13 Sociological Jurisprudence
13 Sociological Jurisprudence
13 Sociological Jurisprudence
SOCIOLOGICAL JURISPRUDENCE
I. INTRODUCTION
Just as manifested by the title of this chapter, the social science associated with
sociological juriprudence is, of course, sociology, and the particular topic within
sociology related to sociological jurisprudence is the sociology of law. Sociological
jurisprudence, in other words, is the legal theory which is the result of
understanding the sociology of law.
The first question concerns the supposition of a legal theory which maintains that
society is the source of law and explains law in terms of this source or origin in the
same manner that the historical jurisprudence of Savigny claimed that the origin of
law is the common consciousness or the national spirit of the people through which
an explanation of law may be generated. One noted advocate of this sociological
perspective is Eugen Ehrlich.
The second question involves a theory of law that focuses on the effect of law and
discusses how law functions and operates. These theories provide a rich and fertile
source of ideas and may be found in the legal theories of Dean Roscoe Pound,
Roger Cotterrell, and Policy Science Theory as among the proponents of Sociological
Jurisprudence. Other legal theories, such as the American Legal Realism, American
Legal Pragmatism and the Economic Jurisprudence of Richard A. Posner also
advocate similar ideas.
Thereafter Selznick described the three stages which the sociology of law must go
through in order to attain a level of maturity as a theoretical discipline. The first
stage he referred to as primitive or missionary:
347
but what there is mostly demonstrative in function, more valuable for
the educational effect than for anything else. In law, such
demonstrative research, has not been particularly important, in part
because of the role played by fact-guided judicial decisions and by the
writings of men with rich experience in legal affairs. Although most of
the theoretical work in this field has been done by European social
scientists, the task of communicating an elementary, not-very-
sophisticated sociological perspective has been accomplished largely
by American legal scholars who were influenced by European thought,
and by some of the more articulate appellate judges.” 4
...
4
Id., p. 3.
5
Freeman, supra. n. 1, pp. 678-679.
348
...
Whatever the difficulties of this stage, they do not include the need to
wrestle with the ultimate problems of definition and of philosophical
perspective. A great deal of work can be carried on, even work of high
theoretical content, without worrying too much about the nature of law
itself, or of justice. At this stage, we can accept working notions of
positive law and we can see most of our work as dealing with social
sources of legal change. By taking this practical view, we can facilitate
the release intellectual energies; it does not follow, however, that we
must remain forever content with that intellectual accommodation.” 6
349
human enterprise he has elected to study. He reasserts the moral
impulse that marked the first stage of sociological interest and
influence. But the third stage is of a higher, more sophisticated level
than the first because the second stage has provided a sounder basis
for critical analysis.
...
350
regarding the nature of man and institutions. Therefore, inevitably,
sociology and every other social science have a part in the legal order.
The underlying role of reason explains why legal scholarship and the
sociology of law are mainly preoccupied with common law, and
therefore with judicial behavior, rather than with legislation. It is true
that somewhat more emphasis in legal training is now placed on
legislation, reflecting the great growth of the legislative process . . .
Freeman noted that Selznick’s later work may have approached the third stage:
“Selznick claimed in 1962 that the third stage had not yet been reached. It is the
8
Selznick, supra. n. 3., pp. 3, 11-13; emphasis Selznick’s.
351
time when sociological jurisprudence will develop an ‘intellectual autonomy and
maturity’, when having learn the necessary skills, the jurists can return to some of
the theoretical questions posed at the outset, the function of law, the role of
legality, the meaning of justice, and a sociology of law will emerge. Selznick, for
example, has tried to understand legality from a sociological position. The
development of a sociology of law does suggest that Selznick’s third stage has been
reached.”9
Apart from the sociology of law and the sociology of jurisprudence, there emerged
what is called ‘socio-legal studies’.
“For much of the twentieth century the sociology of law was eclipsed
by sociological jurisprudence. It was Pound, rather than Weber or
Durkheim, who was the dominant figure. From the 1960s the term
‘sociological jurisprudence’ was used less frequently, and what came
to be known as socio-legal studies took its place. Advocates of socio-
legal studies emphasise the importance of placing law in its social
context, of using social-scientific research methods, of recognising that
many traditional jurisprudential questions are empirical in nature and
not just conceptual. A pervasive theme is the gap between legal rules
and actually lived social norms. But this gap, often said to be between
‘law in the books’ and ‘law in action’, was too often only described and
too rarely analysed. For Cotterrell, socio-legal studies was a ‘transition
phase’. It had considerable impact: on the law, on legal education and
on law publishing. It helped focus greater attention on concepts like
discretion, institutions such as tribunals, and different techniques of
decision-making and conflict resolution, such as alternative dispute
resolution.
‘To many observers, the work done so far amounts to very little:
an incoherent or inconclusive jumble of case studies. There is (it
seems) no foundation; some work merely proves the obvious,
some is poorly designed; there are no axioms, no ‘laws’ of legal
behavior, nothing cumulates. The studies are at times
interesting and are sporadically useful. But there is no ‘science’;
nothing adds up. . . . Grand theories do appear from time to
time, but they have no survival power; they are nibbled to death
by case studies. There is no central core.’
352
efficiently or effectively. And the emphasis was more on the
‘behaviour’ of institutions rather then on trying to understand the legal
doctrine.”10
II. METHODOLOGY
There allegedly exists a dichotomy between the concerns of the legal sociologist
and that of the legal theorist or philosopher.
That this division of labor was in no way inevitable is clear from the
briefest glance at the work of the classic founders of the sociology of
law. While Max Weber saw sociology’s object as the study of social
action, he treated the nature of legal ideas and the varieties of types of
legal reasoning as central to his sociological concern with law. Emile
Durkheim intended that the enterprise of understanding law as
doctrine should itself become a field of sociology, so that lawyers’
questions would eventually be reformulated through sociological
insight. For Eugen Ehrlich, the lawyer’s understanding of law would be
simultaneously subverted and set on surer foundations by means of
sociological inquiry into popular understandings of legal ideas. Leon
Petrazycki considered that law should be studied as a variety of forms
of consciousness and understanding. Equally numerous contributions
to legal philosophy, including modern realist jurisprudence in
Scandinavia, the United States of America, and elsewhere, showed that
jurists had serious concerns with behaviour in legal contexts in their
efforts to grasp the nature of legal ideas.
10
Id., pp. 683-684.
353
To remove a focus on legal doctrine from sociological inquiry would
prevent legal sociology from integrating, rather than merely
juxtaposing, its studies with other kinds of legal analysis. Without this
focus, sociological observation of behaviour might influence policy
expressed in legal doctrine, but this would amount not to a sociology of
law but to a diversity of sociological information presented to legal
policy-makers. The old claim that social science should be ‘on tap
rather than on top’ in legal inquiries reflected the idea that sociology
and other social sciences were debarred from offering insight into the
meaning of law (as doctrine, interpretation, reasoning, and argument).
Hence, in so far as proponents of legal sociology accepted the myth of
an inevitable division of labour, they were tempted to argue
defensively that lawyers’ debates on doctrine were trivial or
mystificatory, and that real knowledge about law as a social
phenomenon was gained only by observing patterns of judicial,
administrative or policing activity, lawyers’ work and organization, or
citizens’ disputing behaviour. Correspondingly, opponents of legal
sociology hastened to dismiss it as unable to speak law at all; fated to
remain for ever ‘external’ and thus irrelevant to legal understanding.” 11
354
capacities as having an intellectual power and resilience which
protects it from social science’s earlier ‘imperial confidence’ that it
could know law better than law knew itself.
From the standpoint of sociology the problem is not merely that its
insights can be made to seem irrelevant to legal understanding. It is
not just the unpleasantness of rejection that dominates this scenario,
but also the frustration of attempting the impossible. The argument
goes as follows. As sociology tries to understand law, law disappears
like a mirage, the closer the approach to it. This is because as
sociology interprets law, law is reduced to sociological terms. It
becomes something different from what it (legally) is; or rather, from
what, in legal thought, law sees itself as being. How can legal ideas be
understood sociologically without, in the process, being turned into
sociological ideas? The ‘legal point of view’, as Robert Samek called it
in a neglected discussion of related themes, disappears; subsumed
into a sociological viewpoint and lost. It cannot be grasped
sociologically because it is not sociological. It is a specifically legal
point of view.
355
produced by law. Not only can law stand alone from sociology with its
own basis of understanding, taking or leaving social scientific insights
as it sees fit, but it is said to be able also to create the central objects
of inquiry—the very ontological basis—of sociology itself. According to
some influential scholars, law has no need, and no possibility, of doing
more than creating its own normative understanding of its social
environment. But, in a more radical view, law is also seen as
responsible, partly at least, for creating the social categories which
sociology itself must work with.”12
“For these reasons a sharp line between the legal and the social can no
longer be drawn: a ‘more holistic understanding is required. Legal
ideas constitute a form of social knowledge in themselves. The often
neglected point that legal speculations once provided prototypes for
early forms of social theory acquires a new significance.
356
to understand legal ideas sociologically is appropriate. My claim is that
the only way to grasp these imaginatively as ideas about the
organization of the social world is through some form of sociological
interpretation.
357
has to use ‘arbitrary cut-off points’ in argument, and often chooses not
to look behind its presumptions. It seeks to provide certainty and to
relate to common sense. It may adopt or reject scientific (including
social scientific) knowledge or reasoning in order to pursue these
objectives. It gathers and presents facts in ways tailored to
adjudicative needs. It operates by means of practical reasoning and
argumentation that may be more or less specific to its governmental,
dispute processing or social control tasks. But any enumeration of
characteristics of law’s truth will miss the point for ‘what truth means
for law is the result of its own processes.’ ‘Ultimately,’ as Arthur Leff
puts it, ‘law is not something we know but something we do.’ It is not
grasped by definition from ‘outside’ but by working and thinking within
it.
358
including sociological ones. Ultimately, it is given discursive coherence
and unity only because its intellectual insecurity, its permanent
cognitive openness, is stabilized by political fiat. The political power of
the state which guarantees the decisions of certain official legal
interpreters, puts an end to argument, determines which interpretive
concepts prevail, asserts favoured normative judgments as superior to
all competing ones, and guarantees normative closure by the threat of
official coercion. The voluntas, or coercive authority, of law,
centralized by political structures and organized through legal
hierarchies, stabilizes and controls potentially unlimited, often
competing and conflicting, elaboration of ratio—reason and doctrinal
principle—in a host of diverse sites and settings of legal argument and
interpretation.
At the same time law defines social relations and influences the shape
of the very phenomena that sociology studies. Thus legal and other
social ideas interpenetrate each other. A line between law and society
is, as has been seen, no longer capable of being sharply drawn. Law
constitutes important aspects of social life by shaping or reinforcing
modes of understanding of social reality. It would be remarkable if the
power of law as officially guaranteed ideas and practices could have no
such effects. One might indeed wonder what law as an expression of
power is for, if not for this. But a sociological perspective makes it
possible to observe and understand this effect of legal discourses and
situate it in relation to the social effects of other kinds of ideas and
practices. Law constitutes society in so far as it is, an aspect of
society, a framework and an expression of understanding that enable
society to exist. A sociological perspective on legal ideas is necessary
to recognize and analyse the intellectual and moral power of law in this
respect. To interpret legal ideas without recognizing, through
sociological insight, this dimension of them would be to understand
them inadequately. It would be to treat them as less significant and
less complex than they are made to appear in a broader sociological
perspective.”14
359
Thereafter Cotterrell explained the sociological perspective, and showed why it has
a privileged status as compared to the economic or psychological viewpoint, for
example. It has three characteristics. It is to view and understand law as a social
phenomenon, empirically and systematically.
“Is it, however, really necessary to invoke the word ‘sociological’ here?
Why privilege sociology? Nelken argues that sociology is sometimes
presented as supreme only by downgrading law’s disciplinary status.
He doubts that sociology can ultimately transcend its own methods of
argument and style. The legal sociologist may stand too close to
sociology to understand law. And, in any case, why should a
sociological, rather than, for example, an economic or psychological
viewpoint be favoured? Why should sociology impose its
understandings? On the other hand, if it does not do so, its analyses of
law can be criticized as being parasitic on law’s own definitions of the
‘the legal’.
360
...
Approaches to legal inquiry that are set up are in some way opposed to
sociological perspectives that are, to the extent that they are
presented in this competitive way, often ultimately more restricted
forms of understanding of law as a social phenomenon to the extent
that they actually exclude sociological insight in certain ways.
Otherwise, most productively, these other approaches are best seen as
allied with and (in so far as they seek to offer social insight) even
appropriately organized by means of a (perhaps implicit) sociological
perspective. They should be treated as specialized co-workers with
sociological inquiry.
Finally, this sociological perspective provides the basis and framework with which
legal ideas should be interpreted.
15
Id., pp. 754-755; emphasis Cotterrell’s.
