Alberto Strumia - A "Potency-Act" Interpretation
Alberto Strumia - A "Potency-Act" Interpretation
Alberto Strumia - A "Potency-Act" Interpretation
https://www.scirp.org/journal/jmp
ISSN Online: 2153-120X
ISSN Print: 2153-1196
A “Potency-Act” Interpretation
of Quantum Physics
Alberto Strumia
Keywords
Quantum Mechanics, Quantum Field Theory, Ontological Interpretation,
Potency-Act
1. Introduction
In the present paper we propose some informal comments on the “ontological”
interpretations of quantum physics starting from Heisenberg’s suggestion of
comparing qualitatively some quantum results with the Aristotelian-Thomistic
“Potency-Act” theory.
After presenting a sketch of the most referenced “ontological” interpretations
of quantum mechanics, and more generally of quantum physics (here both refe-
renced shortly as QM), in Section 2, we propose to reconsider, as especially “up
to date”, Heisenberg’s suggestion of retaining QM as a sort of contemporary re-
2. Conventional Interpretations of QM
In his well known book The Road to Reality. A Complete Guide to the Laws of
the Universe [1] at p. 786, Roger Penrose lists six known “ontological” interpre-
tations of QM, i.e.:
1) “Copenhagen”,
2) Many worlds,
3) Environmental decoherence,
4) Consistent histories,
5) Pilot wave,
6) New theory with objective R.
Moreover, in the last years, a new approach to QM has been opened by quan-
tum information leading to a formalism, even if not to a proper new interpreta-
tion, in terms of qubits (see e.g. [2] [3]).
First we will shortly summarize all of them and later we will go back to an
original suggestion by Werner Heisenberg.
1) The “Copenhagen” interpretation
The so called “Copenhagen” interpretation, (for a review see, e.g. [4]) initially
proposed by Niels Bohr, offers a non-realistic viewpoint according to which QM
does not provide a genuine and predictive description of what really is happen-
ing within the world, but it allows to make computations about the measure-
ments an observer is able to do thanks to a suitable detecting apparatus. The ir-
reducible wave and particle frames are considered as “complementary”. Wave
are all really existent in some world, So an infinite number of “parallel worlds”
are intended to be “actually” existent, each within its “real” universe. All the pa-
rallel universes are non-connected components of a whole, so that only one of
them may be observed by us. The wave function involves a superposition of
many “real” worlds together.
While the “Copenhagen” interpretation is “instrumentalisitc” (in the sense of
Popper [6] and T.S. Kuhn [7]) (or even idealistic or “conventionalistic” in the
sense of P. Feyerabend, see, e.g. [8]), the “many worlds” interpretation is exces-
sively “realistic”. Moreover, the latter interpretation, even if it is fascinating, ma-
nifestly violates the “Occam’s razor” simplicity principle [9]. which is normally
assumed as scientifically basic. Why to suppose the true “actual” existence of in-
finite worlds when only one of them is observable by us?
3) The “Environmental decoherence” interpretation
The “Environmental decoherence” interpretation includes the interaction with
the environment, i.e., what is considered as “external” to the system on which an
observer (human or instrumental) is performing measurements.
So the wave function governing the “whole” is required to include, beside the
wave function ψ S related to the system on which one is performing mea-
surements and the wave function ψ A describing the instrumental apparatus
needed to exploit measurements, also an almost inaccessible wave function for
the “external” environment ψ env , which must be considered no longer as “ex-
ternal”.
ψ = ψ S ⊗ ψ A ⊗ ψ env . (3)
Interactions of the system with the environment and the apparatus appear
both as the “causal agent” determining the collapse from coherence of the wave
function. Such interaction, which may be even “non-local”, is recognized as the
physical basis of entanglement [10].
The causal contribution of environment to decoherence needs to be added to
the interaction between the measurement apparatus and the system itself. Such
approach is “holistic” in the sense that a quantum system cannot be treated as an
isolated one, being always influenced by the environment.
4) Consistent histories
The “Consistent histories” interpretation [11] considers QM as an intrinsically
probabilistic theory, in which probability does not depend on observational and
measurement operations, but is involved in the wave equation itself as a “true
law of nature”.
Ontologically it appears that “probabilistic causation” is a kind of causality re-
lation in the physical microscopic world, aside “deterministic causation” in the
physical macroscopic world. Introduction of “probability” within the causality is
no longer interpreted as a lack of causation, or as a consequence of our ignor-
ance about the physical world, but as a new way of actuating causation in QM,
aside the “deterministic” causality in classical mechanics.
5) Pilot wave
The “pilot wave” interpretation proposed by Louis De Broglie and later mod-
ified by David Bohm attempts a classical-like approach to quantum mechanics
suggesting that the particle trajectories are driven by a pilot wave, being oscilla-
tions of some matter field ψ just as a photon is a quantum of oscillating elec-
tromagnetic fields E , B . In Bohm’s variant of the theory, a sort of “quantum
potential” is guessed and evaluated, the effect of which is to drive particles along
definite trajectories leading to interference and wave effects. But the last ap-
proach, in its original form, is not compatible with Einstein’s relativity.
