(Anna Greenspan) Capitalism's Transcendental Time PDF
(Anna Greenspan) Capitalism's Transcendental Time PDF
(Anna Greenspan) Capitalism's Transcendental Time PDF
Anna Greenspan
PhD Thesis
Philosophy Department
Universityof Warwick
September, 2000
Acknowledgements
This thesis has been written with the help of Louis Greenspan, Michelle
Contents
0. Introduction
[p. 2]
5. Conclusion
[p. 207]
Appendix
[p. 218]
Bibliography
[p. 219]
Summary
' Much contemporary or postmodern thought has dealt with the segregation between inside
and out by concentrating on the interiority of language. Deconstruction, in particular, has held
that this zone of interiority is so all encompassing that it renders an occupation of the outside
impossible (note Derrida's famous phrase: il nya pas d'hors du texte). Subversion, from this
point of view, can only occur as a disruption from within.
2 This claim, that interiority has more to do with time than with space is one of the crucial
insights of transcendental philosophy and will be discussed in detail in the chapter 1.
3 Though extremely widespread, the notion that liberation is an escape from time is perhaps
most clearly expressed in the religions of the East such as Hinduism and Buddhism. Both
these religions have developed meditative techniques (yoga) that aim to release the
practitioner from the never-ending cycle of time, and both maintain that enlightenment is
reached through an escape from the illusion of time, or Maya. The details of this thought and
its relation to the arguments which follow are, however, beyond the scope of this thesis.
2
For an inside that is bounded by temporal rhythms must find its outside in a
realm which is exterior to time.
In the classical western tradition this connection between the
philosophy of time and the notion of inside and out is based on a disjunction
which opposes time to eternity. This disjunction is articulated most famously
by Plato who defines time "as the movable image of eternity, " (T, 77) a
definition which establishes the interiority of time in opposition to an exteriority
which is eternal. Though immensely widespread, this contrast between time
and eternity, rests, at least in its classical formulation, as we will see, on a
very specific understanding of both the nature of time and of the relation
between inside and out. 4
The classical tradition equated time with astronomy. Conceived of as a
'movable image', it was thought to be perceived in the cyclical changes of the
heavenly spheres. 5 Equivalent to celestial movement, time was made the very
6
principle of variation. Manifestingitself as a never ending processof change
and activity, it governed the continuous flow of becoming in which all
existence was trapped.
Thus, it was precisely due to its associations with variation that time
was considered to be a mode of capture. For the classical tradition
5 See Plato `Timeaus' in Plato: The Collected Dialogues. Ed. Edith Hamilton
and Huntington
Cairns. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1961(especially section 38 -39). Also note the
following from Definitions: "(chronos) time: the motion of the sun, the measure of its course. "
("Definitions" in Plato: Complete Works. Indianapolis: Hacket Publishing Company, 1997, p
1678.)
3
considered temporal rhythms, the passage of seasons, and the changes of
day into night as an elaborate simulation which belonged only to the created
world of phenomena. It held that the processes of movement and change
were but a shadow of a timeless realm that lies beyond, and it was inside this
world of shadow and mirage that the '
subject was caught. Governed by the
variations of matter, entangled in the multiplicity of becoming, humans were
held prisoner, duped by the illusory movement of time.
This vision of time found its direct opposition in the concept of eternity.
Differentiated from the temporal image of movement and variation, the eternal
was conceived of as a realm of constant stasis. In contrasting change with
identity, multiplicity with unity, and becoming with being, it offered an
alternative to the world of sensible appearance, and thus constituted a realm
which existed outside the phenomenology of time.
It is within this dualistic framework, then, that the exteriority of the
eternal must be understood. Eternity, conceived of in opposition to
temporality, should not be confused with the ever-lasting which is a
continuous extension of time. 8 Situated neither in the deep past nor in the
distant future, eternity is not a stretch of time but a timelessness. Co-existing
simultaneously with each and every moment, it is the essence of
appearances, the constant form which the variations of time can only
represent in a shadowy fashion.
TI am referring here, of course, to the writings of Plato. It is interesting to note that in the most
famous section of these writings Plato uses a spatial metaphor, the image of an underground
cave, to illustrate his conception of interiority. Even here, however, the prisoners are captured
not so much by spatial boundaries, but rather by their incapability of breaking free from the
entrapment produced by a fascination with the moving images of time. See: Plato. 'The
Republic. ' in Plato: The Collected Dialogues. Ed. Edith Hamilton and Huntington Cairns.
Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1961
8 "Because eternity touches each and every time, it is easily confused with the closely related
concept of what "always was, is, and will be, " or, in a word, the everlasting. But in its own
proper concept, the eternal only "is"; only in the present tense can it be said to be or act in any
way. Exempted from all having-been and going-to-be, eternity is familiarly defined as
timelessness, in distinction from the everlasting (sometimes also called the sempiternal). "
Encyclopedia of Religion: Volume 5. Edited by Mircea Eliade, p 167.
4
As the essence of time, the eternal was revered as the divine
archetype. Operating from above, it was eternity that created time.
Considered to be the essence of transcendent production, it was able to
create without getting involved in the matter of its creation9 "Eternity, " writes
Plotinus "is a majestic thing and thought declares it identical with the
God. "(TE, 226)10
With this quote the obvious convergence between the classical notion
of eternity and the conception of the deity produced by the monotheistic
traditions of the West is clearly revealed. The form of the eternal - as the
genesis of the image of time - is paralleled in the opening section of the Old
Testament where we encounter God, as the eternal, who is presented as the
creator of time.
And God said, Let there be light: and there was light. And God
saw the light, that it was good: and God divided the light from
the darkness. And God called the light day, and the darkness he
called night. And the evening and the morning were the first day.
(Genesis, 1: 3- 4)
According to the bible, then, time originates with the first act of
creation. Moving across the waters of the unformed void, God acts initially to
generate light and begin the passage of time. This primordial event is the
Drawing on the work of such feminist thinkers as Luce Irigaray (esp. Speculum of the Other
Woman. Trans. Gillian C Gill. Ithaca New York: Cornell University Press, 1985) it appears that
the classical distinction between the phenomenon of time and the transcendence of eternity is
essentially masculine in nature. For the notion of a transcendent eternity, beyond or above the
enclosure of time, only occurs by differentiating the eternal from matter, creation, becoming,
and multiplicity- that is from all things traditionally thought of as female. It is interesting to note
in this respect that in Hinduism, Shakti, the principle of female power, is sometimes conceived
of as time. See Zimmer, Heimrich. Myths and Symbols in Indian Art and civilization. Edited by
Joseph Campbell. New York: Pantheon Books, 1963
5
singular occurrence which takes place outside the confines of temporality.
For, once it is established, a time determined by the passage of day into night
6
system that is based on the clock. By bringing these two revolutions together,
the thesis seeks to establish a connection between abstract conceptual
thought and concrete material practices, a connection which is exemplified by
the convergence between the transcendental philosophy of time and the
socio-history of time-keeping practices. Establishing this connection, however,
requires not only a reformulation of the classical conception of time -
produced, as we will see, through the creation of a split between, on the one
hand, the constant structure of formal time, and, on the other, empirical
change conceived of as history - but also a reinvention of the classical notion
of eternity. This latter is found in the work of Deleuze and Guattari who
substitute the transcendence of eternity with the immanent concept of Aeon,
or the absolute Outside, conceived of as the continuous variation of an
intensive temporality. It is by way of this concept of Aeon that we will find, in
what appears as the "history" of capitalist time, Aeonic events which are at
once entirely abstract and fully material. The abstract materiality of these
events, as we will see, transfigure the boundaries between inside and out, for
though they are in no way eternal they nevertheless occur on an exterior
plane outside the interior confines of time.
From the point of view of the philosophy of time, the revolutionary
break brought on by both Kant and capitalism rests on a transformation which
occurs in how time is mapped on to the distinction between constant and
13
variable. As we will see in the chapters which follow, both critique and clock-
time differentiate themselves from the classical tradition by insisting that it is
not time itself which varies, but rather that variation inheres in that which
exists in time. This distinction, between time and that which is in time, arises
from the fact that both Kant and capitalism separate temporality from the
changing patterns of astronomical cycles. Split off from the concrete rhythms
of the phenomenal world, time becomes an abstract grid, the a priori frame
13This distinction corresponds to a set of oppositions including quantity and quality, and
content and expression which will be discussed throughout this thesis. It is a contention of the
thesis that these oppositional couples -or stratified distinctions - are what constitutes the
interiority of time.
7
which structures both philosophical thought and the socio-economic and
cultural milieu. Time is no longer variable since it has become the very
presupposition of change. The stasis of eternity is thus replaced by the
constant fixture of formal time.
This transformation in the nature of time is, as will be made clear, of
fundamental importance to the whole of the Kantian system. For it is this
division, between time and what occurs in time, which ultimately
distinguishes the empirical (a posteriori) from the transcendental (a priori).
Kant first insists that time cannot be equated with alteration in the
'Transcendental Aesthetic', the very first section of the Critique. "Alteration is
an empirical phenomenon, " claims Kant, and is thus "only possible through
and in the representation of time. " (CPR, 76) This paves the way for what
Deleuze has called the 'first great Kantian reversal' (KCP, vii) which frees time
from its age old subordination to movement. Unhinged from its ties to change
and activity, time becomes an abstract condition of experience, the a priori
structure within which all change and movement takes place.
In capitalism this differentiation - between a constant temporality and
the variation of that which occurs in time - receives concrete expression
through the division between clocks and calendars. Though this split has
existed for thousands 14
of years, it is only within capitalism that the distinction
between these two types of time-keeping devices has become an abstract
distinction in the nature of time itself. Through the continuous innovation and
growing ubiquity of the clock, capitalism contrasts the qualitative time of the
calendar (with its differences in seasons, light, temperature etc) with the
precise, homogenous, standardized and purely quantitative ticking of the
clock. It is within the formers qualitative time that variation takes place.
Change in time is recorded by the calendar which has ceased to measure the
rhythms of everyday life and become instead a mechanism subordinated to
the developmental narrative of history. Though capitalism makes use of these
14 Sundials have been in use since the third millennium B.C. and evidence of water clocks (or
clepsydra) have been found as early as the sixth century B.C. (HH, 20-21)
8
variations in calendric time, 15it is also essential for the capitalist mode of
production that time be treated as an abstract quantity that does not vary. It is
this that is provided by the time of the clock.
By establishing the difference between the structure of a constant
temporality and the variable experiences of history, both Kant and capitalism
have created a fracture in the appearance of time. It is by way of this fracture,
(and its coinciding synthesis) that these two revolutions have managed to
overturn the classical tradition and inaugurate what may be called the modern
conception of time. 16
Yet, despite the fact that the critical understanding of temporality finds
its parallel in the culture and technics of capitalism there is an adamant
insistence, on both sides, that a fundamental distinction be maintained
between the philosophy of time and its socio-economic and cultural
manifestations. This distinction rests, as we will see, on the apparent
divergence between transcendental and historical production. The explicit aim
15This is a crucial point that will be made clear in our discussion of the economist Boehm-
Bawerk found in chapter 2.
16Deleuze uses this phrase when describing the Kantian conception of time. Though I have
not included any strict definition of modernity, I have used the term to describe both the
Kantian philosophy of time and the time-keeping practices that developed with the clock. Used
In this manner it is meant to differentiate both Kant and clock time from, on the one hand, the
philosophy of time upheld in the classical tradition, and, on the other, from the contemporary
or'postmodem' time-keeping practices that have emerged within cyberspace.
"To quote Kant's famous passage: it is obviously the effect not of levity but of the matured
judgment of the age, which refuses to be put off with illusory knowledge. It is a call to reason
to undertake anew the most difficult of all its tasks, namely that of self-knowledge, and to
institute a tribunal which will assure to reason its lawful claims, and dismiss all groundless
pretensions, not by despotic decrees, but in accordance with its own eternal and unalterable
laws. This tribunal is no other than the critique of pure reason. ' (CPR, 9)
9
therefore, it is strictly illegitimate to hold that time is the product (or the image)
of eternity. In revolt against this classical doctrine, Kant replaces transcendent
creation with the immanent synthesis of the understanding. Operating in a
realm which is constitutive of experience these synthetic processes construct
time as an a priori epistemological representation. This representation, which
Kant calls the form of inner sense, is the universal and necessary
precondition for all empirical phenomena. Put simply then, time, for Kant, is a
mental construct within which empirical reality takes place. History, which
develops in time, cannot be equated with transcendental synthesis since the
very existence of history presupposes and is dependent upon the
transcendental construction of time.
