Politicka Misao 1 2011 94 107 PDF
Politicka Misao 1 2011 94 107 PDF
Politicka Misao 1 2011 94 107 PDF
NEBOJŠA BLANUŠA*
Summary
Publicly, conspiracy theories are considered a bizarre mode of thought. In the
academic discourse, they are unserious statements positioned between bad
imitation of scientific theory and political pathology. Therefore, their authors
and consumers experience a procedure of exclusion from the community of
“serious people”. But there are situations in which conspiracy theories are
taken seriously, and established precisely as an exclusion device. These situ-
ations are predominantly interpreted as collective endangerment or political
crisis. In that case, conspiracy theories stem from the center of political power
as legitimate interpretation of reality. This was realized in an extreme way
in the Nazi regime. So, the present academic discourse produces the Other
by reason of standing for conspiracy theories. In political crisis and authori-
tarian or totalitarian regimes, the Other is produced by conspiracy theories.
Historically, the academic attitude is partly produced by the consequences of
the other attitude, through triple “demystification” of the conspiracy panic of
Nazism/Fascism, Stalinism and, in the West, McCarthyism. But, structurally,
it is the attitude of conspiracy-theory panic, or mimicry in exclusion. We pro-
pose a different approach, one that will simultaneously avoid acceptance of
conspiracy theories as “facts” and their reduction to a phenomenon of mass
hysteria. They should be considered beyond the opposition between delusion
and hidden truth. Therefore, we define them as an interpretation pattern, struc-
tured as a double phantasm with the possibility of being traversed. This defini-
tion is close to Sloterdijk’s conception of Cynical Reason, according to which
we can differentiate between cynical and kynical conspiracy theories. Cynical
conspiracy theories speak in the name of totalitarian and authoritarian power
trying to defend an organismic community, and preserve a phantasmatic struc-
ture. Kynical conspiracy theories are speaking from the position of particular,
fragmentational and singular agents. From the periphery of discourse, they
*
Nebojša Blanuša, lecturer at the Faculty of Political Science in courses Political Psychology,
Social Psychology, Methods of Research and Political Behaviour.
Politička misao, god. 48, br. 1, 2011, str. 94-107 95
criticize the power elite by indicating the cleavages that are concealed by cyn-
ics. In that way, kynical conspiracy theories perform a positive function as a
way of “exposing the dirty linen” of the political regime.
Keywords: conspiracy theory, cynical reason, cynicism, kynicism, psychoana-
lysis, double phantasm
The purpose of this paper is twofold. First, to depathologize conspiracy theory (fur-
ther in the text: “CT”), and second, to place it, as a valuable scientific concept, into
the context of the theory of cynical reason and psychoanalysis. According to this
argumentation, CTs are a sort of symptomal reading of reality wherein it is assumed
that, under the influence of the undeclared (hidden) interest (in domination, exploi-
tation, etc.), there is a gap between the “official”, public meaning of some interpreta-
tion and its “actual” intention, where there is a tension between the explicitly enun-
ciated content of the text and its pragmatic presuppositions (Žižek, 1994: 10). Also,
CTs are much more present in the political discourse than it is usually assumed, and
the holders of conspiratorial thinking are subjects from various domains of power
(ranging from prominent politicians of the central state to newspaper satirists). Fur-
thermore, the political potentials of CTs are not merely authoritarian. Part of them
could function as a way of “exposing the dirty linen “of the political regime.
Let’s start with the analysis of something that used to be called the “common
wisdom” or the point of pathologization of CTs.
(1) Publicly, CTs are considered a bizarre mode of thought or obscure gestures.
In the academic discourse, they are perceived as unserious statements positioned
between bad imitation of scientific theory and political pathology. Therefore, their
authors and consumers experience an exclusion procedure from the community of
“serious people”. So, labelling them as “conspiracy theorists” is a form of disquali-
fication and stigmatization, a manner of calling someone a crackpot for his/her
holding of illegitimate knowledge (Bratich, 2008: 3-5).
