Ghazali's Account of Signification PDF
Ghazali's Account of Signification PDF
Ghazali's Account of Signification PDF
Ghazali‟s Account
Of Signification
Ass. Hadi Ensar Ceylan
Ankara University, Faculty of Divinity
[email protected]
I. INTRODUCTION
Signification is a crucial subject in Islamic thought particularly in logic and
methodology. Signification is primarily a subject of logic in all its details. In
methodology, the subject is considered in terms of the signification of utter-
ance to meaning in acknowledged sources for obtaining judgment. In logic
and methodology, the subject of signification is certainly treated in different
ways. However, this does not prevent signification from having common
foundations in both sciences. Therefore, it is possible to compare the
sciences of logic and methodology with respect to signification. This possi-
bility implies a vast area. The present study will only attempt to compare
“the ways in which meaning is signified by utterances” in logic and metho-
dology based on Ghazali‟s (d.505/1111) ideas. Our choice of Ghazali could
concisely be expressed in a few points. First, Ghazali occupies a prominent
place in methodology. His prominence stems from the fact that his work al-
Mustasfâ was a turning point in the systematization of methodology. Al-
though we can talk about an established framework for the books on metho-
dology compiled before Ghazali in general, the framework was not so much
organized in itself.1 This was also a source of complaint for Ghazali, who
1
This lack of organization is observed about which subject should be dealt with where and
how. It was a result of different ideas about the subject matter of methodology and can be
regarded as normal in a sense because such periods are inevitable for all sciences in their
process of formation and systematization. For a more detailed examination, see Cessâs
(ö.370/980), al-Fusûl; Bâkıllânî (ö.403/1012), al-Takrîb ve‟l-Irshâd; Debûsî (ö.430/1039),
Takvîmu‟l-Edille; Abu‟l-Huseyn al-Basrî (ö.436/1044), al-Mu‟temed; Ibn Hazm
(ö.456/1063), al-Ihkâm; Imâmu‟l-Harameyn al-Cuveynî (ö.473/1080), al-Burhân; Abu‟l-
Velîd al-Bâcî (ö.474/1081), Ihkâmu‟l-Fusûl; Abû Ishâk al-Shîrâzî (ö.476/1083), Sharhu‟l-
Luma‟.
2
Abu Hamed Muhammad b. Muhammad al-Ghazali (d.505/1111), al-Mustasfâ min Ilmi‟l-
Usûl, Dâru‟l-Erkam, Beirut (p.d), I/24,27.
3
For Ghazali, these sources of the Sharia include the Quran, Sunnah and ijmâ (consensus).
For him, qiyâs (analogy) is not a source but a way to deduce provisions from the source,
and thus, is a subject under matters on signification. So Ghazali‟s approach to qiyâs is high-
ly important.
4
Ghazali, al-Mustasfâ, I/29.
5
A literature review on certain texts would be sufficient to see to what extent the science of
logic developed after Ghazali. See Esîruddîn al-Ebherî (d.663/1265), Îsâgocî; Necmeddîn
al-Kazvînî (d.675/1276), al-Risâletu‟s-Shamsiyye; Sirâcuddîn al-Urmevî (d.682/1283),
Metâliu‟l-Envâr. On the other hand, that logic gained prominence with and through Ghazali
is a sufficient response to the claims that thought died with Ghazali. The proponents of such
claim lack insight into the position of logic among Islamic sciences.
6
In the introduction to al-Mustasfâ, Ghazali tells about another book on methodology he
compiled (I/15). We learn from here that this work called Tehzîbu‟l-Usûl is more compre-
hensive than al-Mustasfâ. Unfortunately, the work is not available among the manuscripts
in our libraries.
7
Most prominent sources of methodology compiled after Ghazali treated the subjects of logic
in their introductions. See Fahreddîn al-Râzî (d.606/1210), al-Mahsûl; Seyfuddîn al-Âmidî
(d.631/1234), al-Ihkâm; Ibn al-Hâcib (d.646/1248), Muhtasar; Ibnu‟s-Sâ‟âtî (d.694/1294),
Bedîu‟n-Nizâm; Molla Fenârî (d.834/1430), Fusûlu‟l-Bedâyi.
8
Ghazali, al-Mustasfâ, I/28.
9
Ghazali, ibid, I/16.
10
Ghazali, ibid, I/29.