Karl Marx, the most famous philosopher of capitalism, shares Kant's
insistence of the need to develop an account of production which does not
seek recourse in divine transcendence. 18However, unlike Kant, Marx
maintains that the ultimate realm of production lies not in the synthetic
processes of reason but rather in the dialectical forces of history. Thus, for
Marx, the a priori are themselves subject to change. Produced by the dynamic
forces of history, formal time is not an epistemological representation but a
contingent historical formation. Marx's historical materialism, 19(his
"Hegelianism turned on its head"), thus maintains that outside the
particularities of the capitalist time machine is a form of variable time with a
logic of its own. The exteriority of this temporality which is not exhaustively
-
structured by any specific mode of production - is ultimately responsible for
creating the time of capitalism (conceived of as both the duration of the
capitalist mode of production and the structure of time prevailing within it).
10
Thus, both critical thought which refuses to acknowledge its socio-
economic surroundings, and Marxism which denies the possibility of
transcendental synthesis, insist that - despite their obvious connections the
-
philosophical and socio-technical revolution of time be kept separate and
opposed. This opposition, as we have seen, ultimately rests on the fact that
the privilege given by transcendental production to the ahistoricity of a
constant time comes into conflict with the primacy that historical materialism
grants to the variations of a temporality governed by the logic of events. With
this conflict, the path to exteriority - on both sides - is lost, as each revolution
seeks to contain the other by presenting itself as a higher and more primary
inside. Neither Kantian thought, nor the Marxist analyses of capitalism, then,
will accept that the exterior realm productive of time is constituted by the
eternal transcendence of God. Yet; they nevertheless come into conflict over
what should substitute for eternal creation in the modern conception of time.
Transcendental critique, the critique of political economy and the secular time
of eternity - the traditional zone exterior to time - has been left basically
unchanged (if only by being ignored).
11
see, a critique of the Kantian system itself. For according to Deleuze and
Guattari, the Kantian notion that transcendental production occurs under the
21To quote from Deleuze: "Everyone knows the first principle of Spinoza: one substance for all
the attributes. But we also know the third, fourth or fifth principle: one Nature for all bodies,
one Nature for all individuals, a Nature that is itself an individual varying in an infinite number
of ways. What is involved is no longer the affirmation of a single substance, but rather the
laying out of a common plane of immanence on which all bodies, all minds and all individuals
are situated. " (SPP, 122)
12
Guattari bring to philosophy a notion of eternity which is not based on the
wholeness and unity of a transcendent beyond but on the flat multiplicity of an
immanent outside.
In the biblical tradition the eternal cuts into time through singular
events that are explosive and highly dramatic in nature. At the limit, it appears
as genesis and apocalypse, the beginning and end of creation. Beyond these
points, the eternal is encountered only after death, on judgment day, where it
carries the threat or promise of damnation and salvation, or when it crashes
into history interrupting the linear order of time through miracles and divine
revelation.
We will see that - though no less intense - the connection between
Aeon and Chronos is much more quiet and subtle. For Aeon does not
manifest itself in time. Though it is itself composed of singular events - which
can be precisely dated and named - these events compose a virtual plane of
intensity that positively avoids climactic actualization. Deleuze and Guattari
call these Aeonic occurrences plateaus and show how they constitute an
exteriority that haunts the successive order of extensive temporality.
The final chapter of the thesis takes the pervasive sense of anticlimax
that accompanied the dawn of the third millennium as indexing one such
event and explores Y2K -a sign that operates as both a date and a name - as
a singular Aeonic occurrence. While this may first appear farfetched, we will
see that, though it has now been dismissed as irrelevant, Y2K is crucial to the
transcendental philosophy of time. This is primarily due to the fact that, as a
singularity, it shares all the characteristic features of Aeon including: an
effective virtuality, a nonsignifying semiotic, a disruption - or positive
avoidance - of extensive succession and an immanent machinic abstraction.
Cutting across the stratified segmentation of Chronos, Y2K thus
22The term machine will be used throughout the thesis as it is crucial to the work of Deleuze
and Guattari. It will be explained in more detail in chapter 3. Briefly, though, Deleuze and
Guattari use the term machine, not to signify a technical apparatus, but rather to designate the
immanent circuits of production that constitute any flat assemblage (regardless of its particular
form or substance)..
13
functions as a mutation (or accident) both in the structure of formal time and
in the empirical development of history. It collapses the distinction between
time's formal expression and the content which happen to fill it, dissolving the
rigid opposition between technics and culture, constant and variable and
temporality and change. In this way Y2K constitutes an event - not in time but
of time - that allows the capitalist production of temporality to escape from
the interiority of history and thus exemplifies the convergence between the
material practices of time-keeping systems and processes of abstraction
which are conventionally located in the philosophy of time.
14
Chapter 1: Philosophy's Copernican Revolution.
p. 108-9
Pure Reason. The history of philosophy registers the date as the moment of
over two centuries earlier, in the realm of astronomy. Traditionally, the story of
15
the human intellect in constituting the external world. It is here, we are told,
that one should locate the dramatic shift that is at the core of Kantian
'
philosophy. What this chapter will argue, however, is that this emphasis, on
the role of the intellect, mistakes what is truly revolutionary in critical thought.
main points. First, that the transformation of the human subject is merely a
revolutionary nature of this discovery we must turn our attention away from
the enlightened subject of reason and focus instead on the occulted nature of
time.
Reason centers around the question: "How are a priori synthetic judgements
1 In the following section this position will be illustrated through the writings of Heinrich
Heine. Though Heine poetic and lyrical language is unique amongst the
commentators on Kant, his views are not at all unconventional. In the '"Past Masters"
text on Kant, for example, Roger Scruton, writes that the essence of the Copernican
revolution is that 'self consciousness requires that the world must appear to conform
to the categories' (Scruton, Roger. Kant. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1982, p.
28). The Encyclopedia of Philosophy concurs that this epistemological view is the key
to understanding Kantian thought. 'Kant's principle task in the Critique of Pure
Reason was to determine the cognitive powers of reason, to find out what it could and
could not achieve in the way of knowledge" ("Kant, Immanuel" in the Encyclopedia of
Philosophy Volume 3. Edited by Paul Edwards. New York: Macmillan Publishing,
1967, p.305)
2 This is comprised both of Deleuze's book on Kant and a series of lectures on Kant
that have been reprinted on the Internet (see bibliography).
16
possible? " (CPR, 59) To answer this question Kant must begin by defining
In the order of time, " writes Kant in the preface to the first Critique,
our knowledge begins. But though all our knowledge begins with experience it
does not follow that it all arises out of experience. " (CPR, 41) With this
which has its sources a posteriori, that is, in experience" (CPR-43) gives rise
to judgments which are particular and contingent (the sun rose today) while a
priori knowledge, on the other hand, gives rise to judgments which are
gained from experience is always particular and contingent it can never be the
basis for judgments which are universal and necessary. Thus, Kant writes,
"necessity and strict universality are the sure criteria of a priori knowledge. "
(CPR, 44) This difference between the a priori and the a posteriori is the first
basic division which allows Kant to demarcate the singular zone of knowledge
the transcendental, yet another distinction was required. The two sides of the
17
table had to be split in half. To accomplish this, Kant drew another line on a
different axes, cutting across both the a priori and the a posteriori. 3 This line
say, for instance 'All bodies are extended' this is an analytic judgment. For
do not require to go beyond the concept which I connect with 'body' in order
not arise empirically. For "judgments of experience, " writes Kant, "are one
and all synthetic" (CPR, 49) By the term 'synthetic' Kant is referring to
is heavy', for example, is to connect concepts 'synthetically'. For since not all
bodies are heavy, one cannot arrive at the concept heavy from an analyses of
table - the one that contains the 'synthetic a priori". The puzzle which it sets
4 On page 49 of the first critique Kant uses this example to explain synthetic
judgements which are made from experience.
18
experience. The prime examples of synthetic a priori knowledge are found
"If what the Critique shows is the possibility of synthetic a priori judgements, it
confidence and success. " (KECI, 147) 7+5' 12, to stick with the example
priori judgment. It is a priori since it, like all mathematical propositions, is both
universal and necessary. It is synthetic since neither the number 7 nor the
number 5 has contained within it the number 12. "The concept of 12, " writes
Kant, "is by no means already thought in merely thinking the union of 7 and 5;
Though philosophers had long been concerned with such a priori truths
as are found in mathematics it was Kant who first recognized them as being
6
synthetic. Thus transcendental philosophy, even when confined to
5 Kant uses this example himself both in the first critique and in the Prolegomena to
Future Metaphysics.
6 As Deleuze
writes, 'analytic a priori judgment that meant something, synthetic a
posteriori judgment that meant something, but synthetic a priori judgment, that's truly
a monster. ' (KST, 9)
19
frames. "(KST, 9) Focusing his attention on the synthetic a priori he exploded
the soul. " Though "we are scarcely ever conscious" of its power, without it,
but on an "extension of our previously possessed concepts. " (CPR, 47) It is,
writes Kant "a genuinely new addition to all previous knowledge. " (CPR, 51)
It is this 'new addition' that accounts for the shift in the subject's
this abstract and productive realm of knowledge. Before Kant, the subject was
cave. According to this traditional vision, the subject was trapped in the body,
shadows for reality, the subject could not help but deform the world, mutating
20
"harmony between the subject and the world, " (KST, 5) philosophy struggled
to cut the chains, to correct the inherent deformity, to free the prisoner from
conforming to the objects of the world, "the rational being discovers he has
new power. " (KCP, 14) After Kant the objects of the world must conform to
us. "The first thing the Copernican Revolution teaches us, " writes Deleuze,
"is that it is we who are giving the orders. " (KCP, 14) The prisoner has
become a legislator.
Formerly, when men conceived the world as standing still, and the sun
as revolving round it, astronomical calculations failed to agree
accurately. But when Copernicus made the sun stand still and the
earth revolve round it, behold! Everything accorded admirably. So
formerly reason, like the sun moved round the universe of phenomena
and sought to throw light upon it. But Kant, bade reason, the sun stand
still, and the universe of phenomena now turns round, and is
illuminated the moment it comes within the region of the intellectual
orb. (RPG, 114)
21
account reveals a certain problem. For if the stress is on human reason,
Heine reminds us, the earth stood as the central pivot or axis around which
Copernican system, removed the earth from this central position, making it
equal to any other planet. The Copernican revolution thus derailed us from
said to have done the exact opposite. Whereas Copernicus displaced us from
the center of the universe, Kant put us there. Why, then, does Kant speak of
his philosophy as Copernican? For it would seem that the emphasis on the
closely, we might find some other reason for this seemingly confused
analogy.
have better success if he made the spectator to revolve and the stars to
remain at rest. " (CPR, 23) Copernicus posited a heliocentric world in which
the stars no longer measured time. He explained the day by the earth's
rotation on its own axes and the year by its annual cycle around the sun. In
22
the Copernican system, then, it is the movement of the earth which marks out
possible.
both from natural philosophy and from the church. For these two institutions
had insisted that the earth stood still. This resistance was heightened by the
fact that despite Copernicus' findings the world still appeared to conform to
Ptolemy's ancient vision. Copernicus was thus responsible for a strange and
everything has been transformed. It is in this way, as we will see, that Kant is
even the way we talk about those perceptions have not altered. Phenomena
remain the same. The sun still appears to revolve. The earth still appears to
stand still. External bodies still appear to be in motion. We still say that the
sun rises and sets. The difference is, and this is the revolution, that now
23
everybody knows it is only a manner of speaking.
onwards, " he writes, "seemed to develop itself within the, frame of a duality
previous to Kant the world was divided between, on the one hand, the
experience, and on the other hand, the realm of ideas, pure forms or
of sensation.
dialogues insist that the very fact that there is knowledge independent of
the body's cage and was free to gaze upon the pure essence of things. 8 The
' One of the most famous examples of the Platonic view of the a priori occurs in the
Meno where Socrates infers the transcendence of the Forms through a slave's
knowledge of geometry. See Plato, 'Meno' in Plato-The Collected Dialogues. edited
by Edith Hamilton and Huntington Cairns. Princeton New Jersey: Princeton University
Press, 1961 (especially pages 363-374).
24
thus, for Plato, evidence of the fact that our capture in the illusory realm of
"For the disjunctive couple appearance/essence, " writes Deleuze, "Kant will
is
apparition, what appears in so far as it appears. Full stop. I don't ask
myself if there is something behind, I don't ask myself if it is false or not false.
