiving a piece of
blotting paper’ and ‘(6) Other people besides myself have seen that piece
of blotting paper’ (Stebbing, 1929, 147). While (1) may be indubitable,
(2) and (6) are not; (2) describes a physical object, and (6) other minds.
Russell regarded belief in physical objects and other minds as ‘a risky
inference’ standing in need of justification (Stebbing, 1933b: 504). But
Stebbing saw no need for an indubitable basis for philosophy. After all,
she viewed philosophy as having the same observational basis of phys-
ics and took it to be obvious that the presuppositions of physics included
the existence of extra-mental entities and other minds. ‘The problem is
not one of justifying an inference; it is a problem of analysis. We must
52 Women in the History of Philosophy
not start from sense-data; we must start from the perceptual judgment’
(Stebbing, 1932–33: 72). Stebbing saw no need for analysis to terminate
in basic facts containing sense-data, nor did she think that our process
of analysing a sentence must start from the consideration of sense-data.
Although Stebbing regularly presented this anti-foundationalist point as
disagreement with Russell, it also constitutes, to a lesser extent, dis-
agreement with Moore. All of Moore’s analyses of ‘This is a hand’ in
‘Defence of Common Sense’ start with ‘This is part of the surface of a
human hand’, which Moore called ‘undoubtedly a proposition about the
sense-datum, which I am seeing’ (Moore, 1925: 55).
It may be that Stebbing’s expertise in the philosophy of physics
enabled her to see clearly how problematic the assumption is that we
have direct epistemic access to unconfigured elements of basic facts.
According to our current best theory of physics, the simples are sub-
atomic particles: quarks, and leptons such as electrons. But we cannot
observe electrons directly. This difficulty is not a matter of our ignor-
ance or issues with our measuring equipment which we can rectify. It is
a matter of physics: to try to observe an electron, we must shine light on
it, but the electron is smaller than the wavelength of visible light (Steb-
bing, 1937: 181). Hence there are at least some candidate simples which
we cannot even in principle observe directly.
Stebbing’s metaphysics, then, retained some aspects of logical atom-
ism but dropped its strongly foundationalist assumptions. She moved
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009026925 Published online by Cambridge University Press
Crooked Thinking preceded both and also aimed to teach the general
public about good reasoning. Yet Stebbing’s book was highly innova-
tive and proved very popular, in part because of her determination to
provide examples of real reasoning, argument, rhetoric, and persuasion,
taken from political speeches, journalism, letters to newspaper editors,
and advertising. To the present day, many critical thinking textbooks still
attempt to teach students to recognise good and bad reasoning based only
on artificial, invented examples. Stebbing was ahead of her time, as a pre-
1950s analytic philosopher, in paying close attention to ordinary usage
and taking great care to supply and analyse ordinary-language examples
in her work on critical thinking and politics. Her view of thinking as an
activity, engaged in by humans tied to a particular culture, language, and
intellectual climate was innovative, too. She aimed to teach the public
54 Women in the History of Philosophy
But what can we do? This is the question that is likely to be asked by
those who are at all sensitive to the avoidable suffering that is being
endured to-day through-out the world . . . in a time of such stress, it
is nevertheless worth while for us to overhaul our mental habits, to
attempt to find reasons for our beliefs, and to subject our assumptions
to rigorous criticisms . . . A person who is called upon thus to act is
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009026925 Published online by Cambridge University Press
You will probably have guessed that he is a man who has not himself
been brought up in a poor family . . . Does he seriously believe – we
should ask him – that it would have been a moral advantage to his own
family had he been poor? If he assents, then he ought in consistency to
wish that he had given up his income, worked hard for a low wage, and
lived in a poor, over-crowded neighbourhood. If, on the contrary, he
is unwilling to apply the principle to the case of his own family, then
he has fallen into a serious logical confusion . . . A safeguard against
this mistake is to change you into I. (Stebbing, 1939: 45–6)
learn the habit of putting to the test whether a slogan makes sense when
we unpack it.
Stebbing took a nuanced view concerning the role of emotion in
reasoning, as we would expect from someone who believes that we
think with our whole personality. Stebbing emphasised that ‘enthusi-
asm is not necessarily an enemy of thinking clearly’ (Stebbing, 1939:
29) and that ‘We are not purely rational beings’ (Stebbing, 1939: 30).