361
If sociological inquiries about law have an intellectual and moral
allegiance, then this is to law itself—that is, to its enrichment through a
radical broadening of the perspectives of the varied participants in the
legal processes, practices, and forms of knowledge. Sociological
inquiry is critical because it insists that the legal perspective of many
of these participants (whether lawyers or non-lawyers) are
insufficiently systematic and theoretically informed or sensitive to
empirical variation, and have too narrow an awareness of law’s social
character. But it is also constructive because it cannot merely
condemn existing legal ideas without also asking at all times how law
might be re-interpreted and so re-imagined and reshaped consistently
with its social character, when understood better in a broader
sociological perspective.
362
perspective which sociological interpretation seeks makes it possible to
enrich understandings of the social condition of justice. The consistent
focus of sociological inquiry on the social, the systematic, and the
empirical provides the essential dimensions of this enriched
understanding. Sociological inquiry cannot abolish disagreement as to
what justice demands in any particular situation. But it can reveal the
meaning of justice claims in a broader perspective by systematically
analysing the empirical conditions that provide postulates underlying
these claims.
The answer must recognize a crucial claim made earlier. This is that, if
sociological inquiry about legal ideas is to be treated as having any
specific intellectual allegiance, it is to law as a social phenomenon, not
to an academic discipline of sociology or to any other social science
discipline. Hence the sociological understanding of legal ideas reflects
methodologically law’s own fragmentary and varied methodological
characteristics as understood by those who participate in or are
affected by legal practices. This is inevitable because of the
interdependence of legal and sociological understanding referred to
earlier. Sociological interpretation extends legal analysis; it broadens
the perspectives of legal participants.
363
When it is asked why English law takes this particular stance on private
purpose trusts and how the law in this area should be developed in the
light of the precedents, answers are not particularly straightforward.
The cases refer to particular private purpose trusts as illustrations, and
offer various reasons for a tradition of judicial hostility to them. The
matter is dealt with by the courts partly by looking at what has been
decided in the past, partly by detailing technical problems that would
be faced by law if private purpose trusts were to be declared generally
valid (for example, problems of enforcement), and partly by offering
policy arguments about the social or economic rights and wrongs of
allowing particular kinds of trusts to be set up.
364
purpose trusts, viewed as an area of legally structured social
relationships. Thus, sociological inquiry seeks a broader, systematic
view of the law by reinterpreting the relationship of ideas which the
lawyer identifies. It puts them into an intellectual context that allows
the identification of other relationships and other connections. And
these in turn help to explain the law as it stands and point to ways of
rethinking and developing it.
Brian Z. Tamanaha adds three last words that is offered by socio-legal studies:
“Socio-legal Studies
The first last word involves drawing out the tripartite social science
related interaction woven through the course of this work. This
involved exploring the complementary aspects of participant reports,
behaviourism and interpretivism. In everyday terms, these coincide
16
Id., pp. 755-758, emphasis Cotterrell’s.
365
with listening to what people say, carefully observing what they do,
and trying to figure out how it all comes together. These are the
elements of ordinary social interaction. The development of socio-
legal studies has been stunted by the disregard for the participant
view, its initial positivism-induced obsessive focus on behaviour to the
exclusion of meaning, and more recently by the opposite error of
rejecting positivism for interpretivism.
366
speak louder than words. Behaviourism goes only so far, however,
because behaviour is underdeterminative with regard to meaning.
Participant reports come close to behaviourism, because it always
helps to know what people think they are doing. Knowing this and
knowing whether they are actually doing what they say or think they
are doing, is essential to an understanding of any situation.
Interpretivism, when it consists of the observations of outsiders,
simultaneously promises to offer the most insight—by informing
participants of a perspective on their own activities they might
otherwise be oblivious to—or the least insight, when it reveals what is
obvious or already known. And it entails the greatest risk of error,
because outsiders observers often have their own agenda which they
project onto their subjects in the course of interpretation, and they lack
the understanding of an activity which can only come from experience.
That is not to demean interpretivism—many of my own observations in
this work are interpretivist—but to remind us that engaging in
interpretivism invokes participating in ordinary social discourse, a fact
which tends to be obscured by the heavy overlay of theory talk and
citation to authorities.
Finally, I should admit that the approach I have set out is so mundane
that to give it a name—‘realistic approach’—is pretentious. My
description of this ‘approach’—keep an eye on what people are doing
367
and listen to what they are saying, strive to be impartial and observe
closely, test when possible, be open to information from all sources—
consists of common sense rules of thumb we should follow whenever
we embark upon an attempt to understand any aspect of social life.
Were it not for the overheated atmosphere (with contributors from all
sides), much of what I say would be truistic. Rather than claim to have
set out an approach, perhaps, I should say that this book has been a
sustained argument for doing socio-legal studies more realistically.
Legal Theory
The second last word is on the misplaced focus of legal theory. In the
course of taking up some of the more prominent issues in legal theory,
I have attempted to shift the way in which these issues are approached
in the direction of a social theory of law. My conviction is that legal
theorists are talking in old ways when the world of law has changed,
and that much of what is said is irrelevant to the everyday reality of
law . . . .
368
The necessity, role and influence of legitimation are also, from a
descriptive standpoint, highly questionable. A good deal of legal
theory assumes that legitimation—or delegitimation—is of central
importance. Descriptively speaking, however, at least in Western
countries, law just is. Law is a social presence with a concrete and
rather stable form that is here to stay as long as society does not
collapse. Its existence is strongly rooted in its own institutional and
meaning-based permanence and it has increasingly been insinuated as
an aspect of social transactions. Many people do law or have
something to do with law; it is grounded in legal and academic
institutions; it undergirds economic and political institutions; it is
carried generation after generation as a tradition, collection of habits
and practices, and body of meaning. Law has a social existence
entirely apart from legal rules, and this existence is the basis upon
which it is perpetuated.
To say that legal theory has little influence in relation to the views of
members of the community at large, and few connections to the
realities of judging and the practice of law today, does not mean that it
will not have an influence on the shape that law takes in the future.
The Legal Realists had a monumental impact in prompting the
instrumental turn in law. The various critical schools of legal theory
that dominate the discussion today also have the potential for leading
to a change to a longer term.
369
These critical schools, however, are in a different position from the
Realists. First, because the Realists already prompted the overdue
paradigm shift in US law away from mechanistic analysis and
conceptual formalism, toward more open consideration of social
purposes and justice in the individual case, no further major change is
possible unless we give up rules altogether for a completely
substantive justice regime, which would be deeply problematic given
the pluralistic circumstances of modern society. Secondly, much of the
critical theory of the past ten years is too theoretical to make a
difference. Hermeneutics, Wittgenstein’s language analysis, anti-
foundational philosophy, and post-modernism, I have argued, either
address the conditions of our existence, which cannot be changed and
therefore discussing them changes nothing, or address issues within
philosophical debates (like the nature of truth) which have absolutely
no impact on everyday activities. Ironically, the point of all of these
theories is that what counts as ongoing social practices, and that to
make a difference one must give up the view that theory can govern
from above and engage in the practices on their own terms . . .,
leading to change from within. For all the espousal of pragmatism, the
recent flight to theory is precisely what the pragmatists argued
against.
370
inequities, but so would any legal system except one run by
benevolent dictators.
Politics
The final last word is about politics, and about why I have aggressively
promoted a descriptive, non-normative approach. It is a reaction
against what I believe to be a profoundly mistaken attitude and
approach that exists today in socio-legal studies. My conviction is that
critical scholars have harmed their cause far more so than advanced it.
Critical scholars made the mistake of attacking everything about law
from every conceivable angle. The wholesale and unrestrained resort
to criticism and skepticism carried two consequences that have
haunted them ever since. The first consequence is that the failure to
be judicious in the critique led to a failure to recognize that the law
does much good for many people. Critical scholars were defenceless
when it was argued in response that rights talk has been a powerful
tool in the advancement of the treatment of minorities. In their well
nigh total denouncement of the rule of law and of rights, they were
living in the elites-only world of theory, out of touch with reality below .
. . . People teaching at law schools might not need law (though they
are not reluctant to use it when the need arises), but the people they
were trying to help sometimes do because they have nowhere else to
resort to in times of trouble. Destroying law does not further any
political interest other than that of those in society so powerful, so able
to call upon resources, that they have the capacity to thrive regardless
of law. Contrary to the intentions of the critical scholars, the politically
inspired systemic assault on law—the attack on the rule of law and
legal liberalism in the absence of any viable alternatives—advances
only the interests of the elite.
The second consequence is that after the orgy of criticism, there was
no basis upon which to build. It is easy to show that there are serious
problems with law. The hard part is suggesting what to do about it.
Their almost total silence on this, with the exception of Roberto
Unger’s utopian proposals, has led more than anything else to the
demise of the movement. Critique without construction is indulgence
in negativism. Suggestions by critical scholars that more conversation
is needed, or more theory, or attention to context, would be laughable
were they not so disappointing.
371
Ironically, matters have come full circle. In recent exchanges, the
leftist self-declared ‘postmodernists’ who were spawned by CLS, at
least indirectly by taking CLS views to their logical extension, are now
being criticized by CLSers as lacking in any positive normative vision . .
. . Mark Tushnet, who in his CLS salad days declared . . . that, ‘critique
is all there is,’ now complains that postmodernists have taken the
critique so far that the very possibility of normative argument has been
destroyed. A related development can be found in other schools with
connections to CLS, including certain versions of critical feminism and
critical race theory. Drawing upon the theory as well as the tactics of
CLS, group-based advocates are setting themselves up with a kind of
epistemological privilege, claiming to represent a particular point of
view which must be judged by its own internal standards (which,
according to some theorists, are superior to the middle-aged white
male standards). Although we have learned a great deal from these
schools of thought about the silent biases contained within law, the
long term destructive potential entailed by such exclusive and
excluding group-bound-standards is reason for concern. What used to
be plain old disagreement is now construed as incommensurable
discourse and a battle against hegemonic ideology. Promoting a cause
of social justice shared by many of the mainstream, left-leaning
academics in law faculties, CLS took its trashing of law to such an
extreme that it left nowhere to go except ever narrower spin-offs.
372
(which presaged modernism). I would not assert, as Llewellyn did, that
the ‘ought’ should be put on hold while figuring out the ‘is’. Rather, I
am proposing a division of labour: legal theory continues with the
ought, as it has always done; realistic socio-legal studies takes care of
the is. For those who claim this is an abdication of moral responsibility,
I respond, with Dewey, that science has an inherently critical capacity
in relation to values because it provides the check and testing ground
for ideas and beliefs. In this work I have applied science to test the
beliefs of legal and socio-legal theorists across the political spectrum.
“It is the function of juristic science, in the first place, to record the
trends of justice that are found in society, and to ascertain what they
17
Brian Z. Tamanaha, Realistic Social Theory, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997, pp. 246-255.
18
R.W.M. Dias, “Sociological Approaches,” Jurisprudence, 4th Edn., London, Butterworths: 1976, pp. 588-589.
373
are, whence they come, and whither they lead; but it cannot possibly
determine which of these is the only just one. In the forum of science,
they are all equally valid. What men consider just depends upon the
ideas they have concerning the ends of human endeavour in this world
of ours, but it is not the function of science to dictate the final end of
human endeavour on earth. That is the function of the founder of a
religion, of the preacher, of the prophet, of the preacher of ethics, of
the practical jurist, of the judge, of the politician. Science can be
concerned only with those things that are susceptible of scientific
demonstration. That a certain thing is just is no more scientifically
demonstrable that is the beauty of a Gothic cathedral or of a
Beethoven symphony to a person who is insensible to it. All of these
are questions of emotional life. Science can ascertain the effects of a
legal proposition, but it cannot make these effects appear either
desirable or loathsome to man. Justice is a social force, and it is
always a question whether it is potent enough to influence the
disinterested persons whose function it is to create juristic and statute
law.
But although science can teach us nothing concerning the end, once
the end is determined, it can enlighten us as to the means to that end.
The practical technical rules that perform this function are based on
the results of pure science. There is no science that teaches men that
they ought to be healthy, but practical medical science teaches men
who desire to be healthy what they can do, to bring about the result.
Practical juristic science is concerned with the manner in which the
ends may be attained that men are endeavouring to attain through
law, but it must utilize the results of the sociology of law for this
purpose. The legal proposition is not only the result, it is also a lever
of social development; it is an instrumentality in the hands of society
whereby society shapes things within its sphere of influence according
to its will. Through the legal proposition man acquires a power, limited
though it be, over the facts of the law; in the legal proposition a willed
legal order is brought face to face with the legal order which has arisen
self-actively in society.”19
Ehrlich continues by talking about the main concerns of the sociology of law.
“The sociology of law must begin with the ascertainment of the living
law. Its attention will be directed primarily to the concrete, not the
abstract. It is only the concrete that can be observed. What the
anatomist places under the microscope is not human tissue in the
abstract but a specific tissue of specific human being; the physiologist
likewise does not study the functions of the liver of mammals in the
abstract, but those of a specific liver of a specific mammal. Only when
he has completed the observation of the concrete does he ask whether
it is universally valid, and this fact, too, he endeavours to establish by
means of a series of concrete observations, for which he has to find
19
Eugen Ehrlich, “Principles of the Sociology of Law,” Lloyd’s Introduction to Jurisprudence, M.D.A. Freeman,
London: Sweet and Maxwell, Seventh Edn., 2001, p. 719.
