Ogden & Richards - 1946 - The Meaning of Meaning
Ogden & Richards - 1946 - The Meaning of Meaning
Ogden & Richards - 1946 - The Meaning of Meaning
by
C. K. Ogden & I. A. Richards
\z
A Harvest Book
LMNOP
PREFACE
To THE THIRD EDITION
CHAPTER I
CHAPTER II
CHAPTER III
SIGN-SITUATIONS
The theory of Meaning dependent upon the theory of Signs.—
Reference, i.e., t h e relation between a thought and w h a t it is
of, not unique, 48. The alleged direct relation of acquaintance
with ' propositions'; Keynes, Lipps, Husserl, van Ginneken, 49,
Previous psychological accounts of Knowledge—in terms of
association, apperception and suggestion—insufficiently dynamic.
—Development in terms of mnemic causation; Semon, 51.
Illustrations and explanations ; Lloyd Morgan's caterpillar, 52.
The defects of causal language, 54. Restatement in terms of
recurrent contexts, 55. Examples of contexts psychological and
external, 56. Definition of a Context, 58. How contexts recur.—
Generality of contexts and their probability, 59.
Defects of accounts based on imagery.—Images as luxuries of
mental life, 59. Their dangers, 61. Russell.—The context
theory of reference illustrated in the difficult case of expectation.—
The t r u t h or falsity of a reference merely a question of the recur-
rence or non-recurrence of a context.—Extension of this view to
CONTENTS xvii
expectations whose signs are themselves beliefs, and further to
all cases of interpretation from particular to particular, 62.
Extension to general references, 63. The generality and par-
ticularity of primitive references not the symbolic generality
and particularity of logic.—The conditions for general refer-
ences, 64. Inclusive and non-inclusive references, i.e., references
to all and some, 65. The detailed investigation of contexts a
future task of psychology, 66.
The referents of false beliefs, 66. Propositions as references,
i.e., relational characters of mental processes. ' Logical form,'
as the structure of references.—Inclusion of references in com-
pound references, 68. All complex references analysable into
simple references, i.e., ideas or concepts which are indefinite and
true, 69. Ideas and beliefs different only in complexity and in
affective-volitional characters.—Definiteness of reference obtained
only through complexity, 70. A false reference composed of
true simple references, 71. Illustrations of compound false
beliefs, 72.
The conformity of the contextual theory of reference with
modern scientific attitudes.—Its dependence upon some theory
of probability, 73. Suggestions towards a theory of probability,
74. Misinterpretation, relevance, emotional interference, 75.
CHAPTER IV
SIGNS IN PERCEPTION
The theory of interpretation applied to perception, 77. The
difficulties of the question ' What do we see ? * due to the neglect
of the sign-situations involved ; Helmholtz, 78. And to bad
symbolic procedure, 80.
Modifications of our sense organs as the initial signs which we
interpret, 80. Direct apprehending as a happening in the
nerves.—Dismissal of the charge of materialism, 81. This view
merely a rounding off of the most comprehensive system of
verified references yet obtained. As such at present unassailable,
82. Some notorious paradoxes removed by the exhibition of
the sign-situations present, 83. Such expansion of symbols as
a general anti-metaphysical method, 85.
CHAPTER V
T H E CANONS OF SYMBOLISM
The postulates of communication.—Logic as the science of
systematic symbolization, 87.
The Canon of Singularity. The symbols of mathematics
peculiar.—The nature of mathematics, 88. Wittgenstein, Rig-
xviii CONTENTS
nano, James Mill, 89. The sameness of references, 90. Symbol
substitution, 91.
The Canon of Definition. Identity of reference and identity of
referent.—Difficulties in discussion, 92.
The Canon of Expansion. The source of ' philosophy/—
Levels of reference.—-Expansion must show the sign-situations
involved, 93. Symbolic overgrowths and contractions.—' Uni-
versal ' symbolic conveniences.—The illusion of a world of
' being/ 94. Russell, 96. Language as an instrument, 98.
Incorrect distinguished from false symbols.—The Universe of
discourse, 102.
The Canon of Actuality. The discovery of the referent.
Bogus referents, 103. Examples of procedure, 104.
The Canon of Compatibility. The avoidance of nonsense and
' antinomies.' The ' Laws of Thought,' 105.
The Canon of Individuality. The ' place' of a referent.
' Place' as a symbolic accessory, 106. Translation and expan-
sion of false propositions.—Importance of expansion in education
and controversy, 107.
CHAPTER VI
DEFINITION
Four difficulties confronting a theory of definition, 109. (i)
Verbal and ' real' definitions, 110. (ii) Definitions and state-
ments, (iii) Definitions ad hoc.—The ' universe of discourse.'
(iv) Intensive and extensive definition, 111.
The technique of definition.—The selection of starting-points
with which to connect doubtful referents.—Types of fundamental
connection few in number. — Reasons for this, 113. Criteria
of starting-points, 114. The merits of gesture-language, 116.
Complex and indirect relations, 116. Enumeration of common
routes of definition, 117.
Application of this technique to discussion.—Fallacy of seeking
the definition of a sjrcnbol.—Systematic and occasional definitions,
121. Non-symbolic, i.e., indefinable terms, 123. Example of
' good,' 124. Influence of purpose on vocabulary, 126. Error
of seeking common element in various uses. Reasons for this
habit, 128. Difficulty of introducing new terms, 180. The
Method of Separation, 131. Rules of thumb.—The naming of
controversial tricks.—Schopenhauer's suggestion, 132. Three
subterfuges distinguished : the phonetic (Mill's case) ; the hypo-
static ; the utraquistic, 133. Further safeguards against con-
troversial malpractices. Dangerous words : Irritants, Degener-
ates, Mendicants (Matthew Arnold)r Nomads (Locke), 134.
The, value of a transferable technique, 138.
CONTENTS xix
CHAPTER VII
T H E MEANING O F B E A U T Y
The perennial discussion of Beauty a suitable field in which
to test the theory of definition.—The chaos in aesthetics, 137.
Rupert Brooke ; Benedetto Croce, 140. Separation of the uses
of the word, 141. Interrelations of these uses, 144. Cognate
and allied terms, 145.
The multiple functions of language.—Frequency of apparent
nonsense in the best critics; Longinus, Coleridge, Bradley,
Mackail, 147. The symbolic and the emotive use of words.—
Statements and appeals.—The speaker and the listener, 149.
The symbolic and emotive functions distinct.—Claim t o t r u t h
as the test.—Dangers in applying the test, 150.
Neglect of this multiplicity by g r a m m a r i a n s ; von der
Gabelentz, Vendryes, 151. The speculative approach, 153.
Bergson, Stephen, 154. Solution of the intellect versus intuition
problem, 155. ' Virtual knowledge ' as aesthetic appreciation,
156. Repose and satisfaction in Synaesthesis.—Interferences
between language uses, 157. D. H . Lawrence and the sun, 159.
CHAPTER VIII
T H E MEANING O F PHILOSOPHERS
Lack of attention to Meaning on the p a r t of philosophers,
160. Summary of the 1920-21 Symposium in Mind ; Schiller,
Russell, Joachim, Sidgwick, Strong, 161. Contemporaneous dis-
cussion of aphasia in Brain.—Inability of current psychology to
assist neurologists ; Parsons, 162.
Recent American contributions.—The Critical Realists, 163.
The ubiquity of the term ' meaning ' in their discussions.—
Drake, Lovejoy, Pratt, Rogers, Santayana, Sellars, Strong-
Uncritical use of the word ' meaning ' their chief bond of union,
164. Particularly reprehensible display by Miinsterberg, 169.
Appreciation of Miinsterberg ; Professor Moore, 173. Vocabulary
of the latter, 174.
F u r t h e r typical examples ; Broad, Nettleship, Haldane, Royce,
177. Keynes, 178. Official psychology ; seven professors, 179.
Psycho-analysis; P u t n a m . Pragmatists, 180. Historians.
Even t h e clearest thinkers ; G. E . Moore, 181. Artists, theo-
logians and others, 182. A crescendo of emotional asseveration,
183.
CHAPTER IX
T H E MEANING O F MEANING
Desirability of improving on the linguistic practice of philo-
sophers.—The framing of a list of definitions as in Chapter V I I ,
xx CONTENTS
185. Sixteen main definitions elicited, 186. Discussion of these
seriatim. Meaning as an intrinsic property of words (I) and as
an unanalysable relation (II) dismissed. Consideration of dic-
tionary meaning (III) postponed. Connotation (IV) and Denota-
tion as logical artifacts ; Johnson, Russell, Mill, 187. Essences
(V) as connotations hypostatized, 188. Meaning as projected
activity (VI) a metaphor, Schiller. Meaning as intention (VII)
analysed ; Joseph, Gardiner, 191. Complications due to mis-
direction, 194. Affective-volitional aspects, 195. Meaning as
place in a system (VIII), 196. A vague usage. This sometimes
narrowed down to meaning as practical consequences (IX),
197. William James and the pragmatists. Or to meaning as
what is implied (X). Meaning as emotional accompaniments
(XI), 198. Urban, 199.
CHAPTER X
SYMBOL SITUATIONS
TAGS
SUMMARY . • . 243
APPENDICES—
A. On Grammar t
. . 251
B. On Contexts . . . 263
C. Aenesidemus' Theory of Signs . . 266
D. Some Moderns—
1. Husserl . . 268 4. Gomperz . 274
2. Russell . , 273 5. Baldwin . 277
3. Frege . . 273 6. Peirce . 279
E. On Negative Facts . . . 291
xxii CONTENTS
SUPPLEMENTS
PAGE
I. The Problem of Meaning in Primitive Languages, by
B. MALINOWSKI, Ph.D., D . S c , Reader in Social
Anthropology, London School of Economics . . 296
II. The Importance of a Theory of Signs and a Critique of
Language in the Study of Medicine, by F. G.
CROOKSHANK, M.D., F.R.C.P 337
I N D E X OF SUBJECTS . 357
I N D E X OF NAMES . . . . .361
THE MEANING OF MEANING
"All life comes back to the question of our speech—the medium
through which we communicate." — H E N R Y JAMES.
' Error is never so difficult to be destroyed as when it has its root
in Language." —BENTHAM.
" We have to make use of language, which is made up necessarily
of preconceived ideas. Such ideas unconsciously held are the most
dangerous of all." —POINCARE\
" By the grammatical structure of a group of languages every-
thing runs smoothly for one kind of philosophical system, whereas
the way is as it were barred for certain other possibilities "
—NIETZSCHE,
" An Englishman, a Frenchman, a German, and an Italian
cannot by any means bring themselves to think quite alike, at least
on subjects that involve any depth of sentiment : they have not the
verbal means" —Prof. J. S. MACKENZIE.
" In Primitive Thought the name and object named are associated
in such wise that the one is regarded as a part of the other. The
imperfect separation of words from things characterizes Greek
speculation in general." — H E R B E R T SPENCER.
" The tendency has always been strong to believe that whatever
receives a name must be an entity or being, having an independent
existence of its own : and if no real entity answering to the name
could be found, men did not for that reason suppose that none
existed, but imagined that it was something peculiarly abstruse and
mysterious, too high to be an object of sense " —J. S. MILL.
" Nothing is more usual than for philosophers to encroach on
the province of grammarians, and to engage in disputes of words,
while they imagine they are handling controversies of the deepest
importance and concern" —HUME,,
" Men content themselves with the same words as other people
use, as if the very sound necessarily carried the same meaning."
—LOCKE.
" A verbal discussion may be important or unimportant, but it
is at least desirable to know that it is verbal."
—Sir G. CORNEWALL LEWIS.
T H O U G H T S , W O R D S A N D THINGS
Let us get nearer to the fire, so that we can see What we are saying.
—The Bubis of Fernando Po.
fff/
\
1
Whether symbols in some form or other are necessary to thought
itself is a difficult problem, and is discussed in The Meaning of Psychology
(Chapter XIII.) as well as in Chapter X. of the present work. But
certainly the recording and the communication of thought (telepathy
apart) require symbols. It seems that thought, so far as it is transitive
and not in the form of an internal dialogue, can dispense with symbols,
and that they only appear when thought takes on this monologue form.
In the normal case the actual development of thought is very closely
bound up with the symbolization which accompanies it.
THOUGHTS, WORDS AND THINGS 15
instinctive belief being given from many sources. The
fundamental and most prolific fallacy is, in other words,
that the base of the triangle given above is filled in.
The completeness of any reference varies; it is more
or less close and clear, it i grasps ' its object in greater
or less degree. Such symbolization as accompanies
it—images of all sorts, words, sentences whole and in
pieces—is in no very close observable connection with
the variation in the perfection of the reference. Since,
then, in any discussion we cannot immediately settle
from the nature of a person's remarks what his opinion
is, we need some technique to keep the parties to an
argument in contact and to clear up misunderstandings
—or, in other words, a Theory of Definition. Such a
technique can only be provided by a theory of knowing,
or of reference, which will avoid, as current theories do
not, the attribution to the knower of powers which it
may be pleasant for him to suppose himself to possess,
but which are not open to the only kind of investigation
hitherto profitably pursued, the kind generally known
as scientific investigation.
Normally, whenever we hear anything said we
spring spontaneously to an immediate conclusion,
namely, that the speaker is referring to what we should
be referring to were we speaking the words ourselves.
In some cases this interpretation may be correct; this
will prove to be what he has referred to. But in most
discussions which attempt greater subtleties than could
be handled in a gesture language this will not be so.
To suppose otherwise is to neglect our subsidiary
gesture languages, whose accuracy within their own
limited provinces is far higher than that yet reached
by any system of spoken or written symbols, with the
exception of the quite special and peculiar case of
mathematical, scientific and musical notations. Words,
whenever they cannot directly ally themselves with and
support themselves upon gestures, are at present a very
imperfect means of communication. Even for private
16 THE MEANING OF MEANING
thinking thought is often ready to advance, and only
held back by the treachery of its natural symbolism ;
and for conversational purposes the latitude acquired
constantly shows itself to all those who make any
serious attempts to compare opinions.
W e have not here in view the more familiar ways
in which words may be used to deceive. In a later
chapter, when the function of language as an instru-
ment for the promotion of purposes rather than as a
means of symbolizing references is fully discussed, we
shall see how the intention of the speaker may com-
plicate the situation. But the honnete homme may be
unprepared for the lengths to which verbal ingenuity
can be carried. At all times these possibilities have
been exploited to the full by interpreters of Holy Writ
who desire to enjoy the best of both worlds. Here,
for example, is a specimen of the exegetic of the late
Dr Lyman Abbott, pastor, publicist, and editor, which,
through the efforts of Mr Upton Sinclair, has now
become classic. Does Christianity condemn the
methods of twentieth-century finance? Doubtless there
are some awkward words in the Gospels, but a little
1
interpretation ' is all that is necessary.
" Jesus did not say ' Lay not up for yourselves treasures upon
earth.' He said ' Lay not up for yourselves treasures upon earth
where moth and rust doth corrupt and where thieves break through
and steal.' And no sensible American does. Moth and rust do
not get at Mr Rockefeller's oil wells, and thieves do not often
break through and steal a railway. What Jesus condemned was
hoarding wealth."
1
Westermarck, The Origin and Development of Moral Ideas, Vol. II.,
p. 100.
2
3
Alagona, Compendium Manualis D. Navarri XII., 88, p. 94.
4
Alfonso di Liguori, Theologia Moralis, III., 151, Vol. I., p. 249.
Meyrick, Moral and Devotional Theology of the Church of Rome,
Vol.
6
I., p 3. Cf. further Westermarck, loc. cit.
Soldier's Pocket Book for Field Service, p. 69.
18 THE MEANING OF MEANING
The Greeks, as we shall see, were in many ways
not far from the attitude of primitive man towards
words. And it is not surprising to read that after the
Peloponnesian war the verbal machinery of peace had
got completely out of gear, and, says Thucydides,
could not be brought back into use—"The meaning
of words had no longer the same relation to things,
but was changed by men as they thought proper."
The Greeks were powerless to cope with such a situation.