The apparition is not at all captured in the oppositional couple, in the binary
distinction where we find a PPearances distinct from essences. " (KST, 4).
Kant transforms the meaning and implications of a priori knowledge. "In the
case of the a priori, " writes Deleuze, "Kant "borrows a word but he
completely renews its sense. " (KST, 1) For unlike Plato, in Kant the a priori,
as we will see, is associated with the immanence of abstraction and not the
transcendence of the eternal forms. To quote from Deleuze: "Kant is the one
25
who discovers the prodigious domain of the transcendental. He is the
analogue of the great explorer - not of another world, but of the upper and
lower reaches of this one. " (DR, 135) In opposition to the transcendent ideas
and logic of the analytic a priori, the synthetic a priori constitute a continuous
the world. The basic question of transcendental philosophy "how are a priori
certain experience what are the conditions that went in to producing it?
time between, on the one hand, the phenomena of temporality and change,
and, on the other, the essence of eternity. Overturning this classical duality
philosophy of time. As we will see in the chapter which follows, the discovery
introduction to Kant that "all the creations and novelties that Kantianism will
26
bring to philosophy turn on a certain problem of time and an entirely new
27
1.1 Transcendental Aesthetic: Time as the Form of Inner Sense.
Until now the task we have given ourselves was to represent space, the
moment has come to think time.
Gilles Deleuze, Kant: Synthesis and Time, p. 1
chapters, and chapters of books, the structure of the Critique of Pure Reason
seems more like the work of a ramshackle artificial intelligence than that of a
human being. ' The immense scale and complexity of Kant's 'thinking
The bulk of the text is divided into two main parts, the 'Transcendental
central distinction in Kantian thought which divides the intuition from the
' De Quincy's text 'The Last Days of Immanuel Kant' gives further evidence of this
seemingly preposterous claim. Besides the meticulous order of his daily schedule,
Kant never perspired, evoked rigorous numerological arrangements for the guests at
his dinner table, and, at his deathbed, when all human faculties had left him, was still
able to speak at length on any problem in history, philosophy or mathematics. See: De
Quincy, Thomas. 'The Last Days of Immanuel Kant! in The Collected Writings of
28
of reason. Time appears first in the former category. It is defined in the
opening section of the Critique of Pure Reason as a 'pure intuition, ' or the
(CPR, 66) begins with a strict process of elimination. It is concerned only with
what is left after both the concepts of the understanding and the matter of
sensibility have been stripped away. What remains are what Kant calls the
'pure intuitions, or 'the form of appearances. ' These are defined as the
transcendental media for the reception of sensible content, they constitute the
structure and form which the apparition must take. For Kant there are only
our mind" through which "we represent to ourselves objects which are
outside us. " (CPR, 67) Thus, for Kant, space is the form in which the external
29
accordingly as not only different but as in different places, the
representation of space must be presupposed. (CPR 68)
Time, on the other hand, is defined as "the form of inner sense, that is
of the intuition of ourselves and of our inner state. " (CPR, 77). In the
'Transcendental Aesthetic, ' then, time provides the underlying structure of all
In the following section we will see that in making time the form of inner
bias.
Pure Reason was to free time from its subordination to movement Taking
Hamlet's phrase the 'time is out of joint' and applying it to Kant, 2 Deleuze
shows how in taking time off its hinges, Kant develops a "sort of modern
separated from the external world of space and thus undergoes a sort of
2 In his text 'On four poetic formulas that might summarize the Kantian philosophy"
(found in both Kant's Critical Philosophy and in Essays Critical and Clinical) Deleuze
uses this Shakespearean quote -'the time is out of joint' - to explore Kantian thought.
To quote Deleuze: 'Hamlet is the first hero who truly needed time to act, whereas
earlier heroes were subject to time as the consequence of an original movement
(Aeschylus) or an aberrant action (Sophocles). The Critique of Pure Reason is the
book of Hamlet, the prince of the north. (ECC, 28)
30
topological twist. What was once located in the external world is folded in.3
Time, detached from the movement of that which is outside us becomes the
making time the form of inner sense Kant not only redefines the classical
mirror. Essences, which are eternal and real, exist in a transcendent realm
outside time. Time, on the other hand, belongs to the world of appearances,
and movement. For Plato, then, it is change and movement that are the
eternity" (T, 1167). He perceives this image in the movement of the stars and
thus equates the production of time with the 'perfect and immutable' cycles
within which the planets revolve. "Such was the mind and thought of God in
the creation of time. The sun and the moon and five other stars which have
the name of planets were created by him in order to distinguish and preserve
the numbers of time. " (T, 1167). In the 'curved time' of a 'circular universe
Plato's God has bent the skies into an arc. "A Demiurge which makes
3 To quote Kant: "Time is not something which exists of itself, or which inheres in
things as an objective determination, and it does not, therefore, remain when
abstraction is made of all subjective conditions of its intuition.... Time is nothing but the
subjective condition under which alone intuition can take place in us. "(CPR, 76)
31
circles, " (SLK, 2) as Deleuze puts it, has created a world whose map is
observed in the heavenly spheres. Thus, for Plato, 'the name' and 'the
number' of time can be found in the changes and motion that take place in
the sky.
Kant's break with Plato is absolute. For, according to the first Critique,
among its a priori data. " (CPR, 75) For Kant the revolutions of the stars, the
swing of a pendulum, the sand in an hourglass all occur in time and as such
fall outside the problematic of critique. Plato's perfect image can not be time,
for, "time itself does not alter but only something which is in time. " (CPR, 82)
is not time. "The concept of alteration and with it the concept of motion, as
alteration of place, he writes, " "is possible only through and in the
Thus, Kant liberates the form of time from the endless cycle of the
the planets. Instead, it is the relation of time to motion itself that revolves. In
measures, but movement is related to the time which conditions it. " The
Critique of Pure Reason conceives of a `straight line" of time that is cut off
32
from its subordination to all that exists in time. 4 To quote from Deleuze:
discover the conditions of their production, Kant finds that time is "not an
empirical concept that has been derived from any experience. " (CPR, 74) In
the abstract realm of the transcendental, Kant discovers a form of time that is
modifies the Platonic vision, by making a distinction between motion and time.
not equate it with them. His argument rests on two points. First, that while
4 It is interesting to note that Foucault, when writing of Deleuze, evokes the 'straightening' of
time that is initially produced by the first Critique. The circle must be abandoned as a faulty
principle of return; we must abandon our tendency to organize everything into a sphere. All
things return on the straight and narrow by way of a straight and labyrinth line" (TP, 166) This
notion of the straight labyrinth of time is used by Deleuze to designate the transcendental form
of time. In the preface to Kant's Critical Philosophy, he writes as follows: We move from one
labyrinth to another. The labyrinth is no longer a circle, or a spiral which would translate its
complications, but a thread, a straight line, all the more mysterious for being simple,
inexorable as Borges says, 'the labyrinth which is composed of a single straight line, and
which is indivisible, incessant. ' (KCP, vii) Deleuze also uses the notion of a straight labyrinth to
describe the time of Aeon (a concept that will be discussed in detail in chapter 3).
33
time exists everywhere, movement only occurs in particular things. Second,
that while things that move can be either fast or slow, time itself does not
shift in speed. "It is evident, then, " writes Aristotle, "that time is neither
Aristotle turns to number. To quote his famous formula "time is just this - the
number of motion. " (P, 372) The circular revolutions, the heavenly spheres
are still linked to time but the two are no longer directly equivalent. "Time, is
only movement, ' writes Aristotle "in so far as it admits of enumeration. " (P,
"Time, then, " for Aristotle, "is a kind of number. " (P, 372) The kind of
number that it is, rests on a distinction made in the Physics, between the
"number with which we count", and "the number of things which are
counted" (P, 373). To quote from the Physics: "Number, is used in two ways -
both of what is counted or countable and also of that which we count. Time,
then, is what is counted, not that with which we count: these are different
Thus, Aristotle, like Kant, seeks to discover time by shifting focus away
34
For Kant, as for Aristotle, time is conceived as being fundamentally
numeric. Kant recognizes that any representation cannot help but serve to
analogy for his new form of time. For Kant, the closest we get to time in
space, is the image of the real number line. 5 "We represent the time
constitutes a series of one dimension only; and we reason from the properties
Yet, despite the fact that both Kant and Aristotle link time to number,
Kant breaks with Aristotle no less than with Plato. For in freeing time from its
of time are unhinged from the concreteness of change. With Kant the number
5 Commentator Alfredo Ferrarin makes much of this, arguing that in Kant numbering
and arithmetic are practically synonymous with the generation of time.
6 This sentence continues as follows: with one exception that while the parts the
of
line are simultaneous the parts of time are always successive' (CPR, 77) Yet, it is
important to note, that while the parts of time are successive, time itself, for Kant, is
not. Deleuze is insistent on this point. "Time, ' he writes, Is no longer defined by
succession because succession concerns only things and movements which are in
time. If time itself were succession, it would need to succeed in another time, and on
to infinity. Things succeed each other in various times, but they are also simultaneous
in the same time, and they remain in an indefinite time. It is no longer a question of
defining time by succession, nor space by simultaneity, nor permanence by eternity.
Permanence, succession and simultaneity are modes and relationships of time. '
(KCP, vii-iii)
35
'the quantity of motion', the 'things that are counted' become 'that with
which we count'.
between cardinal and ordinal numbers. Cardinal numbers [one, two, three... ]
are used to express amount or quantity. Ordinal numbers, on the other hand,
are used to express position [first, second, third]. Bound to keep track of that
which it belongs to, the cardinal number is tied down, attached to what is in
time. "Cardinal, writes Deleuze, "comes from cardo; cardo is precisely the
hinge, the hinge around which the sphere of celestial bodies turns and which
makes them pass time and again through the so-called cardinal points. "
(KST, 12) Ordinal numbers, on the other hand, are indifferent to the space of
'
measurement. What counts, for them, is order not measure. In unchaining
time from its bonds to what is in time, Kant silmutaneously freed number from
7A familiar
example of ordinal numbering is that used by the library cataloguing
system. It is clear, in this case, that what is important is the order of the books and not
the amount of space between them.
36
philosophy, they are basically alike. For both belong to "a certain tradition of
happens in it, and this something can be determined as being change. " (SLK,
(or discovers) a disjunction between the form of time itself and the changes
This distinction between the abstract form of time and the changes
which occur within it requires that time be released from its spatial
as nothing but a pure ordinal sequence. Since time has no spatial dimension,
whole of exteriority inside itself. Thus in order to separate time from space,
time which was once located in the external world, must be folded in. For,
according to the first Critique, the only thing that is not in space is the inner
determinations of our mind. In making time the 'form of inner sense' Kant
thus locates time in the singular domain which exists outside the
representation of space.
37
This process of interiorization gives time a certain dominance over
belongs to our inner states). "Appearances", writes Kant, "may, one and all,
vanish; but time (as the universal condition of their possibility) cannot itself be
removed. " (CPR, 75) Thus, for Kant, while everything that exists is in time,
time is the one thing that does not exist in space, since everything in space
Productive of the actual rhythm of thought and sensation it gains control over
inescapable. For everything we see, think, feel, hear and know has already
been given a speed, an order and a rhythm in time. With Kant, then, the
8 From the
perspective of transcendental philosophy, then, William Burroughs
38
thought transcendentally (as an interiority over against space and not merely
in space). One can never escape time, since time is a limit that works us from
the inside. Yet, as Deleuze notes, there is something very strange in this
both the inside and the outside. Time conditions an inescapable interiority,
but in doing so opens a new and more radical exteriority, since the production
of time itself cannot be captured "within" time. In other words, the one thing
that is not interior to time is the transcendental form of time itself. Thus, in
world but that is no less alien for that. "The greatest initiative of
time into thought. " (DR, 86) Yet, as the next section will show, it is only a very
formula, The only way out of time is into space' ("H, 19) can only be a trick.
39
the exteriority of time.
40
1.2 Transcendental Deduction: Time and the `I think'
How can man think what he does not think, inhabit by a mute occupation
something that eludes him, animate with a kind of frozen movement that
figure of himself that takes the form of a stubborn exteriority.