374
specific methods. The same may be said of an investigator of law. He
must first concern himself with concrete usages, relations of
domination, legal relations, contracts, articles of association,
dispositions by last will and testament. It is not true, therefore, that
the investigation of the living law is concerned only with ‘customary
law’ or with ‘business usage.’ If one does any thinking at all when one
uses these words—which is not always the case—one will realize that
they do not refer to the concrete, but to that which has been
universalized. But only the concrete usages, the relations of
domination, the legal relations, the contracts, the articles of
association, the dispositions by last will and testament, yield the rules
according to which men regulate their conduct. And it is only on the
basis of these rules that the norms for decision that the courts apply
and the statutory provisions that alone have hitherto occupied the
attention of jurists arise. The great majority of judicial decisions are
based on concrete usages, relations of possession, contracts, articles
of association, and dispositions by last will and testament, that the
courts have found to exist. If we would comprehend the
universalizations, the reductions to unity, and the other methods of
finding forms that the judge and the lawgiver employ, we must first of
all know the basis upon which they were carried out. To this extent
Savigny was right when the said that the law—and by law he means
above all the legal proposition—can be understood only from its
historical connection; but the historical connection does not lie in the
hoary past, but in the present, out of which the legal proposition
grows.
But the scientific significance of the living law is not confined to its
influence upon the norms for decision which the courts apply or upon
the content of statutes. The knowledge of the living law has an
independent value, and this consists in the fact that it constitutes the
foundation of the legal order of human society. In order to acquire a
knowledge of this order we must know the usages, relations of
domination, legal relations, contracts, articles of association,
declarations by last will and testament, quite independently of the
question whether they have already found expression in a judicial
decision or in a statute or whether they will ever find it. The provisions
contained in the German Commercial Code regulating stock
exchanges, banks, publishing houses, and other supplementary
provisions were full of gaps when they were enacted and, for the most
part, have become antiquated. Modern commerce has meanwhile
created an enormous number of new forms, which ought to be the
subject matter of scientific study as well as those that have been
enumerated in the statute. Very much that is of genuine value can be
found on this point in the literature on the science of commerce that is
blossoming forth so abundantly. A part of the order in the sphere of
mining and navigation has been made accessible to legal science
through mining law, maritime law, and the law of inland navigation,
but for the most part this has long since become antiquated. The
factory, the bank, the railroad, the great landed estate, the labour
375
union, the association of employers, and a thousand other forms of life
—each of these likewise has an order, and this order has a legal side as
well as that of the mercantile establishment, which is being regulated
in detail only by the Commercial Code. In addition there are countless
forms in which the activity of these associations manifests itself
outwardly, above all the contracts. In studying the manufacturing
establishment, the legal investigator must pursue the countless
intricate paths that lead from the acceptance of the order to the
delivery of the finished products to the customer.” 20
Then he arrived at the main thesis of his book, a primary principle in the sociology
of law and a comprehensive observation about law: “At the present and at any
other time, the center of gravity of legal development lies not in legislation, nor in
juristic science, nor in judicial decision, but in society itself.” 21 From this he arrives
at his own meaning of law, that “law consists of the inner order of associations.” He
strove to prove this by means of a lengthy, comprehensive, historical, sociological,
and empirical study of society.
Ehrlich first explained that all the studies in the field of social science, among this
the study of law, is based on the concept of society. In other words, Ehrlich
proposed that if law is to be scrutinized deeply enough, the study must focus on
society and there will be found the origin of law. He placed significance on the
development of society as “the sum total of all human associations that have
mutual relations with one another.” 22 He continued his proof by means of a long,
empirical, and historical exposition of the various kinds of societies according to
rank. He demonstrated that by means of this exposition that these associations
have an inner order which reflect the law of the organization. Hence, if society is
composed of the various human associations, the law is composed of the inner
order of these associations.
a. The Various Kinds of Organized Associations in Society and the Kinds of Society
according to Rank
There exist various organized associations in society; there are two comprehensive
classifications of these associations; there are three kinds of society in Europe
according to historical or chronological age, there are other non-European societies,
and various roles and duties of the members of these associations within society. In
any case, whatever the association or society, the law of society consists of the
inner order of these associations.
These associations which make up human society are many and distinct from each
other. Ehrlich itemized them.
20
Id., pp. 719-720.
21
Eugen Ehrlich, “Law and the Inner Order of Associations,” The Nature of Law, edited by M.P. Golding (New
York: Random House, 1997), reprinted from Ehrlich, Fundamental Principles of the Sociology of Law (Cambridge,
Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1936), p. 200.
22
Id., p. 201.
376
“. . . The state, the nation, the community of states which are bound
together by ties of international law, i.e. the political, economic,
intellectual, and social association of the civilized nations of the earth
extending far beyond the bounds of the individual state and nation, the
religious communions and the individual churches, the various sects
and religious groups, the corporations, the classes, the professions, the
political parties within the state, the families in the narrowest and in
the widest sense, the social groups and cliques—this universe of
interlacing rings and intersecting circles—constitute a society to the
extent that acting and reacting upon another is at all perceptible
among them.”23
Apart from this, Ehrlich classified these organized associations into two: the
primitive, genetic association and the non-genetic association. “From these various
kinds of groups of human beings, we must select, first of all, a certain kind of
organized association, which we shall hereafter designate as the primitive (genetic)
association. We meet with it in primitive times in various forms as clan ( Geschlect,
gens, Sippe), family, house community.”24 These genetic associations merge into
larger associations which are no longer genetic. “(T)he family develops into the
house community, which is usually also called the family. Out of the union of
genetic associations, clans, families, house communities, grows the tribe, and, in
course of time, the nation.”25 Within the larger association can be found the
numerous and various non-genetic associations, which have already been itemized.
In the history of mankind, there have arisen three kinds of societies: the early
primitive, the middle feudal and the present civilized. When society has reached
the highest stage, there arise various and many associations and the role and value
of the genetic associations in society is no longer as great. There emerge many and
various non-genetic associations which change and which take upon the role of
what the previous genetic associations assumed and because of this they enjoy a
pervasive and widespread effect on the kind of life the individuals in society live.
“In the primitive stage, the whole legal order consists in the inner order
of the human associations, of which, indeed the state is one. Each
association creates this order for itself, even though it is true that an
association often copies an order existing in other associations, or in
the case of splitting up of an association, takes over an order and
continues it. Because of these facts, to which must be added the
similarities caused by the similarity of the relations, common features
will not be lacking. To an observer from the outside these common
features might appear to constitute a common law of the nation. But
this is only a generalization made by the observer himself on the basis
of what he has seen and heard. Tacitus makes a number of
statements about the legal relations of the ancient Germans, but a
cursory glance at his account suffices to show that it contains no legal
propositions, but only statements about what the Germans customarily
did and left undone. Society, if one may use the term with reference
23
Id.
24
Id.
25
Id., p. 202.
377
to those times, maintained its balance not by means of rules of law,
but by means of the inner order of its associations.” 26
From this viewpoint, Ehrlich scrutinized the law of these three kinds of societies, the
law of the lower primitive or original cultures which predated the civilized nations of
Europe, the feudal law of Europe and the law of a higher culture, that of the
civilized nations of Europe itself. He also discussed the law of non-European
societies. He demonstrated that whatever the society or culture, law consists of the
inner order of associations.
b. The Law of Primitive Society which Gave Rise to the Civilized Nations of Europe
The law of the earlier societies, from where emerged the civilized nations of Europe,
differ from the law of today: the law as “a fixed rule of law, formulated words, which
issues from a power superior to the individual, and which is imposed upon the latter
from without.”27 Very rarely did this kind of law surface during primitive times.
So too is the law of property the law of the inner order of associations.
It is likewise true that the law of contracts is based on this inner order; more
exactly, it is based only on the contents of these contracts which have been
attested to, and there are no universal legal propositions which govern the
agreement. Therefore:
26
Id., pp. 203-204.
27
Id., p. 202.
28
Id., p. 203.
29
Id.
378
“In the primitive stage, the whole legal order consists in the inner order
of associations, of which, indeed, the state is one. Each association
creates this order for itself, even though it is true that an association
often copies an order existing in other associations, or in case of a
splitting up of an association, takes over an order and continues it.
Because of these facts, to which must be added the similarities caused
by the similarity of the relations, common features will not be lacking.
To an observer from the outside these common features might appear
to constitute a common law of the nation. But this is only a
generalization made by the observer himself on the basis of what he
has seen and heard. Tacitus makes a number of statements about the
legal relations of the ancient Germans, but a cursory glance at his
account suffices to show that it contains no legal propositions, but only
statements about what Germans customarily did and left undone.
Society, if one may use the term with reference to those times,
maintained its balance not by means of rules of la, but by means of the
inner order of its associations.” 30
“. . . the chief characteristic of the feudal state is the fact that it has
no constitution, but only agreements. The relation between the king
and the great lords to whom he has granted fiefs is a contractual one.
Likewise the relation between the great lords and those whom they
have enfeoffed; likewise the relation between the latter and those
whom they, in turn, have enfeoffed. On the lowest rung of the ladder
are the serfs. Of course, one or more rungs may be omitted, and the
feudal lords have serfs at any level in this scale. In order to write an
exhaustive description of the feudal state, one must be able to state
the content of all the agreements entered into between the lords and
their liegemen and of the relation between the lords and the villeins,
which often is merely contractual. The agreements and the relation
between the lord and the villeins may be very much alike in a certain
district and among a certain people. But this similarity also is based
upon the similarity of the attendant circumstances, upon direct
imitation or borrowing, not a general rule. What is called ‘feudal law’ is
primarily a scientific elaboration of the common element in the
individual agreements, which at a later period is transformed into a
general rule of law which ekes out the content of the agreements.” 31
379
being accepted by the feudal lord, and thereby become collective agreements with
the feudal lord.”32
However, a feudal constitution is part only of the contents of the societal order of a
feudal state. Nevertheless, it does not follow that feudal law cannot be found in the
inner order of associations. There existed also cities, which were placed outside of
the feudal constitutions, where there arose and grew many social associations and
vibrant legal ways of life. “Here for the first time fully developed legal institutions
were expressed in a number of legal propositions: the law of real property, of
pledge, of contract, of inheritance.”33
Contrary to the first two ages, contemporary thought is dominated by the viewpoint
that the law consists only of legal propositions. This is because, due to the passage
of time, great value is placed upon the legal proposition, which is expressed and
enacted by those in authority.
However, this viewpoint brought about numerous contradictions. These inner rules
are not contained in the Public Law or in the Administrative Law or in Remedial Law;
however, if the actual operation of government of the city administrations is
observed, it will be perceived that the law consists not only of legal propositions. If
substantive law is to be examined, the contradiction will become more evident.
“. . . On the other hand, the legal rules barely touch the surface of the
modern order of the family. The law of corporations and of foundations
is based in the main upon the articles of association. In spite of the
detailed provisions of the law of contracts, the content of the contract
is of greater importance in the law of inheritance than the rules of law
concerning it. Every judge, every administrative official, knows that,
comparatively speaking, he rarely renders a decision based solely on
legal propositions. By far the greatest number of decisions are based
upon documents, testimony of witnesses or experts, contracts, articles
32
Id., p. 205.
33
Id.
34
Id., pp. 205-206.
380
of association, last wills and testaments, and other declarations. In
other words, in the language of jurists, in a much greater number of
instances judgment is being rendered on questions of fact than upon
questions of law. And the fact is a matter of the inner order of the
human associations, as to which the judge obtains testimony from the
testimony of witnesses and experts, from contracts, agreements
among heirs, declarations by last will and testament. Even today, just
as in primitive times, the fate of man is determined to a much greater
extent by the inner order of the associations than by legal
propositions.”35
In truth, man and society come first, human behavior in society, and the interaction
and coordination of the people with each other in society before law has been
enacted by the state government. In other words, the concrete precedes the
abstract. Hence, law originates merely from the inter-actions of the people.
“. . . The state existed before the constitution, the family is older than
the order of the family, possession antedates ownership; there were
contracts before there were was a law of contracts; and even the
testament, where it is of native origin, is much older than the law of
last wills and testaments. If the jurists think that before a binding
contract was entered into, before a valid testament was made, there
must have been in existence a legal proposition according to which
agreements or testaments are binding, they are placing the abstract
before the concrete. Perhaps it seems more readily understandable to
a jurist that a legal proposition concerning the law of contracts or the
law of wills might be binding than that of a contract or will might be
binding without a legal proposition. But the mental processes of
nations and of men, excepting the jurists among them, do not function
in this fashion. It can be shown that the idea that prevailed among
men in the past was that their right had arisen from a contract or from
a grant; the idea that it had arisen from a legal proposition was
altogether foreign to them. And at the present time, unless legal
theory exerts its influence, men generally assume that their rights
arise not from legal propositions but from relations of man to man,
from marriage, contract, last will and testament. That anyone might
owe his rights to a legal proposition, is a notion that even today is
current only among jurists. Social phenomena, however, can be
explained not by construing them juristically but by inferring from facts
the modes of thought that underlie them.”36
The same thing happens in law if the societies of the primitive races and the
undeveloped countries of the East, and in the Eastern and Southern parts of Europe
are considered. The “traditional order of the small association, of the household, of
the family, of the clan, is followed.”37
35
Id., pp. 206-207.