W e in our wisdom seem to have created institutions
which render us more powerless still.1
On a less gigantic scale the technique of deliberate
misdirection can profitably be studied with a view to
corrective measures. In accounting for Newman's
Grammar of Assent Dr E. A. Abbott had occasion to
describe the process of i lubrication,' the art of greas-
ing the descent from the premises to the conclusion,
which his namesake cited above so aptly employs.
In order to lubricate well, various qualifications are
necessary :
" First a nice discrimination of words, enabling you to form,
easily and naturally, a great number of finely graduated pro-
positions, shading away, as it were, from the assertion • x is white '
to the assertion ' x is black.' Secondly an inward and absolute
contempt for logic and for words. . . . And what are words but
toys and sweetmeats for grown-up babies who call themselves
men?"*
But even where the actual referents are not in doubt*
it is perhaps hardly realized how widespread is the
1
As the late C. E. Montague (Disenchantment, p. 101) well put it,
" the only new thing about deception in war is modern man's more
perfect means for its practice. The thing has become, in his hand,
a trumpet more efficacious than Gideon's own. . . . To match the
Lewis gun with which he now fires his solids, he has to his hand the
newspaper Press, to let fiy at the enemy's head the thing which is not."
But this was a temporary use of the modern technique of misdirection,
and with the return of peace the habit is lost ? Not so, says Mr
Montague. " Any weapon you use in a war leaves some bill to be
settled in peace, and the Propaganda arm has its cost like another."
The return of the exploiters of the verbal machine.to their civil posts,
is a return in triumph, and its effects will be felt for many years in all
countries where the power of the word amongst the masses remains
paramount.
2
Philomythus, p. 214.
THOUGHTS, WORDS AND THINGS 19
habit of using the power of words not only for bona fide
communications, but also as a method of misdirection 5
and in the world as it is to-day the naive interpreter
is likely on many occasions to be seriously misled if
the existence of thisunpleasing trait—equally prevalent
amongst the classes and the masses without distinction
of race, creed, sex, or colour—is overlooked.
Throughout this work, however, we are treating of
bona fide communication only, except in so far as we
shall find it necessary in Chapter IX. to discuss that
derivate use of Meaning to which misdirection gives
rise. For the rest, the verbal treachery with which
we are concerned is only that involved by the use of
symbols as such. As we proceed to examine the
conditions of communication we shall see why any
symbolic apparatus which is in general use is liable to
incompleteness and defect.
But if our linguistic outfit is treacherous, it never-
theless is indispensable, nor would another complete
outfit necessarily improve matters, even if it were ten
times as complete. It is not always new words that
are needed, but a means of controlling them as symbols,
a means of readily discovering to what in the world
on any occasion they are used to refer, and this is what
an adequate theory of definition should provide.
But a theory of Definition must follow, not precede,
a theory of Signs, and it is little realized how large a
place is taken both in abstract thought and in practical
affairs by sign-situations. But if an account of sign-
situations is to be scientific it must take its observations
from the most suitable instances, and must not derive
its general principles from an exceptional case. The
person actually interpreting a sign is not well placed
for observing what is happening: We should develop
our theory of signs from observations of other people,
and only admit evidence drawn from introspection when
we know how to appraise it. The adoption of the
other method, on the ground that all our knowledge of
20 THE MEANING OF MEANING
others is inferred from knowledge of our own states,
can only lead to the impasse of solipsism from which
modern speculation has yet to recoil. Those who allow
beyond question that there are people like themselves
also interpreting signs and open to study should not
find it difficult to admit that their observation of the
behaviour of others may provide at least a framework
within which their own introspection, that special and
deceptive case, may be fitted. That this is the practice
of all the sciences need hardly be pointed out. Any
sensible doctor when stricken by disease distrusts his
own introspective diagnosis and calls in a colleague.
There are, indeed, good reasons why what is
happening in ourselves should be partially hidden
from us, and we are generally better Judges of what
other people are doing than of what we are doing
ourselves. Before we looked carefully into other
people's heads it was commonly believed that an
entity called the soul resided therein, just as children
commonly believe that there is a little man inside the
skull who looks out at the eyes, the windows of the
soul, and listens at the ears. The child has the
strongest introspective evidence for this belief, which,
but for scalpels and microscopes, it would be difficult
to disturb. The tacitly solipsistic presumption that
this naive approach is in some way a necessity of
method disqualifies the majority of philosophical and
psychological discussions of Interpretation. If we
restrict the subject-matter of the inquiry to i ideas 9
and words, /.*., to the left side of our triangle, and
omit all frank recognition of the world outside us, we
inevitably introduce confusion on such subjects as
knowledge in perception, verification and Meaning
itself.1
1
This tendency is particularly noticeable in such works as Baldwin's
elaborate treatise on Thoughts and Things, where a psychological
apparatus of ' controls' and ' contents' is hard to reconcile with
the subsequent claim to discuss communication. The twist given to
grammatical analysis by Aristotle's similar neglect of Reference is
dealt with in Appendix A.
THOUGHTS, WORDS AND THINGS 21
If we stand in the neighbourhood of a cross road
and observe a pedestrian confronted by a notice To
Grantchester displayed on a post, we commonly dis-
tinguish three important factors in the situation. There
is, we are sure, (1) a Sign which (2) refers to a Place
and (3) is being interpreted by a person. All situations in
which Signs are considered are similar to this. A doctor
noting that his patient has a temperature and so forth
is said to diagnose his disease as influenza. If we talk
like this we do not make it clear that signs are here
also involved. Even when we speak of symptoms we
often do not think of these as closely related to other
groups of signs. But if we say that the doctor
interprets the temperature, etc., as a Sign of influenza,
we are at any rate on the way to an inquiry as to
whether there is anything in common between the
manner in which the pedestrian treated the object at
the cross road and that in which the doctor treated
his thermometer and the flushed countenance.
On close examination it will be found that very
many situations which we do not ordinarily regard as
Sign-situations are essentially of the same nature. The
chemist dips litmus paper in his test-tube, and interprets
the sign red or the sign blue as meaning acid or base.
A Hebrew prophet notes a small black cloud, and
remarks u W e shall have rain." Lessing scrutinizes
the Laocoon, and concludes that the features of Lao-
coon pere are in repose. A New Zealand school-girl
looks at certain letters on a page in her Historical
Manual for the use of Lower Grades and knows that
Queen Anne is dead.
The method which recognizes the common feature
of sign-interpretation 1 has its dangers, but opens the
1
In all these cases a sign has been interpreted rightly or wrongly,
i.e., something has been not only experienced or enjoyed, but under-
stood as referring to something else. Anything which can be experi-
enced can also be thus understood, i.e., can also be a sign ; and it is
important to remember that interpretation, or what happens to (or
in the mind of) an Interpreter is quite distinct both from the sign
and from that for which the sign stands or to which it refers. If then
22 THE MEANING OF MEANING
way to a fresh treatment of many widely different
topics.
As an instance of an occasion in which the theory
of signs is of special use, the subject dealt with in our
fourth chapter may be cited. If we realize that in all
perception, as distinguished from mere awareness, sign-
situations are involved, we shall have a new method
of approaching problems where a verbal deadlock seems
to have arisen. Whenever, we iperceive' Vhat we
name 'a chair,' we are interpreting a certain group
of data (modifications of the sense-organs), and treating
them as signs of a referent. Similarly, even before the
interpretation of a word, there is the almost automatic
interpretation of a group of successive noises or letters
as a word. And in addition to the external world we
can also explore with a new technique the sign-situations
involved by mental events, the ' goings o n ' or pro-
cesses of interpretation themselves. W e need neither
confine ourselves to arbitrary generalizations from intro-
spection after the manner of classical psychology, nor
deny the existence of images and other ' mental' occur-
rences to their signs with the extreme Behaviorists.1
The Double language hypothesis, which is suggested
by the theory of signs and supported by linguistic
analysis, would absolve Dr Watson and his followers
we speak of the meaning of a sign we must not, as philosophers,
psychologists and logicians are wont to do, confuse the (imputed)
relation between a sign and that to which it refers, either with the
referent (what is referred to) or with the process of interpretation (the
' goings on ' in the mind of the interpreter). It is this sort of confusion
which has made so much previous work on the subject of signs and
their meaning unfruitful. In particular, by using the same term
' meaning' both for the ' Goings on * inside their heads (the images,
associations, etc., which enabled them to interpret signs) and for
the Referents (the things to which the signs refer) philosophers have
been forced to locate Grantchester, Influenza, Queen Anne, and indeed
the whole Universe equally inside their fheads—or, if alarmed by the
prospect of cerebral congestion, at least in their minds ' in such wise
that all these objects become conveniently ' mental.' Great care,
therefore, is required in the use of the term ' meaning,' since its associa-
tions are dangerous.
1
That the mind-body problem is due to a duplication of symbolic
machinery is maintained in Chapter IV., p. 81. Cf. also The Meaning
of Psychology, by C. K. Ogden (1926), Chapter II., where this view is
supported with reference to contemporary authorities who hold it.
THOUGHTS, WORDS AND THINGS 23
from the logical necessity of affecting general anaesthesia.
Images, etc., are often most useful signs of our present
and future behaviour—notably in the modern interpreta-
tion of dreams.1 An improved Behaviorism will have
much to say concerning the chaotic attempts at symbolic
interpretation and construction by which Psycho-analysts
discredit their valuable labours.
The problems which arise in connection with any
* sign-situation' are of the same general form. The
relations between the elements concerned are no doubt
different, but they are of the same sort. A thorough
classification of these problems in one field, such as the
field of symbols, may be expected, therefore, to throw
light upon analogous problems in fields at first sight
of a very different order.
When we consider the various kinds of Sign-situa-
tions instanced above, we find that those signs which
men use to communicate one with another and as
instruments of thought, occupy a peculiar place. It
is convenient to group these under a distinctive name ;
and for words, arrangements of words, images, gestures,
and such representations as drawings or mimetic sounds
we use the term symbols. The influence of Symbols
upon human life and thought in numberless unexpected
ways has never been fully recognized, and to this chapter
of history we now proceed.
1
In the terminology of the present work, many of the analyst's
' symbols ' are, of course, signs only ; they are not used for purposes
of communication. But in the literature of psycho-analysis there is
much valuable insistence on the need of wider forms of interpretation,
especially in relation to emotional overcharge. Cf., e.g.. the late
Dr Jelliffe's " The Symbol as an Energy Condenser" (Journal of
Nervous and Mental Diseases, December 1919), though the metaphor,
like many other psycho-analytic locutions, must not be stretched too far
in view of what has been said above and of what is to follow (cf. pages
102-3 and 200 infra).
CHAPTER II
T H E P O W E R OF W O R D S
Le mot, qu'on le sache, est un &tre vivant . . . le mot
est le verbe, et le verbe est Dieu,—Victor Hugo.
Athenians 1 I observe that in all respects you are
deeply reverential towards the Gods.—Paul of Tarsus.
He who shall duly consider these matters will find that
there is a certain bewitchery or fascination in words,
which makes them operate with a force beyond what
we can naturally give account of.—South.
1
F. M. Cornford, From Religion to Philosophy, p. 45.
2
J. A. Macculloch, The Childhood of Fiction, pp. 26-30, is the last
to collect the references to these, and to relate them, as did Mr Clodd
in his Tom-Tit-Tot, to the general practice of Verbal Magic.
T H E POWER OF WORDS 27
of power, for nomina as numina^ must have appeared
overwhelming.
In ancient Egypt precautions were taken to prevent
the extinction of the eighth or Name-soul, and to cause
its continuance along with the names of the Gods. 1 In
the Pyramid texts we find mentioned a God called
Khern, i.e., Word : the Word having a personality like
that of a human being. The Creation of the world
was due to the interpretation in words by Thoth of the
will of the deity. The greater part of mankind must
once have believed the name to be that integral part
of a man identified with the soul, or to be so important
a portion of him that it might be substituted for the
whole, as employers speak of factory i hands.' In
Revelation we read " There were killed in the earthquake
names of men seven thousand," and again in the letter
to the Church of Sardis, " Thou hast a few names in
Sardis which did not defile their garments." The
beast coming up out of the sea has upon his head
" names of blasphemy." Blasphemy itself is just such
an instance; for the god is supposed to be personally
offended by the desecration of his name : and even in
the reign of Henry V I I I . a boy was put to death by
burning because of some idle words he had chanced to
hear respecting the sacrament — which he ignorantly
repeated.*
" W h y askest thou after my name, seeing it is
secret" (or i ineffable' with Prof. G. F . Moore), says the
angel of the Lord to Manoah in the book of Judges.
Nearly all primitive peoples show great dislike to their
names being mentioned ; when a New Zealand chief
was called Wai, which means water, a new name had
to be given to water; and in Frazer's Golden Bough
numerous examples of word taboos are collected to
show the universality of the attitude. Not only chiefs
but gods, and moreover the priest in whom gods were
1
Budge, The Book of the Dead, pp. lxxxvi-xc.
2
Pike, History of Crime in England, Vol. II., p. 56.
28 THE MEANING OF MEANING
supposed to dwell (a belief which induced the Cantonese
to apply the term * god-boxes * to such favoured person-
ages), are amongst the victims of this logophobia.
W e know how Herodotus (II. 132, 171) refuses to
mention the name of Osiris. The true and great name
of Allah is a secret name,1 and similarly with the gods
of Brahmanism 2 and the real name of Confucius.3
Orthodox Jews apparently avoid the name Jahweh
altogether.4 We may compare i Thank Goodness'
1
Morbleu'—and the majority of euphemisms. Among
the Hindus if one child has been lost, it is customary
to call the next by some opprobrious name. A male
child is called Kuriya, or Dunghill—the spirit of
course knows folk as their names and will overlook the
worthless. Similarly, God knows each man by his
name—"and the Lord said unto Moses ' Thou hast
found grace in my sight and I know thee by thy name/ "
Every ancient Egyptian had two names—one for the
world, and another by which he was known to the
supernal powers. The Abyssinian Christian's second
name, given at baptism, is never to be divulged. The
guardian deity of Rome had an incommunicable name,
and in parte of ancient Greece the holy names of the
gods to ensure against profanation were engraved on
lead tablets and sunk in the sea.
Children are often similarly anxious to conceal their
names; and just as children always demand what the
name of a thing is (never if it has a name) and regard
that name as a valuable acquisition, so we know that
the stars all have names. " H e telleth the number of
the stars and calleth them all by their names." Here
we may note the delightful proverb which might appear
on the title-page of every work dealing with Symbolism:
" The Divine is rightly so called."
1
Sell, The Faith of Islam, p. 185.
2
Hopkins, Religions of India, p. 184.
3
Friend, Folk-Lore Record, IV., p. 76.
4
Herzog-Plitt, Real-Encyclopddie, VI., p. 501. Hence the name
Adonai, read instead of the ineffable Name; from which, by insertion
of the vowels of Adonai in the tetragrammaton. we got Jehovah.
THE POWER OF WORDS 29
In some ways the twentieth century suffers more
grievously than any previous age from the ravages of
such verbal superstitions. Owing, however, to develop-
ments in the methods of communication, and the creation
of many special symbolic systems, the form of the
disease has altered considerably; and, apart from the
peculiar survival of religious apologetic, now takes
more insidious forms than of yore. Influences making
for its wide diffusion are the baffling complexity of the
symbolic apparatus now at our disposal; the possession
by journalists and men of letters of an immense semi-
technical vocabulary and their lack of opportunity, or
unwillingness, to inquire into its proper use ; the success
of analytic thinkers in fields bordering on mathematics,
where the divorce between symbol and reality is most
pronounced and the tendency to hypostatization most
alluring; the extension of a knowledge of the cruder
forms of symbolic convention (the three R's), combined
with a widening of the gulf between the public and
the scientific thought of the age; and finally the ex-
ploitation, for political and commercial purposes, of
the printing press by the dissemination and reiteration
of cliches.