This line of thinking, claiming that “there is something wrong about CTs!”, is
usually associated with Karl Popper (2003) and his consideration of CTs as secular-
ized religious superstition. For him, CTs are similar to Homer’s theory of society,
according to which whatever is happening on the fields of Troy is only a reflec-
tion of conspiracies on Mount Olympus. In the place of the gods, CTs only install
powerful and malicious groups responsible for critical social events such as wars,
famine, unemployment, political crisis, etc. According to Popper, there is not much
truth in CTs. Only few conspiracies are fully consumed or accomplished. So, as an
explanation of a social phenomenon, CT overlooks the fact that nothing happens as
it was planned. There have always been unintended consequences of social activi-
ties, and that is exactly what the main goal of social theory is: to explain unintended
96 Blanuša, N., Depathologized Conspiracy Theories and Cynical Reason: Discursive Positions...
Even a modicum of security under present-day conditions calls for the disco-
very, neutralization and eventual prevention of the paranoid. (ibid.: 184)
What is interesting here is the paranoid nature of these lines themselves!
Franz Neumann is another contributor to the pathologization of conspirato-
rial thinking. In his seminal work “Fear and Politics” (1957), he perceives the be-
lief in CTs as a consequence of alienation. To be more precise, as a consequence
of alienation on three levels: psychological, social and political. The first level is a
consequence of universal social repression of libidinous drives (well-known as the
“repressive hypothesis”), manifested as ego alienation from drives. The second is
the product of industrial society – alienation from work – produced by a monoto-
nous, stultifying job and by values of the bourgeois society, which makes the mid-
dle class in particular prone to caesarism or regressive identification with authori-
tarian political leaders, regression to a horde and loss of the ego. The competitive
market situation increases the fear from status degradation and paranoid ideas that
are exemplified by CTs of authoritarian leaders. In this social constellation, CT
transforms real fear into neurotic fear which is restrained by identification with the
leader-demagogue and his clique. These affective tendencies gradually disable the
citizens from independent thinking and active civic participation, and foster politi-
Politička misao, god. 48, br. 1, 2011, str. 94-107 97
cal alienation or rejection of the whole political system that leads to political apa-
thy. This paves the way for the caesaristic movement which despises the rules and
institutionalizes the fear.
American historian Richard Hofstadter relied on these previous ideas. His clas-
sic essay “The Paranoid Style in American Politics” (1965) describes his under-
standing of CTs as the products of (not clinical but) political paranoia. He describes
belief in CTs as a paranoid style of thought “simply because no other word ad-
equately evokes the qualities of heated exaggeration, suspiciousness, and conspira-
torial fantasy that I have in mind” (ibid.: 3). It is a worldview and a way of self-ex-
pression in which the central role is played by a sense of persecution, systematized
in grandiose CTs about historical events and processes. For him, style is the most
important feature here, “the way in which ideas are believed and advocated, rather
than... the truth or falsity of their content” (ibid.: 5), since “any system of beliefs can
be espoused in the paranoid style”. As the most rationalistic derangement, paranoia
is very close to reason.1 So, paranoid style and normal political reasoning differ not
in “the absence of facts, but (in) the leap of the imagination” (ibid.: 37). It is an “ex-
aggeration of the ordinary”, which threatens to become unreasonable mainstream
(Bratich, 2008: 38).2 For Hofstadter, this paranoid style is peculiar to Fascism,
Stalinism, “frustrated nationalisms”, populist movements and political extremists
which do not support the pluralistic consensus of liberal society.
This specific conceptual suture of irrationality and dangerous political activity
has become the official attitude of the liberal state. It is very often used for patholo-
gization of political dissent (Bratich, 2008: 31) and consequently for exclusion. So,
due to this exclusionary approach, one cannot hope to be taken seriously if one be-
lieves in CTs.
Nevertheless, CTs are not merely a marginalized and obscure form of thinking,
the function of which is only to establish contours of normality. There are situations
in which CTs are taken seriously, and are no longer established as a reason for ex-
clusion, but precisely as an exclusion device: as the mode of interpretation for de-
fining the enemy. These situations are dominantly interpreted as collective endan-
germent or political crisis. In that case, CTs stem from the centre of political power
as a legitimate interpretation of reality. Here, the following are invoked by enuncia-
tion of CTs: state of emergency, defensive consensus, and suspension of democratic
rules and values (if there are any). In the name of protection of state, order, com-
munity or “our way of life”, the line of exclusion is drawn by CTs. The well-known
1
Daniel Pipes would say that it is the “secret vice of the rational mind” (1997: 34).