Foucault, Order of Things, p. 323
It is false to say: I think. One should say: one thinks me.... I is another
Rimbaud, Complete Works, p 101
borders which separates the inside from the outside. His book, The
Descartes speculates that God has been replaced by an evil demon who
tricks us into taking the exterior world for reality. Determined to escape these
demonic delusions, Descartes supposes 'that the heavens, the air, the earth,
colours, shapes, sounds and all external things that we see, are only illusions
and deceptions which he [the demon] uses to take me in. " (M, 100) Stripped
of all faith in reason and truth, Descartes imagines the external world as a
I As Slavoj Zizek
writes, the Cartesian cogito "opens up, for a brief moment, the hypothesis of
the Evil Genius who, behind my back, dominates me and pulls the strings of what I experience
as reality." Slavoj Zizek. Tarrying with the Negative: Kant, Hegel and the Critique of Ideology.
Durham: Duke University Press, 1993, p. 12
41
mad and uncontrollable experiment. The senses, which grant us access to
this outside world, must no longer be trusted. Even the certainties of abstract
For once the demon has been let in, there is no telling how far his influence
Descartes tries to flee from the demon, demarcating the outside by a rigorous
Yet, as time passes, Descartes manages to gain control and dispel the
the doubt which haunts the outside serves to ground the inside in an
2
undeniable certainty. The fact that I doubt, the Meditations famously
concludes, assures me that I exist. For, "when I doubt, there is one thing
which I cannot doubt, which is that as a self that doubts, I think. " (SLK, 2) In
doubting the objects, properties, truths and sensations of the external world,
Descartes thus carves out a secure container for the subjects insides. The
famous formula "I think therefore I am" guards us against the demonic
games that threaten our perception and knowledge of the outside world.
thus finds its protection by folding in. For though everything outside us may
2 To quote Descartes: "There is a deceiver know not who he is most highly powerful and
-I -
most highly cunning, who always industriously deceives me. If he is deceiving me then without
doubt I also am. And he might deceive me as much as he can, he will still never effect that I
would be nothing, so long as I shall cogitate that I am something. So that - all things having
been weighed enough, and more - this statement were, finally, to be established: "/ am, I exist"
is necessarily true, so often as it is uttered by me or conceived by the mind. "(Meditation 11: 3)
42
be a trick, nothing, Descartes contends, can fool us about what exists inside.
After Descartes, it is this certainty of interiority which has became the sure
follows:
By his taking cogito ergo sum as the only thing certain, and
provisionally regarding the existence of the world as problematical, the
essential and only correct starting point, and at the same time the true
point of support, of all philosophy was really found. This point, indeed,
is essentially and of necessity the subjective, our own consciousness.
For this alone is that which is immediate; everything else, be it what it
may, is first mediated by consciousness, and therefore dependent on
it. It is thus rightly considered that the philosophy of the moderns starts
with Descartes as its father. (WWR 2,3)
revolution, with its emphasis on the synthetic powers of the human intellect,
3As Deleuze writes, in Descartes "doubt was only a deter to a more secure
edifice of
43
All this dissolves, however, with the contention that Kant's 'modern
consciousness' stems not from his repositioning of the subject but from his
redefinition of time. For in making time the form of inner sense, Kant
discovering an outside line that divides the inside from within, the Critique of
Pure Reason riddles interiority with the difference between the receptive
nature of what exists in time and the synthesizing processes of the form of
time itself. With Kant, then, the certainty of self consciousness dissolves into
questions about the relation of time to itself. Critical thought thus not only
differentiates itself from the tradition of modem philosophy which stems from
the first critique divides the inside from the outside through the distinction that
it makes between space and time. Space, for Kant, as the form of outer
sense, constitutes the structure in which the objects of the external world are
presented to the mind. The form of interiority, on the other hand, is time. Kant
here defines the outside as that which exists in space and the inside as that
which occurs in time. Yet, as we have already noted, since the exteriority of
44
in space is also in time. For Kant, then, all our experiences, whether internal
has an implicit spatial bias. Descartes seems far more concerned with the
ways in which the evil demon may be deceiving us about the external world of
space than he is with the deception that might be taking place in the internal
realm of time. 4 This becomes startlingly apparent when one recognizes that
Descartes seems blind to the fact that his entire philosophical method unfolds
must be located here. It is impossible for Kant to make the inside the "true
all, on shifting the line which. separates the inside from the outside. The
4 Though Descartes claims that amongst the things which he doubts is the time in which
things endure' (Meditations 1:8) this has little practical consequence. For Descartes'
reconstruction of certainty occurs inside the passage of temporal succession (that is the days
in which the Meditations unfold). Thus, though Descartes claims he is questioning time, his
philosophical method does little to challenge the interior structure of time.
5 Deleuze claims that this structure of the Meditation makes it `the first text to introduce time
into philosophical discourse. " For unlike previous philosophical texts, with Descartes, the
unfolding of temporal succession has positive implications for what can or cannot be said. In
Descartes, says Deleuze, "there is a temporality which has unfolded which meant that he
could not say in the second what he will say in the fifth. "(TLK, 4) There is undoubtedly an irony
here. For despite the fact that time operates in the Meditations as a positive structuring
principle, Descartes nevertheless ignores the operations of time when securing his
philosophical foundations.
45
border which Descartes locates at the break between the certainty of self
consciousness and the doubt which haunts our knowledge of the outside
world is radically altered by the first critique. With Kant the division between
plane, which is to say that in Kant, the inside is defined as that which occurs
in time, while the outside is left to the only thing which escapes this interiority,
Descartes' philosophy, is, for Kant, relegated to the level of the empirical. It is
Cartesian formula. The proposition 'I think' or 'I exist thinking, ' writes Kant,
"is an empirical proposition. " (CPR, 381) To quote from the first critique:
6 As Deleuze writes the assertion 'I am a thing which thinks' serves however implicitly to
- -
bind the I think to a determinate entity in time "We cannot say with Descartes 'I think therefore
I am. I am a thing which thinks. ' If it is true that the I think is a determination, it implies in this
respect an indeterminate existence (1am). But nothing so far tells us under what form this
existence is determined by the I think: it is determinable only in time, under the form of time,
thus as the existence of a phenomenal, receptive or changing ego. (KCP, viii)
46
Therefore, what Descartes perceived as an asylum from doubt,
constitutes, not the stability of the I think, but the superficiality of the empirical
ego.
to the structuring principles which condition it. As Deleuze writes, "the Ego
receptive Ego, which experiences changes in time. " (ECC, 29) No longer
something which it cannot reach. For, the experience of interiority, like all
the form of inner sense. The primary position granted to the self as an object
time. Caught inside the web of temporality, the being which doubts cannot
ego after it has already been given a sequence, an order and a rhythm by
'Transcendental Aesthetic', but only fully brought to light in the 'Deduction, '
47
the paradox of inner sense, writes Kant, arises from the fact that "this sense
then have to be in a passive relation [of active affection] to ourselves. " (CPR,
ourselves that we can never know. For one only becomes aware of the ego
after it has affected itself from within. For Kant, then, inner sense is governed
appearance, demands that one look behind empirical reality to the abstract
knowledge of the empirical ego is not an answer but a riddle. For the concrete
production that ensures the shift away from the subject to time. For, the only
thing that can produce the experience of being in time is the operation of time
48
itself.
abstract and empty form defined as nothing but a pure ordinal sequence.
continuous process of production. The form of temporality, for Kant, is, above
all, not a static eternity. For as we will see, time, in transcendental philosophy,
outlined by Kant in his discussion of the three fold synthesis set out in the first
writes, they do "not bear on diversity as it appears in space and time, but on
the diversity of space and time themselves. Indeed, without them, space and
uncover the productive constituting forces of the form of time itself. "All our
knowledge, " writes Kant in the introduction to the section, "is finally subject to
time, the formal condition of inner sense. In it they must all be ordered,
49
connected and brought into relation. " (CPR, 131) The synthetic processes of
the deduction are meant to explain the means through which this occurs.
put the world in time. The focus, then, is not on a realm of production that
occurs in time, but rather on the 'spontaneous' activity that accounts for the
After cautioning the reader of the difficulties which will inevitably beset
an enterprise "never before attempted, " Kant begins his discussion with
grid that renders them capable of being perceived. For according to Kant, as
Deleuze makes clear, there is not only a diversity that exists in time but a
diversity of time itself. The very possibility of perception requires that this
into the units that constitute moments in time. It thus operates, as Deleuze
is the act through which the imagination ensures the a priori rules which
50
at the ones following. " (KCP, 15) Without this second synthesis the order and
appearances are duplicated. It thus assures the coexistence and order of that
The third and final synthesis Kant calls the synthesis of recognition in a
Kant it is only through this final synthesis that one gains knowledge of the
Deleuze, "is not simply the act by which the manifold is synthesized, but the
is a table, this is an apple, this is such and such an object). " (KCP, 15) In the
through time.
51
Through this final synthesis, Kant deduces what is known as the
consciousness' (CPR, 136) which constitutes the Kantian 'I think'. For, the
ensures the temporal continuity necessary for recognition to take place (from
is the necessary 'condition which precedes all experience, and which makes
belongs to 7
guaranteeing that all my experience me.
most clearly reveals his radical departure from the modern philosophical line
that has its roots in Descartes. The security of self consciousness which
serves as the ground for Cartesian thought rests on the identity that exists
conscious entity that I am. The Kantian 'I' on the other hand, does not
determinate 8
entity. For, as has already been noted, the
correspond to any
7 As Deleuze writes, 'My representations are mine in so far as they are linked in the unity of a
consciousness in such a way that the 'I think' accompanies them! (KCP, 15)
8 According to Deleuze, this notion that the I think is not attached to a determinate entity is at
the heart of Kant's objection to Descartes. With the Cartesian cogito, writes Deleuze, the I
think is an act of instantaneous determination, which implies an undetermined existence (I
am) and determines this existence as that of a thinking substance (I am a thing that thinks).
But how can the determination apply to the undetermined if we cannot say under what form it
is 'determinable'? (ECC, 29) With this objection Kant profoundly challenges the Cartesian
52
self of transcendental philosophy, is paradoxically split, fractured by a line that
realm of the synthetic a priori. As Deleuze writes, "the I and the Ego are thus
separated by the line of time which relates them to each other, but under the
through the split between time as an abstract synthetic process and the
knowledge whereas the I, for Kant, can never be known (but is always
formulation which equates the empty representation 'I think' to the determinate substance'
am a thing which thinks. '
53
There is then, in Kant, a radical difference between what we are and
what we know ourselves to be. For according to the 'paradox of inner sense'
we are only conscious of ourselves after we have been worked over by that
part of ourselves that we can never know. Kant thus posits a subject that is
in
exterior relation to itself. 9 An empty synthetic process that accompanies all
you but because wherever you are it is. In Deleuze's reading of Kant, this
What this section has sought to show is that this 'other is time.
transcendental form of time. For Kant, "I is an act which constantly carries
out the synthesis of time. " (KCP, viii) Thus, while the Ego marks the interiority
introducing time into thought, Kant inserts an irreparable fissure into the core
of the subject. To quote Deleuze: "the form of interiority means not only that
9 This notion of a subject in an exterior relation to itself has obvious resonance with the
psychoanalytic distinction between the ego and the id. Freud himself recognized that his
notion of the unconscious borrowed much from transcendental thought. The psychoanalytic
assumption of unconscious mental activity appears to us, he writes in his essay The
Unconscious, as an extension of the corrections undertaken by Kant" (U, 173).
54
According to Heinrich Heine "The name of Immanuel Kant has the
might of an exorcism. " "His thought, " he writes "was a revolution and one not
wanting in horrors. " Even night wandering spirits, are stricken in terror at the
sight of Kant's Critique of Pure Reason. " (RPG, 107) Deleuze agrees, Kant's
"thinking machine is absolutely frightening. " (KST, 1) This fright arises from
the fact that Kant has transformed the nature of philosophical horror,
replacing Cartesian fear with a sort of transcendental dread against which the
certainty that guards us against the demon is powerless. For Kant there is no
uncertainty at the core of interiority, Kant riddles even the cogito with doubt.
torments the subject with the taunting refrain 'you are not what you think you
are. '10 With Kant, then, "everything happens as if the "enemy" of thought
was within. " This enemy - the transcendental outside - does not exist in
another time or another space. Its exteriority consists only of the fact that it
locked out nor contained. One no longer need be afraid that the 'reality' of
exteriority which infiltrates the inside at the very level of its production, the
Kantian outside (or the syntheses of time) not only constitutes the experience
10 In Tarrying
with the Negative, Zizek writes of Blade Runner as a Kantian film in Blade
Runner Deckard, after learning that Rachel is a replicant who (mis)perceives herself as
human, asks in astonishment: "How can it not know what it is? " We can see, now, how more
55
of the external world, it generates the very experience of ourselves. For, as
Deleuze writes, with Kant "it is not time that is interior to us; it is we who are
than two hundredyears ago, Kant's philosophyoutlinedan answerto this enigma. (TN, 15)
56
1.3 The Schematism: Time and Abstraction
the principle figure of classical thought. "What philosophy, " he writes, "has
not tried to overturn Platonism?.. .Are all philosophies individual species of the
rejection? " (TP, 166). These questions, when applied to Kant, will serve as
the guiding thread in the final pages of this chapter. For to follow Kant in his
Platonism by discovering an abstract form of time that has been freed from its
this implies that Kant's argument with Plato can be restricted to any particular
dialogue. ' For, the notion of abstract time does much more than
zone or
clear, abstract time subverts Plato at its core by revolutionising the notion of
abstraction.