The persistence of the primitive linguistic outlook
not only throughout the whole religious world, but in
the work of the profoundest thinkers, is indeed one
of the most curious features of modern thought. The
philosophy of the nineteenth century was dominated
by an idealist tradition in which the elaboration of mon-
strous symbolic machinery (the Hegelian Dialectic 1
provides a striking example) was substituted for direct
research, and occupied the centre of attention. The
twentieth opened with a subtle analysis of the mysteries
of mathematics on the basis of a i Platonism' even
1
Jowett in comparing the Dialectic of Hegel with that of Plato
remarks: " Perhaps there is no greater defect in Hegel's system than
the want of a sound theory of language/'—The Dialogues of Plato,
Vol. IV., p. 420.
30 THE MEANING OF MEANING
more pronounced than that of certain Critical Realists
of 1921.1 Thus we read :—
" Whatever may be an object of thought, or may occur in any
true or false proposition, or can be accounted as one, I call a term.
. . . A man, a moment, a number, a class, a relation, a chimera,
or anything else that can be mentioned is sure to be a term; and
to deny that such and such a thing is a term must always be
false. . . . A term is possessed of all the properties commonly
assigned to substances or substantives. . . . Every term is im-
mutable and indestructible. What a term is it is, and no change
can be conceived in it which would not destroy its identity and
make it another term. . . . Among terms it is possible to dis-
tinguish two kinds, which I shall call respectively things and
concepts." 2
With the aid of this strange verbal rapier many
palpable hits were claimed. Thus the theory of
" adjectives or attributes or ideal things in some way
less substantial, less self subsistent, less self identical,
than true substantives, appears to be wholly erroneous " ;s
whole philosophical systems were excluded, for " t h e
admission (involved in the mention of a man and a
chimera) of many terms destroys monism" ; 4 and a
modern Platonism reconstructed, whereby a world of
certain of the ' things' i mentioned ' by means of s terms
the world of universals, was rehabilitated. Here the
reason builds a habitation, " o r rather finds a habitation
eternally standing, where our ideals are fully satisfied
and our best hopes are not thwarted. It is only when
we thoroughly understand the entire independence of
ourselves, which belongs to this world that reason finds,
that we can adequately realize the profound importance
of its beauty." 5 For here everything is "unchange-
able, rigid, exact, delightful to the mathematician, the
logician, the builder of metaphysical systems, and all
who love perfection more than life.'* This world was
commended to the working man, in contrast to the
1
2
Cf. Chapter VIII., pp. 164 fif.
3
B. Russell, The Principles of Mathematics (1903), Vol. I., pp. 43-44.
4
Ibid., p. 46.
B
Ibid., p. 44.
Mysticism and Logic (1918), p. 69.
THE POWER OF WORDS 31
world of existence which is "fleeting, vague, without
sharp boundaries, without any clear plan or arrange-
ment though it "contains all thoughts and feelings/'
Both worlds are equally there, equally worth con-
templation, and "according to our temperaments, we
shall prefer the contemplation of the one or of the
other." 1
It is regrettable that modern Platonists so seldom
follow Plato in his attempts at a scientific study of
Symbolism, but it is interesting to note that they
recognize the kinship of their theory with Greek
speculation, for both have their origin in the same
linguistic habits. The ingenuity of the modern logi-
cian tends to conceal the verbal foundations of his
structure, but in Greek philosophy these foundations
are clearly revealed. The earlier writers are full of
the relics of primitive word-magic. To classify things
is to name them, and for magic the name of a thing
or group of things is its soul; to know their names
is to have power over their souls. Nothing, whether
human or superhuman, is beyond the power of words.
Language itself is a duplicate, a shadow-soul, of the
whole structure of reality. Hence the doctrine of the
Logosy variously conceived as this supreme reality, the
divine soul-substance, as the ' Meaning' or reason of
everything, and as the ' Meaning' or essence of a name.1
The Greeks were clearly assisted in their acceptance
of an Otherworld of Being by the legacy of religious
material which earlier philosophers incorporated in
their respective systems. The nature of things, their
physisy was regarded, e.g., by Thales, as supersensible,
a stuff of that attenuated sort which has always been
attributed to souls and ghosts; differing from body
1
B. Russell, The Problems of Philosophy, Home University Library,
p. 156. That portions of this world, which Mr Russell would probably
recognize to-day as having a purely linguistic basis, still adhere to the
cosmos envisaged in his Analysts of Mind. 1921, is suggested at p. 54
infra. His latest admissions are to be found on page 688 of The Phil-
osophy
2
of Bertrand Russell (1944^ and page 34 of Polemic 2 (1946).
Cornford, op. cil., From Religion to Philosophy, pp. 141, 186, 248.
32 THE MEANING OF MEANING
only in being intangible and invisible. Consequently
the World of Being, in which bogus entities reside,
had at first that minimum of materiality without which
nothing could be conceived. But as logic developed
and the power of words attracted more attention, this
materiality was gradually lost, until in the Symposiums
211, and the Phaedo^ 80, Plato has evolved a realm of
pure ideality, also described as physis, in which these
name-souls dwell, pure, divine, immortal, intelligible,
uniform, indissoluble and unchangeable.
This development has been shown to be due largely
to the influence of Pythagoreanism and the intervening
stages are of peculiar interest for the history of Symbols,
It was Heracleitus who first appealed to words as
embodying the nature of things, and his influence on
Plato is manifest in the Cratylus. Heracleitus saw in
language the most constant thing in a world of cease-
less change, an expression of that common wisdom
which is in all men ; and for him the structure of human
speech reflects the structure of the world. It is an em-
bodiment of that structure—"the Logos is contained
and in it, as one meaning may be contained in many
outwardly different symbols." 1
The Pythagoreans on the other hand were chiefly
puzzled by number symbols. "Since everything
appeared to be modelled in its entire character on
numbers," says Aristotle,* "and numbers to be the
ultimate things in the whole universe, they became
convinced that the elements of numbers are the elements
of everything." In fact, in its final stages, Pytha-
goreanism passed from a doctrine of the world as a
procession of numbers out of the One, to the con-
struction of everything out of Number-souls, each
claiming an immortal and separate existence. 8
1
2
Cornford, op. cit.. p. 192.
3
Metaphysics., A. 5 ; trans. A. E. Taylor.
A record of Pythagoreanism and arithmosophy generally is pro-
vided by Dr R. Allendy in Le Symbolisme des Nombrest Essai d'Arith-
fyosophie, 1921. The author's object has been " to examine some
THE POWER OF WORDS 33
Parmenides, who followed, was occupied with the
functions of negative symbols. If * Cold' only means
the same as ' not hot/ and ' d a r k ' the same as * not
light,' how can we talk about absences of things?
" Two bodies there are,*' he says, u which mortals have
decided to name, one of which they ought not to name,
and that is where they have gone wrong." They have
given names to things which simply are not, to the
not-things (jmrj £6v). But in addition to the problem of
Negative Facts, which involved Plato in the first
serious examination of the relations of thought and
language [Sophist\ 261), Parmenides handed on to
Plato his own Orphic conundra about the One and
the Many, which also have their roots in language. So
that, quite apart from the difficulties raised by his Ideal
World where the Name-souls dwelt, and its relations
with the world of mud and blood (to which entities
on aesthetic grounds he hesitated to allow i ideas/
much as theologians debated the existence of souls in
darkies), Plato had every reason to be occupied by
linguistic theory.
It is, therefore, all the more unfortunate that the
dialogue, The Cratylus, in which his views on language
are set forth, should have been so neglected in modern
times* Plato's theory of Ideas or Name-souls was
accepted from the Pythagoreans ; but as a scientist he
was constantly approaching the problem of names and
their meaning as one of the most difficult inquiries which
could be encountered. His analysis, in an age when
comparative philology, grammar, and psychology were
all unknown, is a remarkable achievement, but he fails
to distinguish consistently between symbols and the
thought symbolized.
aspects of the numerical key under which the religious and occult
philosophy of all times and of all schools has veiled its teachings. . . .
From this standpoint the study of Numbers should constitute the
foundation of all Occultism, of all Theosophy.1' In the preposterous
medley which results, the curious will find ample evidence that numerical
magic has been hardly less prevalent than the magic of words.
34 THE MEANING OF MEANING
The main tradition of Greek speculation remained
faithful to the verbal approach. There are two ways,
wrote Dr Whewell, of comprehending nature, " t h e
one by examining the words only and the thoughts
which they call u p ; the other by attending to the facts
and things which bring these notions into,being. . . .
The Greeks followed the former, the verbal or notional
course, and railed." And again, " T h e propensity to
seek for principles in the common usages of language
may be discovered at a very early period. . . . In
Aristotle we have the consummation of this mode of
speculation." l It has been generally accepted since
the time of Trendelenburg 2 that the Categories, and
similar distinctions which play a large part in Aristotle's
system, cannot be studied apart from the peculiarities
of the Greek language. "Aristotle," says Gomperz,
"often suffers himself to be led by the forms of
language, not always from inability to free himself from
those bonds, but at least as often because the demands
of dialectic will not allow him to quit his arena. . . .
Thus a distinction is drawn between knowledge in
general and the particular sciences, based solely on the
fact that the objects of the latter are included in their
names. . . . His classification of the categories is
frequently governed by considerations of linguistic
expediency, a circumstance which, it must be allowed
(sic), ought to have restrained him from applying it to
ontological purposes." 3
The practice of dialectical disputation in Aristotle's
time was based on the notion of a definite simple
meaning for every term, as we see from the Scholia of
Ammonius to the De Interpretations Thus the ques-
1
History of the Inductive Sciences, L, pp. 27, 29.
2
Kategorienlehre, p. 209. where it is contended that linguistic con-
siderations " guided, but did not decide " the classification. Already
in the first century A.D. various peripatetic eclectics had maintained
that the categories were entirely concerned with words, though as Dr
P. Rotta suggests (La Filosofia del Linguaggio nella Pattistica e nella
Scholastica, p. 56), this is, perhaps, rather from the angle of the
nominalist-realist
3
controversy.
T. Gomperz, Greek Thinkers, IV., pp. 40-41.
THE POWER OF WORDS 35
tioner asked, " Is Rhetoric estimable?"; and in one
form of the game, at any rate, the respondent was
expected to answer simply Yes or No. Certain words
were regarded as equivocal, chiefly as a result of
studying their 'contraries,' in the current vocabulary.
Aristotle enumerates various rules with regard to equivo-
cation and other devices conceived with the object of
driving an opponent into some form of verbal incon-
sistency, in his Topics.
Mauthner, after a detailed argument to show that
the Aristotelian docrines of the Negative and the Cate-
gories "made the extant forms of speech the objects
of a superstitious cult, as though they had been actual
deities," remarks that "Aristotle is dead because he
was, more than perhaps any other notable writer in
the whole history of Philosophy, superstitiously devoted
to words. Even in his logic he is absolutely dependent
on the accidents of language, on the accidents of his
mother-tongue. His superstitious reverence for words
was never out of season." l And again :—
"For full two thousand years human thought
has lain under the influence of this man's catchwords,
an influence which has been wholly pernicious in
its results. There is no parallel instance of the
enduring potency of a system of words." 2
It is curious that in the De Interpretatione Aristotle
puts forward views which are hard to reconcile with
such a verbal approach. He there insists that words
are signs primarily of mental affections, and only
secondarily of the things of which these are likenesses. 8
1
Mauthner, Aristotle, English Translation, pp. 84, 103-4. Cf. t n e
same author's Kritik der Sprache> Vol. III., p. 4, " If Aristotle had
spoken Chinese or Dacotan, he would have had to adopt an entirely
different
2
Logic, or at any rate an entirely different theory of Categories."
Ibid... p. 19. See also Appendix A for a discussion of the influence
of 8Aristotle on Grammar.
De Interpretatione, 16, a. 3. It is worth noting that Andronicus of
Rhodes, who edited the first complete edition of Aristotle's works when
the Library of Theophrastus was brought to Rome from Athens as part
of Sulla's loot, marked this treatise as spurious. Maier's arguments in
iis favour have, however, persuaded scholars to accept it as Aristotelian.
36 THE MEANING OF MEANING
And he elaborates a theory of the proposition which,
though incomplete and a source of endless confusion,
yet indicates a far more critical attitude to language
than his logical apparatus as a whole would suggest.
For here Aristotle finds no difficulty in settling the
main question raised by Plato in the Cratylus. All
significant speech, he says, is significant by convention
only, and not by nature or as a natural instrument—
thereby neglecting Plato's acute observations as to the
part played by onomatopoeia in verbal origins. In the
De Interpretatione various branches of significant speech
are deliberately excluded, and we are there invited to
consider only that variety known as enunciative^ which,
as declaring truth or falsehood, is all that belongs to
Logic ; other modes of speech, the precative, imperative,
interrogative, etc., being more naturally regarded as
part of Rhetoric or Poetic. 1
That verbal superstition would play a large part
in Greek philosophy might have been expected from
the evidence of Greek literature as a whole; and
Farrar finds it necessary to suppose that ^Eschylus
and Sophocles, for example, must have believed in
Onomancy, which, as we shall see, is always bound up
with primitive word-magic. Even the practical Romans,
as he goes on to show, were the victims of such beliefs ;
and would all have echoed the language of Ausonius :—
N a m divinare est nomen componere, quod sit Fortunae,
morum, vel necis indicium.
1
In the Poetics (1456 b. Margoliouth, p. 198) Aristotle again alludes
to " the operations of which Speech is the instrument, of which the
Divisions are demonstration and refutation, the arousing of emotions,
such as pity, fear, anger, etc., exaggeration and depreciation." In
commenting on the enunciative or ' apophantic' use of language
(D. I. 17 a. 2), Ammonius refers to a passage in one of the lost works
of Theophrastus, where ' apophantic ' language, which is concerned
with things, is distinguished from other varieties of language, which
are concerned with the effect on the hearer and vary with the individuals
addressed. These different kinds of propositions, five in number
according to the later Peripatetics, were further elaborated by the Stoics.
Cf. Prantl (Geschichte der Logik, Vol. I., p. 441), Steinthal (Geschichte
der Sprachwissenschaft bei den Griechen und Romem, Vol. I., p. 317),
H. Maier, Psychologic des Emotionalen Denkens, pp. 9-10.
THE POWER OF WORDS 37
In their levies, Cicero informs us, they took care
l<
to enrol first such names as Victor, and Felix, and
Faustus, and Secundus ; and were anxious to head the
roll of the census with a word of such happy augury
as Salvius Valerius. Caesar gave a command in Spain
to an obscure Scipio simply for the sake of the omen
which his name involved. Scipio upbraids his mutinous
soldiers with having followed an Atrius Umber, a i dux
abominandi nominis/ being, as De Quincey calls him,
a 'pleonasm of darkness.' The Emperor Severus
consoled himself for the immoralities of his Empress
Julia, because she bore the same name as the profligate
daughter of Augustus " ; x just as Adrian VI., when he
became Pope, was persuaded by his Cardinals not to
retain his own name, on the ground that all Popes who
had done so had died in the first year of their reign.2
When we reflect on the influences which might have
concentrated the attention of Graeco-Roman thinkers
on linguistic problems, it is at first sight surprising
that many of those whose constructions were so largely
verbal were also in certain respects fully aware of the
misleading character of their medium. The appeal of
the Heracliteans to language as evidence for the doctrine
of Change was, as we know from the Cratylus, vigorously
opposed by the Parmenidean logicians, as well as by
believers in the Ideas. And an equal readiness to
admit that the presuppositions of Language have to be
combated was manifested by Plotinus. Language, in
the Neo-Platonic view, "can only be made to express
the nature of the soul by constraining it to purposes
for which most men never even think of employing
it"; moreover, "the soul cannot be described at all
except by phrases which would be nonsensical if applied
to body or its qualities, or to determinations of
particular bodies." 8
1
2
F. W. Farrar, Language and Languages, pp. 235-6.
3
Mervoyer, Etude sur.I'association des idies, p. 376.
Whittaker, The Neo-Platonists, p. 42.
38 T H E MEANING OF MEANING
The rejection of misleading forms of language was
carried still further by Buddhist writers in their treatment
of the 'soul.' Whether it was called satta (being), attd
(self), jiva (living principle), or pugg&la (person) did
not matter:
" For these are merely names, expressions, turns
of speech, designations in common use in the world.