36
Id., pp. 207-208.
37
Id., p. 208.
381
The comprehensive, historical and sociological analysis reaches only one
conclusion:
According to Ehrlich, all the attempts to study law during his time were by means of
the legal proposition and not the inner order of associations. It is not surprising
therefore that all these attempts proved fruitless. Consequently, there arises the
need for an explanation of law with regard to its origin, its growth and development,
and its nature based on the inner order of associations.
There is a great difference between legal norms and legal propositions. The legal
proposition “is the precise, universally binding formulation of the legal precept in a
book of statutes or in a law book.” 39 On the other hand, a legal norm “is the legal
command, reduced to practice, as it obtains in a definite association, perhaps of
very small size, even without formulation in words.” 40 Thus, a legal rule may be
considered as an effective legal proposition.
Ehrlich argued that the inner order of associations consists in legal norms, and not
legal propositions. In every society, legal norms are more plentiful or numerous
than legal propositions. The dominance of the legal norm may be explained as
follows:
382
they are norms, abstract commands and prohibitions, concerning the
social life within the association and directed to members of the
association. In addition to rules of conduct of this kind, there are rules
that are not norms because they do not refer to the social life of
human beings: e.g. the rules of language, of taste, or of hygiene.
The legal norm, therefore, is merely one of the rules of conduct, one of
the same nature as all other rules of conduct.” 41
According to the predominant concept of the nature of law, a rule is a legal norm if
it is posited by the state as a legal norm. this means that the rule, from wherever it
came, becomes a legal norm only if it is recognized by the state as a legal norm,
and it is surrounded by rules of the second order, rules concerning punishment,
methods, and administrative regulations.
Ehrlich already established that this concept is mistaken because a rule becomes a
legal rule only if the state enacted it as a legal rule. The order of the houses in
Rome, mediaeval haciendas, and primitive communities are not part of law
according to the above conception.
It is true that state law has a great influence on the state of the law today.
This does not mean, however, that the state has no role in creating state law. The
law is the result only of the interaction and coordination between the state and
society. Even juristic law is shaped in accordance with the influence of society.
“As soon as state law has actually become part and parcel of everyday
life, and has exerted a moulding influence upon it, jurists will no longer
confine their attention to the words of the statute but will be
concerned with the forms of life that have come into being under its
influence. The universalizations which they arrive at in doing this, the
norms which they find, will, of course, be juristic law. This happened in
41
Id., pp. 209-210.
42
Id., p. 210.
383
Rome in the case of the Lex Falcidia and of the senatusconsultum
Velleianum, and has happened again and again since that time.
English commerce is regulated by the Statute of Frauds to such an
extent that the English were unwilling to change it although it is quite
antiquated, but took it over in apart almost verbatim into the Sales of
Goods Act of that year 1893. Inasmuch as the German testament is
derived from the Roman testament, the Lex Falcidia was received into
German law together with the latter, and has become a part of the
living German law no less than the testament. It is well known and
generally understood that the canon law prohibition against usury is in
exactly the same case. It has all the hall-marks of state-made law.
The church, which promulgated it, was an association partaking of the
nature of the state, and was, in this case, as the state is in other cases,
an agency of society for the purpose of creating law. Through its own
courts and through its influence upon the courts of the state, the
church was enabled to give effect to its law as readily as the state.” 43
Hence, the state has a very limited role in the making of law. Nonetheless, we
completely believe in ideas such as the unlimited power of the state, and the
analogous ideas such as: “the power to legislate is the highest power in modern
society, and that resistance to it is to be condemned under all circumstances; that
there cannot be any law within the territory of the state that is in conflict with
statute law; and that a judge who in the administration of law disregards a statute is
guilty of a gross violation of duty.” 44
This opinion constitutes great error. The center of gravity of the development of
law is society, even if the rules to be used by the courts for judging are being
referred to.
43
Id., p.
44
Id., p. 212.
45
Id., p. 212.
384
that the actual state of the law does not conform to the legal norms that have been
promulgated or enacted by the state.
“In order to understand the actual state of the law we must institute an
investigation as to the contribution that is being made by society itself
as well as by state law, and also to the actual influence of the state
upon social law. We must know what kinds of marriages and families
exist in a country, what kinds of contracts are being entered into, what
their content is as a general rule, what kinds of declarations by last will
and testament are being drawn up, how all of these things ought to be
adjudged according to the law that is in force in the courts and other
tribunals, how they are actually being adjudged, and to what extent
these judgments, and other decisions are actually effective. An
investigation of this sort will reveal that although the legislation of two
different countries may be identical, e.g. of France and Roumania, the
law of one country may differ from that of the other; that in spite of the
fact that the courts and other tribunals of Bohemia, Dalmatia, and
Galicia apply the same code, the law of these countries is by no means
the same; and that because of the differences in the actual state of the
law, there is no uniform law even in the various parts of Germany in
spite of the Civil Code, quite apart from the particular divergences of
legislation.”46
A theory of law is a theory about what the law is. Ehrlich stressed that he had
already answered this problem. He based his answer on his methodical and
comprehensive research and study of various cultures, societies, and civilizations,
included in this the associations which make them up and in his detailed
investigations and observations of the interaction between law and society. From
these comprehensive studies, he reached the conclusion that the law is nothing but
the inner order of associations which contain the legal rules.
Hence, Ehrlich is a theorist based on the phenomenon of what the law is.
Nonetheless, the law that Ehrlich refers to is a law distinct from that which should
be the concern of a legal theorist. The law that he refers to is the law that is truly
obeyed, followed, complied with, and made by the individuals and officials in
society. On the other hand, the legal theorist has in mind the positive law, the state
law as Ehrlich calls it, or the law that the individual citizen follows, that is taken up
by the students in the law colleges, that is argued by the lawyers in the courtrooms,
and the law that is applied by the courts.
It cannot be denied that the law actually complied with, followed, and made in
society comprises a valuable field of knowledge, it is only that it is more
appropriately an aspect of the sociology of law and not of legal theory. Apart from
these, I myself maintain that this sociological studies provide meaningful
understanding and comprehension towards a complete knowledge of positive law;
and, because of this, ought to constitute a valuable aspect of legal theory. That
being said, these two senses of law must be explained, that one may not be
46
Id., pp. 212-213.
385
confused with the other, and that the legal theorist has as his concerns the positive
law and not the law that is actually followed or complied with.
Consequently, Ehrlich was mistaken when he maintained that the inner order of
associations or the legal rules are truly valid law. His mistake is similar to that of
the Classical Natural Law theorists when they opined that the real or actual valid
law is the natural law. This is the mistake which substitutes two distinct kinds of
phenomena or two distinct meanings of ‘law’. The legal theorist is not interested in
the question of what the real or actual law is. For him, there are various kinds of
law and various senses of ‘law’. He is interested only in one kind of law, the law in
its positive sense. As long as the many kinds of law provides valuable knowledge
and understanding of the phenomenon of the positive law, the legal theorist accepts
the conclusions that arise from an investigation and analysis of these kinds of law.
However, he is not concerned with these kinds of law. He would then become a
different kind of theorist. Whether it be the real or actual law, he is also not
interested. His only concern is the positive law. This does not mean that the
positive law is the real or actual law, but this is the law that he analyzes and
attempts to understand.
Nonetheless, Ehrlich’s theory of law may be amended to create a legal theory that
may be said to explain or illuminate positive law. Under this interpretation, the law
that is made and applied by society is not considered the real or actual law but only
the source or origin of positive law. The true or actual positive law may be
explained as a legal rule in the meaning of Ehrlich or as a law that consists in the
inner order of associations. So long as the putative law does not manifest the rules
that are obeyed, complied with, and made in society, it may not become real or
actual law.
This definition of positive law, nevertheless, may create confusion which has been
explained by Kelsen, and this confusion concerns the validity or efficacy of law. If
Ehrlich were to explain a valid law that is followed or complied with, he is only
stating the conditions for the effectivity of law and not its validity. These are two
different concepts.
For example, the traffic law in the Philippines is known not to be complied with. In
truth, when my uncle had a foreign visitor and he was showing him the sights of
Manila, the foreigner was taken aback when he saw a car keep on going despite a
red light. He suddenly blurted out: “Why is it that that car kept on going despite the
red light?” My uncle replied: “In the Philippines, there are many shades of green.”
Nonetheless, the law like the traffic laws in the Philippines may be valid but not
effective. Practically no one, just as in the example, stops at a red light. However,
the non-compliance with this rule does not signify that the validity of that law has
been reduced rather than when it is followed. If not, consult the unlucky motorist
386
who has been caught beating a red light. He may argue with the policeman as
much as he likes but this does not mean that his arrest should be considered as
lacking in validity. On the other hand, a rule may be effective but not valid.
This programme was in line with what Pound indicated was the new way of doing
legal theory; focus was transferred from the human will to human wants.
“At the end of the last and the beginning of the present century, a new
way of thinking grew up. Jurists began to think in terms of human
wants or desires or expectations rather than of human wills. They
began to think that what they had to do was not simply to equalize or
harmonize wills, but, if not to equalize, at least to harmonize the
47
Roscoe Pound, “Outlines of Jurisprudence,” 5th edn., 1943, in M.D.A. Freeman, Lloyd’s Introduction to
Jurisprudence, London: Sweet and Maxwell, Seventh Edn., 2001, p. 723.
387
satisfaction of wants. They began to weigh or balance and reconcile
claims or wants or desires or expectations, as formerly they had
balanced or reconciled wills. They began to think of the end of law, not
as a maximum of self-assertion, but as a maximum satisfaction of
wants. Hence for a time they thought of the problems of ethics, of
jurisprudence, and of politics as chiefly one of valuing; as a problem of
finding criteria of the relative value of interests. In jurisprudence and
politics they saw that we must add practical problems of the possibility
of making interest effective through governmental action, judicial or
administrative. But the first question was one of the wants to be
recognized—of the interests to be recognized and secured. Having
inventoried the wants or claims or interests which are asserting and for
which are asserting and for which legal security is sought, we were to
value them, select those to be recognized, determined the limits within
which they were to be given effect in view of other recognized
interests, and ascertain how far we might give them effect by law in
view of the inherent limitations upon effective legal action. This mode
of thinking may be seen, concealed under different terminologies, in
more than one type of jurist.
Pound likened the tasks of the lawyer to engineering. The aim of social engineering
is to build as efficient a structure of society as possible, which requires the
48
Roscoe Pound, “Philosophy of Law,” rev. ed., in M.D.A. Freeman, Lloyd’s Introduction to Jurisprudence,
London: Sweet and Maxwell, Seventh Edn., 2001, p. 721.
388
satisfaction of the maximum of wants with the minimum of friction and waste. 49 In
other words, law, to him, is an ordering of conduct so as to make the goods of
existence and the means of satisfying claims go round as far as possible with the
least friction and waste. Pound regards these claims as interests which exist
independently of the law and which are ‘pressing for recognition and security’. To a
theory of interests thus I now turn.
C. A Theory of Interests
“A legal system attains the ends of the legal order (1) by recognizing
certain interests, individual, public, and social; (2) by defining the
limits within which those interests shall be recognized and given effect
through legal precepts developed and applied by the judicial (and
today the administrative) process according to an authoritative
technique; and (3) by endeavoring to secure the interests so
recognized within the defined limits.
Pound continued first by specifying the necessary ingredients for determining the
scope and subject matter of a legal system, which consists of interests, by
49
Roscoe Pound, Social Control Through Law, p. 65.
50
Roscoe Pound, Jurisprudence, vol. III, St. Paul, Minn.: West Publishing Co., 1959, pp.16-17.
389
classifying those interests into three, individual, public, and social, and finally by
making a reasoned inventory of these interests.
“We begin, then, with the proposition that the law does not create
these interests. It finds them pressing for recognition and security.
First, a legal system classifies them and recognizes a larger or smaller
number. Second it fixes the limits within which it endeavors to secure
the interests so selected. These limits may be fixed in view of other
interests which are also recognized, either directly or indirectly by the
limitations imposed on directly recognized interests. Or the limits may
be fixed in view of the possibilities of effectively securing them through
the judicial or administrative processes. Third, a legal system works
out means by which the interests may be secured when recognized
and delimited. It prescribes canons of values for determining what
interests to recognize, for fixing the limits of securing recognized
interests, and for judging the weight to be accorded in any given case
to the practical limitations on effective legal action.