It is important to note from the start, however, that these two moves,
the redefinition of time and the reformulation of the abstract, are ultimately
1 Plato's most explicit discussion of time is found in the dialogue Timeaus', but as we
will see the Kantian engagement with Plato has implications which extend far beyond
57
indistinguishable. For critical thought only makes time abstract by equating
the abstract with time-production. This circuit, explicated in the chapter on the
to the abstract production of time. For this reason, the attempt to situate Kant
revolution that extends far beyond the history of ideas. For, as we will see in
the following chapter, the Kantian notion of transcendental time has at least
58
in Kant, the schematism is best understood by the crucial function that it
stated, is one of the basic distinctions at work in the Critique of Pure Reason.
The schematism, as the abstract plane that connects these two sides, is thus
the necessary link which provides coherence to the underlying structure of the
first critique.
given, ordering sense data into a transcendental grid. As Deleuze writes they
are the "means by which we pose the manifold as occupying a certain space
and a certain time. " (KCP, 15) Dedicated to the presentation of the manifold,
categories are laid out in 4 groups of three with specific principles which
in chapter 2.
59
determine both their order and their relations. 3 By making use of the table of
which is presented; hence an activity and a unity distinct from the diversity
Thus, by the time one reaches the chapter on schematism, the realm
of the transcendental has been divided, split between, on the one side, the
production of the image, and, on the other, the production of concepts. Yet, in
so far as these processes remain separated they work in vain. For, neither
without contents are empty, intuitions without concepts are blind. " (CPR, 93)
concepts with our intuition of the objects of experience. Crucial here is the
fact that, for Kant, unlike for Plato, concepts only gain their legislative power
through some ulterior mechanism which makes them directly and immediately
impossible and can have no meaning if no object has been given to them. "
60
(CPR, 181)
question. "How, then, " asks Kant, "is the subsumption of intuitions under
(CPR, 180) Kant is here searching for a key. The task of the schematism is to
and sensible - which can serve to fuse the two halves of his system together.
"Obviously, " writes Kant, "there must be some third thing, which is
homogeneous on the one hand with the category, and on the other hand with
appearance, and which thus makes the application of the former to the latter
This 'third thing' is time. Thus, while it initially seemed as if the form of
time was clearly situated along side space in the 'Transcendental Aesthetic',
in his discussion of the schematism, Kant abstracts the form of time from this
showed, it is not only sensation but thought as well which occurs in time.
Thus, for Kant, just as all appearances are subject to temporal form so too
are the categories. In order for the a priori concepts to connect with the
61
shall entitle the schema of the concept. " (CPR, 182) By ensuring that they
relation to intuition.
Although both the concept and the image are conditioned by time, the
production of the schema arises neither from the understanding nor from
Kant writes "the two extremes, namely sensibility and understanding, must
stand in necessary connection with each other through the meditation of the
mere form, is an art concealed in the depths of the human soul, whose real
and the understanding production occurs in a linear flow, channelled into the
62
the product (the schema) is itself nothing other than the process of abstract
production. 4
The schema is neither an image nor a concept but a diagram. Like all
5
component. As an aspect of transcendental time it operates, for Kant, as the
the schematism, then, Kant frees time from being locked into any particular
determination, either on the side of the image or on the side of the concept,
and makes of it instead the abstract plane of connectivity on which his whole
system depends.
outside time. Universal and eternal, this realm is only accessed through the
appearances, abstraction was thus used to connect one with a realm outside
time.6
63
Defined in this way, the abstract is dialectically opposed to the
have seen, functions as the structure for the whole of classical thought.
Separated in this way, the abstract and concrete exist on two separate levels.
essence of the idea so, for Plato, the concrete is conceived of as a shadow of
the abstract.
For Kant it is not a realm outside time, but time itself that is abstract.
transcendence of the idea and is instead the process by which concepts (or
ideas) are applied to the objects of sense perception. That is to say, for Kant
64
transcendental thought abstraction operates within the concrete. 7 It is thus
conceived of, not as a means through which one can escape from the illusion
of appearances into the truth of the idea, but rather as the virtual synthetic
Kant still seeks to maintain that at its most abstract, the production of time
takes place inside the mind of the knowing subject. Yet, the fact that the
that is neither perceived nor understood, 9 the production of abstract time (or
plane which produces the inside. 10Kant's contention that the schema is
found 'hidden in the depths of the human soul' is ultimately nothing but
65
transcendental thought the production of time cannot be confined to the
seen, however, that the Kantian revolution has demolished this belief. With
his sustained attack on the 'Queen of all sciences', critique undermined the
Developing a theory of production which does not pass through God, Kant
placed the transcendental subject in the role of the ultimate creator. To quote
Alistair Welchman in his thesis Wild above rule or art., Creation and Critique,
nothing less than the production of the empirical world, of the universe as
such." (CC, 46) In this thesis it is argued that it is the inhuman forces of time
that surpass the power of the subject as the ultimate agent of transcendental
production.
66
transcendental required a revolution in the nature of time. The classical
account of a constant, formal time within which all variation takes place. He
called this the 'form of inner sense' due to the fact that it conditions all
thoughts and perceptions from within. Yet, as we have seen, in located time
67
Chapter 2: Time in Modern Capitalism
role of the human subject, but is instead about a transformation in the nature
demonstrates that it is not the subject that produces time but rather time that
centuries before the writing of the first Critique, history registers a change at
the empirical level, in the culture and technology of time. ' Thus, we will find,
' This will be explored by examining the work of a variety of socio-historians of time, including,
amongst others, David Landes, Lewis Mumford and Gerhard Dohm-van Rossum.
2This phrase is taken from DavidS. Landes' book Revolutionin Time:Clocksand the Making
68
two revolutions, the chapter seeks to investigate links between the production
development of the clock and the emergence of a new form of time, 2) the
GMT and on the equation 'time = money'), and 3) the problems and
In his book History of the Hour. Clocks and Modem Temporal Orders,
wisdom' that in the Late Middle Ages, there occurred, in the culture of the
mechanical clock. The impact of the clock, which Lewis Mumford has called
the "key machine of the modem industrial age" (TC, 14) is impossible to
influence of this new device attests to the fact that the clock was not merely
fundamental alteration in the nature of time itself. With the arrival of the
mechanical clock there arose, for the first time in history, an abstract, secular,
and distinct from the historical, astronomical and qualitative time of the
clock time - its distinction from the movement of objects in the external world
and its autonomy from the events which happen inside it - closely correspond
would thus appear, that the first great critical reversal which revolutionizes the
under capitalism.
technology of time should come as no surprise. For, as we will see, the lore
which surrounds Kant's life and habits suggest that, as an empirical subject,
Kant was obsessed with the temporality of the clock. What this chapter seeks
to maintain is that the time which governed Kant's life seeped into his writings
Kant's life and his writings the chapter seeks to propose that Kant discovered
a new form of time, not by looking into the hidden recesses of the human
soul, but through his sensitivity to the way time was functioning in the culture
It is not only the technology of the clock, however, which links Kantian
3The distinction between clocks and calendars will be discussed in detail in the following
section.
4This is not to say that Kantian philosophy can be reduced to socioeconomics. For the
connection between Kantian thought and clock time cannot be explained through a linear
causal relation. In fact the precise relation between these two aspects of the 'revolution in
time' is extremely complex and is thus treated as one of the main themes addressed
throughout this thesis.
70
thought to the production of capitalist time. For when seen through the
struggle. In a tale riddled with nostalgia and warnings, these thinkers lament
the fact that in the modem period the concrete, organic, and natural time of
the calendar has been overwhelmed and dominated by the artificial time of
the clock. 5
Seen through the lens of the Kantian system, however, clocks and
seen, the Critique of Pure Reason operates with a tripartite structure which is
capitalism, not as the tyrannical rule of the clock, but rather as the
plane of connection which brings together the time of the clock with the
5 To quote Mumford: 'Abstract time became the new medium of existence. Organic functions
were themselves regulated by it one ate, not upon feeling hungry, but when prompted by the
clock: one slept, not when one was tired but when the clock sanctioned it.'
71
Greenwich Mean Time (GMT), an 'artificial' synthesis which acts as the
succinctly captured by the phrase 'time equals money'. This equation - which
see, not only a new and autonomous form of time but also a transformation in
economics of time and the practices which they make possible which provide
capitalist production of time could only have taken place within a particular
the establishment of Greenwich Mean Time and the practices which equate
time with money required that certain contingent socio-economic forces were
in place. And yet, the paradoxical fact is that these forces were determined in
large part by the temporality that they made possible. In short, capitalist time
e As we will see these practices include such phenomena as wage labour, credit and interest.
and is productive not of events that occur inside experience but of the
of interiority it functions, not only through that which happens in time - but as
The difficulty with this claim, however, is that the attempt to equate
transcendental time with capitalist time runs into the familiar problem of how
Kantian thought. For, as we have seen, the first crucial step in identifying the
relationship between the empirical change in time that occurred at the onset
transcendental philosophy?
This is the problem which the final section of this chapter seeks to
address. It does so, first, by turning to the work of Karl Marx. For it is in Marx
where one finds one of the most consistent and well known attempts to
73
material practice. Marx concurs with Kant that analyses should not be based
ultimately rests with the dialectical struggles of the past. For Marx the a priori
the transcendental back into the empirical. Thus, though offering a bridge
writings manage to hide precisely the zone that Kant's work makes visible.
In order to bridge the gap that has opened between Kant and Marx,
the chapter turns finally to the work of Michel Foucault. By taking on board the
Foucault develops a theory that has the potential to link Kant with capitalism
For Foucault, just as for Marx, the a priori is historical. His books are
famous for mapping the ways in which transcendental structures vary from
74
these changes to the internal dynamics of history. According to Foucault the
"does not follow the smooth, continuist schemas of development which are
normally accepted. " (PK 112) Foucault's work thus leads us to the conclusion
that though transcendental structures change in time, these changes are not
is meant to signal the breaks in history, when, in the space of only a few
years an entire regime of power, which governs all that can be said and seen,
to forces from the outside. Thus, for Foucault it is not that the transcendental
75
2.1 Clock-Time
sought to inaugurate their reign through the introduction of a new calendar. For
the calendar, as we will see, is closely tied to the specificity and individuation of
as the means through which they can separate themselves both from their
immediate past and from their existing surroundings. Thus, calendric change has
been seen by cultures as the first and most crucial step in establishing their
practical conservatism - to its calendric milieu. In its entire history there has
been but one successful attempt at calendric reform. ' This occurred in 1582, at
the dawn of capitalism, when Pope Gregory XIII introduced modifications into the
1 There was a serious attempt at calendric reform during the French Revolution. This occured
through the introduction of a time-keeping system known as the 'Calendar of Reason. ' `Launched
in 1792 - the revolutionary Year One - this new calendar had uniform months of 30 days each,
taking on an extra 5 (or 6) days at the end. These were reserved for holidays called Virtue,
Genius, Labor, Opinion and Recompense. Instead of gods and emperors it used names for the
months: Nivose for snowing months, Pluvoise for Rainy Month, Thermidor for Heat Month, and
Brumaire for Foggy Month. Weeks were 10 days long, with three weeks per month. Days were
likewise divided in a decimal arrangement into 10 hours each of 100 minutes, with every minute
containing 100 seconds. ' (C, 238) However the 'Calendar of Reason' lasted only until 1806 when
Napoleon quietly reintroduced the Gregorian system.