2
Lipset and Raab (1970) would say: “The same values and moral commitments that have been
the constant strength of our democratic life (individualism, antistatism, egalitarianism)... provide
the substance of extremist threats to that democratic life” (p. 30 in: Bratich, 2008: 39).
98 Blanuša, N., Depathologized Conspiracy Theories and Cynical Reason: Discursive Positions...
theories about internal and external enemies fall within this category. According to
Salecl (2002: 52), this is the situation where the usual distinction between ideologi-
cal discourse and allusion disappears. Here we have a direct and open statement
about the enemy, the existence of which can only be alluded to in regular ideologi-
cal discourse. No ideological mask is present here any more. This was realized in
an extreme manner in the Nazi regime. After having gained power, Hitler tried to
defeat the alleged conspiracy of the Elders of Zion by his own (and his fellows’)
counter-conspiracy. There are numerous historical examples of a similar function of
CTs in the communist, but also in the so-called democratic world (recall the “Red
Scare”, the theory of Saddam’s weaponry of mass destruction, or Tudjman’s theory
of “black, yellow and green devils”).
Let us resume! The present academic discourse produces the Other by denoting
as such those who advocate CTs. But, in times of political crisis and authoritarian
or totalitarian regimes, the Other is produced by CTs. Historically, the academic at-
titude is partly produced by the consequences of the other attitude, mostly through
triple “demystification” of the conspiracy panic3 of Nazism/Fascism, Stalinism
and, in the West, McCarthyism, repeated and exemplified during the 1990s (and
the present decade) in the US as a way of labelling domestic and international ter-
rorism. But, structurally, the academic attitude is also a form of conspiracy-theory
panic, or mimicry in exclusion, guided by the will for moderation.
The outcome of this exclusion of CTs from the “community of serious state-
ments” is the attitude that they “should be neither believed in nor investigated”
(Pigden, 2007: 219). For Charles Pigden, this attitude became conventional wisdom
(ibid.), but a very dangerous one in terms of democratic culture and various intellec-
tual disciplines. On the contrary, in his opinion “we are rationally entitled to believe
in conspiracy theories if that is what the evidence suggests. Some conspiracy theories
are sensible and some are silly, but if they are silly this is not because they are con-
spiracy theories but because they suffer from some specific defect – for instance, that
the conspiracies they postulate are impossible or far-fetched” (ibid.). Belief in CTs
is often a rational option and every historically or politically literate person is to a
great extent a conspiracy theorist, even though many intellectuals and political com-
mentators are not aware of this fact. If one believes in sources of public information
(media, institutions, historical texts, etc.), a great deal of what they present to us is
not possible to explain outside of the conspiratorial interpretation framework. Also,
there are so many CTs that are accepted as unproblematic and legitimate knowledge.
For example, whatever we might think about 9/11, it is rational to believe that this
3
I borrow this term from Bratich (2008: 8). It designates a form of moral panic, or a way of de-
fining a minority group as folk devils, “a condition, episode, person or group of persons [who]
become defined as a threat to societal values and interests” (Cohen, 1972: 9).
Politička misao, god. 48, br. 1, 2011, str. 94-107 99
event is the result of conspiracy. Otherwise, we should assume that the perpetrators
have been assembled by accident, with a sudden idea to hijack the planes and crash
them into the Twins, the White House, and the Pentagon. But this is not even con-
sidered as a credible CT. Moreover, history abounds in coups, assassinations, mass
murders, etc. that are inconceivable outside of the conspiratorial framework. (Had
the plans of Brutus and Cassius, or of the “Black Hand” been public, Caesar could
have avoided the Senate House, and Franz Ferdinand Sarajevo, or arrested the po-
tential murderers. Holocaust and Stalin purges are the most pronounced examples
of mass killings planned and partly executed in secret [ibid.: 223].) Conspiracies are
common even at the everyday level of democratic politics, for example: in leadership
challenge, or in bribery, corruption, etc. So, people are prone to conspire.