Interests, that is, the claims or demands or desires for which or about
which the law has to make some provision if civilization is to be
maintained and furthered and society is not to be disrupted or
dissolved, are asserted by individual human beings. But they are not
for that reason all individual interests. We must not confuse interest
as claim, as jurists use the term, with interest as advantage as
economists use it. Thinking of the claims and demands which men
assert and press upon the legal order, interests fall conveniently into
three classes, individual interests, public interests, and social interests.
Individual interests are claims or demands or desires involved in and
looked at from the standpoint of the individual life, immediately as
such—asserted in the title of the individual life. Public interests are the
claims or demands or desires asserted by individuals involved in or
looked at from the standpoint of political life—life in politically
organized society. They are asserted in the title of that organization.
390
It is convenient to treat them as the claims of a politically organized
society thought of as a legal entity. Social interests are claims or
demands or desires, even some of the foregoing in other aspects,
thought of in terms of social life and generalized as claims of the social
group. They are the claims which are involved in the maintenance, the
activity and the functioning of society; the wider demands or desires
asserted in title of social life and looked at from the standpoint of
social life in civilized society.
Every claim does not necessarily go once and for all in one of
these categories exclusively. The same claim may be asserted
in different titles and may have to be looked at from different
standpoints. It may be asserted in title of more than one aspect
of life. Thus my claim to my watch may be asserted as an
individual interest of substance when I sue some one who walks
off with it without my consent, either to recover possession of it
or to obtain its money value as damages for depriving me of it.
But my claim may be looked at also as subsumed under a social
interest in the security of acquisitions and may be asserted as
such when I, by making due complaint, procure the public
prosecutor to prosecute for larceny some one who has stolen it
from me.
Our first step, then, in considering the scope and subject matter of a
system of law is to take a reasoned inventory of the claims or demands
or desires which are or have been made which press or have pressed
for recognition. But these are so many and so varied that we must
classify them in order to understand them. I take them up, therefore,
according to the threefold classification just indicated, classifying them
further under each head.”51
a. Individual Interests
i. Interests of personality
51
Id., pp. 21-24.
52
Id., p. 28.
391
“What then are the claims or demands which the individual makes or
may make which jurist and lawmaker must consider and provide for?
One might seek to ascertain them logically by inquiring what claims,
demands, desires are logically presupposed by or involved in the
individual existence in civilized society. He might seek to formulate
the jural postulates of the civilization of the time and place as a
measure of interests to be recognized and secured. Or he might seek
to ascertain them psychologically by considering the so-called instincts
or fundamental behavior tendencies of men and the claims, demands,
desires which they involve. Or he might attempt no more than to
catalogue and classify the claims, demands, desires which they
involve. Or he might attempt no more than to catalogue and classify
the claims, demands, desires, which he finds men actually asserting;
the claims that have pressed or are pressing for recognition. What I
seek to do is to generalize the claims or demands which the law, past
or present, has had to take account of or has been seeking to secure
and those which may be seen pressing for recognition or for more
complete recognition in the immediate present. It is convenient to
take them up under five heads: (1) The physical person, (2) freedom of
the will, (3) honor and reputation, (4) privacy and sensibilities, and (5)
belief and opinion.
392
Injuries to the body are among the first wrongs dealt with in the history
of law. But they are not thought of at first as infringements of an
individual interest. They are thought of as rather as involving, on the
one hand, injury to the interest of a group of kindred, affront to the kin
whose kinsman is assailed, and on the other hand, injury to a social
interest in peace and order, in that a desire for vengeance is awakened
and hence there is danger of private vengeance and private war. It is
not an individual interest which is regarded, but a group interest.
Hence at first the remedy (composition) is imposed to secure a social
interest in peace and order, not to vindicate an individual interest or
private right. Often in primitive law a composition is payable to the
kindred not to dependents; it is exacted to satisfy vengeance for an
insult to the kindred, not to compensate for those who are deprived of
support. Thus at first the ideas are (1) a group interest against insult,
and (2) a social interest against disorder, rather than an individual
interest in the physical person. Out of these there evolves gradually
the idea of an individual interest secured by an individual right.
...
...
Where the injury is to mental comfort only, the practical difficulties are
much greater. Hence the law can recognize an ‘interest in the peace
and comfort of one’s thoughts and emotions’ only to a limited extent.
An objective standard is required here by the social interest in free
393
individual action and the social interest in the general security as one
against imposture and use of the legal system to extort with which the
social interest in the individual life (under which the individual interest
is to be subsumed for purposes of comparison) must be weighed.
Accordingly, the tendency of the law is to secure an interest in mental
comfort only to the extent of ordinary sensibilities of ordinary men, and
then only when the mental suffering is caused by and involved in the
infringement of some other interest. Here, again, the law does not
secure the whole demand which the individual may make, but it does
secure the interest in case of ordinary sensibilities against a wanton
attack or where there is objective injury. Thus, no doubt, it secures the
interest in the general run of cases for the average man. No more may
well be attempted as the possibilities of proof are at present and in
view of the applicability to such injuries of the means of redress known
to our law.
(2) Freedom of will. In one aspect the interest in freedom of the will is
behind the legal right of ‘free choice of location’ or, as the common-law
authorities have called it, the right of ‘personal liberty.’ Interference
with this right involves a trespass upon the physical person and calls
for nothing in addition to what has been said above in that connection.
But overcoming another’s will may be achieved either by force or
threat of force applied to the physical person or by wrongful pressure
applied to the will without any aggression upon corporal integrity.
Hence the claim to free exercise of the will, free determination of what
one will do and what transactions and relations he will enter into, made
as part of one’s personality, presses for recognition and security
beyond and apart from security of the body.
...
394
to the fame [i.e. reputation], if the matter whereby he is accused be
scandalous;’ (2) injury to his person by imprisonment; and (3) injury to
his property by putting him to cost and expense unlawfully. The
second is obviously an infringement of an interest of personality. The
first may involve personality or substance or both. . . .
...
395
problems are rather to devise suitable redress and to limit the right in
view of other interests involved.
...
396
it as of securing other interests of personality. The individual will fight
for his beliefs no less than for his life and limb and for his honor.
Hence the social interest in the general security is involved in
interference with the former as well as in interference with the two
latter. Moreover, free exercise of one’s mental and spiritual faculties is
a large part of life. As civilization proceeds it may become the largest
part. No one who is restrained in this respect may be said to live a full
moral and social life. Thus the social interest in the moral and social
life of the individual is also involved.”53
Secondly, there are the individual interests in domestic relations, which may be
classified in turn.
397
feature of these relations, since injuries to them touch men on their
most sensitive side, and no injuries are more certain to provoke self-
redress and even private war. With the development of civilization,
the social interest in individual life, the claim of the individual to a
social existence as a human being, reinforces this requirement. On the
other hand, there is the individual economic existence in which the
purely economic side of such relations may be of great importance.
Here, sometimes, along with the social interest in the individual life,
the social interest in the relations as social institutions may require
careful securing of the purely economic advantages. An example may
be seen in legal provisions for support of dependent wives and
children. At other times the social interest in the individual life may
demand that the individual economic advantages of one of the parties
to the relation be less regarded. For example, in a weighing of marital
interests with the individual interests of the wife, it may be expedient
to leave the purely economic claim of the husband unsecured as
against the wife or secured but partially.
398
‘A parent has an interest in his relation with his child. The
elements of the interest are three: (1) The industrial services
received from the child; (2) the social pleasure ministered by the
child; (3) the chastity of a female child, as ministering to the
parent’s sentiments of family, self-respect and honor.’
...
Turning to the claims of the parent against the child, legal security is
given to the interest in respect and obedience, as far as such interests
admit of effective securing through law, by the internal discipline of the
household backed up by the legal privilege of ‘moderate correction.’
Today this is reinforced to some extent by the powers of juvenile
courts with respect to truancy and incorrigibility. The claim of the
parent to the services of the child for the profit of the household is
secured in the same way and also by the legal right of the parent, as
between parent and child, to the latter’s earnings. But legal
recognition of this interest is much restricted today in view of the
social interests which are secured by legislation as to child labor. On
the other hand, the interest of the indigent parent in support by a child
of age, capacity, and sufficient means, an interest which is reinforced
by the moral sentiment of mankind and by the social interest in the
individual life, was not recognized by the strict law.
...
399
or, after majority, because circumstances precluding self-support
render it improper or impossible for him to be left to himself. Also he
has an interest in the society and affection of his parent, at least while
he remains in the household. But the law has done little to secure
those interests. At common law there were no legal rights securing
them. In case the parent is killed through the wrongful act of another,
the legislation which goes by the name of Lord Campbell’s Act usually
takes account directly of the interest of the independent children. Also
in many jurisdictions the ‘civil damage acts,’ which create liability for
sale of intoxicating liquor to a parent whereby through intoxication the
parent is killed or disabled or rendered incompetent to provide, secure
immediately the interest of the child in the relation which involves
support and protection.
As against the parent, the child may claim: (1) Support during infancy;
(2) education and training so far as the situation of the parent permits,
and (3) in case of indigent children of nature years who are unable to
support themselves, maintenance at least so far as the parent can
afford. The first two, however, are not secured directly by our law, and
derive their effective support almost entirely from morals. There has
been legislation permitting an action by the child against the parent to
enforce a statutory duty of support. But the courts have refused
equitable enforcement at suit of the child where there is no more than
the statutory duty. The statutes are considered to secure a social
rather than an individual interest and the social interest is weighed
with the social interest in the security of domestic institutions. This
construction of the statutes is clear as to legislation making desertion
of wife and child a crime or providing for compulsory education. In
Roman law and in the civil-law world the third interest is secured by
the doctrines as to reciprocal duties of support of ascendants and
descendants heretofore considered.
...
4. Marital Interests. As against the world at large, the claims which the
husband may assert with respect to the marital relation are four. (1)
He has an interest in the society of his wife which may be infringed by
abducting her, by enticing her away, or by so injuring her as to deprive
the husband of her companionship. While this interest is not entirely
separable from that in the economic advantage in the relation, it is, on
the whole, more nearly an interest of personality. (2) He has an
interest in the affection of the wife which may be infringed by
persuasion or pressure addressed to her mind and will. This interest
also is intimately connected with his spiritual existence and mental
comfort as to be in effect an interest of personality. (3) He has an
interest in the chastity of the wife, which is so related to his feelings of
self-respect and to his honor as to be in effect an interest of
personality. (4) He has an interest in the services of the wife in the
household. Perhaps it would be better to call this an interest in the
relation as economically advantageous. Obviously it is in effect an
400
interest of substance. All four of these interests are secured at
common law by legal rights redressed by an action on the case. The
first and fourth are not very clearly differentiated. In either event the
deprivation of the wife’s services is often spoken of as the significant
thing. Yet in an old case the judges spoke of the action as brought ‘for
the loss and damage of the husband for want of her company and aid.’
And although under modern statutes the wife’s time and earnings may
be her own and there may be no valuable right to her services, the
husband may maintain an action for an injury to the wife which
deprives him of her companionship. In effect, therefore, the action
may be for loss of consortium without any loss of service. It is clear
also that there is at common law a cause action where the wife’s
affections are alienated without more, and in this action for alienation
of affections and even more in the action for criminal conversation with
the plaintiff’s wife, which secures the husband’s interest in the chastity
of the wife, the essential point is the injury to honor and ‘domestic
comfort’ of the husband. So far, then, as interest that have to do with
personality may be protected through actions for money damages, the
common law covers the whole field of the husband’s interests in this
relation. The defect of specific and preventive remedies already noted
in the case of interests of personality, obtains here also. But there is
more excuse in the present connection in that anything in the nature
of specific relief would be futile in the general run of cases and usually
preventive relief would be impossible. It is seldom that danger of
injury to this relation is apprehended before the injury is complete and
the acts which threaten injury are likely to be too subtle and intangible
to permit of judicial interference in advance.
...
As against the wife, the first interest of the husband is a claim to the
wife’s society. The claim used to be put more strongly as one to a
certain degree of custody and control of the wife’s person and to
obedience. But it can hardly be put in this way today except where
older ideas of the subjection of women still linger, and if a stronger
claim were asserted, the individual interests of the wife and the social
interest in her individual moral and social life should be deemed
decisive. Formerly our legal system secured the interest of in the
wife’s society in three ways, namely, by a marital privilege of restraint
and correction, by a suit for restitution of conjugal rights, and by the
writ of habeas corpus directed to one who harbored the wife apart
from the husband. But the privilege of restraint and correction is no
longer recognized, the suit for restitution and correction is no longer
recognized, the suit for restitution of conjugal rights, an ecclesiastical
proceeding for the correction of morals, is obsolete, and the writ of
habeas corpus can be used only when the wife is detained from the
husband against her will. Thus the writ of habeas corpus now operates
chiefly to secure her interest and is available to secure the interest of
the husband only when his interest and hers happens to coincide.