Of these he who has won truth makes use indeed,
but he is not led astray by t h e m . " 1
The Buddhists, whose attitude towards language
was exceptional, Were quite ready to make use of
customary phrases for popular exposition, but it is not clear
whether any more subtle approach to fictional problems had
been developed.2
But though all the post-Aristotelian schools, and
particularly the Stoics, whose view of language had
considerable influence on Roman jurists, 3 devoted some
attention to linguistic theory, nowhere in ancient times
do we find evidence of these admissions leading to a
study of symbols such as Plato and Aristotle seemed
at times to be approaching. As we shall see, this was
owing to the lack of any attempt to deal with signs as
such, and so to understand the functions of words in
relation to the more general sign-situations on which
all thought depends. Yet just before the critical spirit
was finally stamped out by Christianity, notable dis-
cussions had taken place in the Graeco-Roman world,
and the central problem was being examined with an
acuity which might have led to really scientific develop-
ments. The religious leaders were aware of the danger,
1
Digha N. I. 263 ; cf. C. A. F. Rhys Davids, Buddhist Psychology,
P- 232.
For an elaborate study of Eastern schools of thought and their
behaviour
3
with words, see op. cit., Word Magic, by C. K. Ogden.
Lersch, Die Sprachphilosophie der Alien, Vol. III., pp. 184-6.
Aelius Gallus is cited for the definition of flumen as " aquam ipsam,
quae fluit " ; and, according to Gellius, Antistius Labeo was profoundly
interested in Grammar and Dialectic,- " Latinarumque vocum origines
rationesque percalluerat, eaque praecipue scientia ad enodandos
plerosque iuris laqueos utebatur."
THE POWER OF WORDS 39
and there is even a passage in St Gregory of Nazian-
zus, where trouble is complained of, since "the Sexti
and Pyrrhoneans and the spirit of contradiction were
perniciously intruded into our churches like some evil
and malignant plague." 1 In fact the whole theory of
signs was examined both by Aenesidemus, the reviver
of Pyrrhonism in Alexandria, and by a Greek doctor
named Sextus between 100 and 250 A.D. The analysis
offered is more fundamental than anything which made
its appearance until the nineteenth century.2
This brief survey of the Graeco-Roman approach to
language must suffice to represent pre-scientific specula-
tion upon the subject. Moreover, it has had a greater
influence on modern European thought than the even
more luxuriant growth of oriental theories. The atmo-
sphere of verbalism in which most Indian philosophy
developed seems to have been even more dense than
that of the scholastics or of the Greek dialecticians.
In this respect the Mimamsa-Nyaya controversy, the
Yoga philosophy, the Vijnanavada categories, the Prab-
hakara Mlmamsakas8 are hardly less remarkable than
the doctrine of the Sacred Word AUM and the verbal
ecstasies of the Sufi mystics, 4 a part of whose technique
was revived by Dr Coue.
The history of spells, verbal magic and verbal
medicine, whether as practised by the Trobriand
magician, 6 by the Egyptian priest of the Pyramid
texts, or by the modern metaphysician, is a subject in
1
Cf. N. Maccoll, The Greek Sceptics (p. 108), where it is noted that
thirteen centuries later, when authority was once again challenged,
the remains of these thinkers at once attracted attention. Foucher
wrote a history of the New Academy and Sorbiere translated the
Hypotheses
2
of Sextus.
See R. D. Hicks, Stoic and Epicurean, p. 390 ff,, on Aenesidemus;
and3
infra, Appendix C.
Keith, Indian Logic, Chapter V. ; Dasgupta, History of Indian
Philosophy, Vol. I., pp. 148-9, 345-54; Rama Prasad, Self-culture
or the Yoga of Patdnjali, pp. 88, 148, 152, 156, 215 ; Vedanta Sutras,
Sacred
4
Books of the East, Vol. XLVIIL, p. 148.
The Science of the Sacred Word (translated by Bhagavan Das) ;
R. A. Nicholson, Studies in Islamic Mysticism, pp. 6-9.
6
Malinowski, Argonauts of the Western Pacific, pp. 408-10.
40 THE MEANING OF MEANING
itself and is dealt with at length in Word Magicy which
is designed as an expansion of the present chapter.
The extent to which primitive attitudes towards
words are still exploited by the astute is fully revealed
only when the achievements of some cynical rhetorician
are accorded the limelight of the law courts, or when
some particularly glaring absurdity is substituted for
the more patient methods of suggestion favoured by
repetitive journalism. But these same attitudes are
universal in childhood, and are so strengthened by the
prevailing verbalism that even the most accurate
scientific training has often done little to render the
adult less subservient to his medium. Indeed, as we
have seen, the ablest logicians are precisely those who
are led to evolve the most fantastic systems by the aid
of their verbal technique. The modern logician may,
in time to come, be regarded as the true mystic, when
the rational basis of the world in which he believes is
scientifically examined.
Turning then to the more emotional aspects of
modern thought, we shall not be surprised to find a
veritable orgy of verbomania. The process whereby
the purely verbal systems so characteristic of pistic
speculation have attained such formidable dimensions,
has recently been examined by Rignano. 1 Attributes
found by experience to be contradictory are gradually
dematenalized, and in their place are put " verbal
envelopes, void of all intelligible content, so as to
eliminate the reciprocal contradiction and inhibition to
which these attributes would inevitably give rise if they
were allowed to furnish matter for the imagination in
however small a degree"; and parallel with this de-
materialization, a formidable dialectic edifice such as
that of scholasticism is constructed, with the object of
convincing human reason of the absence of logical
inconsistency in the greatest of absurdities.2
1
The Psychology of Reasoning, Chap. XI.. on Metaphysical Reasoning.
* Cf. Guignebert, " Le dogme de la TriniteV' Scientia, Nos. 32, 33,
37 (1919-14).
THE POWER OF WORDS 41
In this way the idea of Divinity, for example, has
been slowly reduced to a " conglomerate of attributes,
purely, or almost purely verbal." So that finally, as
William James puts it, "the ensemble of the meta-
physical attributes imagined by the theologian " (God
being First Cause, possesses an existence a se; he is
necessary and absolute, absolutely unlimited, infinitely
perfect; he is One and only, Spiritual, metaphysically
simple, immutable, eternal, omnipotent, omniscient, omni-
present, etc.) "is but a shuffling and matching of
pedantic dictionary adjectives. One feels that in
the theologians' hands they are only a set of titles
obtained by a mechanical manipulation of synonyms ;
verbality has stepped into the place of vision,
professionalism into that of life." 1
Similarly, in reasoning commonly spoken of as
metaphysical, language has chiefly the function of
furnishing " a stable verbal support, so that inexact,
nebulous, and fluctuating concepts may be recalled to
the mind whenever required, without any prejudice to
the elasticity of the concepts " ; for which purpose the
phraseology adopted is "as vaporous and mysterious
as possible. Hence the so-called terms 'written in
profundity,' referred to by Ribot, and dear to all
metaphysicians, just because they are so admirably
suited both to contain everything that it is desired to
have them include, and to conceal the contradictions
and absurdities of the doctrines based on the concepts
in question. . . . The function of the verbal symbol
is therefore to keep inconsistent attributes forcibly
united, though all of them could not possibly be
present to the mind at the same moment just because
they inhibit each other; it being important that the
metaphysician should have them at his disposal in
order to deduct from the concept, from their aggre-
gate, sometimes one set of conclusions and some-
1
W. James, The Varieties of Religious Experience, pp, 439-46.
42 THE MEANING OF MEANING
times another, according to the presentation of reality
desired.'*
Ultimately the word completely takes the place of
the thought—Denn eben wo BegrifFe fehlen, da stellt
ein Wort zur rechten Zeit sich ein, as Mephistopheles
remarked. And Rignano aptly likens the process to
the shedding of the carapace by a crustacean. " Without
this verbal carapace the disappearance of all intellectual
content would involve the disappearance of all trace
of the past existence of such content. But the carapace
preserves something which, just because it proves the
past existence of a concept which formerly had a real
life, may quite well be taken for one still existing. So
that this something, although devoid of all intellectual
content, always constitutes a valuable point of attach-
ment and support for the corresponding emotion, which
is so intense that it does not perceive that the cherished
resemblances no longer clothe the beloved object." 1
But the carapace, the verbal husk, is not merely a
valedictory point (Tappui; it also has a certain bombic
capacity, an ' affective resonance' which enables the
manipulator of symbols such as the Absolute to assure
himself that his labours are not altogether vain.
44
When language is once grown familiar," says
Berkeley, "the hearing of the sounds or sight of the
characters is often immediately attended with those
passions which at first were wont to be produced by
the intervention of ideas that are now quite omitted." 2
From the symbolic use of words we thus pass to the
emotive; and with regard to words so used, as in
poetry, Ribot has well remarked that "they no longer
act as signs but as sounds ; they are musical notations
at the service of an emotional psychology." 8 So that
though at this extreme limit "metaphysical reasoning
1
Rignano, op. cit.t Chap. XI.
2
Treatise, Introduction, § 20.
8
La Logique des Sentiments, p. 187. Cf. Erdmann, op, cit., p. 120,
where the methods of kindling " das Strohfeuer einer wohlfeilen und
gedankenlosen Begeisterung " are considered.
T H E POWER OF WORDS 43
may be intellectually quite incomprehensible; though,
that is to say, it may actually become * vocem proferre
et nihil concipere/ it acquires by way of compensation,"
as Rignano says, "an emotive signification which is
peculiar to it, i.e., it is transformed into a kind of
musical language stimulative of sentiments and emo-
tions. " Its success is due entirely to the harmonious
series of emotional echoes with which the naive mind
responds—et reboat regio cita barbara bombum.
In practical affairs these influences are no less
potent and far more disastrous. W e need only instance
the contention of the late Dr. Crookshank, supported by
an abundance of detailed evidence, that " under the
influence of certain schools of thought, and certain
habits of expression, we have become accustomed to
speak and write as if a disease were a natural object" ;
that these disastrous verbal habits must be resisted, for
" no great advance is probable in the domain of
Medicine until the belief in the real existence of diseases
is abandoned " ; and that the linguistic problem must
be faced at once, for " no measure of useful agreement
will be achieved unless we are first in accord concerning
the principles of method and thought." 1 Coming from
one with thirty years' experience of the healing art, so
striking a confirmation of the views we have been
advancing cannot be lightly rejected; and on another
page Dr Crookshank himself gives further reasons for
considering that its rejection could only be based on
a failure to appreciate the facts.2
SIGN-SITUATIONS
Studiufn linguarum in universis, in ipsis primor-
diis triste est et ingratuin; sed primis diflicultatibus
labore improbo et ardore nobili perruptis, postea
cumulatissime beamur.—Valcknaer.
1
2
D. Hartley, Observations on Man, Prop. X.
3
G. C. Lange, Apperception, Part I, §§ i, 2.
4
I. Miller, The Psychology of Thinking, p. 154.
C. Lloyd Morgan, Instinct and Experience, p. 194.
52 THE MEANING OF MEANING
and deals merely with observable correlations or con-
textual uniformities among events.
The effects upon the organism due to any sign,
which may be any stimulus from without, or any process
taking place within, depend upon the past history of
the organism, both generally and in a more precise
fashion. In a sense, no doubt, the whole past history
is relevant: but there will be some among the past
events in that history which more directly determine
the nature of the present agitation than others. Thus
when we strike a match, the movements we make and
the sound of the scrape are present stimuli. But the
excitation which results is different from what it would
be had we never struck matches before. Past strikings
have left, in our organization, engrams, 1 residual traces,
which help to determine what the mental process will be.
For instance, this mental process is among other things
an awareness that we are striking a match. Apart from
the effects of similar previous situations we should have
no such awareness. Suppose further that the aware-
ness is accompanied by an expectation of a flame.
This expectation again will be due to the effects of
situations in which the striking of a match has been
followed by a flame. The expectation is the excitation
of part of an engram complex, which is called up by
a stimulus (the scrape) similar to a part only of the
original stimulus-situation,
A further example will serve to make this clearer.
The most celebrated of all caterpillars, whose history
is in part recorded in the late Professor Lloyd Morgan's
Habit and Instinct^ p. 4 1 , was striped yellow and black and
was seized by one of the professor's chickens. Being
offensive in taste to the chicken he was rejected. Thence-
forth the chicken refrained from seizing similar cater-
pillars. W h y ? Because the sight of such a cater-
1
Semon's terminology : Die Mneme, particularly Part II. (English
translation, p. 138 n\). For a critique of Semon's theory, see op. cit.,
Principles of Literary Criticism, Chapter XIV., and op. cit., The Meaning
of Psychology, Chapter IV.
SIGN-SITUATIONS 53
pillar, a part that is of the whole sight-seize-taste
context of the original experience, now excites the
chicken in a way sufficiently 1 like that in which the
whole context did, for the seizing at least not to occur,
whether the tasting (in images) does or not.
This simple case is typical of all interpretation, the
peculiarity of interpretation being that when a context
has affected us in the past the recurrence of merely a
part of the context will cause us to react in the way
in which we reacted before.2 A sign is always a
stimulus similar to some part of an original stimulus
and sufficient to call up the engram B formed by that
stimulus.
An engram is the residual trace of an adaptation 4
made by the organism to a stimulus. The mental
process 5 due to the calling up of an engram is a
similar adaptation: so far as it is cognitive, what it is
adapted to is its referent, and is what the sign which
excites it stands for or signifies.
The term 'adapted,' though convenient, requires
expansion if this account is to be made clear—and to
this expansion the remainder of the present chapter
is devoted. Returning to our instance, we will sup-
pose that the match ignites and that we have been
expecting a flame. In this case the flame is what we
1
The degree of likeness necessary is a matter of dispute. Yellow
and black thus becomes a sign for offensiveness in taste.
2
To use the terminology of the Gestalt school, when a ' g e s t a l t '
or ' configuration ' has been formed, a system that has been disturbed
will tend towards the ' end-state ' determined b y former occurrences.
This view and terminology are discussed in op. cit., The Meaning
of Psychology, pp. 108-11, and 114-15 where a paragraph will be
found in which six different phrases could all be replaced b y the word
gestalt, if desired (though the paragraph seems clearer as it is).
3
If the reader is doubtful about en grams he may read " t o call
up an excitation similar to that caused by the original stimulus."
4
This is not necessarily a right or appropriate adaptation. We are
here only considering adaptation so far as it is cognitive, and may
disregard the affective-volitional character of the process.
6
The account here given may be read as neutral in regard to psycho-
neural parallelism, interaction, and double aspect hypotheses, since
the problem of the relation of mind and body is—in so far as it is not
itself a phantom p r o b l e m — a later one. Cf. Chapter IV., p. 81, and
op. cit.t The Meaning of Psychology, Chapter II.
54 THE MEANING OF MEANING
are adapted to. More fully, the mental process which
is the expectation is similar to processes which have
been caused by flames in the past, and further it is
1
directed to* the future. If we can discover what this
'directed to' stands for we shall have filled in the chief
part of our account of interpretation.
Besides being ' directed to' the future our expecta-
tion is also 'directed to 1 flame. But here 'directed to'
stands for nothing more than 'similar A? what has been
caused by.' A thought is directed to flame when it is similar
in certain respects to thoughts which have been caused
by flame. As has been pointed out above, we must not
allow the defects of causal language either to mislead us
here or alternatively to make us abandon the method of
approach so indicated. We shall find, if we improve
this language, both that this kind of substitute for
'directed to 1 loses its strangeness, and also that the
same kind of substitution will meet the case of ' direc-
tion to the future' and will in fact explain the ' direction '
or reference of thinking processes in general.