Therefore, consistent acceptance of conventional wisdom might lead us into an
absurd situation, and render many parts of history unbelievable and unknowable,
along with being politically extremely dangerous. If we did not believe in CTs, then
“we would not even be allowed to investigate these questions, since any answer we
came up with would be something we were not entitled to believe” (ibid.: 225). In
the interpretation of current events:
We could believe in the dead bodies but not that anyone had conspired to kill
them; believe in the missing money, but not in the felonious theft. And it would
be a political disaster, since it would confer immunity on political criminals of all
sorts, from the perpetrators of genocide down to bribe-taking congressmen. We
could not punish people for crimes that we were not entitled to believe in or in-
vestigate. (ibid.: 226)
In that case, the principle that the price of freedom is constant vigilance would
be a meaningless phrase. We would be officially blind to most serious threats to the
democratic order.
This critique has initiated the debate about CTs as knowledge.
The main questions were: Is it possible to establish the criteria for differentia-
tion between epistemically unwarranted and warranted CTs? How to differentiate the
flawed features of some CT as such from conspiracy theorists’ epistemic errors? Is it
correct to apply the criterion of falsifiability to CTs? Is the conspiracy theorists’ sus-
picion against mechanisms of public production of information reasonable? Finally,
is it possible to determine or to estimate the level of conspirativity of a society?
There is not enough space here to reconstruct this debate, but the main conclu-
sions were:
– it is very hard to establish the criteria for the determination of unwarranted
CTs as such without confusing them with conspiracy theorists’ tendencies,
e.g. fetishist relationship to errant data;
100 Blanuša, N., Depathologized Conspiracy Theories and Cynical Reason: Discursive Positions...
4
The reliability and stability of records depends mainly on the larger question of the level of
conspiratorial activity in the surrounding institutions. This point is all the more pressing in the
digital age, in which many records take the form of highly malleable digital encodings (Basham,
2003: 102-103).
5
Steve Clarke in: Coady, 2006: 126.
6
Lee Basham in: Coady, 2006: 72.
Politička misao, god. 48, br. 1, 2011, str. 94-107 101
(2) I propose a different approach, one that will simultaneously avoid accept-
ance of CTs as “facts” and their mere reduction to a phenomenon of mass hysteria
(Žižek, 1999: 6). CTs should be considered beyond the opposition between delusion
and hidden truth. Therefore, I define them simply as theories that posit conspira-
cies (Pigden, 2007: 226).7 They are more or less popular interpretations of politics
regardless of their conclusiveness. Their primary function is to determine the front-
line friend/enemy and they should, therefore, be studied as a manifestation of po-
litical cleavages.
First, I will examine their structure, and after that, their political function.
My thesis is that we can explain their structure using the tools of Lacanian psy-
choanalysis, particularly the theory of double phantasm (Salecl, 2002: 31; Žižek,
1996: 87; Stavrakakis, 1999).
7
CTs are an interpretative framework which defines political events and wider political pro-
cesses as a consequence of premeditated and deceptively random activities, i.e. secret agree-
ments regarding the performance of illegal and immoral activities (and objectives), or their ap-
plication in accomplishing illegal objectives.
8
Literally translated from Italian, it means: What do you want? See how it is elaborated in La-
can’s graph of desire (1983: 291-295) and by Žižek (2002: 155-168), who claims that it is a wide-
spread phenomenon in politics since every political request is caught up in the dialectic which
always implies something different from its literal meaning.
102 Blanuša, N., Depathologized Conspiracy Theories and Cynical Reason: Discursive Positions...
is our society not functioning”, “who is to blame for our pauperization”, “who is
exploiting us” – and, in the long run, “who is stealing our enjoyment”. “In the case
of anti-Semitism, the answer to ‘What does the Jew want?’ is a fantasy of ‘Jewish
conspiracy’: a mysterious power of Jews to manipulate events, to pull the strings
behind the scenes” (ibid.: 160). This image of the enemy is the pre-ideological core
of ideology containing the spectral phantasm which fills the void in the Real while
functioning as defence from “Che vuoi?” and, at the same time, as the framework
which coordinates our desire, or the “formal matrix, on which are grafted various
ideological formations” (Žižek, 1994: 13). In the sense of the latter, a CT also pos-
sesses a symbolic dimension which manifests itself through a series of signifiers,
specific of the ideological context within which they manifest themselves, most
usually in the form of more or less elaborated narratives.