76
Julian calendar. The Gregorian reforms, however, were not - intended as the
Pope Gregory had no desire to challenge the culture of the existing calendar, he
was slowly coming out of sync with the seasons. In order to stop this slide Pope
Gregory XIII initiated a number of fairly modest changes. He decreed that the 4th
of October would skip to the 15th of October, 2 moved the beginning of the year
from March 25th to January 1st, and made a slight adjustment to the Julian leap
year axiom3. These reforms gave the Julian calendar an added degree of
precision while leaving all the essential elements, the eras, the numerals, the
planet4 and now appears as the dominant time-registry of the global oecumenon,
5
overcoding local calendars without serious challenge. This is a testament to an
2 This particular reform prompted a series of riots in which 'mobs collected in the streets and
shouted 'give us back our 11 days'. ' (C, 228)
3 The Gregorian calendar, like the Julian calendar, treats every fourth year as a leap year. The
only difference is that in the Gregorian calendar no century year is a leap year unless it is exactly
divisible by 400 (eg 1600,2000). 'A further refinement, the designation of years evenly divisible by
4,000 as common (not leap) years, will keep the Gregorian calendar accurate to within one day in
20,000 years". Encyclopaedia Britannica, Volume 5, Micropedia, p.476.
4 The Gregorian calendar was adopted by the protestant German states in 1699, England and its
colonies in 1752, Sweden in 1873, Japan in 1873, China in 1912, Soviet Union in 1918.
5 The first, serious challenge to global dominance of the Gregorian calendar occurred at the dawn
of the third millennium and was brought on by a computer bug known as Y2K. This will be
discussed in detail in chapter 4.
77
ultra conservatism in capitalist time. For despite its globalized culture, capitalism
capitalist time occurred with the development of the mechanical clock. Though it
has so far proved impossible to pinpoint the precise place, time and
6
the late thirteenth or early fourteenth century. (HH) It is commonly agreed that
known as the verge and foliot escapement. By regulating the speed and flow of a
spoked wheel this small metallic lever was able to internally generate a
standardized beat or pulse. This was undoubtedly a crucial step in making the
clock a consistent and reliable device for keeping track of the time. As Lewis
Mumford writes, after the creation of the mechanical clock "the clouds that could
6 Joseph Needham's work on Chinese science has shown that some type of mechanical clock
was developed centuries earlier (perhaps as early as the eighth century) by the Chinese.
Nevertheless, by the time Jesuits came to China in the 16thcentury there was no sign of these
devices. For a good summary of this work and the issues that it raises see History of the Hour pp
86-88.
78
paralyse the sundial, the freezing that could stop the water clock on a winter
one was aware of the measured clank of the clock. (TS, 14) This first
(from the pendulum to the metric beats of the caesium atom) which have
combined to make the clock the most precise and accurate machine that has
ever been built. As Mumford suggests, from the mechanism of early clockwork to
the digital pulse of cybernetic computers, clocks and clock making have
At first glance it would appear that the difference between clocks and
calendar is used to count the days, months and years, the clock divides the day
into hours, minutes, seconds, (and now ever more intricately divided
we will eventually see, implicit in the distinction between these two types of time-
developing the technology of the clock, capitalism has discovered and unleashed
79
In order to understand what is peculiar about clock-time it must be first
distinguished from the temporality of the calendar. At its most abstract this
distinction rests on the different ways these two devices combine a beat and a
count - the two elements that are necessary in calculating the time. The beat, a
regular and repeating pulse or tick, is used as the basic unit of measure. While
the count, on the other hand, provides the numerical sequence which places the
units of measurement into an ordinal series. In order to tell the time, all time-
Calendric time is based on astronomy. The calendar takes its beats from
the revolutions of the planets. Its' tick is determined by the earth's rotation
around the sun. For all calendars, from the ancient Egyptian to the modern
Gregorian, use the day as their basic unit of measure. Defined most simply then,
is
the calendar a day count. Yet, as Thomas Crump writes in his book The
counting of days. " ("N, 85) For calendric uniformity, the constraint on the side of
the beat, is made up for by the complicated web of differences which are added
The calendar complicates the linear numerical sequence that adds up the
tradition (i.e. the yearly cycle of earth around the sun, the monthly cycle of the
80
moon, and the 7 day week of the Genesis story) the calendar envelopes the day
The great problem for calendrics is that these cycles are inevitably
lunar month with the solar year which results from the discrepancy that exists
between the time it takes for the earth to travel around the sun (365 days, 5 hr
48 min 46 sec) and the 12 months (29.5 days each) which, make up a lunar year.
Since almost all calendars seek some mode of accounting for both these cycles
the different elements of the calendar invariably come out of sync. Thus, in all
ensure that the time of the calendar is intrinsically rhythmic. Produced through a
count.
7In the Gregorian calendar, for example the day-count is subsumed under four cycles, the week,
the month, the year and the era (BC/"D).
8 In the Gregorian calendar this is known as the leap year axiom, the practice of inserting one day
every four years.
81
dating. Viewed as a numerical sequence or pattern the date is the record of a
rhythm. Using a combination of temporal units which are qualitatively distinct, the
expression, speaks to the fact that the time of the calendar is itself composed of
qualitative variations. Calendric time is directed towards the question 'when? '
This temporal marker, which depends on the difference between past, present
and future, presupposes qualitative distinctions in the nature of time itself. Thus,
it'is not only the internal variation at the abstract level of the count which makes
In the calendar, temporal units are not only determined numerically, but
Thus, the calendar not only dates events, but is also, as we will see, a time-
dating. For in the calendar, the separation between time and that which occurs in
calendar's close links with astronomy. Based on the revolutions of the planets,
82
macrocosm for organic life, further strengthening the qualitative nature of
calendric time.
The discipline of chronobiology, for example, attests to the fact that the 24
hour day is connected to the internal rhythms of the human sleep/wake cycle.
The lunar month, which governs the movement of the tides, is in almost all
-
cultures - closely linked with a woman's menstrual cycle? While the year is tied
to the passage of the seasons which regulates everything from life cycles, to
cycles of civilization, the calendar has always had a close affinity to ritual and
religion. Traditionally the calendar was the sole responsibility of religious leaders
(in Egyptian the word for priest means star watcher). Almost all cultures give
structures the rhythms of religious life. Punctuated by ritual, holy festivals and
9As Samuel Macy writes in his book The Dynamics of Progress: Time, Method and Progress,
"months, moons and menstruation are so closely related that we use the same root-word for all
83
the Sabbath, a weekly reminder of tradition which operates to structure and
determine the rest of the week. "The Jewish calendar, " writes Zerubavel, "has
been hailed as the single most important book of the people of Israel. It has
been said to have preserved the Jews as a people, to have united all those who
have been scattered around the world and made them one people" (HR, 73)
celebrating different holy days and not sharing in the same festivities a new
itself from Judaism through the adoption of a luni-solar calendar and by switching
the Sabbath from Saturday to Sunday. Mohammed, operating with the same
principle, "replaced the luni-solar calendar that had prevailed in Arabia with an
entirely lunar calendar. " (HR, 81) He also made the Islamic day of rest fall on a
Friday, thus distinguishing his-followers from both the Christians and the Jews.
emphasis on the count by innovating on the side of ticks or beats. Using cardinal
rather than ordinal numbers the clock does not count time: it measures it. The
clock is by its nature indifferent to astronomy. It can, as is the case with the
84
sundial, use the rotations of the planets as its mode of measure but its tendency
has been to find the tick of time elsewhere. Following a line through metallurgy
and on to geology the clock extracts the beat away from astronomical
movement. -For as D S.. Landes writes in his book Revolution in Time: Clocks and
the Making of the Modem World, "to the physicist any stable oscillation is a
clock. " (RT, 6) The clock, then is a machine which either engineers its own tick,
as is the case with the mechanical clock or it incorporates one from the outside
into its own internal mechanism, as is the case with clocks which run on the
pulse of the quartz crystal. Thus, unlike the calendar in which a vast distance
separates the count from the beat, clocks have assimilated natural time into the
machine.10
calendar in which each date has a specificity of its own, clock time is
historical year (the year the presidency was rocked by scandal, two years away
from the millennium etc... ), allied with a specific season (summer), allocated to a
particular time at that season (towards the end), and linked to designated day of
10This tendency for clock's to develop a new form of time independent of astronomy reached its
apex in the 1960's with the development of the atomic clock. This machine "which depends for its
operation on the incredibly precise rate of decay of a caesium isotope," (BT 71) has now become
the ultimate chronometric reference. "Atomic clocks, which operate at accuracies equivalent to an
error of one second in 150,000 years enable us with ease to measure irregularities in the rotation
period of the Earth itself the former standard of timekeeping." (BT 161)
85
the week (Friday). Yet, while calendric units are constrained by the qualitative
aspects of the time which they are meant to designate the units of clock time are
based on arbitrary divisions which are purely conventional. " The results in a
strong tendency of the clock to autonomize the time from any events outside its
own mechanism. 12
Unlike the calendar, clock time does not date events but determines the
length of time they take. It replaces the internal variation and complicated system
of counting with a metric and homogeneous measure. Extracted from history and
stripped of ceremony, ritual and religion, the regular beat of the clock is allied
with quantity rather than quality. It is an abstract and formalized time indifferent
For the majority of history the clock has been subordinated to the
they existed (as sundials, water clocks and sand glasses) operated within the
confines of the calendar. Using variable hours which were determined by the
length of the day and fluctuated with the seasons, the time of the clock had little
"Traditionally clock time has been organized according to the Babylonian 60 based system (there
are 60 minutes in an hour and 60 seconds in a minute). However, with the rise of digital
technology clocks have begun to split the second into gradations based on the decimal system
(e.g the nanosecond, the picosecond etc... )
12This is most evident with cyberspace time which does not distinguish between the days of the
week or even between night and day. This results in businesses having to develop new models in
which they are 'open' 24 hours, 7 days a week, and is also an increasing factor in processes of
globalization which make use of different time-zones to increase productivity.
86
or no autonomy. Though it was used for certain civil functions, 13in comparison to
capitalism has actualized a distinction in time which had, until the capitalist
made clock time ever more independent from the calendar, capitalism not only
time.
interesting." Days are invariably filled with some mixture of reading, writing, and
event biographical details rarely hold much importance. In the case of Immanuel
Kant, however, the situation is somewhat different. For the legends surrounding
Kant's life suggest that he performed the monotonous routine of his academic
schedule with such extreme regularity and precision that one cannot fail to
become absorbed in the meticulous, almost psychotic timing of his day to day
existence.
In an essay entitled The Last Days of Immanuel Kant Thomas Dequincy
13For example, in the fifth century water clocks were used in Athenian law courts to limit the time
of speeches. "Since court proceedings usually had to be concluded within a day, the total
speaking time in criminal trials was split three ways between the accuser, the accused, and the
judges, using as a basis the approximate amount of water that flowed out of vessels on a short
day (about nine hours). (HH, 23)
87
combines historical fact with fictional flare to describe this existence in detail.