The unpurified notion of cause is especially mis-
leading in this connection since it has led even the
hardiest thinkers 1 to shrink from the identification of
1
Exceptions such as Mr E . B. Holt and Mr Russell, who have
independently adopted causal theories of reference, have not succeeded
in giving precision to this view. The iormer, who holds (The Freudian
Wish, p. 168) that in behaviour there is " a genuine objective reference
to the environment," yet continues—" Even when one is conscious
of things that are not there, as in hallucination, one's body is adjusted
to them as if they were there/ 1 or again (p. 202), " W h y does a boy go
fishing ? . . . Because the behaviour of the growing organism is so
far integrated as to respond specifically to such an environmental object
as fish in the pond. . . . The boy's thought (content) is the fish.1' It
will be seen that the contextual theory of reference outlined in the
present chapter provides an account of specific response which applies,
as Mr Holt's does not, to erroneous and to truly adapted behaviour
alike. Mr Russell, on the other hand, who, like Mr Holt, has now
abandoned the theory of direct knowledge relations between minds
and things, obscures the formulation of the causal account in his Analysis
of Mind by introducing considerations which arise from a quite incom-
patible treatment. " It is a very singular thing," he says (p. 235),
" that meaning which is single should generate objective reference,
which is dual, namely, true and false." When we come to the analysis
of complex references we shall see how this anomaly disappears. The
supposed distinction between ' meaning ' in this sense and objective
reference is one merely of degree of complexity accentuated by symbolic
SIGN-SITUATIONS 55
i
thinking of' with ' being caused b y / The suggestion
that to say ' I am thinking of A* is the same thing as
to say ' My thought is being caused by A,' will shock
every right-minded person ; and yet when for l caused '
we substitute an expanded account, this strange sugges-
tion will be found to be the solution.
A Cause indeed, in the sense of a something which
forces another something called an effect to occur, is
so obvious a phantom that it has been rejected even
by metaphysicians. The current scientific account, on
the other hand, which reduces causation to correlation,
is awkward for purposes of exposition, since in the
absence of a 'conjugating' vocabulary constant peri-
phrasis is unavoidable. If we recognize, however, as
the basis of this account the fact that experience has
the character of recurrence, that is, comes to us in more
or less uniform contexts, we have in this all that is
required for the theory of signs and all that the old
theory of causes was entitled to maintain. Some of
these contexts are temporally and spatially closer
than others : the contexts investigated by physics for
instance narrow themselves down until differential
equations are invoked; those which psychology has
hitherto succeeded in detecting are wide, the uniformly
linked events being often far apart in time. Interpreta-
tion, however, is only possible thanks to these recurrent
contexts, a statement which is very generally admitted
1
See The Analysis of Mind, especially pp. 207-210. One point in
this treatment is of extreme importance. " Generality and par-
ticularity," according to Mr Russell, " are a matter of degree " (p. 209).
For a causal theory of reference no other conclusion appears possible.
Absolute particulars and absolute universals ought therefore to be out
of 2court and beneath discussion.
A more formal and elaborate account of this crucial step in the
theory of interpretation will be found in Appendix B, to which those
who appreciate the complexity of the subject are directed.
SIGN-SITUATIONS 63
sensation. Instead of a present sensation a belief may
itself be a sign for a further belief which will then be
an interpretation of this belief. The only cases of this
which appear to occur are introspective beliefs of the
form ' I believe that I am believing, etc/ which may,
it is important to recognize, be false as often as, or
more often than, other beliefs. As a rule a belief not
prompted by a sensation requires a number of beliefs
simultaneous or successive for its signs. The beliefs,
1
There will be a flame' and 'I am in a powder factory,'
will, for most believers, be signs together interpreted
by the belief i The end is at hand.* Such is one of
the psychological contexts determinative in respect of
the character of this last belief.1 Whether the belief
in question is true or not will depend upon whether
there is or is not some entity forming together with
the referents of the two sign beliefs, in virtue of its
characters and their characters and a multiple relation,
a context determinative in respect of their characters.
In other words—upon whether the place does blow up.
In this way the account given can be extended to
all cases of particular expectations. Further, since the
uniting relations of contexts are not restricted to suc-
cessions it will also apply to all cases of inference or
interpretation from particular to particular. The next
step, therefore, is to inquire what kind of account can
be given of general references.
The abstract language which it is necessary to
employ raises certain difficulties. In a later chapter
arguments will be brought in favour of regarding such
apparent symbols as i character/ i relation,' * property/
1
The additional assumption required here is that the effects of a
belief are often similar, in respect of derivative beliefs, to the effects
of the verifying sensation. Few people will deny that the belief that
an unseen man in a bush is shooting at me will have effects (in respect'
of such derivative beliefs as that it would be better for me to be else-
where) similar to those which would be occasioned by the sight of the
man 'so shooting. Such contexts, in which a belief in the occurrence
of A and A's occurrence itself are alternative signs for interpretations
the same in these respects, are as well established as any in psychology.
64 THE MEANING OF MEANING
'concept,' etc., as standing for nothing beyond (in-
directly) the individuals to which the alleged character
would be applicable. The most important of these
arguments is the natural incredibility of there being
such universal denizens of a world of being. As we
shall see, these apparent symbols are indispensable as
machinery, and thus for some purposes such credulity
is harmless. But for other purposes these baseless (or
purely symbolically based) beliefs are dangerous im-
pediments. Thus a chief source of opposition to an
extension of the account here outlined to general
references, is phantom difficulties deriving from faith
in this other world.
Such references may be formulated in a variety
of ways:—'All 5 is P% and ' (x) : </>(x)~) \fr (x)' are
favourites. What we have to discover is what happens
when we have a belief which can be symbolized in
these ways. Let us take as an instance the belief
4
All match-scrapes are followed by flames.' There is
good reason to suppose that such beliefs are a later
psychological development than beliefs of the form
which we have been considering. It is plausible to
suppose that some animals and infants have particular
expectations but not any general beliefs. General beliefs,
it is said, arise by reflection upon particular beliefs.
Thus we may expect to find that general beliefs arise
in some way out of particular beliefs. But the gener-
ality and particularity to be attributed to simple or
primordial references are certainly not those which
logical formulation endeavours to introduce. Nor
should it be supposed that genetically a stage or era
of particular reference precedes general thinking. It
is rather the case that in all thought processes two
tendencies are present, one towards greater definiteness
or precision, the other towards wider scope and range.
It is the conditions under which this second tendency
takes effect that we are here considering.
Following this clue let us try to set down some of the
SIGN-SITUATIONS 65
conditions under which a general belief might develop
from such particular references as we have been con-
sidering. To begin with we may suppose
(1) that a number of true and verified interpreta-
tions of match-scrapes have occurred in the
same organism, and
(2) that no interpretation which has been shown
to be false, by the absence in the related
sensation of the expected flame character, is
concerned in the genesis of the general belief.
The second of these conditions is plainly more
important than the first. W e often seem to pass to
general beliefs from single experiences and not to
require a plurality, but (exceptionally powerful thinkers
apart) we do not base general beliefs upon directly
contradictory evidence. W e may therefore retain the
second condition, but must revise the first. In some
cases, no doubt, repeated verified expectations do
condition the general expectation, but they condition
its degree rather than its reference. On the other hand
some experience of repetition would seem to be required.
A primordial mind's first thought could hardly be a
general thought in the sense here considered. It seems
justifiable to assume that some series of similar verified
interpretations should be included in the context of a
general belief, though how closely this need be con-
nected with the particular interpretation which is being
generalized must at present be left uncertain.
Another condition which can only be put rather
vaguely concerns the inclusiveness of a general
reference. The togetherness involved in such a refer-
ence does not seem to require any properties in a
'mind' beyond those already assumed and stated, but
the inclusiveness might be thought to raise an addi-
tional problem. The kind of experience required,
however, is not difficult to discover. On many occasions
so far as the verifying stimuli are concerned it is
66 THE MEANING OF MEANING
indifferent whether we think of all of a given set of
objects or of each of them in turn. The child who finds
all his fingers sticky might equally well have found
each of them sticky. On other occasions his smallest
fingers will not need to be washed. Thus the difference
between inclusive and non-inclusive sets of objects
as referents, the difference between ' some' and ' all'
references, will early develop appropriate signs.
Individuals can be found who throughout their lives
i
think' of these differences by means of such images,
z.e.y use such images as adjunct-signs in their inter-
pretations. In other cases no such imagery nor even
the use of the words * all' or ' some,' or any equivalents,
is discoverable. Yet even in these cases some linger-
ing trace of the engraphic action due to situations of
this sort may reasonably be supposed as conditioning
interpretations which i employ these notions.' In
attempting therefore to set out the kind of psychological
context of which a general reference consists, terms
representing them would require inclusion.
Such in very tentative outline is the account which
the causal theory of reference would give of general
beliefs. The detailed investigation of such contexts is
a task to which sooner or later psychology must address
itself, but the methods required are of a kind for which
the science has only recently begun to seek. Much
may be expected when the theory of the conditioned
reflex, due to Pavlov, has been further developed.1
It remains to discuss in what sense, if any, a false
belief, particular or general, has a referent. From the
definitions given it will be plain that the sense in which
a false belief may be said to have a referent must be
quite other than that in which a true belief has a
referent. Thus the arguments now to be given for
a more extended use of the term in no way affect what
has been said ; and it will also be purely as a matter
1
For an account of this method and its applications see op. cit., The
Meaning of Psychology, Chapter IV.
SIGN-SITUATIONS 67
of convenience that we shall use the term in connection
with false beliefs.
In the first place it is clear that true and false
references alike agree in a respect in which processes
such as sensing, breathing, contracting muscles,
secreting, desiring, etc., do not agree with them. It
is convenient to have a term, such as reference, to stand
for this respect in which they agree. The term i belief
which might at first appear most suitable is less con-
venient, both because of its association with doctrines
such as those above discussed which postulate an
unique relation ' thinking of/ and because it is becom-
ing more and more often used with special reference
to the affective-volitional characters of the process. A
second and stronger reason derives from what may be
called the analysis of references. If we compare, say,
the references symbolized by ' There will be a flash
soon/ and ' There will be a noise soon/ it is at least
plausible to suppose that they are compounds contain-
ing some similar and some dissimilar parts. The
parts symbolized by i flash' and * noise' we may
suppose to be dissimilar, and the remaining parts to
be similar in the two cases. The question then arises :
u
W h a t are these parts from which it would seem
references can be compounded ? "
The answer which we shall give will be that they
are themselves references, that every compound
reference is composed wholly of simple references
united in such a way as will give the required structure
to the compound reference they compose But in
attempting to carry out this analysis a special difficulty
has to be guarded against. W e must not suppose that
the structure of the symbol by which we symbolize the
reference to be analysed does in any regular fashion
reflect its structure. Thus in speaking of the parts
symbolized by * flash' and i noise' above we are
running a risk. Illegitimate analyses of symbols are
the source of nearly all the difficulties in these subjects.
68 THE MEANING OF MEANING
Another point which must first be made clear con-
cerns the sense in whch references may be compounded.
To speak of a reference is to speak of the contexts
psychological and external by which a sign is linked to
its referent. Thus a discussion of the compounding of
references is a discussion of the relations of contexts
to one another.
What are usually called the ilogical forms' of
propositions, and what we may call the forms of
references, are, for the view here maintained, forms or
structures of the determinative contexts of interpreta-
tions. They are at present approached by logicians
mainly through the study of symbolic procedure. A
more direct approach appears however to be possible,
though, as yet, difficult. Thus the remaining portions
of the complete contextual theory of reference, namely
the accounts of references of the forms 4 p or q / ' p and
q,' 'not p,' and of the difference between 'all S ' and
' some S,' regarded as concerned with the interweaving
of contexts, are, if still conjectural, plainly not beyond
conjecture.
With this proviso, we may resume the consideration
of the referents of false and of the analysis of compound
beliefs.
We have seen that true and false beliefs are members
of the same kinds of psychological contexts, and that
they differ only in respect of external contexts.1 Let
1
A complex of things as united in a context may be called a ' fact.'
There need be no harm in this, but as a rule the verbal habits thus
incited overpower the sense of actuality even in the best philosophers.
Out of facts spring ' negative facts '; ' that no flame occurs ' becomes
a negative fact with which our expectation fails to correspond when
we are in error. It is then natural to suppose that there are two modes
of reference, towards a fact for a true reference, away from it for a false.
In this way the theory of reference can be made very complicated
and difficult, as for instance by Mr Russell in his Analysis of Mind,
pp. 271-78. As regards negative facts, Mr Russell has allowed his
earlier theories to remain undisturbed by his recent study of Meaning.
The general question of ' negative facts ' is discussed in Appendix E ;
and we shall find, when we come to distinguish the various senses of
meaning, that to raise the question of the correspondence of belief
with fact is for a causal theory of reference to attempt to solve the
problem twice over. When the problem of reference is settled that of
truth is found to be solved as well.
SIGN-SITUATIONS 69
us consider this difference again, taking for the sake
of simplicity the case of particular beliefs. Suppose
that of two possible beliefs, i There will be something
green here in a moment/ * There will be something red
here in a moment/ the first is true and the second false.
But the second, if it can be regarded, as having
contained or included the belief, i There will be some-
thing here in a moment/ will have included a belief
which is true and similar to a belief included in the
first belief. Reverting now to our definition of a
context let us see in what sense this belief is included
and how it can be true.
In such a case the external context may consist of
two entities, say s (a sign) and g (something green),
having the characters S, G, and related by space and
time relations which may be taken together. But it is
clear that both s and g will have other characters
besides 6* and G. For instance, s has succeeded other
entities and may he interpreted in respect of this
character as well as in respect of S, s o 1 interpreted it
gives rise to the belief, i There will be something here
in a moment 5 ; interpreted also in the further respect
of 5 it gives rise to the complex belief, ' There will be
something green here in a moment/ or to the complex
belief, ' There will be something red here in a moment/
true and false interpretation of sm this further respect
as the case may be. In either case, however, the
contained belief, i There will be something here in a
moment/ will be true if there is something (say g)
which forms with s} in virtue of s's character of being a
successor (or other temporal characters) and g*s tem-
poral characters, a context determinative of this
character of s. Thanks to the generality of these
characters such contexts never fail to recur, a fact which
accounts for the ease with which true predictions of
this unspecific kind can be made.
1
Whether this is a sufficient character for the interpretation need
not be considered in this brief outline of the theory.
70 THE MEANING OF .MEANING
It appears then that a belief may contain other less
specific beliefs, and that a compound definite belief is
composed of simpler, less specific beliefs, united by
such relations as will yield the required structure.1
One objection to such a view derives from language.
It is usual to restrict the term belief to such processes
as are naturally symbolized by propositions and further
to those among such processes as have certain affective-
volitional characters in addition to their characters as
cognitions. The simple references which would be
required if the analysis suggested were adopted would
rarely lend themselves to propositional formulation and
would be lacking as a rule in accompanying belief,
feelings and promptings to action. Thus the terms
' idea * and {conception ' would often be more suitable
for such processes. To extend a metaphor which is
becoming familiar, these might be regarded as
i
electronic' references. But the ideas or conception
with which we are here concerned would have to be
clearly distinguished from the i concepts' of those
metaphysicians who believe in a world of universals.
W e shall deal at greater length with the question in
Chapter V.
Let us consider the idea or conception of green.
It arises in the reader in this case through the occur-
rence of the word ' green.' On many occasions this
word has been accompanied by presentations of green
things. Thus the occurrence of the word causes in him
a certain process which we may call the idea of green.
But this process is not the idea of any one green thing ;
such an idea would be more complex and would require
a sign (or symbol in this case) with further characters
for him to interpret—only so will his idea be specific.
1
The important and intricate problems raised, by these relations
are to be approached in the same fashion as the problem of the generality
of references, which is in fact an instance. The great question ' What
is logical form ? ' left at present to logicians whose only method is the
superstitious rite * direct inspection/ must in time be made amenable
to investigation.
SIGN-SITUATIONS 71
The psychological context to which it belongs is not of
a form to link any one green thing with the sign rather
than any other. If now we write instead, * a green
thing/ the same process occurs—unless the reader is a
logician or philosopher with special theories (z.e.y pecu-
liar linguistic contexts). In both cases the idea can
be said to be ' o f any sensation similar to certain
sensations which have accompanied in the past the
occurrence of the sensation taken as a sign. Compare
now the indefinite belief symbolized by * There are
green things.' Here any one of the same set of
sensations that the idea was said to be ' of' will verify
the belief. For if there be one or more entities similar
to certain entities which are rrtembers of its psycho-
logical context, it will be true; otherwise it will be
false. W e may therefore extend the term ' referent' to
cover these entities, if there be any such, without the
usage leading to confusion.