The main function of the Symbolic order, in the framework of which CTs take
form, is to make co-existence with others at least bearable by imposing laws and ob-
ligations, i.e. to act as a kind of attenuator and consideration generator. It manifests
itself as the third element which, while it is functional, prevents the relationship
“between me and my neighbours so that our relations do not explode in murderous
violence” (Žižek, 2006: 46). Therefore, as long as the Symbolic order is functional,
CTs remain a local phenomenon which reflects the dynamics of the interrelation
between various agents and the modalities of coping with different problems. If
the symbolic network is narrowed down, and its constituents are suspended, for
instance in the context of social anomy or collapse of a certain order, the black-
-and-white description technique provided by CTs becomes more prominent. With-
in such a context, a single moment of its temporary complete suspension is enough
to induce violence, conflict, or war.
Nevertheless, in order to enable a relatively successful functioning of the sym-
bolic order, it has to be supported by the phantasm of its functional completeness. It
is a phantasm which accompanies the spectral phantasm of CTs. In other words, we
can talk about two types of phantasms. One is the idealistic construction of society
or community, whereas the other is the unsettling explanation as to why something
(or everything) “went wrong”. These two phantasms – used to express the afore-
mentioned dichotomy – are closely interrelated. Under certain circumstances, on
the level of an individual subject and a certain discourse, these two phantasms may
become mutually interchangeable as to which shall dominate and which shall be
subordinate. A more dominant first phantasm shall imply a higher level of identifi-
cation with the symbolic order, and thus more pronounced confidence in official au-
thorities and structures, a situation which corresponds to the context of a relatively
“peaceful” reproduction of the existing order, wherein disturbing factors are easy to
neutralize or present as exceptions to the rule. The situation in which a more pro-
Politička misao, god. 48, br. 1, 2011, str. 94-107 103
nounced dislocation of the Symbolic order, due to some Real antagonism, causes the
first concept to lose its functionality, leads to the explanation and, quite often, identi-
fication of the agent responsible for the problems who has the role of “thief of enjoy-
ment” (Salecl, 2002). Quite often, these social agents may be various ethnic, linguis-
tic, or racial minority groups, civil associations and organizations, but also political
and other elites within the community which perceives itself as being threatened, or
outside of it. In this situation, the dominant position is taken over by the unsettling
aspect of the phantasm which leads to distancing from and distrust of the designated
culprits, accompanied by the request for their neutralisation and/or removal.
Such an interpretation of the subject split between the phantasms is close to
Sloterdijk’s (1992) definition of the cynical reason as a universal and diffuse phe-
nomenon of the present. According to this author, the cynical subject is quite aware
of the distance between the ideological mask and the social reality, but he nonethe-
less still insists upon the mask. Translated into the language of the previous psy-
choanalytical explanation, this means that, on the level of everyday experience, in
the course of reception and interpretation of politically relevant events, the subject
experiences a gap between the ideological meaning of discourse, i.e. the formal
vocabulary used to publicly describe the event in the framework of the “stable and
well-functioning” system (phantasm1), and premonition in the sense of decoding
the “actual” meaning of this event on the level of political games of particular in-
terest of the actual participants in a wider temporal perspective (phantasm2). In this
process, phantasm2 quite often acquires the form of CT. In order to become clearly
articulated and expressed, it requires an acute experience of personal and/or col-
lective instrumentalization and/or threat, and an available or conceivable culprit.
In that situation, the actual opinion (or, rather, what the critical mass suspects to be
true) is expressed in order to go through a “purification ritual” and establish the old
or new ideological discourse, i.e. remain in the framework of double phantasms.
