Karl H. Pribram - The Realization of The Mind PDF
Karl H. Pribram - The Realization of The Mind PDF
Karl H. Pribram - The Realization of The Mind PDF
PRIBRAM
T H E R E A L I Z A T I O N OF M I N D
T H E W O R L D OF L A N G U A G E S
Dualistic theory does not fare much better. Since Descartes an emphasis
has been placed on the distinction between the phenomenal, subjectively
experienced, and the objective world which can be instrumentally
validated. Dualism ought not to be dismissed out of hand for it points up
an important distinction. There is a difference between the subjective
and the objective constructions we experience, a difference between the
'phenomenal' and the 'real' world. The difference lies in how each
becomes validated. Empiricists have emphasized the fact that we perceive
the world through our senses. Empirical studies enhance these perceptions
through instrumentation that augments and refines the senses. The
physical, the 'real' world is constructed by us from detailed descriptions
fed to our senses that achieve information about the world. On the other
hand, the phenomenal, the 'ideal' world is a world of ideas. We validate
experience in this world through social communication, through enact-
ment, through communicative acts. In science this distinction between
real and phenomenal becomes externalized in a distinction between
descriptive and normative, between more or less certain facts and those
THE R E A L I Z A T I O N OF MIND 315
... I believe that.., the behavioral, biological-social scientist interested in the mind-
body problem finds his universe to be a mirror image of the universe constructed by
the physical scientist who deals with the same problem. And it should not come as a
surprise when each of these mirror images, these isomers, the one produced by the
physicist and the one produced by the behavioral scientist, on occasion display pro-
perties that differ considerably from one another, much as do optical isomers in
organic chemistry.
I believe these images are mirrors because of differences in the direction generally
pursued from each investigator's effective starting point, his own observations. The
physical scientist for the most part, constructs his universe by ever more refined
analysis of input variables, that is, sensory stimuli to which he reacts. The form of the
reaction (cathode ray tube, solid-state device, chromatography, or galvanometer) is
unimportant, except that it provides a sufficiently broad communicative base. Con-
stancies are gradually retrieved from manipulations and observations of these input
variables under a variety of conditions. As these constants achieve stability, the
'correctness' of the views that produced them is asserted: the ['real'] physical universe
is properly described.
In the social disciplines the direction pursued is often just the reverse. Analysis is
made of action systems. The exact nature of the input to the actor (including the
observing scientist) is of little consequence, provided it has sufficient communicative
base; the effect of action on the system is the subject of analysis. It matters little
(perhaps because the cause is usually multiple [overdetermined] and/or indeter-
minable) if a currency is deflated because of fear of inflation, depression, personal
whim, or misguided economic theory. The effects of deflation can be studied, are
knowable. And once known, the action becomes corrective; the resulting stabilization,
constancy, is interpreted as evidence for the [practical, pragmatic] 'correctness' of the
action that produced the correction. Appropriate norms for the social universe
become established.
One striking difference between the two images thus formed is immediately apparent.
The physicist's macroscopic universe is the more stable, predictable one: "It does not
hurt the moon to look at it" (Eddington, 1958, p. 227). For the most part, it is as he
moves to ever more microscopic worlds that uncertainties are asserted. [By contrast]
the scientist concerned with social matters finds it just the other way around: it seem-
ingly does little harm to the man to look at him; but seriously look at his family, his
friendships, or his political-economic systems and what you had started out to look
at changes with the looking. Here indeterminacy comes to plague the macrostructure;
it is in the stabilities of microanalysis that the mirage of safety appears.
The problem can be grasped.., if it is dealt with in terms of isomeric forms of the
same event universe - isomers differing in that their structures mirror each other. Put
another way, the problem resolves itself into a meshing of the descriptive and the
normative sciences. The suggestion is that structure in descriptive science ordinarily
emerges from the analysis of the relations between systems and their subsystems; that
316 KARL H. PRIBRAM
in the normative sciences, it goes in the opposite direction: structure emerges when
the relation between a system and its 'supersystem' is studied.
If this view is correct, we should find normative statements about the nature of the
physical world when these are constructed from the examination of relations between
a set of systems and a higher order system. Is not relativity just this sort of statement?
This is not a social scientist speaking about the 'criterion problem':
The modern observer... [is] faced with the task of choosing between a number of
frames of space with nothing to guide his choice. They are different in the sense
that they frame the material objects of the world, including the observer himself,
differently; but they are indistinguishable in the sense that the world as framed in
one space conducts itself according to precisely the same laws as the world framed
in another space. Owing to the accident of having been born on a particular planet
our observer has hitherto unthinkingly adopted one of the frames; but he realizes
that this is no ground for obstinately asserting that it must be the right frame.
Which is the right franae?
At this juncture Einstein comes forward with a suggestion -
'You are seeking a frame of space which you call the right frame. In what does
its rightness consist?"
You are standing with a label in your hand before a row of packages all precisely
similar. You are worried because there is nothing to help you to decide which of the
packages it should be attached to. Look at the label and see what is written on it.