“The most thoroughly worked-out theory of this type is the pilot wave
theory developed by de Broglie and presented by him at the Fifth Solvay
Conference held in Brussels in 1927, revived by David Bohm in 1952, and
currently an active area of research by a small group of physicists and phi-
losophers.
According to this theory, there are particles with definite trajectories, that
are guided by the quantum wave function.” [12]
“Often referred as ‘objective-R’ theory. ‘R’ stands for the quantum state re-
duction when a measurement is taking place. Supporters of this interpreta-
tion believe that today’s quantum mechanics is not here to stay and will be
“the relationship between this use and Aristotle’s notion was not made by
Heisenberg in full detail, beyond noting their common character: that of
signifying the system’s objective capacity to be found later to possess a
property in actuality. For such actualization, Heisenberg required measure-
ment to have taken place, an interaction with external systems that disrupts
the otherwise independent, natural evolution of the quantum system. The
notion of state actualization was later taken up by others, including Shimo-
ny, in the search for a law-like measurement process. Yet, the relation of
quantum potentiality to Aristotle’s original notion has been viewed as mainly
terminological, even by those who used it thus.”
world”.
iii) As a remarkable epistemological consequence it follows that the “Occam’s
razor” principle which requires to minimize the number of entities and assump-
tions within a scientific theory, is fully satisfied. No superfluous actual worlds
are required: “Entities must not be multiplied without necessity” (Latin, “entia
non sunt multiplicanda sine necessitate”).
“in modern physics the concept of possibility, that played such a decisive
role in Aristotle’s philosophy, has moved again into a central place.” [20]
The third ones behave like “human freedom”, being unpredictable in each in-
dividual choice which may be indifferently oriented, if it is left alone.
Manifestly according to the “Aristotelian-Thomistic” philosophy of nature, on
which the “Potency-Act” interpretation of QM is based, the probability is intrin-
sic to the system and is not induced by external or subjective factors. Moreover:
“the transition from the ‘possible’ to the ‘actual’ takes place as soon as the
interaction between the object and the measuring device, and thereby with
the rest of the world, has come into play; it is not connected with the act of
registration of the result in the mind of the observer.” [14] (pgs 54-55).
“Final causes in fact provide a better ontology for quantum mechanics than
spontaneous causation. The idea of ‘spontaneity’ is unanalyzable and there-
fore of little use in quantum mechanics.
In addition, it is ontologically sterile in the context of quantum measure-
ment, as shown by a historical and conceptual review of the role of efficient
causation in experimental physics.” [19]
8. Conclusions
We have proposed an introductory sketch on the recent revival of interest in
Aristotelian-Thomistic “Potency-Act” theory of matter states (and more gener-
ally “entities”) in order to provide an intriguing ontological interpretation of
quantum physics, as originally was suggested by Werner Heisenberg at the very
beginning of quantum mechanics. New perspectives appear especially promising
even in order to rediscover the Thomistic doctrine of “analogy of being” (Latin,
“analogia entis”) [21].
The latter way of investigation, about quantum physics, appears to be com-
Acknowledgement
I want to thank especially J.E. Brenner for relevant interesting suggestions he
proposed to improve the quality of my paper.
Conflicts of Interest
The author declares no conflicts of interest regarding the publication of this pa-
per.
References
[1] Penrose, R. (2004) The Road to Reality. A Complete Guid to the Laws of the Un-
iverse. Jonathan Cape, London.
[2] Deutsch, D. (2004) It from Qubit. In: Barrow, J., et al., Eds., Science & Ultimate Re-
ality, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 90-102.
https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511814990.008
[3] Dür, W. and Heusler, S. (2014) The Physics Teacher, 52, 489.
https://arxiv.org/abs/1312.1463
https://doi.org/10.1119/1.4897588
[4] Faye, J. (2019) Copenhagen Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics.
https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2019/entries/qm-copenhagen
[5] Vaidman, L. (2018) Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics.
https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2018/entries/qm-manyworlds
[6] Popper, K.R. (1992) The Logic of Scientific Discovery. Routledge, London and New
York.
[7] Kuhn, T.S. (1996) The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. The University of Chica-
go Press, Chicago and London.
[8] Feyerabend, P. (1993) Against Method. Verso, London.
[9] Baker, A. (2016) Simplicity. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/simplicity
[10] Zeh, H.D. (1995) Decoherence: Basic Concepts and Their Interpretation.
https://arXiv:quant-ph/9506020
[11] Griffiths, R.B. (2019) The Consistent Histories Approach to Quantum Mechanics.
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/qm-consistent-histories
[12] Myrvold, W. (2018) Philosophical Issues in Quantum Theory. Stanford Encyclope-
dia of Philosophy.
https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2018/entries/qt-issues
[13] Lazarou, D.K. (2018) Interpretation of Quantum Theory. An Overview. Stanford