401
Today the husband’s interest in the wife’s society has no security
beyond morals and the opinion of the community.
...
...
A wife may assert against the world at large four claims growing out of
the marital relation. (1) She has an interest in the society of her
husband, quite apart from an economic advantage, as something so
related to her spiritual existence as to be in effect an interest of
personality. (2) She has an interest in the affection of the husband, in
all respects analogous to the interest of the husband in the affection of
the wife, which is clearly an interest in personality. (3) She has an
interest in the chastity and constancy of the husband, involving her
self-respect and honor, and hence obviously an interest of personality.
(4) She has an interest in the relation as an economically
advantageous relation, providing her with support and shelter, which is
manifestly an interest in substance. These interests, however, are not
all of them recognized to their full extent and are not fully secured
even in legal theory. As in the case of interests of the husband, the
first and fourth are often closely connected in practice and have not
been well differentiated. The clearest recognition is to be seen in
cases where the husband is enticed or induced to abandon the wife or
402
divert his earnings which should be devoted to her support. Where
these interests are infringed by physical injury to the husband or by
abduction of the husband, a difficulty arises in that the husband has an
action in which he may recover for diminution of his earning power,
loss of earnings, and impairment of his ability to support those
dependent upon him. The same question arises in case of like
interests of children. The reason for not securing the interest of wife or
child in these cases seems to be that our modes of trial are such and
our mode of assessment of damages by the verdict of a jury is
necessarily so crude that if husband and wife were each allowed to
sue, instead of each recovering an exact reparation, each would be
pretty sure to recover what would repair the injury to both. Moreover,
the injury to wife or child is very hard to measure in money. Hence on
a practical weighing of interests the wife is usually denied an action.
...
The second interest (and first when involved along with it) is protected
by an action for alienating the husband’s affections or for criminal
conversation with the husband, recognized by the overwhelming
preponderance of American authority. At first the third interest was at
most but partially and only indirectly secured. An action based solely
upon his interest was denied. It is only in very recent times that views
as to the relation of the sexes have made such an interest in the wife
notable. Recovery of damages might be had, however, incidentally in
an action based on the second or fourth. An action by the wife against
another woman for criminal conversation was allowed in New York in
1923. Perhaps it need not be said that the observations with respect
to the difficulties involved in practical securing of the corresponding
interests of the husband apply here also.
...
As against the husband, the claims of the wife growing out of the
marital relation are two: (1) A claim to the society and affection of the
husband, and (2) a claim to support. As to the first, it need not be said
that no legal sanctions can control human affections. The interest in
society of the husband was formerly secured by a suit of the restitution
of conjugal rights. But this has everywhere become obsolete or has
lost its efficacy for reasons considered in connection with the
corresponding interest of the husband. On the other hand, the interest
in support is fully recognized and thoroughly secured by proceedings in
equity for maintenance, by the legal doctrine that the husband’s credit
is pledged for necessaries to the wife, so that if he fails in his duty any
one may provide them and hold the husband therefore, by orders of
support under modern statutes, especially in domestic relations courts
in the United States and in summary proceedings before magistrates
of England, and by criminal prosecutions for non-support which,
however, primarily secure a social interest. Moreover, as the Married
Woman’s Acts, giving the wife full control of her separate property do
403
not affect the common-law duty of the husband to support his wife, a
wife who has supported herself out of her earnings can sue her
husband for restitution.
iii. Substance
Next are the individual interests of substance, which concern economic life.
404
general existence may depend to a large extent upon individual labor
in specialized occupations and so the power to labor freely at one’s
chosen occupation may be his chief asset. Yet this power is very
closely related to personality, as shown, this power is very closely
related to personality, as shown, for example, by the difficulties
encountered by equity in enforcement of contracts of personal service.
The power of working for reward may involve infringement of liberty if
treated as property. Thus this interest raises different questions from
those raised by the claim to control corporeal things. For example,
even if all corporeal things were excluded from individual control and
held to be exclusively, as it were, social assets, there would remain a
question whether all individual control over individual productive
activity should be excluded and all individual potential labor should be
treated as no more than a social asset. Third, there are claims to
promised advantages; to promised performances of pecuniary value,
since in a complex economic order, with minute division of labor and
enterprises extending over long periods, credit more and more
replaces corporeal things as the medium of exchange and agency of
commercial activity, and becomes an increasingly important form of
wealth. Promised advantages are commonly called incorporeal
property. Fourth, there are claims to be secured against interference
by outsiders with economically advantageous relations with others,
whether contractual, social, business, official, or domestic. Not only do
relations which have an economic value involve claims against the
other party to the relation, which one may demand that the law
secure, but they also involve claims against the world at large that
these advantageous relations, which form an important part of the
substance of the individual, shall not be interfered with. Legal
recognition of these four types of individual claims, securing of
individual interests of substance, is at the foundation of our economic
organization of society.
In civilized society men must be able to assume that they may control
for purposes beneficial to themselves what they have discovered and
appropriated to their own use, what they have created by their own
labor, and what they have acquired under the existing social and
economic order. This is a jural postulate of civilized society as we
know it. The law of property in the widest sense, including incorporeal
property and the growing doctrines as to protection of economically
advantageous relations, gives effect to the social want or demand
formulated in this postulate. So also (although proceeding on another
postulate) does the law of contract in an economic order based on
credit. A social interest in the security of acquisitions and a social
interest in the security of transactions are forms of the interest in the
general security which give the law most to do. The general safety,
peace and order, and the general health are secured for the most part
by police and administrative agencies. Property and contract, security
of acquisitions and security of transactions, are the domain in which
law in the second sense is most effective and is chiefly invoked. Hence
405
property and contract are the two subjects about which philosophy of
law has had the most to say.
...
...
406
(1) Custody (natural possession)—a conception of pure fact, not in any
degree dependent upon law. The law secures the physical person of
the one who has custody, not the relation to the thing.
...
407
by will. That idea has been much urged by nineteenth-century writers
on the philosophy of law. Most of them have recognized a right of free
gift and bequest and have deduced it from the very idea of property.
Let us look first at the supposed natural right of succession or natural
right of inheritance.
...
...
408
4. PROMISED ADVANTAGES. In a developed economic order the claim
to promised advantages is one of the most important of the individual
interests that press for recognition. If it is a task of the legal order to
secure reasonable individual expectations so far as they may be
harmonized with the least friction and waste, in an economic order
those arising from promises have a chief place. Credit is a principal
form of wealth. It is a presupposition of the whole economic order that
promises will be kept. Indeed the matter goes deeper. The social
order rests upon stability and predictability of conduct, of which
keeping promises is a large item. From the Greek philosophers of
social control who recognized this stability and predictability if conduct
as fundamental the morally binding force of a promise has been a
starting point in systems of ideal or natural law. As Strykius put it, in
arguing as to the basis of politically organized society, “Agreements
are to be kept . . . this maxim has proceeded from the mouth of God,
and for that reason God is bound by a pact, and the devil and the
prince, and there is no greater justice than to observe pacts.’ But the
law has been slow in coming toward this demand of the economic
order, and Anglo-American law has not yet fully secured individual
interests in promised advantages to the extent of the jural postulate of
the economic order. The reason is historical. Moreover, philosophical
discussion has been largely influenced by the condition of the law as
determined by history and hence has been directed more to
justification of fallings short of what the jural postulate calls for or what
a weighing of the interest with reference to conflicting or overlapping
interests demands.
What is the extent of this interest? What may the individual demand in
this respect? In a commercial age wealth is largely made up of
promises. A very important part of one’s substance is made up of
advantages which others have promised to provide or render him; of
claims which he may make not against the world at large but against
particular individuals to have the advantages promised him. Thus,
applying the method I have sought to use in other connections, the
individual claims to have secured to him the performance of
advantageous promises—the satisfaction of reasonable expectations
created by promises and agreements, and ought to be secured in this
interest unless there is some countervailing interest. This is further
than jurists generally have gone. But their philosophical views have
been influenced by the historical jurisprudence of the last century, by
the law of the time and place and by the history of the law on this
subject.
...
409
interest in the stability of promises as a social and economic institution
—the social interest in the security of transactions which is a phase of
the social interest in the general security. On the other hand, there
are individual interests of personality of the promisor, e.g. in case of
specific enforcement of contracts for personal service of a confining
nature or under the supervision of the promise as to details, or where
enforcement involves interference with privacy or personal liberty,
which are ultimately referable to the social interest in the individual
life. Also the social interest in the individual life must be taken into
account in cases of economic inequality, as in recent labor legislation,
the social interest in the general morals in certain agreements against
public policy, and the social interest in the general security where
danger of fraud or imposition by false evidence has to be guarded
against. But restriction of enforcement of promises has grown much
more out of the history of the subject than out of a weighing of those
interests.
...
410
action for depriving one wrongfully of the profits or emoluments of
public office. But strong interests, both social and public, must be
taken into account. The later cases have settled that this power of
removal after investigation may be given to executive officials or
boards. The idea of property in a public office must be at least much
modified.
...
...
411
self-organization, to form, to join, or assist labor organizations, to
bargain collectively, through representatives of their own choosing,
and to engage in concerted activities for the purpose of collecting
bargaining or other mutual aid and protection.’ It defines as ‘unfair
labor practices’ (1) interference, restraint or coercion of employees in
the exercise of guaranteed rights, (2) dominating or interfering with
the formation or administration of any labor organization, (3)
discrimination as to hire or tenure of employment or any term or
condition of employment to encourage or discourage membership in
any labor organization, (4) discharge of or discrimination against an
employee for filing charges or giving testimony under the act, and (5)
refusal to bargain collectively with representatives of the employees.
Accordingly there is not, as at common law, an action for damages for
breach of contract in case of discharge without legitimate cause, nor is
there an employment at will, from which there could be a discharge at
pleasure of the employer. The employee can have the benefit of a
fully protected collective agreement and on the expiration of that
agreement can require a new bargain, likewise fully protected, and is
secured as to tenure and against discrimination in that the employer
may be ordered to reinstate him with back pay. There has been like
legislation in a number of states. As to employees in industry, so far as
within the purview of federal legislation, security of tenure in
employment is now well provided for. Security and opportunity in
obtaining employment where the relation has not therefore existed is
provided for only to the extent of making refusal to hire in order to
discourage membership in a labor organization an unfair labor
practice. The further question of discrimination and unfair practices
whereby an individual is prevented from obtaining employment has
been considered in another connection. These are relatively newly
urged interests. Recognition of them is very recent and it is likely to
be a long time before experience will have shown how to adjust them
to other conflicting and overlapping interests and develop a just body
of law consistently fitting into the legal system as a whole.” 55
b. Public Interests.
The second kind of interests is public interests. They too may be classified.
412
facto asserted by those who wield political power under the
organization. The law has long taken account of them as such.
413
foreigners. (3) Rights of equality and dignity and rights of legation, of
sending and receiving diplomatic representatives. The latter is chiefly
an interest in honor, and both are interests of personality. Although
usually treated separately they may well be put in one category. This
was formerly of much greater importance in international law than it is
now, as shown by the stress upon it and space devoted to it in older
books. It should be compared with the stress upon honor in the
beginnings of private law. An ancient law for a long time looked at
interests of personality and interests of substance as matters of honor,
so does international law even largely today. It feebly developed
political organization of society the task of the legal order to keep the
peace. Insult is the conspicuous cause of private desire for vengeance
and private war. Not only must the law deal vigorously with insult but
it must be very tender of the dignity of the individual wrongdoer in its
method of bringing him before its tribunals and inducing him to abide
trial and judgment. Legal procedure was held back for a long time by
difficulties growing out of this, and the interest of dignity and honor of
the state makes like difficulties for international law. (4) There are said
to be rights of property. But this is not an interest of substance.
Certain territory and the persons and material objects within it are
subjected to the territorial supremacy of the imperium of the state. To
think of this as property comes from the seventeenth century, the
formative era of international law, when states could be thought of in
terms of absolute personal sovereigns. But we are only concerned
here with the interests of states recognized in international law in that
they show how the analogy of individual interests has been applied to
public interests.
...
...
c. Social interests
414
“§ 93. SOCIAL INTERESTS.—1. THEORY AND CLASSIFICATION. Some
years ago one of the justices of the highest Court, dissenting from the
judgment of that Court in the Arizona Emplyers’ Liability Cases, told us
that there was a ‘menace in the . . . judgment to all rights, subjecting
them unreservedly to conceptions of public policy.’ Undoubtedly, if
certain legal rights were definitely established by the Constitution
there would be a menace to the general security if the Court which
must ultimately interpret and apply the provisions of that instrument
were to suffer a state legislature to infringe those legal rights on mere
considerations of political expediency. But it was only the ambiguity of
the term ‘right,’ a word of many meanings, and want of clear
understanding of what our law has been seeking to achieve through
the obscure conception of ‘public policy’ that made it possible to think
of the decision in question in such a way. The ‘rights’ of which Mr.