Nothing.
'Right' as applied to frames of space is a blank label. It implies that there is
something distinguishing a right frame from a wrong frame; but when we ask what
is the distinguishing property, the only answer we receive is 'Rightness', which does
not make the meaning clearer or convince us that there is a meaning (Eddington,
1958, p. 2O).
Obversely, we should find descriptive statements about the nature of the social
world when these derive from a study of the relations between a system and its sub-
systems. Doesn't the following passage fit this requirement?:
Role behavior depends first of all on the role positions that society establishes;
that is certain ways of behaving toward others are defined by different positions
(Hilgard, 1962, p. 432).
Aren't statements about roles unambiguously descriptive? (Pribram, 1965).
What happens when a man, or for that matter an animal, has no need to work for a
living?.., the simplest case is that of the domesticated cat - a paradigm of affluent
living more extreme than that of the horse or the cow. All the basic needs of a domesti-
cated cat are provided for almost before they are expressed. It is protected against
danger and inclement weather. Its food is there before it is hungry or thirsty. What
then does it do? How does it pass its time?
We might expect that having taken its food in a perfunctory way it would curl up
on its cushion and sleep until faint internal stimulation gave some information of the
need for another perfunctory meal. But no, it does not just sleep. It proms the garden
and thewoods killing young birds and mice. It enjoys life in its own way. The fact that
life can be enjoyed, and is most enjoyed, by many living beings in the state of affluence
(as defined) draws attention to the dramatic change that occurs in the working of the
organic machinery at a certain stage of the evolutionary process. This is the reversal o f
the means-end relation in behavior. In the state of nature the cat must kill to live. In
the state of affluence it lives to kill. This happens with men. When men have no need
to work for a living there are broadly only two things left to them to do. They can
'play' and they can cultivate the arts. These are their two ways of enjoying life. It is
true that many men work because they enjoy it, but in this case 'work' has changed its
meaning. It has become a form of 'play'. 'Play' is characteristically an activity which
is engaged in for its own sake - without concern for utility or any further end. 'Work'
is characteristically activity in which effort is directed to the production of some
utility in the simplest and easiest way. Hence the importance of ergonomics and work
study - the objective of which is to reduce difficulty and save time. In play the activity
is often directed to attaining a pointless objective in a difficult way, as when a golfer,
using curious instruments, guides a small ball into a not much larger hole from remote
distances and in the face of obstructions deliberately designed to make the operation
as difficult as may be. This involves the reversal of the means-end relation. The 'end' -
getting the ball into the hole - is set up as a means to the new end, the real end, the
enjoyment of difficult activity for its own sake (Mace, 1961, p. 10-11).
T h u s t h e m e a n s - e n d s reversal c o m p o u n d s c o m p l e x i t y a n d t h e o r i g i n a l
o r g a n i z i n g p o t e n t i a l c a n easily b e lost sight of. Biological processes h a v e
b u i l t i n r e n e w a l m e c h a n i s m s , h o w e v e r . W h e n the a c c u l t u r a t e d s t r u c t u r e s
b e g i n to b e c o m e t o o c u m b e r s o m e o r t o o conflicting w i t h each o t h e r t h e y
are o f t e n d e g r a d e d , p r u n e d b a c k to their m o r e essential roots. C l e a r e r
v i s i o n is t h e n a t t a i n e d o f t h e basic o r g a n i z a t i o n w h i c h gave rise to the
process initially because now historical comparison can be made between
t h e p r i m i t i v e a n d t h e s o p h i s t i c a t e d r e a l i z a t i o n o f t h e process.
322 KARL H. PRIBRAM
ACKNOWLEDGEMENT
Stanford University
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Calhoun, J. B., 'A Comparative Study of the Social Behavior of Two Inbred Strains
of House Mice', EcoL Monogr. 26 (1956) 81-03.
Eccles, J. C., Facing Reality, Springer-Verlag,New York, Heidelberg, Berlin, 1970.
Eddington, A., The Nature of the Physical World, University of Michigan Press, Ann
Arbor, Mich., 1958.
Hilgard, E., Introduction to Psychology, Harcourt, Brace and World, New York, 1962.
Mace, C. A., 'Psychology and Aesthetics', British Journal of Aesthetics 2 (1962) 3-16.
Polanyi, M., Personal Knowledge, Towards a Post-Critical Philosophy, University of
Chicago Press, Chicago, 1960.
Pribram, K. H., 'Proposal for a Structural Pragmatism: Some Neuropsychological
Considerations of Problems in Philosophy', in B. Wolman and E. Nagel (eds.),
Scientific Psychology: Principles and Approaches, Basic Books, New York, 1965,
426-459.
Pribram, K. H., The Language of the Brain, Prentice Hall, Englewood Cliffs, N.J., 1971.
Quine, W. V. O., Word and Object, John Wiley, New York, 1960.
Sperry, R., 'A Modified Concept of Consciousness', Psychological Review 76 (1969)
532-536.