11
Tasavvur (envision) refers to the occurrence of a thing‟s image in mind. Tasdîk (confirma-
tion) is attributing something to another in terms of affirmation and negation. Classical logic
consists of two parts, one involving matters about tasavvur and the other examining matters
about tasdîk.
12
Signification is usually defined as follows: “Signification refers to a case in which know-
ledge of one thing requires knowing another thing.” See Seyyid Sharîf al-Curcânî
(ö.816/1413), al-Ta‟rîfât, Dâru‟n-Nefâis, Beirut 2003, s.172.
13
For detailed information, see Kutbuddin al-Râzî (ö.766/1365), Tahrîru‟l-Kavâidi‟l-
Mantıkıyye, Intişârât-ı Bîdâr, Kum 1424, s.82-89.
14
Ghazali, al-Mustasfâ, I/77.
15
Lexical meaning of “vaz‘” is “to put, place”. As a term, it refers to placing an utterance in a
way to correspond to a meaning. For instance, the word “human” has placed to correspond
to the meaning “a thinking living being”. For detailed information, see: Isâmuddîn Ibrâhîm
b. Muhammed al-Isferâyînî (ö.951/1544), Sharhu‟r-Risâleti‟l-Vad‟iyye, (m.y.), Istanbul
1280, p. 6.
16
Ghazali, al-Mustasfâ, I/77.
17
Ghazali, ibid., I/93.
18
Ghazali, al-Mustasfâ, I/96.
19
Ghazali, ibid., I/93.
his answer to this question with respect to the science of methodology, Gha-
zali describes signification in analogy as signification through reason. As we
said earlier, Ghazali also argues that logical analogy and jurisprudential
analogy are parallel in their forms. Then, signification through reason should
also apply to logical analogy. Yet, as we said before, Ghazali divides in three
the ways through which meaning is signified by utterance in logic: mutaba-
kat, tazammun and iltizam. There is no such thing as “signification through
reason” among them. So we ask a second question: what place does signifi-
cation through reason occupy among these three categories? That question is
of great importance for our point. Though we find a clear answer to this
question in Ghazali, one of the leading followers of Ghazali, Fahreddîn al-
Râzî (d.606/1209), clearly stated that signification by tazammun and ilti-
zam are signification through reason.20 Yet, another argument is also possi-
ble. The relationship between attribute and designated thing cannot be de-
scribed either as a mutabakat or tazammun relationship. Because the
meaning of attribute is neither the whole nor part of the meaning of the des-
ignated thing; yet, there exists a relationship of necessity between them. The
designated thing requires that the meaning contained in the attribute also
apply to itself. Then, it seems to be the most probable choice to consider the
relationship between the designated things and attributes as signification by
iltizam. Therefore, although we admit that our result is open to debate, the
signification in analogy is arguably signification by iltizam.
On the other, what places our result under serious doubt is Ghazali‟s recom-
mendation not to use signification by iltizam for reasoning. Since Ghazali
made logical analogy an indispensable part of reasoning, it is improbable
that for him, analogy can overlap with signification by iltizam, which, as he
argues, should be kept away from reasoning. Instead, analogy can be said to
be signification by tazammun as there also exists a relationship of necessity
in signification by tazammun. While in signification by iltizam, the word as
a signifier necessitates a meaning other than its own, there is a need for a
meaning contained under the word‟s own meaning in signification by ta-
zammun. Therefore, the relationship of necessity is common in both types
of signification. One involves an external necessity, while the other involves
an internal one.21 Thus, the relationship between analogy and signification
by tazammun is a subject that requires a separate discussion.
In his introduction to al-Mustasfâ, Ghazali expressed the above comments
about signification of meaning by utterance. To sum up, utterance signifies
meaning in three ways: mutabakat, tazammun and iltizam. And there is
also signification in the form of analogy, which we have concluded to refer
20
Fahreddîn al-Râzî, al-Mahsûl, Muessesetu‟r-Risâle, Beirut 1997, I/219.
21
Muhammed b. Velî al-Izmîrî (ö.1165/1751), Hâshiyetu Mir‟âti‟l-Usûl, al-Hâc Muharrem
Efendi Matbaası, Istanbul 1302, II/83.
22
Ghazali, al-Mustasfâ, I/18.
23
Ghazali, ibid, I/20.
24
Ghazali, ibid, I/22, 25.
25
Ghazali, al-Mustasfâ, I/657.
26
Ghazali, ibid, I/658.