Kant's day, according to Dequincy, began "precisely at five minutes before five
o'clock, winter or summer, when Lampe, Kant's footman, who had formerly
served in the army, marched into his master's room with the air of a sentinel on
duty, and cried aloud in a military tone. "Mr Professor, the time is come. " (LDIK,
341 ) Upon hearing this pronouncement Kant rose immediately and "as the clock
struck five he was seated at the breakfast table" (LDIK, 341) In accordance with
his passion for order and "love for architectonic symmetry" (WWR, 448) Kant -
so the story goes - adopted a routine reminiscent of the tables that structure the
first critique. His daily schedule was divided into 3 parts of 8 hours each, the first
dedicated to work, the second to leisure, and the third to sleep. The first part, the
one he arose from his chair and called aloud to his cook, 'It has struck three-
quarters' (LDIK, 341) Kant then closed up his office and preceded to lunch. After
the meal at 3: 30 pm, almost half way into the section of the day reserved for
leisure, Kant would go on his daily walk. He was greeted, according to legend, by
the citizens of Konigsberg who would look out their windows, wave to the
professor and set their watches by his movements. Thus, when Heine compares
Kant to the "great clock of the cathedral" he is not speaking metaphorically. For
if the stories are even partially true, the extremity of Kant's punctuality was such
88
As an empirical subject, then, Kant was deeply influenced by the clock.
achieved a certain amount of ubiquity and were well on their way of establishing
publication of the first critique, clocks made the first step in supplanting
astronomy as the ultimate chronometric reference, when "in 1780 Geneva first
started to use "mean time" in preference to solar time. " (ST, 4) Kant lived in a
world in which clocks had long since been introduced to urban centres and it is
undoubtedly the case, as is clear from Heine's analogy, that central to the town
of Konigsberg was a public time piece. Moreover, the lore which surrounds
Kant's life suggests that some form of clock or watch adorned every room of his
Yet, while it is clear that clock time was a crucial factor in Kant's life, the
especially in the discipline of; philosophy, to separate a thinkers life from his
work. This is reinforced in the case of Kant, since at the very foundations of
89
commonly held assumption that Kant, like most other thinkers, made his
to this view, Kant, explored the transcendental in the solitary confines of his
The problem with this view is that it cannot help but ignore the uncanny
resemblance which exists between the time of the clock which governed Kant's
life and the discussion of time found in the 'Transcendental Aesthetic'. This
First, clocks converge with Kantian critique in that with both time ceases
ceased to be in the hands of the priest or the ruler of the state and becomes
technology both echo and support the autonomy of the modern subject. To quote
Where people had once depended on the cry of the night watch, the bell
of the church, or the turret clock in the town square, now they had the time
at home or on their person and could order their life and work in a manner
to
once reserved regulated communities. In this way the privatisation
(personalization) of time was a major stimulus to the individualism that
was an ever more salient aspect of Western civilization. (RT, 89)
90
In both the history of the clock and in the first critique, this personalisation
time as the form of inner sense moves inside the subject to become both the
limit and the defining feature of interiority. An analogous process can be said to
have occurred with the technology of the clock. The clock, like the Kantian
Furthermore, clock time is similar to time as pure intuition in that with both
and usurpation. The clock is a machine for producing time. Once developed, its
internal processes. Even those objects and events of the external world that had
once been used to mark the time (i.e. the rotation of the planets) are now given
The final and most important point of convergence, however, is that both
clock time and time as a pure intuition revolutionizes the classical conception of
time by liberating temporality from the events which happen inside it. In creating
a purely quantitative time - distinct from astronomy -14 clocks developed a mode
14In 1967 the rate of cesium's pulse was calibrated to 9,192,631,770 oscillations per second.
This is now the official measurement of world time, replacing the old standard based on the
earth's rotation and orbit, which had used as its base number a second equal to 1/31556925.9747
of a year. This means that under this new regime of cesium the year is no longer measured as
91
world. In this way, the autonomy of clock technology parallels the Kantian
distinction between a formalized structure of time and the changes which occur
inside it. Thus, in paying relatively little attention to the calendar as a time-
92
2.2 The Synthetic Culture of Clock Time, or Time = Money
Joseph Conrad's book The Secret Agent turns upon the idea that the
most effective way of attacking capitalist culture is to target the time. Set in
London in 1884, The Secret Agent is a tale based on the historic attempt to
bomb the observatory at Greenwich. In Conrad's fiction the rationale for this
Verloc and his boss Vladimir, the Russian agent provocateur. Appearing on
summons to Vladimir's office, Verloc is informed that in order to earn his keep
he must use his links with the anarchist group 'Future of the Proletariat' to
the British, discredit the revolutionaries and provoke panic amongst the
religion will not do. Assassinations are expected. Assaults on public buildings,
while they undoubtedly cause some alarm, are easily dismissed as the act of
a lone maniac. "A bomb in the National Gallery would, " Vladimir concedes,
`make some noise, " but not amongst the right people. To hit at the heart of
the bourgeoisie, Verloc is instructed, one must strike against `the true fetish of
the hour - science and learning. " (SA, 35) "It would be really telling, " says his
boss, gloating in the persuasiveness of his own logic, if one could throw a
bomb into pure mathematics. " (SA, 36) Though this is unfortunately
impossible Vladimir contents himself with the next best thing, "What do you
93
think, " he asks, of having a go at astronomy? " (SA, 36) By the end of the
meeting it is dear that in order for Verloc to stay on the payroll he must stage
Conrad's book sets out to ridicule the cruel and baseless inanity of this
ideology, emotional betrayal and personal grief. And yet, the notion that
first appears. Though the bombing of Greenwich is perhaps ill advised, the
thinking behind it is sound. For, as we will see, there are few things as central
'
eighteenth century, when the clockmaker John Harrison devised a solution to
what had come to be known as the longitude problem. Up until this point,
ocean travellers had only one coordinate with which to determine their
location. The means of judging one's latitude which depends on natural signs
such as temperature and planetary positions had been known for thousands
of years. The much more arbitrary task of determining one's longitude, on the
other hand, was, to quote from Dava Sobel's best selling book on the subject,
a 'dilemma which stumped the wisest minds of the world for the better part of
' The precise date for the development of H4, the clock that eventually won the Longitude
prize is 1759.
94
In 1714 the British Parliament, sought to resolve this dilemma by
means of determining longitude. " (L, 8) What followed was a struggle that
clock. Since longitude is a fusion of space and time the solution to the
problem could come from one of two ways, either through the perfection of
life to producing a clock which could keep the time at sea. In 1759 Harrison's
work came to fruition with the completion of H4, the "time-keeper that
influential machines ever built. It played a critical role in securing control over
established Greenwich at the heart of the British empire, and was thus crucial
It was not until over a hundred years later, however, that the power of
Greenwich was globally entrenched. By the late 19th century the rapid growth
2 This latter
method rests on the fact that longitudecan be inferred by knowingthe time on
95
essential. With each city, town, or village governed by its own local time the
longitude wide and one hour apart was initially devised to co-ordinate North
American rail way traffic. The installation of this plan, however, demanded
that world time be synchronized on a zero point. This occurred in 1884 at the
agreed that the prime meridian would be the one passing through the 'centre
time and space'. Still today Greenwich is the 'keeper of the stroke of
midnight'(L, 168) It marks the beginning of the 'universal day' for all the
world and defines the east/west position of everywhere else on the planet.
"Greenwich time even extends into outer space: Astronomers use GMT to
time predictions and observations, except that they call it Universal Time, or
96
astronomers against engineers, it tells the story of a transition into a new age
in which the entrenched power of the 'star watchers' gives way to remarkable
neglect the calendar in order to celebrate instead the manifest triumph of the
clock.
culture of the clock back to the monastic tradition of the Middle Ages. For,
one finds the first signs of a culture based on the quantifiable and abstract
divided their day into measurable units in order to develop a strict daily regime
of work, rest and prayer. 'For centuries the religious orders had been the
masters of discipline: they were the specialists of time, the great technicians
of rhythm and regular activities. " (DP, 150) By scheduling time and
'synchronizing the action of men' (TC 14) they creating a mode of existence
have arose initially in order to provide shelter against the unpredictability and
from the chaos of ordinary life. To quote Lewis Mumford: Within the walls of
the monastery was sanctuary: under the rule of the order surprise and doubt
and caprice were put at bay. Opposed to the erratic fluctuations and
pulsations of the worldly life was the iron discipline of the rule. " (TC, 13)
The force which imposed the time table, however, should not be seen
as a solely negative one. Time scheduling was more than a means of trying to
keep the forces of chaos under control. It was also a positive religious
account of the division of time. "The central element in monastic daily routine
was divine worship. In keeping with Psalm 119, verses 164 (A Seven times a
day I praise thee") and 62 (At midnight I rise to give thee thanks") it was
performed seven times during the day and once during the night. " (HH 35)
The fact that prayers occurred so often, and that their scheduling did not
determining midnight) meant that monks had to develop some other way of
keeping track of the time. In order to accomplish this the monasteries put the
longer structured by the concrete rhythms of the planets but was determined
98
instead in accordance with the dictates of the monastic rule. Signalling the
time by the ringing of a bell, the abbot would call the monks to prayer. Thus,
unlike other religious practices in which the passage of time dictates when to
wrote Benedict, is an enemy of the soul. " His text, the Benedictine rule,
time. Leisure was not permitted. For unless one adopted a disciplined
would seep into the soul and steal away time that was meant to be dedicated
to God. Thus, if monks were to fulfil their religious duty and live according to
the will of their creator, time had to be strictly rationalized. According to this
story, then, the clock was developed almost as a form of worship, necessary
This thesis, that clock time originated inside the walls of monasteries,
has been challenged along a number of lines. In his book History of the Hour,
Gerhard Dohm-van Rossum argues, for example, that while it is true that the
monastic tradition rationalised time it did not pay much attention to measuring
it.6 Time in the monasteries was regulated but it was not yet made regular.
clock but by the ringing of the bell. Still dependent on the temporality of the
calendar, monastic time operated with hours that fluctuated with the
seasons.? Temporal distinctions were made through divine office not by the
Ages the historian Jack Le Goff makes the claim that clock time arose, not in
the monasteries, but rather through the pragmatic culture of the merchants.
He argues that in order for clocks to take hold, time had to be freed from the
clutches of God. His essay begins with a discussion of usury. "Among the
principal criticism levelled against the merchants, " he writes, "was the charge
that their profit implied a mrtgage on time which was supposed to belong to
God alone. " (MT/CT, 29) Both credit and interest, which are of course crucial
to the merchant, demand tliat the prohibition on usury be lifted and that -as
we will later see - money not God be equated with time. 9 Furthermore, in that
" 'Talk of'Tron discipline' or the machine-like or clockwork rhythm of monastic life,
even in a
purely metaphorical sense, is misleading, because it suggests a time giver (a machine or
clock) external to natural rhythms and the daily round of human life. In actual fact, life
according to the Rule was bound in a very high degree to natural time givers, daylight and the
seasons, and was by no means marked by ascetic resistance to the natural environment. "
(HH, 38)
a'Despite the density of activities, the ordering of the daily monastic routine got by
with
remarkably few indications of time. The beginning of the offices was linked not to a particular
point in time but to a signal or short sequence of signals. ' (HH, 36)
Le Goff writes that once commercial networks were organized, time (and its relation to
monetization) became an object of measurement. The duration of a sea voyage or of a
journey by land to one place or the other, the problem of prices which rose or fell in the course
of a commercialtransaction(the more so as the circuit became increasinglycomplex,
100
they were operating in an environment of technological precision, navigational
hours, one in which the science of technology rather than the authority of
priests is in control.
Yet another factor, crucial to the development of clock time, was the
"
process of urbanization. Historically, rural life had been governed by the
qualitative time of the calendar. The passage of the seasons, the natural
cycle of the day and the concrete rhythms of agriculture dictated how time
was structured and filled. In the country, working time was task driven and the
from events. From a very early period, public clocks were installed in the city
affecting profits), the duration of the labor of craftsmen and workers (since the merchant was
almost always an employer of labor), all made increasing claims on [the merchant's] attention
and became the object of evermore explicit regulation. (MT/CT, 35)
10This was absolutely necessary due to the emphasis on facts, documentation
and double
entry book keeping that were a crucial component to the life of the merchant. To quote Le
Goff: 'The statuses of corporations, together with such commercial documents as account
sheets, travel diaries, manuals of commercial practice and the letters of exchange then
coming into common use in the fairs of Champagne (which in the twelfth and thirteenth
century became the 'clearinghouse' of international commerce), all show how important the
exact measurement of time was becoming to the orderly conduct of business. ' (MT/CT, 35)
11Deleuze emphasizes this aspect in speaking of the relation between clock time
and Kant.
For Deleuze it is Kant's'historical situation which allows him to grasp the implications of the
critical reversal [in the philosophy of time]. Time is no longer the cosmic time of an original
celestial movement, nor is it the rural time of derived metereological movements. It has
become the time of the city and nothing other, the pure order of time. ' (ECC, 28)
101
centres and time in the towns became governed by these new machines. The
time of the clock began to regulate when one was to eat, sleep and especially
when and for how long to work. As Mumford writes, "the bells of the clock
tower almost defined urban existence. (TC, 14) With the migration from the
country to the towns, then, there arose 'a regular, normal time associated
with daily life, a sort of chronological net in which urban life was caught" (TL
48)
All three of these cultural forces crucial to the development of the clock
- the discipline of monastic life, the secular world of merchant capital, and the
growth of industrialized urban centres - have also been strongly linked to the
Mumford, that the structure and discipline of the monastic tradition was a
crucial precursor to modem industrial society. Operating with the same model
give human enterprise the regular collective beat and rhythm of the machine. "
(TC, 14), Having built a society based on order, rationalism and rules, the
"the Benedictines, the great working order, " can be seen as 'the original
102
capitalism which extends capitalist relations into the sphere of production.
develop. 12
the transition to the capitalist mode of production. The move away from the
particular tasks or positions (the peasant, the farmer, the baker) vast portions
in
system which labour could be traded with relative ease. A factor which
many - from Smith to Marx and beyond - believe to be the key to capitalist
production.
accountancy and credit practised by the merchants and the large and fluid
labour markets that arose through the process of urbanization, are all
considered key, both in the history of the clock and in the history of
capitalism. Yet, one should not be surprised that the development of clock-
12It has been argued, by Engels in particular, that merchant capital was the vehicle by which
capitalism replaced feudal society.