It will be noticed that strictly simple indefinite
beliefs (illustrated by, ' There are green things' as
opposed to ' There are green things now') only require
for their truth a condition which is present among
their psychological contexts. This happy state of
things has its parallel in the fact that strictly simple
ideas raise no problem as to whether they are ideas
' o f anything or not But complex id^as, such as
glass mountains, phoenixes, round squares, and
virtuous triangles may be made to bristle with such
problems. The distinction between an idea and a belief
is, however, one of degree, although through symbolic
conventions it can sometimes appear insuperable.
We can now define the usage of the term i referent *
for false beliefs. All beliefs whether true or false are
theoretically analysable into compounds whose con-
stituents are simple references, either definite or in-
definite, united by the relations which give its ' logical
form* to the reference.
Definite simple references are not very common.
72 THE MEANING OF MEANING
Sometimes when we say ' this !' ' there !' ' now ! * we
seem to have them. But usually, even when our refer-
ence is such that it can have but one referent, it can
be analysed. Even references for which we use simple
symbols (names), e.g., Dostoevski, are perhaps always
compound, distinct contexts being involved severally
determinative of distinct characters of the referent.1
What is more important is to understand the peculiar
dispersion which occurs in false reference. Illustrations
perhaps make this clearer than do arguments.
Thus, if we say, ' This is a book' and are in error,
our reference will be composed of a simple indefinite
reference to any book, another to anything now, another
to anything which may be here, and so on. These
constituents will all be true, but the whole reference to
this book which they together make up (by cancelling
out, as it were, all but the one referent which can be
a book and here and now) will be false, if we are in
error and what is there is actually a box or something
which fails to complete the three contexts, book, here,
and now. To take a slightly more intricate case, a
golfer may exclaim, "Nicely over!" and it may be
obvious to the onlooker that his reference is to a divot
and its flight, to his stroke, to a bunker, and to a ball.
Yet the ball remains stationary, and these constituent
or component references, each adequate in itself, are
combined in his complex reference otherwise than are
their separate referents in actual fact. There is clearly
no case for a non-occurrent flight of a golf-ball as an
object of his belief; though he may have been referring
to the feel of his stroke, or to an image of a travelling
ball. In these last cases we should have to suppose
him to be shortening his own interpretative chain
instead of breaking loose and venturing a step too far
1
This sentence like all sentences containing words such as' character/
is redundant and should rather read . . . " distinct contexts1 being
involved severally, indefinitely, determinative of the referent. ' But
this pruning of its redundancies would lead to failure in its commit ni-
active function. Cf. p. 96 infra.
SIGN-SITUATIONS 73
by what may be called saltatory interpretation. His
language (cf. also Canon IV., page 103 infra) does not
bind us to either alternative. Thus we see in outline
how compound false beliefs may be analysed.
The referent of a compound false belief will be the
set of the scattered referents of the true simple beliefs
which it contains. We shall, in what follows, speak of
beliefs, and interpretations, whether true or false, and
of ideas, as references, implying that in the senses
above defined they have referents.
W e thus see how the contextual theory of reference
can be extended to cover all beliefs, ideas, conceptions
and 'thinkings of.' The details of its application to
special cases remain to be worked out. Logicians will
no doubt be able to propound many puzzles,1 the
solving of which will provide healthy exercise for
psychologists. The general hypothesis that thinking
or reference is reducible to causal relations otight how-
ever to commend itself more and more to tnose who
take up (at least sometimes) a scientific attitude to the
world. Subject to the proviso that some satisfactory
account of probability can be given, ' meaning * in the
sense of reference becomes according to this theory a
matter open to experimental methods.
A satisfactory account of probability, however,
though very desirable, does not seem likely to be
forthcoming by current methods. Evidently a change
of attack is required. The late Lord Keynes* Treatise
starting as it does with an unanalysable logical relation,
called probability, which holds between equally mysteri-
ous and unapproachable entities, called propositions,
is too mediaeval in its outlook to be fruitful; and it remains
to be seen whether scientists will be able to profit by
Reichenbach's more empirical Wahrscheinlichkeitslehre.
It seems possible on the contextual theory of refer-
1
As, for instance, whether in the example taken above, if one or
both of the sign beliefs were false, and yet the room we were in did
blow up through other causes, our belief could be true ? This problem
is easily solved if we notice that although the belief symbolized in the
speaker would be false, a belief incited in a hearer might be true.
74 THE MEANING OF MEANING
ence to suggest an expansion of this kind of obscure
shorthand and so come nearer the formulation of the
yet undiscovered central question of probability. What
are talked about by logicians as propositions are,
according to this theory, relational characters of acts of
referring—those relational characters for which the term
i
references' is used. Thus to believe, or entertain, or
think of, a proposition, is on this view simply to refer,
and the proposition as a separate entity is to be regarded
as nothing but a linguistic fiction foisted upon us by
the utraquistic subterfuge.1 Two ' thinkings of* the
same ' proposition' are two thinkings with the same
reference, the same relational property, namely i being
contextually linked in the same way with the same
referent.1 It will be noted that on this account of
propositions the logical relations of propositions to one
another must be dealt with far less summarily and
formally than has hitherto been the case.
With propositions so understood there occurs a sense
in which a single proposition by itself without relation
to other propositions, can intelligibly be said to be
probable. Probability here has still a relational aspect,
and it is only because propositions (t\e.9 references) are
relational that they can be said to be probable. This
very fundamental sense is that in which the uniformity
of the context upon which the truth of a reference depends
is probable.
W e have seen that by taking very general consti-
tutive characters and uniting relation, we obtain contexts
of the highest probability. Similarly by taking too
specific characters and relation the probability of the
context dwindles until we should no longer call it a
context. In this way, whether a context is probable
can be seen to be a question about the degree of
generality of its constitutive characters and uniting
relation ; about the number of its members, the other
contexts to which they belong and so on . . . a question
1
Cf. Chapter VI., p. 134.
SIGN-SITUATIONS 75
not about one feature of the context but about many.
W e can always for instance raise the probability of
a context by adding suitable members. But this last
though a natural remark suffers from the linguistic
redundance to which the difficulties of the problem are
chiefly due. ' Probability' in the fundamental sense
in which a context is probable is a shorthand symbol
for all those of its features upon which the degree of
its uniformity depends.
In considering conscious and critical processes of
interpretation we must not fail to realize that all such
activity, e.g., of the kind discussed in the theory of
induction, rests upon ' instinctive' interpretations. If
we recognize how essential * instinctive' interpretation
is throughout, we shall be able to pursue our investiga-
tions undisturbed by the doubts, of causal purists or
the delay of the mathematicians in bringing their
differential equations into action. For the working
of a differential equation itself, that most rational
process of interpretation, will break down unless many
1
instinctive' interpretations, which are not at present
capable of any mathematical treatment, are successfully
performed.
It is sometimes very easy by experimental methods
to discover what a thought process is referring to. If
for instance we ask a subject to ' think of' magenta
we shall, by showing various colours to him, as often
as not find that he is thinking of some other colour. It
is this kind of consideraton which makes the phrase
i
adapted to ' so convenient an equivalent for ' referring
to,' and if we bear in mind that * being adapted to*
something is only a shorthand symbol for being linked
with it in the manner described, through external and
psychological contexts, we may be able to use the
term without its purposive and biological associations
leading to misunderstanding.
We have still to give an account of misinterpreta-
tion, and to explain how unfounded beliefs can arise. To
76 THE MEANING OF MEANING
begin with the first, a person is often said to have
introduced irrelevant^ or to have omitted relevant, con-
siderations or notions when he has misinterpreted some
sign. The notion of relevance is of great importance
in the theory of meaning. A consideration (notion,
idea) or an experience, we shall say, is relevant to an
interpretation when it forms part of the psychological
context which links other contexts together in the
peculiar fashion in which interpretation so links them. 1
An irrelevant consideration is a non-linking member of
a psychological context. The fact that 'baseless*
convictions occur might be thought to be an objection
to the view of thinking here maintained. The explana-
tion is however to be found in the fact that mental
processes are not determined purely psychologically
but, for example, by blood pressure also. If our in-
terpretation depended only upon purely psychological
contexts it might be that we should always be justified
in our beliefs, true or false. W e misinterpret typically
when we are asleep or tired. Misinterpretaton there-
fore is due to interference with psychological contexts,
to ' mistakes.' Whether an interpretation is true or
false on the other hand does not depend only upon
psychological contexts—unless we are discussing psy-
chology. W e may have had every reason to expect
a flame when we struck our match, but this, alas I will
not have made the flame certain to occur. That depends
upon a physical not a psychological context.
1
Other psychological Unkings of external contexts are not essentially
different from interpretation, but we are only here concerned with
the cognitive aspect of mental process. The same sense of relevance
would be appropriate in discussing conation. The context method of
analysis is capable of throwing much light upon the problems of desire
and motive.
CHAPTER IV
SIGNS IN PERCEPTION
La Nature est un temple ou de vivants piliers
Laissent parfois sortir de confuses paroles ;
L'bomme y passe a travers des forets de symboles
Qui robservent avec des regards familiers.—
Baudelaire.
T H E CANONS O F SYMBOLISM
A happy nomenclature has sometimes been more
powerful than rigorous logic in allowing a new train
of thought to be quickly and generally accepted.—
Prof. A. Schuster.
For the rest I should not be displeased, sir, did you
enter a little farther into the details of the turns of
mind which appear marvellous in the use of the
particles.—Leibnitz.
T H E T H E O R Y OF DEFINITION
The first cause of absurd conclusions I ascribe to
the want of method ; in that they begin not their
ratiocination from definitions.—Hobbes.
" Do, as a concession to my poor wits, Lord
Darlington, just explain to me what you really
mean."—" I think I had better not, Duchess.
Nowadays to be intelligible is to be found out."—
Lady Windermere's Fan,
T H E MEANING OF B E A U T Y
This I have here mentioned by the bye to show of what
Consequence it is for Men to define their Words when
there is Occasion. And it must be a great want of Inge-
nuity (to say no more of it) to refuse to do i t : Since a
Definition is the only way, whereby the precise Meaning
of moral Words can be known.—Locke.
41
Disputes are multiplied, as if everything was uncer-
tain, and these disputes are managed with the greatest
warmth, as if everything was certain. Amidst all this
bustle 'tis not reason which gains the prize, but elo-
quence ; and no man need ever despair of gaining pro-
selytes to the most extravagant hypothesis, who has art
enough to represent it in any favourable colours. The
victory is not gained by the men at arms, who manage the
pike and sword ; but by the trumpeters, drummers, and
musicians of the army."-—Hume.
And so, on the next page (430), the last of the book,
we conclude with the assurance that " T o progress in
the sense of the self-assertion of the will in will-
enhancement remains for mankind, too, the ultimate
MEANING o f d u t y . "
A study of these extracts in the German version of
Munsterberg's work is an interesting exercise in com-
parative linguistic, and the contribution of the term
i
meianing' to the cogency of the argument is consider-
able. There may be those who find it hard to believe
that any writer responsible for such a verbal exploit
could also enjoy a reputation as a thinker of the first
rank. There is, however, another ambitious modern
attempt by an American theorist to deal specifically
with the fundamentals of psychology; and in the
preface to this work x we find a reference to Miinster-
berg's "illuminating work on the great problems of
philosophy and of natural and mental science. . . .
It may be truthfully said that in his death America has
lost its one great theoretical psychologist." Professor
Moore has no occasion to quote largely from the par-
ticular work selected above, but his extracts (pp. 107-
110) from Munsterberg's Psychology General and Applied^
and Psychotherapy are equally bespattered with the term.
And as might be expected Professor Moore's own
treatment is also vitiated at its most crucial points by
his too hospitable attitude to this plausible nomad.
1
The Foundations of Psychology, by Jared Sparks Moore, 1921.
174 THE MEANING OF MEANING
To understand the nature of psychology as a science
we must, he holds, carefully distinguish Science from
Metaphysics, and " t h e key-word of the problem of
metaphysics is Interpretation, To interpret anything is
to determine its MEANING. If the fundamental pre-
supposition of all science is that every fact has a cause ;
the fundamental presupposition of metaphysics is that
every fact has a MEANING " (p. 97). In other words, in
philosophy as opposed to science, '' each fact is treated
not as the effect of some antecedent cause, but as the
expression of a Meaning." Science must precede
metaphysics—" W e cannot know what facts MEAN until
we know what the facts are, we cannot interpret the
facts until we have described them."
But, objects the critic (p. 100), " is it not true that
the very essence of a mental process is its M E A N I N G ? "
No. Titchener has given six good reasons why mental
processes are " not intrinsically MEANINGFUL" (p. 101).
But, the critic insists (p. 102), Do not all our experiences
" i n their inmost nature MEAN something. Do we ever
experience a 'MEANINGLESS* sensation?" W e have
no reason, the reply runs, to believe that the mind
" began with MEANINGLESS sensations, and progressed
to MEANINGFUL perceptions. On the contrary we must
suppose that the mind was MEANINGFUL from the very
outset."
And here we pause at the very pertinent question :
" W h a t then from the psychological point of view is
this M E A N I N G ? " T h e answer is given without hesita-
tion and in italics—"From the psychological point of
view, MEANING is context." To explain : In every per-
ception, or group of sensations and images, " t h e
associated images form as it were a context or * fringe'
which binds together the whole and gives it a definite
MEANING," and it is this "fringe of MEANING that
makes the sensations not i mere' sensations but
symbols of a physical object." So when we see an
orange it is the contextual images of smell and taste
T H E MEANING OF PHILOSOPHERS 175
i
" which enable us to recognize' the object—i.e., give
a MEANING to the sensations " of colour and brightness.
Similarly (p. 103) " every idea has a core or nucleus of
images, and a fringe of associated images . . . which
give MEANING to the nuclear images."
To sum u p :
" I n all these cases, the MEANING of the perception
or idea is * carried' by the contextual images or sensa-
tions, and it is context which gives MEANING to every
experience, and yet it would be inaccurate to say that
the MEANING of a sensation or symbolic image is
through and through nothing but its associated images
or sensations, for this would be a violation of the
principle that psychology is not concerned with
MEANINGS. All that is implied is that the MEANINGS of
our experiences are represented in the realm of mental
processes by i the fringe of related processes that
gathers about the central group 'of sensations or
images/ Psychologically MEANING is context, but
logically and metaphysically MEANING is much more
than psychological context; or, to put it the other way
round, whatever MEANING may be, psychology is
concerned with it only so far as it can be represented
in terms of contextual imagery" (p. 103).
It is a curious approach to the problems of sign-
interpretation, this account of Meaning which (psycho-
logically) is context, which is carried by context, which
is muck more than context, which is expressed by facts,
with which psychology is not concerned—and yet is con-
cerned, so far as it can be represented by contextual
imagery. 1
1
In a letter printed by Mind (April 1924), but unfortunately marred
by four lapsus calami (' nuclear image ' for nuclear images] ' 102 ' for
i°3, ' 193 **for 293, and ' 541 ' for 544) Professor Moore, after drawing
attention to three typist's errors in the above (now corrected) complains
that this paragraph " makes chaos of my whole position by ridiculing
my account " of Meaning. Says he : " My whole point is that Meaning
is ' much more than context' though c carried ' or ' represented ' in
the mind by context; and that for this reason, ' psychology is not
concerned with Meaning, but only with its representatives in the mind.' "
lie adds : " I nowhere say that Meaning' is context,' or that psychology
176 THE MEANING OF MEANING
But there are stranger things to follow, for here
True Meaning makes its appearance—in connection
with a bell. " T h e true MEANING of the percept of the
bell is its reference to the real objective bell," and this
reference is represented in the mind by contextual
images which "constitute its MEANING 'translated into
the language of' psychology. So the true MEANING of
an idea lies in its logical reference to an objective
system of ideas" (p. 104); and a little later (p. 111) we
find that " a l l experiences are expressions of the inner
MEANINGS of the self."