27
Ghazali, ibid., I/658.
sign, (3) understanding the reason for the existence of a provision from the
attribute mentioned along with the provision, (4) signification by utterance
of cases that are subject to one about which a provision was made and (5)
signification by utterance of cases that are against the one about which a
provision was made. As said earlier, Ghazali discussed in this part the signi-
fication of necessity and signification of the sign together. Now let us move
onto these discussions.
In the signification of necessity, an utterance signifies a meaning it necessar-
ily requires, not its literal meaning. Signification of necessity can only take
place in three ways.
1. Such signification is necessary to exist so that one can judge that the ut-
terer speaks the truth. For example, for the hadith “Mistakes and forgetful-
ness has been lifted from my ummah” to be true, the word “mistakes” should
mean the sentence for mistakes. Because we know that, the ummah is not
immune to mistakes and forgetfulness. Then, for this utterance to be true, the
word “mistakes” should necessarily signify the sentence for mistakes. After
all, this utterance signifies its own meaning by necessity.28
2. Legal validity of an utterance depends on the presence of such significa-
tion. As an example, let us take the utterance “free your slave in my name”
told by someone to another. For this utterance to be legally valid, the slave
must have bought before by the demander. Thus, this utterance signifies that
the slave had been bought before he was freed, which is a necessary signifi-
cation.29
3. The ability to envision an utterance depends on the rational existence of
such signification. Surat an-Nisâ verse 23 says, “Forbidden to you are your
mothers”. What is forbidden in this verse is to marry one‟s mother. There-
fore, the word “mother” in the verse signifies marrying mothers.30
To sum up the signification of necessity, there is neither a direct nor an indi-
rect relation between utterance and the meaning signified by the utterance.
However, for the utterance to be meaningful, one needs a link between the
utterance and the meaning it signifies. In this regard, signification of necessi-
ty is distinguished from both the signification of what is uttered and signifi-
cation of the sign. For as we have already seen, the signification of what is
uttered concerns the meaning directly understood from the utterance. In sig-
nification of the sign, on the other hand, there is a reference to the indirectly,
though not directly, understood meaning from the utterance. However, there
28
Ghazali, al-Mustasfâ, II/217.
29
Ghazali, ibid., II/218.
30
Ghazali, ibid., II/219.
is no direct link between the utterance and the signified meaning here, and
what requires us to establish this link is simply a necessity.
Secondly, in this chapter, Ghazali discusses the signification of the sign,
which is defined as follows: “It is signification of meaning understood from
the sign of the utterance, not the utterance itself. What we mean by this is
that the meaning that is not the aim of the utterance is understood from the
utterance.”31 Ghazali makes an analogy to a case in which things other than
those understood simply from a speaker‟s utterance are understood from his
behavior and attitude. Similarly, other meanings that are not understood
from the utterance itself are sometimes attached to an utterance.
Surat al-Baqarah verse 187 says that prohibitions of fasting are removed
until daylight. Thus, one is free to eat, drink and have sexual intercourse
from fast break until sunrise. Although this is the meaning understood from
the utterance of the verse, it is also understood from the sign of the verse that
starting the day without ghusl will not damage fasting. If intercourse is al-
lowed until daylight, then there is a possibility that one can start the day
without ghusl. So signification of this provision by the verse is the significa-
tion of by an utterance a meaning that is not directly understood from the
utterance itself, but from its sign.
Thirdly, Ghazali provides an example for understanding the reason for the
existence of a provision from the attribute mentioned along with the provi-
sion.32 From Surat al-Mâide verse 38, which orders to cut off the hands of
the man who steals and the woman who steals, one can also understand that
stealing is a reason for this provision. Yet, this secondary meaning is not
clearly expressed in the verse. The verse does not contain an explicit state-
ment that “the reason for this provision is stealing” The reason for the provi-
sion is understood from the sign of the verse.
The difference between this kind of signification and the signification of the
sign mentioned in the second part does not seem to be a big one. In the last
analysis, the meaning signified by the utterance in both is a meaning that not
uttered. Still, one can make such distinction between the two. The meaning
understood in the signification of the sign is not used as an element in analo-
gy, while the meaning concluded from this signification is used as an ele-
ment of analogy. Yet, this difference stems from the state of what is signi-
fied. It is still possible to argue that there is not a great difference between
the two in terms of being ways of signification.
The fourth type of signification concerns cases in which utterance is subject
to one about which a provision was made. An example of such signification
31
Ghazali, al-Mustasfâ, II/220.
32
Ghazali, ibid, II/222.
33
Ghazali, al-Mustasfâ, II/222.