Sloterdijk also differentiates cynicism from kynicism, two terms which have in
common the “motive of self-preservation in times of crisis”, cheekiness, “releasing
the breaks” and “blurting things which are not for the public” (ibid.: 118), i.e. “a
kind of shameless, ‘dirty’ realism” (ibid.: 197). Nevertheless, they are the expres-
sion of different positions of power. Sloterdijk associates cynicism with the Mas-
ter’s culture and “refinement”, whereas kynicism is associated with the popular,
plebeian thought, i.e. opposition to official ideology which is expressed in the most
plastic manner through satirical subversion. In doing so, kynicism acts as “a reso-
luteness not to let the naked truth that hides behind cultural disguises to elude it”
(ibid.: 158). Cynicism, on the other hand, tries to reduce everything “higher” to the
lowest denominator, and represents “the masters’ antithesis to their own idealism as
ideology and as masquerade” (ibid.: 118). Since, in history, it appeared after kyni-
104 Blanuša, N., Depathologized Conspiracy Theories and Cynical Reason: Discursive Positions...
cism, cynicism may be defined as kynicism that passed over to the side of power
and idealism of the governing ideology, and became its shadow, i.e. its dark side.
Therefore, depending on whether they are critically oriented towards the governing
structures and dominant ideology or they support them, we may differentiate be-
tween kynical and cynical CTs.
Hypothetical Conclusion
1. According to the previous analysis of cynicism and kynicism, cynical CTs would
support the integration and homogenization of the community, as well as the totali-
tarian and authoritarian power. They are communicated from the position of unity
towards a potentially dangerous and unacceptable particularity. These are theories
which speak from the position of (or on behalf of) the centre of political power, and
strive to protect a monolithically conceived system and a certain form of organical-
ly conceived community. This is not an instance of non-reflexive dogmatism, as it
may look like at first sight, but rather a way of functioning of cynicism in conditions
that are perceived as a crisis. Cynicism usually functions according to the formula
“They know very well what they are doing, but still, they are doing it”, which means
that it is manifested as hypocrisy in the interpretation of political events – by means
of declarative acceptance of public interpretations and guessing the “true” motives
and goals of the protagonists, which is a fertile ground for interpretation through
CTs. It is a backside of the public façade which Žižek identifies with the distancing
from the public law and its derision from the position of the obscene internal side,
structured by phantasms, which is manifested through the imagining of conspiracies
against their own object of enjoyment. When the situation is perceived as danger-
ous, or is just represented that way, CTs start cropping up among the public, regard-
less of whether it is an instance of a political group (such as a party or coalition)
which is trying to preserve or regain its own position of power and/or implement
a certain more or less hegemonic project, or of bitter and distrustful citizens. In all
these instances, public discourse is conceptually reduced in order to protect in the
most efficient possible manner the imaginary source of pleasure, which is actually
the “Common Thing”, represented as a live organism.
2. Unlike previous theories, kynical theories speak from the position of particu-
lar, fragmentational and singular agents. They criticise the (governing) power elite
from the periphery of the political discourse, pointing at cleavages which the cynics
tacitly ignore, except when they feel endangered. Through kynical CTs could be ex-
pressed the criticism of the Government or dominant political agents in the activi-
ties of which CTs find tendencies of deliberate restriction of freedoms and rights,
usurpation of power and illegitimacy of its operation, manipulation, corruption, be-
trayal of trust, etc.
Politička misao, god. 48, br. 1, 2011, str. 94-107 105
Although they may be embittered by political events, the behaviour of the elite
and the functioning of the order to the same extent as the cynics, they differ from
them at least by partially abandoning the phantasmatic framework. In this sense,
they either identify with the inability to establish a community as a harmonious
whole and with the inability to establish a democratic order based on a permanent-
ly occupied position of power – and thus either deride these attempts or denounce
them as dangerous political acts – or they sublimate their previous identification
with the Common Thing into an Ego-ideal expressed through some kind of demo-
cratic ideology from which they later on criticise the behaviour of the bearers of
political power. In that way, kynical CTs perform a positive function as a way of
“exposing the dirty linen” of the political regime.9
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Blanuša, Nebojša, 2010: The Structure of Conspiratorial Beliefs in Croatia, Anali Hrvat-
skog politološkog društva 2009 (6): 113-143.