It is hard to believe that Professor Moore would
have been satisfied with such a vocabulary had he
attempted to investigate the psychology of signs and
symbols ; and this investigation could not but have
shown him how much of his present work had its
origin in an unfortunate choice of, and attitude towards,
symbols. As it is, the constant appeal to an esoteric
Doctrine of Meaning is reminiscent of the dialectical
devices of mediaeval theologians, and we may conclude
by noting that the Doctrine is specifically invoked in
relation to Religion.
" Psychology may discuss as freely the mental processes in-
volved in religious experience as it does those concerned in our
experience of physical things; but in neither case can its decisions
affect the question of the MEANING . . . of those experiences.
The question of the nature of the processes undergone by the
human mind in any spheres of activity is a question of fact,
calling for analytical description and explanation in causal terms:
the problem of the validity or truth-value of these processes is a
question of MEANING, calling for interpretation " (p. 122).
1
J. Dewey, The Influence of Darwin upon Philosophy, 1910, pp. 88,
104.
2
" Ideas, we may say generally, are symbols, as serving to express
some actual moment or phase of experience and guiding towards
fuller actualization of what is, or seems to be, involved in its existence
or MEANING. . . . That no idea is ever wholly adequate MEANS that
the suggestiveness of experience is inexhaustible." Forsyth, English
Philosophy, 1910, pp. 180, 183.
3
" Babies learn to speak words partly by adopting sounds of their
own and giving them a MEANING, partly by pure imitation. . . .
Whether the baby invents both sounds and MEANING seems doubtful.
. . , Certainly they change the MEANING of words.'' E. L. Cabot,
Seven Ages of Childhood, 1921, pp. 22, 23, 24.
4
" The MEANING of Marriage ! How really simple it is for you
and me to ascertain its precise MEANING, and yet what desperate
and disappointing efforts have been made to discover it. . . . If
our children knew all about them they would yet have missed the
essential MEANING of human marriage. A knowledge of life outside
humanity would not enlighten us as to what marriage MEANT for men
and women. . . . Manifestly, if we desire to know the MEANING
of marriage, we ought to search out homes where the conditions are
favourable. . . . We may ungrudgingly pay a well-deserved tribute to
the mother cat. Motherhood MEANS already much in the animal
world I " G. Spiller, The Meaning of Marriage, 1914, pp. 1-3.
5
Strictly speaking, the image is often both a part of the MEANING
and a symbol of the rest of it. As part it gives one of the MEANING'S
details. Part of the MEANING of an idea is its fixed reference to some
objective identity. . . . MEANING alone passes between mind and
mind. A. D. Sheffield, Grammar and Thinking, pp. 3-4.
182 THE MEANING OF MEANING
'bad,' the only simple object of thought which is peculiar to
Ethics.
It would be absolutely MEANINGLESS to say that oranges
were yellow, unless yellow did in the end MEAN j u s t ' yellow' . . .
We should not get very far with our science if we were bound to
hold that everything which was yellow MEANT exactly the same
thing as yellow.
In general, however, ethical philosophers have attempted to
define good without recognizing what such an attempt must
1
MEAN."
2
J. M. Baldwin, Genetic Theory of Reality, 1915, pp. 108, 227.
E. Belfort Bax, The Real, the Rational, and the A logical, 1920,
pp.3 233, 243.
Professor K. J. Spalding, Desire and Reason, 1922, p. 8.
CHAPTER IX
T H E MEANING OF MEANING
Father! these are terrible words, but I have no time
now but for Meanings.—Melmoth the Wanderer.
SYMBOL SITUATIONS
For one word a man is often deemed to be wise
and for one word he is often deemed to be foolish.
We ought to be careful indeed what we say.—
Confucius.
Abba Amnion asked Abba Sisoes,, saying, " When
I read in the Book my mind wisheth to arrange the
words so that there may be an answer to any ques-
tion." The old man said unto him, " This is unneces-
sary, for only purity of heart is required. From this
it ariseth that a man should speak without over-
much care."—Palladius, " The Book of Paradise."
3.—Sign-situations.
In all thinking we are interpreting signs.
In obvious cases this is readily admitted. In the
more complex cases of mathematics and grammar more
complicated forms of the same activity only are involved.
This is hidden from us by an uncritical use of symbols,
favouring analyses of ' meaning 1 and i thinking' which
are mainly occupied with mirages due to 'linguistic
refraction.'
W e must begin therefore with Interpretation.
Our Interpretation of any sign is our psycho-
logical reaction to it, as determined by our past
experience in similar situations, and by our present
experience.
If this is stated with due care in terms of causal
contexts or correlated groups we get an account of
judgment, belief and interpretation which places the
psychology of thinking on the same level as the other
SUMMARY 245
inductive sciences, and incidentally disposes of the
1
Problem of Truth.'
A theory of thinking which discards mystical rela-
tions between the knower and the known and treats
knowledge as a causal affair open to ordinary scientific
investigation, is one which will appeal to common-
sense inquirers.
4.—Signs in Perception.
The certainty of our knowledge of the external
world has suffered much at the hands of philosophers
through the lack of a theory of signs, and through
conundrums made possible by our habit of naming
things in haste without providing methods of identifi-
cation.
The paradoxes of really round pennies which appear
elliptical, and so forth, are due to misuses of symbols;
principally of the symbol i datum.'
What we ' s e e ' when we look at a table is first,
modifications of our retinae. These are our initial signs.
W e interpret them and arrive at fields of vision, bounded
by surfaces of tables and the like. By taking beliefs in
these as second order signs and so on, we can proceed
with our interpretation, reaching as results tables, wood,
fibres, cells, molecules, atoms, electrons, etc. The later
stages of this interpretative effort are physics. Thus
there is no study called i philosophy' which can add to
or correct physics, though symbolism may contribute
to a systematization of the levels of discourse at which
1
table ' and * system of molecules ' are the appropriate
symbols.
The method by which confusions are to be extirpated
in this field is required wherever philosophy has been
246 THE MEANING OF MEANING
applied. It rests partly upon the theory of signs, partly
upon the Rules of Symbolization discussed in the next
chapter.
6.—Definition.
In any discussion or interpretation of symbols we
need a means of identifying referents. The reply to
the question what any word or symbol refers to consists
in the substitution of a symbol or symbols which can
be better understood.
Such substitution is Definition. It involves the
selection of known referents as starting-points, and
SUMMARY 247
the identification of the definiendum by its connection
with these.
The defining routes, the relations most commonly
used for this purpose, are few in number, though
specialists in abstract thought can employ others. In
fact they may be pragmatically generalized under eight
headings. Familiarity with these defining routes not
only conduces to ease of deportment in reasoning and
argument, but offers a means of escape from the maze
of verbal cross-classifications which the great variety
of possible view-points has produced.
10.—Symbol Situations.
ON GRAMMAR
ponent parts. Each of these parts, noun and verb, has a signi-
ficance of its own ; but these are the ultimate elements of speech,
for the parts of the noun or of the verb have no significance at all."1
In this statement may be found all the uncertainty and hesi-
tation which since Aristotle's time have beset both grammarians
and logicians. Notably the doubt whether words signify ' mental
affections ' or the facts which these' represent,' and the confusion
between the assertive character of the proposition (which is here
used as equivalent to sentence) and the states of belief and dis-
belief which may occur in connection with it.
With the first source of confusion we have dealt at length, but
the second demands further attention if it is to be avoided.
Recent psychological research, especially into the nature of sug-
gestion and into the effects of drugs upon the feelings, has done
nothing to invalidate William James' view as to the relation of
belief to reference. " In its inner nature, belief, or the sense of
reality, is a sort of feeling more allied to the emotions than to
anything else." Belief and disbelief as opposed to doubt are
" characterized by repose on the purely intellectual side," and
" intimately connected with subsequent practical activity."a
Belief and disbelief, doubt and questioning, seem to be what
nowadays would be called affective-volitional characteristics of
mental states, and thus theoretically separable from the states to
which they attach. The same reference, that is to say, may at one
time be accompanied by belief and at another by disbelief or
doubt. For this reason, so far as language is modified by the
nature of the belief-feelings present, these modifications come
under the heading of expression of attitude to referent, the third
of the language functions distinguished in Chapter X.
This separation greatly assists a clear analysis of the most
important character of the proposition, namely, the way in which
it seems to symbolize assertion, to stand for a complete object of
thought, a character lacking to the parts of a simple sentence.
A noun by itself or a verb by itself somehow differs from the
whole which is made up when they are suitably juxtaposed,
and this difference has been the pivotal point upon which not
merely grammatical analysis, but logic and philosophy have also
turned ever since Aristotle s time.
The confusion has been further aggravated by the introduction
of the problem of truth in an unsolved condition. Propositions
have been almost universally regarded as the only objects to
1
Grote, Aristotle, Vol. I., p. 157.
2
Principles of Psychology, Vol. II., p. 284.
258 APPENDIX A
which the words ' true ' and * false ' are properly applied; though
this unanimity has been somewhat disguised by differences of
view as to whether true propositions are those which express
true beliefs or whether true beliefs are those whose objects are
true propositions. In these controversies the various shifts of
the symbol ' proposition ', standing, as it does, at one time for
a sentence, at another for a referent, and yet another for a re-
lational character of a mental act or process, provide a fascinating
field for the Science of Symbolism to explore. But in view of
what has been said above in Chapter III. on the analysis of the
differences which distinguish a complex symbol such as c Snow
chills ' from the single symbols such as ' snow ' and ' chills '
which compose it, the apparent complications due to the intro-
duction of truth raise no difficulty. They are merely a bewilder-
ing, because imperfectly parallel, re-naming of the problem.
According to the theory of signs all references, no matter how
simple they may be, are either true or false, and no difference in
this respect is to be found between the reference symbolized by
' snow ' and that symbolized by ' snow chills.' This statement
requires to be guarded from over-hasty interpretation. It is
easy to use single words in such a way that they are not symbols,
and so do not stand for anything. When this is done no doubt
some stray images and other mental goings-on may be aroused,
and if we are not careful in our use of ' meaning ' we may then
suppose that non-symbolic words so considered have meaning
just as much and in the same sense as they do when present
symbolically in a proposition. The single word, whether noun
or verb, only has meaning in the sense here required, when taken
in such a way that it enters a reference contest of the normal
kind; and only so taken is it a symbolic (as distinguished from
an emotive) component of a proposition. Any word so considered
comes to be, qua symbol of a reference to some state of affairs,
capable of truth and falsehood ; and in this respect it differs in
no way from a sentence used symbolically for purposes of state-
ment.
We have yet to see, therefore, in what the marked difference
between single words and sentences consists ; and, as we should
expect from the nature of the symbol situation, we find the
difference to be not one but several, none of which is always or
necessarily present although some may be said to be normally
involved.1 In the first place the references of the symbols will
1
This multiple function of the noun-verb combination .is recognized
as an important feature for analysis by Sheffield (Grammar and Thinking,
APPENDIX A 259
often differ structurally. Thus the reference of ' larks sing/
since it has two components, will differ from that of € larks '
just as do * soaring larks ' or * lark pie/ being also dual references.
This difference is therefore unessential, though most complex
references do in fact use the propositional form. One reason
for the use of this form is because it is the normal means by
which the togetherness of the component references is symbolized
in cases where ambiguity is possible. Thus the sentence is the
chief, but not the only symbolic device by which the togetherness
of references is made plain. It is this which is usually described
as the ' synthetic ' function of the proposition,1 an unsatisfactory
term, since verbal arrangements which are not of the propositional
form, such as * lark pie ', or ' this lark pie '2—are equally syn-
thetic. In logic the translation of all propositions into the subject-
copula-predicate form has been a convention to avoid ambiguity,
though modern logicians have found that more elaborate con-
ventions are desirable for relational propositions.
But the sentence also serves emotively in various ways.8 It is
the conventional mode of Address, since listeners expect some
special signal that a reference is occurring before they incline
their ears cognitively. Further, it is the conventional verbal
sign of the presence of Belief, of feelings of acceptance, rejection
or doubt, in the speaker ; and a stimulus to similar feelings in the
p. 34), though his use of the word ' meaning ' may have obscured the
value
1
of his distinctions for the grammarians whom he criticizes.
Cf. e.g., Baldwin's treatment in Thought and Things, Vol. II.,
Experimental
8
Logic, p. 262.
8
Cf. C. Dickens, Works, Autograph Edition, 1903, Vol. I., p. 16.
Subject and Predicate reappear at this point in the writings of
the modern Leipzig glotto-psychologists. Professor Dittrich and his
followers. For them the Generalsubjekt or Protosubjekt seems to corre-
spond in great part with the Referent in our terminology, while the
Generalprddikat or Protoprddihat is the attitude (assent, doubt, desire,
or any other emotion) adopted towards this state of affairs. The
protosubjekt is a constant (Dittrich, in his Probleme, p. 61), the proto-
prddikat a variant. In comparison with these two components, ' sub-
ject ' and ' predicate ' are regarded as secondary in character, ' noun '
and ' verb * as tertiary. " Fall in Home Rails " is on this view a
sentence, its protosubjekt is ' fall in Home Hails,1 its protoprddihat
a feeling of assent. The sentence would thus contain no expressed
subject; ' fall * being regarded as an unindexing impersonal pr&di-
kativum. The reason why the subject of ' fall' is not expressed is
said to be because it is not of interest here ; and it must on this view
be sought in all that is capable of falling, in the Aussagegrundlage.
With these elaborations we are not here concerned, and the reader is
referred to Appendix D and the work of Dittrich for the terminology
of Gomperz, on which this system is based. It is sufficient to remark
that this use of the traditional terms ' subject' and ' predicate ' is
likely to confuse those not well acquainted with the writings of this
school. The new use lias little in common with that already familiar.
260 APPENDIX A
ON CONTEXTS
'•j
Other psychological
contexts.
s_
f?"
strate the existence of the soul; they are its sign. It is ' sign '
then, in this latter sense, the indicative or demonstrative sign,
whose existence Sextus disputes and undertakes to refute."
If such an interpretation of their views is correct it is clear
that with their account of reminiscent signs the Sceptics came
very near to formulating a modern theory of scientific induction,
while their scepticism about demonstrative signs amounts to a
denial of the possibility of inferring to the transcendental. Given
a fact, or as the Stoics called it, a ' sign/ we cannot determine a
priori the nature of the thing signified. That the main terms in
which the discussion was conducted suffered from confusions
which still haunt their modern equivalents, is not surprising ;
there can be no signs of things to which we cannot refer, but
things can be referred to which are not experienced.
When the excavation of Herculaneum is accomplished, the
lost treatise of Philodemus on the Epicurean theory of signs and
inference which is likely to become available, together with other
similar documents relative to this remarkable controversy, may
throw more light on the progress which had been made in these
early times towards a rational account of the universe ; and so
enable us to realize something of what a healthy scepticism might
have achieved had theological interests not so completely domin-
ated the next fifteen hundred years.
APPENDIX D
SOME MODERNS
§i. Husserl
We may begin with what is perhaps the best known modern
attempt to deal comprehensively with the problem of Signs and
Meaning, that of Professor Edmund Husserl. And it is important
for the understanding of Husserl *s terminology to realize that
everything he writes is developed out of the " Phenomenological
Method and Phenomenological Philosophy " which he has been
elaborating since 1910, as Professor of Philosophy, first at Gottin-
gen and later at Freiburg. In June, 1922, in a course of lectures
at London University, he gave an exposition of his system to a
large English audience, and the following sentences are taken
from the explanatory Syllabus in which he, or his official trans-
lator, endeavoured to indicate both his method and his vocabulary.
" There has been made possible and is now on foot, a
new a priori science extracted purely from concrete phen-
omenological intuition (Anschauung)y the science, namely,
of transcendental phenomenology, which inquires into the
totality of ideal possibilities that fall within the framework
270 APPENDIX D
§3. Frege
Frege's theory of Meaning is given in his Begriffsschrift,
Grundlagen der Arithmetik and his articles on " Begriff und
Gegenstand," and " Sinn und Bedeutung." A convenient sum-
mary, which we here follow, is given at p. 502 of his Principles
by Mr Russell, who holds that Frege*s work " abounds in subtle
1
Logic, Book I., Chapter L, §§ 17, 18 (pp. 58-60).