Justice McKenna spoke were not legal rights in the same sense as my
legal right to the integrity of my physical person or my legal right of
ownership in my watch. They were individual expectations, individual
claims, individual interests, which it was felt ought to be secured
through legal rights or through some other legal machinery. In other
words, there was a policy of securing them. The Fourth Amendment
did not set up these or any other individual interests as absolute legal
rights. It imposed a standard upon the legislator. It said to him that if
he trenched upon these individual interests as absolute legal rights. It
imposed a standard upon the legislator. It said to him that if he
trenched upon these individual interests he must not do so arbitrarily.
His action must have some basis in reason. It is submitted that that
basis must be the one upon which the common law has always sought
to proceed, the one implied of the very term ‘due process of law,’
namely, a weighing or balancing of the various interests which overlap
or come in conflict and a rational reconciling or adjustment. Thus the
public policy of which Mr. Justice McKenna spoke is seen to be
something at least on no lower plane than the so-called rights. As the
latter term refers to individual interests which we feel ought to be
secured by law, the former refers to social interests which we feel the
law ought to or which in fact the law does secure in delimiting
individual interests and establishing legal rights. There is a policy in
the one case as much as in the other. The body of the common law is
made up of adjustments or compromises of conflicting individual
interests in which we turn to some social interest, frequently under the
name of public policy, to determine the limits of a reasonable
adjustment.
415
validity of an acquisition from the Federal Government ought to be put
at rest as against a claim of fraud, although limitation did not run
against the Government, the Court spoke of the ‘policy’ behind the
statute of limitations and invoked the doctrine of election of remedies
as expressing the same policy. So, too, when a great teacher of law
wished to say that another fundamental legal doctrine was sometimes
limited in its application because of the social interest in the general
security, he stated that ‘except in certain cases based on public policy’
the law of today makes liability dependent upon fault. But this
limitation of the application of principles, of setting off of exceptions,
on grounds of public policy, was felt to be something abnormal. The
classical expression of this feeling is the opinions of the judges in
Everton v. Lord Brownlow. Although the case was decided ultimately
on the ground of public policy, the remarks of the judges have colored
all subsequent judicial thinking on the subject. From the seventeenth
century to the end of the nineteenth, juristic theory sought to state all
interests in terms of individual natural rights.
...
416
This paramount of social interest takes many forms. In its simplest
form it is an interest in the general safety, long recognized in the legal
order in the maxim that the safety of the people is the highest law. It
was recognized in American constitutional law in the nineteenth
century by putting the general safety along with the general health
and general morals in the ‘police power’ as a ground of reasonable
restraint to which natural rights must give way. In another form, quite
as obvious today but not so apparent in the past, before the nature
and causes of disease were understood, it is an interest in the general
health. In another form, recognized from the very beginnings of law, it
is an interest in peace and public order. In an economically developed
society it takes on two other closely related forms, namely, a social
interest in the security of acquisitions and a social interest in the
security of transactions. The two last came to be well understood in
the nineteenth century, in which they were more or less identified with
individual interests of substance and individual interests in freedom of
contract. Yet a characteristic difference between the law of the
eighteenth century and the law of the nineteenth century brings about
their true nature. Eighteenth-century courts, taking a purely
individualist view, regarded the statute of limitations as something to
be held down as much as possible and to be evaded in every way.
Lord Mansfield in particular, under the influence of natural-law ideas
and thinking of the statute only as an individual plea which enabled
the individual interest of a plaintiff to be deprived of legal security,
sought out numerous astute contrivances to get around its most
obvious provisions. If one said, ‘I am ready to account, but nothing is
due you,’ if he made provision in his will for the payment of his ‘just
debts,’ if his executors advertised, notifying those who had ‘just debts’
owing them to present their claims, in these and like cases it was held
there was an acknowledgment sufficing to take a barred debt out of
the statute. Modern courts came to see that there was something
more here than the individual interests of plaintiff and defendant.
They came to see that the basis of the statute was a social interest in
the security of acquisitions, which demands that titles shall not be
insecure by being open to attack indefinitely, and a social interest in
the security of transactions which demands that the transactions of the
past shall not be subject to inquiry indefinitely, so as to unsettle credit
and disturb business and trade. If we compare the French rule, en tout
cas de meuble possession vaut titre with the Roman doctrine that no
one can transfer a greater title than he has, if we note the growth of
the idea of negotiability in the law everywhere, and in our law both by
legislation and by judicial decision, we may see something of how far
recognition of the social interest in the security of transactions went in
the maturity of law.
417
recognition of the social interest in the security of acquisitions, note
the insistence upon stare decisis where rules of property are involved.
In such cases it is better that the law be settled than it be settled right.
‘It is no doubt too soon to be sure even of the path which juristic
thought of the immediate future will follow. But increased
weight given to the social interest in the individual life in the
concrete, instead of upon abstract liberty, seems to be
indicated. There is emphasis upon the concrete claims of
concrete human beings. . . . Family law, in which there must be
a balance between the security of social institutions and the
individual life, is necessarily much affected by such a change.’
418
husband and wife and duty to the state. Also legislation as to mothers’
pensions proceeds at least in large part upon this interest.
419
an interest in maintaining the industrial regime in the face of persistent
pressure from the claims of organized workingmen. Some of the
policies to be considered presently under the social interest in general
progress might be referred to this head.’
420
administrative appointment of receivers of agricultural land cultivated
or managed by the owner ‘in such a manner as to prejudice materially
the production of food thereon . . . .’ Restrictions with respect to
housing proceed on another aspect of this same social interest.
421
everyday law. It may be thought that some of them should be
classified rather as forms of a social interest in the security of
economic institutions. As I read the cases, however, these demands
have pressed upon courts and jurists from the standpoint of their
relation to economic progress. If that relation fails, they are not likely
to maintain themselves. Likewise, the law has long recognized a social
interest in political progress. In American bills of rights, and in written
constitutions generally, a policy of free criticism of public men, public
acts, and public officers, and a policy of free formation, free holding,
and free expression of political opinion are guaranteed as identified
with individual rights. Moreover, at common law, the privilege of fair
comment upon public men and public affairs recognizes and secures
the same interest. But the third form, the social interest in cultural
progress, has not been recognized in the law so clearly. It may be said
to involve four policies: a policy of free science, a policy of free letters,
a policy of encouragement of arts and letters, and a policy of
promotion of education and learning. The last two have been
recognized to some extent in copyright laws and in American
constitutional provisions for the promotion of higher learning. The first
two have made their way more slowly because of conflict or supposed
conflict with the security of religious and political institutions.
422
individual conditions of life. The first, the interest in free self-assertion,
includes physical, mental, and economic activity. In Spencer’s scheme
of natural rights, they appear as a ‘right of free motion and
locomotion,’ a ‘right of free exchange and free contract,’ deduced as a
sort of free economic motion and locomotion; a ‘right of free industry,’
deduced expressly as a modern outgrowth of free motion and
locomotion; as right of free economic activity; a ‘right of free religious
belief and opinion’ and a right of free political belief and opinion; the
two last being deduced also as modern developments of the same
natural right of free motion and locomotion. These are deduced from a
‘law of equal freedom’ which is taken to have been discovered by
observation of social phenomena and verified by further observation.
Without the aid of his ‘law of equal freedom’ he might have found
them by observation of the policies set forth in the law books. The old
common-law policy in favor of freedom, the doctrine that one may
justify action injurious to others by his natural liberty of action, except
where his action takes the form of aggression and so threatens the
general security, and in part the policy of free industry, are examples
of recognition of social interest in individual physical self-assertion.
The policy in favor of free speech and free belief and opinion, although
related also to the social interest in political progress, must be referred
in part to a social interest in individual self-assertion. Policies favoring
free trade and free industry are in part referable to a social interest in
free economic self-assertion.
But the most important phase of the social interest in individual self-
assertion, from the standpoint of modern law; is what might be called
the social interest in freedom of the individual will—the claim or
interest, or policy recognizing it, that the individual will shall not be
subjected arbitrarily to the will of others. This interest is recognized in
an old common-law policy which is declared in the Fifth and Fourteenth
Amendments. If one will is subjected to the will of another through the
force of politically organized society, it is not to be done arbitrarily, but
is to be done upon some rational basis, which the person coerced, if
reasonable, could appreciate. It is to be done upon a reasoned
weighing of the interests involved and a reasoned attempt to reconcile
them or adjust them. This policy obviously expresses political and
juristic experience of what modern psychology has discovered as to
the ill effects of repression. For example, it is more and more
recognized today in our penal legislation and in our treatment of
offenders. It has come to be recognized particularly of late as a result
of pressure upon courts and lawmakers for security in the relation of
employer and employee. It is coming to be recognized also in juristic
thought in another connection as sociological theories of property
replace metaphysical theories. There are many signs of a growing
feeling that complete exclusion of all but him whom the law
pronounces owner from objects which are the natural media of human
existence or means of human activity, must be measured and justified
by a reasoned weighing of the interests on both sides and a reasoned
attempt to harmonize them or to save as much as we may with the
423
sacrifice of as little on the part of the excluded, no less than on the
part of the owner, as we may.
424
creditor relation, or, if a social interest was considered, sought to think
only of the general security, which here takes the form of security of
transactions. Other recognitions of this interest may be seen in
restrictions on the power of debtors or contractors to saddle
themselves with oppressive burdens, as in the doctrines of equity
herein referred to, as in usury laws, and more recently in ‘loan shark’
legislation. A notable instance in recent judicial decision may be seen
in the English doctrine as to covenants not to exercise the calling for
which one has trained himself. Statutes forbidding contracts by
laborers take their pay in orders on company stores, and as to
conditions and hours of labor, minimum wage laws, child labor laws,
and housing laws, are recognitions of the same interest.
Such in outline are the social interests which are recognized or are
coming to be recognized in modern law. Looked at functionally, the
law is an attempt to satisfy, to reconcile, to harmonize, to adjust those
overlapping and often conflicting claims and demands, either through
securing them directly and immediately, or through securing certain
individual interests, or through delimitations or compromises of
individual interests, so as to give effect to the greatest total of
interests or to the interests that weigh most in our civilization, with the
least sacrifice of the scheme of interests as a whole.” 57
The securing of interests consists of three phases: (a.) the valuing of interests; (b.)
the means of securing interests; and (c.) the limits of effective legal action.
57
Id., pp. 268-324.
425
weighed. How are they to be valued? What principle is to determine
their relative weight? Which shall give way in case of conflict?
426
If this were possible it would greatly simplify the task of legislators,
judges, administrative officials and jurists and would conduce to
greater stability, uniformity and certainty in the administration of
justice. Whether it is possible is a fundamental question of social and
political philosophy. The quest of such a method is not, as has been
urged, a mere matter of disinclination to the hard work of thinking
upon the difficult practical problems of adjusting relations in a complex
economic order. It grows out of the need of equality of operation,
predictability, and assured certainty of results under known situations
of fact which men feel strongly to be intrinsic in a just ordering of
relations and of conduct. But however common and natural it is for
philosophers and jurists to seek such a method, we have come to think
today that the quest is futile. Probably the jurist can do no more than
recognize the problem and perceive that it is put to him as a practical
one of securing the whole scheme of social interests so far as he may;
of maintaining a balance or a harmony or adjustment among them
compatible with recognition of all of them. Recently it has been put as
a problem of integration of interests; of taking them all into account in
an adjustment that gives effect to the totality with the least sacrifice.
The last century preferred the general security. The present century
shows many signs of preferring the individual life. It is doubtful
whether such preferences can maintain themselves.” 58
...
58
Id., pp. 327-334
427
So much for the means of securing individual interests. Public
interests are secured, first, by legal rights, powers and privileges
attributed to the state or to public corporations as juristic persons. The
state (in Roman law the fisc, i.e. fiscus Caesaris, the purse of Caesar,
the treasury) is regarded as having legal rights analogous to those of
individuals, legal powers, analogous to those of individuals, and
privileges, such as that of non-suability. The personal sovereign at the
time modern public law grew up made it natural to identify the state
with him and this mode of securing public interests proved convenient
and effective. Second, they are secured by powers conferred on
individuals where coincidence of public interest and private advantage
is relied on to move the individual to exercise the power and thus
vindicate the public interest. Examples are: Taxpayers’ suits to enjoin
unlawful imposition of burdens upon a county or municipality or illegal
disposition of its moneys, and the power of the individual citizen, as
relator, to institute proceedings of mandamus or quo warranto, where
he has an individual interest. Third, they may be secured by privileges
conferred on individuals, for example, comment upon and criticism of
the conduct of public officers privileged in order to secure the public
interest in proper administration of public affairs. Fourth, they are
secured by imposing absolute duties enforced by proceedings at the
instance of public officers or by administrative agencies.
Social interests are secured, first, by imposing absolute duties, that is,
duties with no correlative legal right, vindicated by penalty or by
criminal prosecution. The criminal law is the chief agency of legal
systems for securing social interests as such, i.e. as dissociated from
any immediate individual interest which might be subsumed under
them. Second, they are secured by legal rights and powers conferred
on public corporations or on the state as guardian of social interests.