She explained, ‘I do not in the least wish to suggest that it is undesir-
able for us to be set on thinking by emotional considerations . . . it is
not emotion that annihilates the capacity to think clearly, but the urge
to establish a conclusion in harmony with the emotion and regardless
of the evidence’ (Stebbing, 1939: 33). Appeals to emotion, neverthe-
less, may lead us away from reasoning in subtle and very unsubtle
ways. Among the subtler ways are constant use of positively charged
words for our own side, or the side we favour, and negatively charged
words for the opposing side. Stebbing cited with approval research
by Julian Huxley on language used by The Times for participants in
the Spanish Civil War. The right-wing government and the socialist
rebellion were labelled respectively as ‘Referring to the Spanish Govern-
ment: Loyal, Spanish, Spanish Government, Republican, Anti-Fascist,
Communist. Referring to their opponents: Revolt, Insurrection, Fascist,
Anti-Government, “Rebel”.’ Stebbing subjoined, ‘You will notice, for
instance, that by putting “Rebel” (in inverted commas) there is conveyed
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009026925 Published online by Cambridge University Press
believe that those who differ from me thereon have seen clearly what
I see. (Stebbing, 1939: 54)
6 Conclusion
Susan Stebbing was not merely a disciple of G. E. Moore or an author
of popular books and textbooks. She was a vital and influential figure
within analytic philosophy from the 1920s to the 1940s and should be
considered as one of its ‘founding mothers’. We must get Stebbing out
from under the shadow of Moore, recover her contributions, and further
the perception of her as an important analytic philosopher, an original,
transitional figure who moved British analytic philosophy on from an
overly narrow and foundationalist logical atomism towards the holism
and philosophy of language of middle analytic philosophy.
We have seen that Stebbing held original views on philosophical ana-
lysis, logical construction, and complete and incomplete symbol theory.
She embraced incomplete symbol theory for its ability to make sense of
negative existentials, so useful in philosophy of science as well as logic,
but she demurred from Russell’s and Moore’s views that analysis ana-
lyses propositions or judgements, is analytically true, and terminates in
sense-data. She took issue in particular with Russell’s assumption that
we can know the termini of analysis directly, by acquaintance. Steb-
bing’s writings on these topics are interesting in isolation but are seen
to have particular strength when we begin to consider her as a systematic
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009026925 Published online by Cambridge University Press
H. Milford.
Stebbing, L. S. (1933–34). ‘Constructions: The Presidential Address’.
Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 34: 1–30.
Stebbing, L. S. (1933c). ‘The “A Priori” ’. Proceedings of the Aristotelian
Society. Suppl. 12: 178–97.
Stebbing, L. S. (1933d). ‘Mr. Joseph’s Defence of Free Thinking in
Logistics’. Mind, 42: 338–51.
Stebbing, L. S. (1934a). Logic in Practice. London: Methuen.
Stebbing, L. S. (1934b). ‘Communication and Verification’. Proceedings
of the Aristotelian Society, Suppl. 13: 159–73.
Stebbing, L. S. (1934c). ‘Directional Analysis and Basic Facts’. Analysis,
2: 33–6.
References 69
sity Press.
Venn, J. (1883). Review of Studies in Logic, ed. by C. S. Peirce. Mind,
8: 594–603.
Warnock, M. (2000). A Memoir: People and Places. London: Duck-
worth.
West, P. (2022). ‘The Philosopher versus the Physicist: Susan Stebbing on
Eddington and the Passage of Time’. British Journal for the History
of Philosophy, 30: 130–51.
Wetzel, L. (2018). ‘Types and Tokens’. Stanford Encyclopedia of Phil-
osophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/types-tokens/.
Whitehead, A. N. (1898). A Treatise on Universal Algebra: With Appli-
cations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
70 References
Jacqueline Broad
Monash University
Advisory Board
Dirk Baltzly
University of Tasmania
Sandrine Bergès
Bilkent University
Marguerite Deslauriers
McGill University
Karen Green
University of Melbourne
Lisa Shapiro
Simon Fraser University
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009026925 Published online by Cambridge University Press
Emily Thomas
Durham University