274 APPENDIX D
distinctions, and avoids all the usual fallacies which beset writers
on Logic/' The distinction which Frege makes between meaning
(Sinn) and indication (Bedeutung) is roughly, though not exactly,
equivalent to Mr Russell's distinction between a concept as such
and what the concept denotes (Principles, §96). Frege did not
possess this distinction in the first two of the works under con-
sideration ; but it makes its appearance in B.u.G., and is speci-
ally dealt with in S.U.B. Before making the distinction, he thought
that identity had to do with the names of objects (Bs., p. 13):
" A is identical with B " means, he says, that the sign A and the
sign B have the same signification (Bs.> p. 15)—a definition which,
in Mr Russell's view, " verbally at least, suffers from circularity."
But later he explains identity in much the same way as Mr
Russell did in the Principles, §64. " Identity," he says, " calls
for reflection owing to questions which attach to it and are not
quite easy to answer. Is it a relation ? A relation between
Gegenstande or between names or signs of Gegenstande ?"
(S.U.B., p. 25). We must distinguish, he adds, the meaning, in
which is contained the way of being given, from what is indicated
(from the Bedeutung). Thus l the evening star' and ' the
morning star ' have the same indication, but not the same mean-
ing. A word ordinarily stands for its indication; if we wish to
speak of its meaning, we must use inverted commas or some
such device. The indication of a proper name is the object which
it indicates ; the presentation which goes with it is quite subjective;
between the two lies the meaning, which is not subjective and yet
is not the object. A proper name expresses its meaning, and
indicates its indication.
" This theory of indication," adds Mr Russell, " is more
sweeping and general than mine, as appears from the fact that
every proper name is supposed to have the two sides. It seems
to me that only such proper names as are derived from con-
cepts by means of the can be said to have meaning, and that
such words as John merely indicate without meaning. If one
allows, as I do, that concepts can be objects and have proper
names, it seems fairly evident that their proper names, as a
rule, will indicate them without having any distinct meaning;
but the opposite view, though it leads to an endless regress,
does not appear to be logically impossible."
§4. Gomperz
The view of H. Gomperz is developed in Vol. II. of his
APPENDIX D 275
Weltanschauungslehre (1908), Part I. of which is devoted to
Semasiology. It is adopted by Professor Dittrich in his Pro-
bleme der Sprach-psychologie (1913), on whose exposition the
following summary is based :—
In every complete statement (Aussage) we can distinguish:
A. The sounds (Aussage-laute), i.e., the verbal form of the state-
ment, or better the phonesis (Lautung); B. The import (Aussage-
inhalt), i.e., the sense (Sinn) of the statement; C. The foundation
(Aussagegrundlage), i.e., the actual fact (Tatsache) to which the
statement is related. The relations between these three elements
can be thus characterized: the sounds (phonesis) are the expres-
sion (Ausdruck) of the import, and the designation (Bezeichnung)
of the foundation, while the import is the interpretation (Auffas-
sung) of the foundation. In so far as the sounds are treated
as the expressions of the import they are grouped with the state-
ment (Aussage). In so far as the foundation is treated as the fact
comprehended by the import, it can be called the stated fact
(ausgesagte Sachverhalt); or simply, the fact. The relation sub-
sisting between the statement and the fact expressed is called
Meaning (Bedeutung).1
According to Gomperz the sounds which correspond to a full
statement, such as " This bird is flying," have a fivefold repre-
sentative function. The statement, as sound, can thus be con-
sidered under five headings :—
1. It represents itself, qua mere noise, as perceived by anyone
unacquainted with the language.
2. It represents the state of affairs (Tatbestand), ' This bird
is flying/ the sense for whose expression it is normally used, the
import of the thought which is thought by everyone who enun-
ciates it or hears it.
3. It further represents the fact,' This bird is flying/ Le.y every
bit of reality which can be comprehended by the thought' This
bird is flying' and denoted by that sound. (This may be very
various—a starling, or an eagle, or merely' Something is moving').
4. It represents the proposition, ' This bird is flying' as a
significant utterance, wherein the sound, which thus becomes a
linguistic sound, expresses the sense or state of affairs * This bird
is flying/ and together with that sense forms the statement.
5! It represents the fact (Sachverhalt) stated in the proposition,
which is characteristically distinguished both from the foundation
and from the import. " The proposition does not merely state
1
Gomperz, loc. ciU, p. 61.
276 APPENDIX D
that a bit of physical reality is present which can be thought of
as the possessing of a property or as a process, as active or passive,
etc. But it states that a physical process is taking place in which
an active object, viz., a bird, an activity (flying), and an immediate
presence of that object denoted by ' this/ are to be distinguished.
In other words, what the proposition states is ' the flying of this
bird.' This is equally a bit of physical reality, but one of univocal
articulation. It is not only in general a bit of physical reality,
but more precisely a physical process., and quite specifically a
physical activity : but these are mere predicates which could not
have been stated of the sounds as such. . . . In other words,
the foundation can be the same for the three propositions. ' This
bird is flying/ * This is a bird/ and ' I see a living creature/
whereas the fact expressed by these three propositions is different
on each occasion. For in the first what it states is the ' flying of
this bird/ in the second the ' being-a-bird of this,' and in the
third * the seeing of a living creature by me.y If, then, the founda-
tion of these propositions can be one and the same, while the
fact stated is not one and the same, the fact cannot possibly
coalesce with the foundation/9 Nor must the fact be identified
with the import or sense (Inhalt oder Sinn), " which is not some-
thing physical, but a group of logical determinations (Bestim-
mungen)."
From all this, says Dittrich, the peculiarly relational character
of that element of the statement named meaning results. Meaning
cannot be identified with mere designation (Bezeichnung). One
and the same sound, e.g., ' top ' can, he urges, designate very
different foundations; and if, with Martinak, we confine meaning
to the relation between the sign and what is designated, we
cannot reach a satisfactory definition. Interpretation (Auffas-
sung) may similarly be a many-one relation; moreover to use
the term meaning for that relation would omit the linguistic'
element. Nor can meaning be identified with the relation of
expression (Ausdruck). Finally, Meaning appears as a definite
but complex relation, based on the theory of ' total-impressions '
(Totalimpression) and common emotional experiences which
distinguishes the pathempiricists.1 " Any sound whatever can
1
As regards this view, Dr E. H. F. Beck, whose treatise on Die
Impersonalien (1922) is an application of the Gomperz-Dittrich analysis
and to whom we are indebted for certain of the English equivalents
given above, writes to us as follows: " The accent falls on the Gesamt-
eindrucksgefuhl. Speaker and hearer have in common certain
emotional experiences which have a common object and common
reflexes. In every effective communication the reflex—whether
APPENDIX D 277
§5. Baldwin
Professor Baldwin's mode of treating the problem of Meaning
is best studied in his Thought and Things. Vol. II. of this work
deals with what he calls * Experimental Logic/ and Chapter VII.
is devoted to the Development of Logical Meaning. " Our most
promising method of procedure would seem to be to take the
various modes or stages in the development of predication, and
to ask of each in turn as to its structural or recognitive meaning,
its c what'— that is, what it now means, as an item of contextuated
and socially available information. The * what' is the subject-
matter of judgment. Having determined this, we may then
inquire into the instrumental use of such a meaning: the * pro-
posal ' that the meaning when considered instrumentally suggests
or intends. This latter we may call the question of the * why '
of a meaning: the for-what-purpose or end, personal or social,
the meaning is available for experimental treatment. If we use
the phrase * selective thinking,' as we have above, for the entire
process whereby meanings grow in the logical mode—the process
of' systematic determination ' sketched in the preceding chapter
—then we may say that every given meaning is both predication
as elucidation of a proposal, and predication as a proposal for
elucidation. It is as his elucidation that the believer proposes
it to another; it is as proposal that the questioner brings it to the
hearer for his elucidation. We may then go forward by this
method. . . . "
In §10, forty pages later, we " gather up certain conclusions
already reached in statements which take us back to our funda-
mental distinction between Implication and Postulation," as
follows :—
" Implication was defined as meaning so far fixed and
reduced by processes of judgment that no hypothetical or
problematic intent was left in it. Implication, in other
phonesis, gesture, or written symbol—re-instates the common (typical-
general) emotional experience which is referred back to its foundation.
The sign—which term, on account of its wider range, might replace
phonesis—is therefore the causa cognoscendi proximately of a certain
emotional
1
state and ultimately its foundation.''
Dittrich, op. cit., p. 52.
278 APPENDIX D
§6. C. 5 . Peirce
By far the most elaborate and determined attempt to give an
account of signs and their meaning is that of the American
logician C. S. Peirce, from whom William James took the idea
and the term Pragmatism, and whose Algebra of Dyadic Relations
was developed by Schroeder. Unfortunately his terminology
was so formidable that few have been willing to devote time to
its mastery, and the work was never completed. " I am now
working desperately to get written before I die a book on Logic
that shall attract some minds through whom I may do some real
good," he wrote to Lady Welby in December, 1908, and by the
kindness of Sir Charles Welby ^uch portions of the correspondence
as serve to throw light on his published articles on Signs are here
reproduced.
In a paper dated 1867, May 14th (Proc. Am. Acad. Arts and Set.
(Boston), VII (1868), 295), Peirce defined logic as the doctrine of
the formal conditions of the truth of symbols ; i.*., of the refer-
ence of symbols to their objects. Later, when he " recognized
that science consists in inquiry not in * doctrine '—the history of
words, not their etymology, being the key to their meanings,
especially with a word so saturated with the idea of progress as
science," he came to realize, as he wrote m 1908, that for a long
time those who devoted themselves to discussing " the general
reference of symbols to their objects would be obliged to make
researches into the references to their interpretants, too, as well
as into other characters of symbols, and not of symbols alone
280 APPENDIX D
but of all sorts of signs. So that for the present, the man who
makes researches into the reference of symbols to their objects
will be forced to make original studies into all branches of the
general theory of signs.1' This theory he called Semeiotic, and
its essentials are developed in an article in the Monist, 1906,
under the title, " Prolegomena to an Apology for Pragmaticism.,,
A sign, it is there stated, " has an Object and an Interpretant,
the latter being that which the Sign produces in the Quasi-mind
that is the Interpreter by determining the latter to a feeling, to
an exertion, or to a Sign, which determination is the Interpretant.
But it remains to point out that there are usually two Objects,
and more than two Interpretants. Namely, we have to distin-
guish the Immediate Object, which is the object as the Sign itself
represents it, and whose Being is thus dependent upon the
Representation of it in the sign, from the Dynamical Object,
which is the Reality which by some means contrives to deter-
mine the Sign to its Representation. In regard to the Inter-
pretant we have equally to distinguish in the first place, the
Immediate Interpretant, which is the interpretant as it is revealed
in the right understanding of the Sign itself, and is ordinarily
called the l meaning ' of the sign ; while, in the second place, we
have to take note of the Dynamical Interpretant, which is the
actual effect which the Sign, as a Sign, really determines. Finally,
there is what I provisionally term the Final Interpretant, which
refers to the manner in which the Sign tends to represent itself
to be related to its Object. I confess that my own conception of
this third interpretant is not yet quite free from mist."
Reference is then made to the " ten divisions of signs which
have seemed to me to call for my special study. Six turn on the
characters of the Interpretant and three on the characters of the
Object. Thus the division into Icons, Indices, and Symbols
depends upon the different possible relations of a Sign to its
Dynamical Object." Only one division is concerned with the
nature of the Sign itself, and to this he proceeds as follows :—
1
The edition of Peirce's Collected Works, now in course of publication
by the Harvard University Press, has so far brought to light nothing which
necessitates a modification or expansion of the above analysis. Cf.
J. Buchler, Charles Peirce's Empiricism, 1939, pp. 4-8, 155-6, and 180-5;
also Psyche, 1935, pp. 5-7, and Vol. XVIII, 1943, art. cit., "Word Magic."
APPENDIX E
ON NEGATIVE FACTS
had been led by the study of primitive languages, was not essen-
tially a different one. I was therefore extremely glad when the
Authors offered me an opportunity to state my problems, and to
outline my tentative solutions, side by side with their remarkable
theories. I accepted it the more gladly because I hope to show
how important a light the theories of this book throw on the
problems of primitive languages.
It is remarkable that a number of independent inquirers, Messrs
Ogden and Richards, Dr Head, Dr Gardiner and myself, starting
from definite and concrete, yet quite different problems, should
arrive, if not exactly at the same results stated in the same ter-
minology, at least at the construction of similar Semantic theories
based on psychological considerations.
I have therefore to show how, in my own case, that of an
Ethnographer studying primitive mentality, culture, and language,
I was driven into a linguistic theory very much on lines parallel
to those of the present work. In the course of my Ethnographic
researches among some Melanesian tribes of Eastern New Guinea,
which I conducted exclusively by means of the local language,
I collected a considerable number of texts : magical formulae,
items of folk-lore, narratives, fragments of conversation, and
statements of my informants. When, in working out this lin-
guistic material, I tried to translate my texts into English, and
incidentally to write out the vocabulary and grammar of the
language, I was faced by fundamental difficulties. These diffi-
culties were not removed, but rather increased, when I consulted
the extant grammars and vocabularies of Oceanic languages.
The authors of these, mainly missionaries who wrote for the
practical purpose of facilitating the task of their successors,
proceeded by rule of thumb. For instance, in writing a voca-
bulary they would give the next best approximation in English
to a native word.
But the object of a scientific translation of a word is not to
give its rough equivalent, sufficient for practical purposes, but
to state exactly whether a native word corresponds to an idea at
least partially existing for English speakers, or whether it covers
an entirely foreign conception. That such foreign conceptions do
exist for native languages and in great number, is clear. All
words which describe the native social order, all expressions
referring to native beliefs, to specific customs, ceremonies, magical
rites—ail such words are obviously absent from English as from
any European language. Such words can only be translated into
English, not by giving their imaginary equivalent—a real one
300 SUPPLEMENT I
III
Returning once more to our native utterance, it needs no
special stressing that in a primitive language the meaning of any
single word is to a very high degree dependent on its context.
The words ' wood ', * paddle ', * place ' had to be retranslated in
the free interpretation in order to show what is their real meaning,
conveyed to a native by the context in which they appear. Again,
it is equally clear that the meaning of the expression * we arrive
near the village (of our destination)' literally : ' we paddle in
place ', is determined only by taking it in the context of the whole
utterance. This latter again, becomes Only intelligible when it is
placed within its context of situation, if I may be allowed to coin
an expression which indicates on the one hand that the conception
of context has to be broadened and on the other that the situation
in which words are uttered can never be passed over as irrelevant
to the linguistic expression. We see how the conception of con-
text must be substantially widened, if it is to furnish us with its
full utility. In fact it must burst the bonds of mere linguistics
and be carried over into the analysis of the general conditions
under which a language is spoken. Thus, starting from the wider
idea of context, we arrive once more at the results of the foregoing
section, namely that the study of any language, spoken by a
people who live under conditions different from our own and
possess a different culture, must be carried out in conjunction
with the study of their culture and of their environment.
But the widened conception of context of situation yields more
than that. It makes clear the difference in scope and method
between the linguistics of dead and of living languages. The
material on which almost all our linguistic study has been done
so far belongs to dead languages. It is present in the form of
written documents, naturally isolated, torn out of any context of
situation. In fact, written statements are set down with the pur-
pose of being self-contained and self-explanatory. A mortuary
inscription, a fragment of primeval laws or precepts, a chapter or
statement in a sacred book, or to take a more modern example,
a passage from a Greek or Latin philosopher, historian or poet—
one and all of these were composed with the purpose of bringing
their message to posterity unaided, and they had to contain this
message within their own bounds.
To take the clearest case, that of a modern scientific book, the
writer of it sets out to address every individual reader who will
peruse the book and has the necessary scientific training. He
SUPPLEMENT I 307
IV