Third, they are sometimes secured by conferring rights and powers on
private persons. Examples are: Private suits to abate public nuisances
where the private individual is specially affected; statutory private
suits to abate public nuisances; and private actions on the case against
public officers and public agencies. Here the idea is that coincidence
of social interest and private advantage will lead individuals to move
and thus to vindicate the social interest. Fourth, as we have seen for
example with respect to privileged communication in case of
defamation, the law sometimes secures social interests by privileging
or exempting certain situations from the operation of ordinary legal
precepts. Fifth, more and more today social interests are secured
through administrative agencies.
...
428
someone be hurt when a wrong has been done is a deep-seated
human demand which the law has not been able to ignore—(2)
redress, which may be (a) specific, or (b) substitutional, and (3)
prevention.”59
429
not be challenged for partiality. At times and in places the oath has
been relied on as a guarantee of the truth. In our law the chancellor
considered that he could ‘search the conscience’ of a party and answer
in chancery had to be under oath. In the civil law an oath in terms of
the issue was a mode of proof and is still in use to some extent. But
the ideas which made an oath effective to assure the truth have at
least lost much of their strength; and perjury, false testimony, and
fabricated documents put serious obstacles in the way of
thoroughgoing attainment of the end of law. Bentham said paintings
or engravings of the death of Ananias and Sapphira ‘capitally punished
on the spot by divine justice for mendacious testimony of the self-
investitive or self-exonerative kind’ ought to be hung in every
courtroom. To guard against this unreliability of oral evidence the law
often requires transactions to be evidenced by writing. Also it requires
witnesses to certain instruments other than the parties and requires
some transactions to be entered into before a magistrate or official.
But these necessary precautions, while they prevent frauds, may often
preclude the establishment of meritorious claims. Again, the law has
had to proceed cautiously in securing against nervous and mental
injuries and injuries to sensibilities because of difficulty or even
impossibility of clear proof in the absence of objectively manifest
illness. Nor is the difficulty merely one of false swearing. Mistaken
observation, mistaken identification, misunderstanding or
misinterpretation of what has been seen and heard afford many
opportunities for honest testifying at variance with the facts. Criminal
procedure provides many checks for the protection of accused persons
in view of the danger, involved in the testimony upon which tribunals
must perforce rely. But in spite of them conviction of the innocent is
by no means unknown.
In the urban industrial society of today not only duties of care for the
health, morals, and education of children but even truancy,
incorrigibility, and want of harmony in the family have come under the
supervision of juvenile courts or courts of domestic relations. But the
moment these things are committed to courts, administrative agencies
have to be invoked to make the legal treatment effective. Probation
officers, boards of children’s guardians, domestic homes and the like at
once develop. It may be doubted whether such institutions or any that
may grow out of them will fully take the place of the old time
household discipline by means of which the intangible duties involved
in the parental relation were formerly made effective.
430
effectively if it might. Thus grave infringements of individual interests
in the domestic relations by tale-bearing or intrigue are often too
intangible to be reached by legal machinery. Our law has struggled
hard with this difficulty. But the result of the action on the case for
criminal conversation and alienation of affections, which long ago
excited the ridicule of Thackeray, does not inspire confidence nor does
the American precedent for enjoining a defendant from flirting with a
plaintiff’s wife assure a better remedy. So also with the ‘right of
privacy.’ The difficulties involved in tracing injuries to their source and
in fitting cause to effect compel some sacrifice of the interests of the
retiring and the sensitive.
431
...
432
pursue their legal rights even in matters of no little moment at the
expense of time, money, and energy, they can more profitably employ
in their everyday work.
Hence we have to deal in new ways with the subject of making legal
precepts effective. We must study the limits of effective legal action.
We must determine what we may expect to do through law and what
we should leave to other agencies of social control. We must examine
our armory of legal weapons, appraise the value of each for the tasks
of today, and ask what new ones may be devised and what we may
expect reasonably to accomplish by them when devised.
“But ‘grand theory’ did not die with Pound. In Lasswell and
MacDougal, we find the same broad generalizations and ‘grand
prospectus’. Their theory is one of decision-making. There are, they
postulate, a number of ‘desired events’, catalogued under such vague
headings as power, enlightenment, wealth, respect for human dignity,
health and well-being, skill, affection, and rectitude. For each of these
categories they ask whether the legal process, in the context of the
social system, is achieving a maximum sharing of the particular value.
So, on health and well-being, it is asked whether ‘the legal system
succeed[s] in stimulating and sustaining progress toward safety, health
and comfort in every community.’ Such a value-laden priority as
60
Id., pp. 353-373.
433
‘progress’ can be explained by the articulated democratic and
utilitarian aim of the philosophy.”61
Harold D. Lasswell and Myres S. McDougal sought the reform of legal education in
order to train law students in policy-making which reflects their grand theory of a
vibrant liberal and social democracy which responds to the needs, wants, and
welfare of the populace.
434
Weimar Germany, as in post-parliamentary Italy and certain other
countries, elections have ceased to be free and have become
ceremonial plebiscites—rituals of tribal union. Balanced public
discussion has given way to discussion directed by a monopoly of
government and party. The multiple party system has yielded to
something called a ‘party,’ though in fact an ‘order,’ a privileged
monopolist of policy-making. In place of dynamic executive and
judicial balance, there has arisen extreme executive concentration.
Where institutions named parliaments yet survive, they are mummified
into assemblies for the performance of rites of ceremonial ratification
of executive decisions. Where there was a balance between
centralized and local authority and control, there has arisen extreme
centralization. The balance between governmental and private
organization is unhinged as the tide moves toward the
governmentalization of all organized life. With the sweep of
regimentation, the balance is lost between private zones of living and
the zones appropriate to official direction. The entire structure of open
and competitive markets has been actively threatened by an economic
structure of closed and monopolistic markets. Processes of production
and distribution that were once carried on by bargaining and pricing
depend on negotiation and rationing.
Looking at the plight of freedom in the world today, can we fail to ask
how the policy-makers of a free society have come to experience such
catastrophic rebuffs? Through what deficiencies of skill or character
have they failed to keep the trend of world development in line with
their basic objective? Such chronic failure suggests that the policy-
makers of recent times have arrived at their decisions without a firm
grasp on reality, and that they have allowed their focus of attention to
be absorbed with trivial non-essentials. Long before the present storm,
clouds of difficulty were plainly visible. Yet decision-makers in
business, government, and in all branches of public life were either
oblivious to these portents or remained sterile and ineffective.
435
The question may be asked whether the lawyer can be held
responsible in any significant degree for the plight in which we find
ourselves. For a moralist, the question is whether the lawyer can be
‘blamed;’ for a scientist, whether he is an important casual variable;
for a reformer, whether he can be acted upon to produce change. The
answer to all of these questions is: most assuredly, yes. It should need
no emphasis that the lawyer is today, even when not himself a ‘maker’
of policy, the one indispensable adviser of every responsible policy-
maker of our society—whether we speak of the head of a government
department or agency, of the executive of a corporation or labor union,
of the secretary of a trade or other private association, or even of the
humble independent enterpriser or professional man. As such an
adviser the lawyer, when informing his policy-maker of what he can or
cannot legally do, is, as policy-makers often complain, in an
unassailably strategic power to influence, if not create, policy. It is a
familiar story, too, of how frequently lawyers who begin as advisers on
policy are transformed into makers of policy: ‘the law’ is one of the few
remaining avenues to ‘success’ open to impecunious talent.
Successful practitioners of law often receive sufficiently large incomes,
from advice and investment, to become powers in their own right and
hence gravitate into positions of influence in industry. How frequently
lawyers turn up in government—whether as legislators, executives, or
administrators, or as judges (where they have a virtual monopoly)—is
again a matter of common knowledge. Nor can the policy-making
power of lawyers as executors, trust administrators, administrators in
insolvency, and so on, be ignored. Certainly it would be difficult to
exaggerate either the direct or indirect influence that members of the
legal profession exert on the public life of this nation. For better or
worse our decision-makers and our lawyers are bound together in a
relation of dependence or of identity.”62
62
Harold D. Lasswell and Myres S. MacDougal, “Legal Education and Public Policy: Professional Training in the
Public Interest,” Yale Law Journal, Vol. 52, 1943, pp. 206-209.
436
Goal-thinking requires the clarification of values. In a democratic
society it should not, of course, be an aim of legal education to impose
a single standard of morals upon every student. But a legitimate aim
of education is to seek to promote the major values of a democratic
society and to reduce the number of moral mavericks who do not
share democratic preferences. The student may be allowed to reject
the morals of democracy and embrace those of despotism; but his
education should be such that, if he does so, he does it by deliberate
choice, with awareness of the consequences for himself and others,
and not by sluggish self-deception.
437
statement of low-level abstraction) can be elaborated an infinite series
of normative propositions of ever increasing generality; conversely,
normative statements of high-level abstraction can be manipulated to
support any specific social goal. Prospective lawyers should be
exposed, by way of warning and sophistication, to the work of
representative specialists in derivation; relatively little time should be
required, however, to teach them how to handle, and how to achieve
emotional freedom from, the ancient exercises.
438
future. The very act of taking thought and of acting on the basis of
thought are among the factors that determine the future trend of
events. In a democratic society a policy-maker must determine which
adjustments of human relationships are in fact compatible with the
realization of democratic ideals. Which procedures actually aid or
hamper the realization of human dignity? How can the institutions of
legislation, adjudication, administration, production, and distribution be
adjusted to democratic survival? What are the slogans and doctrines—
in which contexts of experience—that create acceptance of democratic
ideals and inspire effort to put them into practice? In short, the policy-
maker needs to guide his judgment by what is scientifically known and
knowable about the causal variable that condition the democratic
variables.
439
Success calls for skill in direct personal contact with client, partner,
clerk, opposing counsel, investigator, witness, jurymen, judge (to name
some conspicuous examples); likewise, there is need of skill in public
relations (in the handling of grand jury investigations, conducting trials,
conducting legislative hearings).
From all the emphasis which we have placed upon certain ways of
thinking, observing and managing, it should not be inferred that we
propose to discard or neglect the traditional skills and knowledge of
the lawyer. It is the lawyer’s mastery over constitutions, statutes,
appellate opinions and textbooks of peculiar idiom, and his skill in
operating the mechanics (procedure) of both governmental institutions
(courts, legislatures, administrative boards, executive offices) and
private associations (corporations, partnerships, trade associations,
labor unions, consumers’ cooperatives), that set him apart from, and
give him a certain advantage over, such other skill groups in our
society as diplomats, economists, social psychologists, social historians
and biologists. But much of what currently passes for instruction in law
schools is a waste of time because it consists of the reiteration of a
limited list of ambiguous terms cut asunder from any institutional
context that would set a limit to their ambiguities. Thus, a student
may learn that if discussion begins with ‘contract’ it must then proceed
by rearrangement of certain meanings to be assigned to a small list of
well-known words, such as ‘offer and acceptance,’ ‘consideration,’
‘mistake,’ ‘performance,’ ‘condition,’ and so on; but he knows very
little unless he has also learned to complete the meaning of these
terms by reference to representative institutional contexts and
important social values. What we propose is that training in the
distinctive core of the lawyer’s repertory of skills and information be
given a new sense of purpose and new criteria of relevance. It is a
fundamental truth of practical and scientific psychology that purpose
increases ease of learning; students can be expected to acquire more
rather than less mastery of legal technicality when the comparatively
small repertory of key legal terms is considered in relation to the goals
and the vital problems and processes of democracy, rather than in a
formalistic framework, unoriented toward policy. The lawyer’s
traditional storehouse of learning is already too tightly stuffed with
legacies from the past to be thoroughly mastered by anyone in a
lifetime of devoted scholarship; a student must, if he is not to choke on
triviality, have extrinsic criteria of relevance. There comes a time, as
Mr. Justice Holmes long ago remarked, when energy can be more
profitably spent than in the reading of cases. Given a new sense of
purpose and trained in the skills and information which should be
common to all policy-makers, the lawyer cannot escape becoming a
better lawyer. Schools which prepare themselves to emphasize such
purposes and to offer such training may succeed in becoming more
truly vocational even as they grow more genuinely professional.” 63
VI. CONCLUSION
63
Id., pp. 212-216.
440
There is no doubt that much can be learned from the sociology of law, as it
progressed into the sociology of jurisprudence and socio-legal studies. Many of its
observations and insights provide important and valuable material for legal
theorizing. However, as a legal theory itself, it has its drawbacks.
First it is more interested, not in legal doctrine, but in social data, the interrelation
between law and society, as they mutually affect each other. Whereas these data
are important to understand law, they are not the focus of legal theory. At most
they only provide raw material for theorizing. A theoretical account of law must
include investigations into legal doctrine. Whereas it is not denied that society
affects legal doctrine, it does not comprise the central aspect of it. Understanding
law as a system of doctrine requires direct investigation into that doctrine, and
social data merely provide background information.
441