Basham, Lee, 2003: Malevolent Global Conspiracy, Journal of Social Philosophy (34) 1:
91-103, Spring 2003, Blackwell Publishing Inc.
Bratich, Jack Z., 2008: Conspiracy panics: political rationality and popular culture, Sta-
te University of New York Press, Albany.
Coady, David (ed.), 2006: Conspiracy theory: the philosophical debate, Ashgate,
Hampshire.
Cohen, Stanley, 1972: Folk devils and moral panics, MacGibbon & Kee, London.
Hofstadter, Richard, 1965: The Paranoid Style in American Politics and Other Essays,
Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.
Lakan, Žak [Lacan, Jacques], 1983: Spisi, Prosveta, Beograd.
Neumann, Franz, 1992: Demokratska i autoritarna država: studije o političkoj i pravnoj
teoriji, Naprijed, Zagreb.
Pigden, Charles, 2007: Conspiracy Theories and the Conventional Wisdom, Episteme: A
Journal of Social Epistemology (4) 2: 219-232.
Pipes, Daniel, 1997: Conspiracy: How the Paranoid Style Flourishes and Where It Co-
mes From, Free Press, New York.
Popper, Karl, R., 2003: Otvoreno društvo i njegovi neprijatelji I-II (sv. II: Plima proro-
štva: Hegel, Marx i posljedice), Kruzak, Zagreb.
9
On whether I am right in the case of Croatian CTs, see another, already published article
(Blanuša, 2010).
106 Blanuša, N., Depathologized Conspiracy Theories and Cynical Reason: Discursive Positions...
Nebojša Blanuša
DEPATOLOGIZACIJA TEORIJA ZAVJERA I CINIČNI UM:
DISKURZIVNE POZICIJE I FANTAZMATSKE STRUKTURE
Sažetak
Teorije zavjera obično se drže bizarnim oblikom mišljenja. Akademski dis-
kurs smatra ih neozbiljnim iskazima i pozicionira ih u prostoru između loše
imitacije znanstvene teorije i političke patologije. Stoga nad njihovim auto-
rima i konzumentima provodi proceduru isključivanja iz zajednice “ozbiljnih
ljudi”. No ima situacija u kojima teorije zavjera bivaju shvaćene ozbiljno i
tada se uspostavljaju kao samo sredstvo isključivanja. Ove su situacije domi-
nantno interpretirane kao kolektivne ugroze ili političke krize. U tom slučaju
teorije zavjera dolaze iz središta političke moći kao legitimne interpretacije
zbilje. Ovakva je situacija u ekstremnom smislu realizirana u nacističkom re-
žimu. Dakle, sadašnji akademski diskurs proizvodi Drugog zbog zastupanja
teorija zavjere. No u političkim krizama, autoritarnim i totalitarnim režimima
Drugi se proizvodi putem teorija zavjera. Povijesno gledano, akademski je
stav dijelom proizvod posljedica drugog stava, putem trostruke “demistifika-
cije” konspirativne panike nacizma/fašizma, staljinizma i, na Zapadu, makar-
tizma. Međutim, strukturalno gledajući ovaj je stav panika o teorijama zavjera
ili mimikrija prethodnog oblika panike u pogledu isključivosti. Autor predla-
že drukčiji pristup koji istovremeno izbjegava prihvaćanje teorija zavjera kao
činjenica, ali i njihovo reduciranje na fenomen masovne histerije. Teorije za-
vjera analizira onkraj opreke deluzije i skrivene istine. Stoga teorije zavjera
definira kao obrazac interpretacije, strukturiran kao dvostruka fantazma s mo-
gućnošću njegova “presijecanja”. Ovakva je definicija bliska Sloterdijkovoj
koncepciji ciničnog uma, sukladno kojoj je moguće razlikovati cinične i ki-
nične teorije zavjera. Cinične teorije zavjera govore u ime totalitarne i autori-
tarne vlasti u obranu organizmički zamišljene zajednice i zadržavaju strukturu
Politička misao, god. 48, br. 1, 2011, str. 94-107 107