34
Ghazali, al-Mustasfâ, II/224.
35
„İlla is the common characteristic of two things compared. It is also raison d‟être of analo-
gy.
through a positive or negative case that brings the two together.”36 The see-
mingly complex definition could be explained as follows. As suggested by
Ghazali, an analogy should contain four elements, which are target, source,
„illa and inference. The definition is more comprehensible if we try to identi-
fy these elements of analogy in the definition. The two known things in the
definition are the source and target. Thus, the source is attributed to the tar-
get in a certain case. What brings these two elements together is „illa. After
these two elements are brought together by „illa, the source is attributed to
the target with respect to the presence or absence of an inference. Inference
is the point at which attribution is realized.
Let us make the definition clear using an example provided by Ghazali for
jurisprudential qiyâs (analogy). Ghazali‟s example is as follows: “Date wine
is intoxicant. All intoxicants are haram. Then date wine is haram.” This
form of qiyâs contains three elements of qiyâs: The source, „illa and infe-
rence. The validity of this qiyâs requires an external evidence, which is a
proof that presents us the target and its inference. Without such external
evidence, one cannot possibly attain the complete form of qiyâs. Using the
example, date wine is the source, “being intoxicant” is the „illa and “being
haram” is the inference. Here, the external evidence is the verse forbidding
grape wine as haram. We first have to know the external evidence to per-
form qiyâs. Then we find the „illa for this provision. The Prophet (pbuh) said
in a hadith “All intoxicants are haram”, which shows us that the „illa is be-
ing intoxicant. Then we have all the elements, and what is left is to identify
the form of qiyâs. From the intoxicant quality of date wine, we can infer the
fact that it is also haram since being intoxicant is a reason for being haram.
Consequently, following the example, we attribute the source (date wine) to
the target (grape wine) based on an inference (being haram) through an „illa
(being intoxicant).
Unfortunately, Ghazali failed to reveal clearly that why he considered analo-
gy as a way of signification. Yet, it seems possible to arrive at an explana-
tion from what he said. As could be understood from Ghazali‟s definition of
an example about jurisprudential qiyâs, the reason for his considering qiyâs
as a way of signification is that jurisprudential qiyâs also takes place in a
form similar to logical analogy. Now, we cannot argue that logical analogy
and jurisprudential qiyâs are totally identical, for as Ghazali suggests, in
order to form a jurisprudential qiyâs, one needs an external evidence con-
taining a target and its inference.37 However, logical analogy lacks this as-
pect. Despite this minor difference, the two types of analogy overlap in
terms of inference since them both have a form. Inference upon the form is
entirely rational. Accordingly, an individual with knowledge on the form of
36
Ghazali, al-Mustasfâ, II/278.
37
Ghazali, al-Mustasfâ, I/93.
qiyâs will be able to arrive at the conclusion from the premises through ra-
tional signification, whatever the content of the qiyâs. That is why Ghazali
regarded qiyâs as the signification of what is reasoned.
Ghazali also said the following to explain jurisprudential qiyâs: “Jurispru-
dential qiyâs relating one thing to another on the basis of identicalness.”38
The two things meant by this are the source and the target. The point of iden-
ticalness at which the former is related to the latter is inference. The raison
d‟être for the inference is the „illa, which is common in both. Therefore, the
source and the target entirely overlap with regard to „illa and inference, and
it is this overlapping that is called qiyâs. This idea is confirmed by the posi-
tion Ghazali mentioned in the introduction to his book. When evaluation
jurisprudential qiyâs in his introduction to logic, he said the following about
the essence of qiyâs: “to combine the particular with the general.”39 Here, the
particular concerns the source and the target, which are particular as they are
for certain situations. The general is „illa. Since these two particulars are
combined under a general „illa, an inference which is valid for one is also
valid for the other. Thus, qiyâs takes place between the two.
38
Ghazali, ibid, II/279.
39
Ghazali, ibid., I/94.
REFERENCES
Âmidî, Seyfuddîn Abu‟l-Hasen „Alî b. Abû „Alî (ö.631/1233), al-Ihkâm fî
Usûli‟l-Ahkâm, Dâru‟l-Kutubi‟l-„İlmiyye, Beirut 2005, I-II.
Bâcî, Abu‟l-Velîd Suleymân b. Halef (ö.474/1081), İhkâmu‟l-Fusûl fî Ahkâmi‟l-
Usûl, Dâru‟l-Garbi‟l-Islâmî, Beirut 1995, I-II.