103
time is so intertwined with the production of capitalist culture. 13 For, as we will
Time Is Money
Remember, that time is money. He that can earn ten shillings a day by
his labour, and goes abroad, or sits idle, one half of that day, though
he spends but sixpence during his diversion or idleness, ought not to
reckon that the only expense; he really has spent, or rather thrown
away, five shillings besides.. ' (PESC, 51)
words, which warn against the dangers of idleness and wasting time, he is
is
argued, the characteristic feature of 'the spirit of capitalism. ' 14For Weber,
13 As we will see, this relation between clock-time and capitalist culture can neither be
explained by the discourse of technological determinism (which presumes a one way causal
relationship which runs from technology to social systems) nor by social constructivism (which
maintains a linear causality but sees it as running in the opposite direction). For as we will see
in the following pages, the culture of capitalism and the technology of the clock are mutually
involved in a circuit of reciprocal presuppositions such that it is impossible to say which
precedes the other. For it is clear, both, that the development of the clock could only have
taken place within capitalist culture and that capitalist culture presumes, from its very
beginning, the ubiquity of the clock.
14The connections between critique and capitalism are no doubt due at least in part to
- -
Kant's obvious connections to Protestantism. This relation is stressed both by Heine, who
argues that Kantianism is 'nothing else than the last consequence of Protestantism. ' (RPG,
59) and by Weber who maintains that "being partly of Scotch ancestry and strongly influenced
by pietism in his bringing up-many of [Kant's] formulations are closely related to the ideas of
ascetic Protestantism. ' (PESC, 270)
104
capitalist culture is a Christian culture since its 'spirit' corresponds to the
beliefs, practices and ethos of a particular strand in the Christian tradition. His
work sets out to show that by cultivating an ethos of 'active asceticism' this
is
ethic which conducive to the capitalist way of life. 15
This ethic depends, first of all, on what Weber has called, the
'disenchantment of the world. ' (FMW, 290) Christianity, like its precursor
spirits and strips objects of their animistic power. Outlawing the sorcerer, it
puts the prophet in charge of a world that is "disenchanted of its gods and
demons. " (FMW, 148) The sacred, which is now captured by the
Judeo-Christian tradition shuns not only sorcery but also what Weber calls the
the divine. (FMW, 289) Trance and possession are criticized since they
attempt to flee from the world that God has created. What is required instead
15It would be
a mistake to assume that Weber's argument is that the Protestant religion is the
cause of capitalism, or the capitalist way of life. No economic ethic, " he writes, has ever been
determined solely by religion. In the face of man's attitudes towards the world - as determined
by religious or other (in our sense) 'inner' factors - an economic ethic has, of course, a high
measure of autonomy. Given factors of economic geography and history determine this
measure of autonomy in the highest degree. The religious determination of life-conduct,
however, is also one - note this - only one, of the determinants of the economic ethic. (FMW,
268)
105
is the 'emissary prophet' who no longer functions as God's 'vessel', but has
become instead, his 'tool'. (PESC, 113-114) With careful sobriety the
emissary prophet encounters the divine as the giver of the law. Working as
name for an asceticism which has turned away from a contemplative 'flight
from the world' and dedicated itself instead to 'work in the world'. (FMW,
290) Placed in the role of custodian or guardian, the active ascetic seeks to
`create the kingdom of heaven on earth, " transforming the world through the
activity of labour. With the active ascetic, then, economic activity ceases to be
Weber maintains that the ethos of active asceticism reached its apex
in Calvinism. " It is clear from his work, however, that the roots of the
Protestant ethic predate the reformation. According to Weber, the first inklings
Middle Ages. For it is in these secluded environments where there first arose
As we have seen these qualities of monastic life arise from the fact that
16In inner-wordly asceticism, the grace and the chosen state of the religiously qualified
man
prove themselves in everyday life. To be sure, they do so not in the everyday life as it is given,
but in methodical and rationalized routine-activities of workaday life in the service of the Lord.
Rationally raised into a vocation, everyday conduct becomes the locus for proving one's state
of grace. ' (FMW, 291)
17For Weber's discussion
of Calvinism as a religious foundation for worldly asceticism see
106
they structured their existence according to a new regime of time. Monks
attempt to access realms that existed outside time. In place of this heretical
fulfilment came from the management and measure of time itself. Like the
Puritans after them, they believed that 'not leisure and enjoyment, but only
activity serves to increase the glory of God. " (PESC, 157) With their
was the first and in principle the deadliest of sins. " (PESC, 157) "For,
according to the Christian ethic which Franklin would later expound "every
hour lost is lost to labour for the glory of God. " (PESC, 158) Thus, writes
Weber, it does not yet hold, with Franklin, that time is money, but the
107
As is well known Marx's work differs from Weber's in that his theory of
money' plays as central a role for Marx as it does for Weber. For regardless
of their differences, these two thinkers share the fact that they have
time.
of value (which he inherited and modified from the prior history of political
Economic theory concerns facts that are expressed in terms of value, and
value is not only the prime mover of the economic cosmos, but also the form
in which its phenomena are made comparable and measurable. " (TGE, 151).
from two points of view of quality and quantity. " (C1,125) Qualitatively
commodities are defined by their use value. That is, their value is derived
from the fact that they fulfil some 'human need. ' Thus, a coat, for example,
viewed according to its use value, is something someone wears to keep out
uses they fulfil and become instead 'the material bearers of exchange value'
(Cl, 126) The coat is no longer a garment to be wom but rather an object that
to Marx, the exchange relation necessarily takes the form of the equation x=
y (i.e. 100 loaves of bread is equal to 1 coat). What, this equation signifies, he
different things... Both are therefore equal to a third thing, which is in itself
neither the one nor the other. Each of them, in so far as it is exchange value,
chemical or other natural property of commodities. " (Cl, 127) since these
function.
by a common property that all commodities share. For Marx, this common
factor is the fact that all commodities are a product of human labour.
Everything from corn to clothes to cars has been created by the hands of the
its concrete manifestation (the labourer as farmer, baker, smith etc.. ) but is
seen instead as 'human labour in the abstract. " (C1,128) Thus, Marx
concurs with the conclusion of modem political economy (from Adam Smith),
the labour theory of value had answered: through aggregate labour time.
The quantity of labour, ' writes Marx, Is measured by its duration, " (Capital
1,46) or, even more emphatically, the measure of labour is time" (PP, 42).
Time, then, is the means through which abstract labour is quantified. It is form
or standard which serves to calculate exchange value, and is thus the means
In the Marxist theory, labour time not only determines exchange value,
110
but is also the crucial use-value for industrial capitalism, and is thus the
principal of surplus value. It is this recognition which has been seen -by Lenin
surplus value which, according to Marx, accounts both for the (rigorously
fact that the capitalist makes the labourer work for more time than is
Under capitalism the working day is divided into two parts. In the first
part-the 'necessary working time' -the worker produces the means
necessary for his own support, or the value of those means; and for
this part of his labour he receives an equivalent in wages. During the
second part -the 'surplus working time '-he is exploited, he produces
'surplus value' without receiving any equivalent for it. (KMCS, 16)
To quote Marx, `the fact that half a day's labour is necessary to keep
the labourer alive during 24 hours, does not in any way prevent him from
working a whole day. (C, 188) In short, "surplus value is produced by the fact
that the capitalist makes the labourer work for him a part of the day without
paying him for it". ( KCS 16) The bourgeois mode of production, then, extracts
surplus from the 'extra' time that the labourer is forced to work.
Thus, the two key features in Marx's analyses of the capitalist system,
exchange value and surplus value - are constituted through the operations
-
at all historical. In his analyses of capitalist time, Marx ignores the qualitative
uniform, and purely quantitative time of the clock. For according to Marx, it is
labour.
The notion that the capitalist synthesis 'time is money' rests solely on
the time of the clock is brought into question by the Austrian economist Eugen
implicit bias of both Marx and Weber by focussing, as we will see, on the
his book Karl Marx and the Close of his System, a work which according to
the theoretical content of Marx's system is concerned. " (TGE, 164) The
54)
112
importance of this book in economic theory stems from the fact that it
show that the labour theory of value is, even within Marx's own writings,
21
confused and unworkable. It's success in this regard is such that as Paul
Sweezy writes in the introduction to the text it "might almost be called the
Marx centres on the question of time. It deals, as Schumpeter says, with "the
process. " (TGE, 165) For, according to Boehm-Bawerk the problem with Marx
and more generally with the labour theory of value is that it misses the overall
20Schumpeter summarizes the problem with Marx's theory as follows: The essential point is
not whether labour is the true 'source' or'cause' of economic value. This question may be of
primary interest to social philosophers who want to deduce from it ethical claims to the
product, and Marc himself was of course not indifferent to this aspect of the problem. For
economics as a positive science, however, which has to describe or explain actual processes,
it is much more important to ask how the labour theory of value works as a tool of analyses,
and the real trouble with it is that it does this very badly.' (TGE, 28)
21Boehm-Bawark's main contention is that the labour theory of value as laid out in Capital:
Volume I cannot be reconciled with the average rate of profit discussed in Capital: Volume 3.
To quote from Boehm-Bawark: "Marx's third volume contradicts the first. The theory of the
average rate of profit and of the prices of production cannot be reconciled with the theory of
value. '(KCS)
113
Capitalism, according to Boehm-Bawerk, is characterized by a
switch away from direct production in which the existence of the good
direct production water is collected by going to the river each day. Whereas in
a system based on roundabout production a pipe is built that can carry the
power, coupled with his insistence that surplus value can only be generated
through variable capital (employed labour), meant that he could only view
change in constant capital has a fundamental role both for the creation of
the crucial fact about roundabout production is that while it obtains a greater
result and yields a larger final product than direct production (it is obviously
114
ultimately more efficient to get your water from a tap than to have to go to the
consumption of goods, but only at a later period of time. This is one of the
ground pillars of the theory of capital" (PTC 82) "In this loss of time which is,
as a rule, bound up with the capitalist process, " he continues, 'lies the sole
on capitalist. "(PTC, 83) The capitalist -as bearer of risk- mobilizes labour,
analyses insists that credit is always coupled with interest. For it is by means
22To attempt Marx does -to calculate a 'rate of exploitation' without reference to this
-as
prospective production radically diminishes the importance of the time element in the system.
23The labour theory of value is
necessarily blind to this fundamental aspect of the capitalist
mode of production. For in determining value through duration of labour time it fails to take
into account the effects of when this labour takes place.
115
of interest that capitalism is able to profit on the sacrifice of time inherent in its
rests on the fact that present goods are more highly valued than those which
become available in the future. (TGE, 174) That is, one is in general willing to
pay more for something which is available now then for the same product
which will only be available at some future date. There is then, in short, a
Thus, whereas the labour theory of value shows how time works as a
force in the construction of the labourer and constitution of the working day,
for Boehm-Bawerk time is itself a positive economic force. Rather than the
relation between time and money being mediated by labour time, the
116
present and future (a difference which is irreducable to the time measured by
clock) which ultimately accounts for the capitalist equation of time with
money.
In the previous section it was argued that the split between calendars
sought to show that in the period since the Middle Ages, a process of
the mechanical clock and its subsequent innovations freed time from its sole
autonomous force.
This section followed on from this distinction and showed how the
In this sense our discussion would appear to concur with the analyses of
capitalist time made by the historians and sociologists that are mentioned
above. For the majority of these thinkers adopt the view capitalist time is
defined by `the dominance of clock time over space and society. " (NS 432)
Writing with a deep nostalgia they wam of the triumph of an abstract and
artificial time that has supplanted the 'natural' organic and concrete time of
the tyrannical rule of an "empty" time, 'divisible into equal, constant, and
117
nonqualitive units. (TLSD 202). With the clock, claims Mumford, "abstract
time became the new medium of existence. " (TC, 17) Alienating people from
shown that the capitalist emphasis on clock time must be combined with an
extract discipline, work and efficiency from the abstract time of the clock, but
also converts the variations of calendric time into direct economic activity.
the clock must be seen as only one side of the story. This is important since,
Aesthetic is only a single piece of the Kantian system. For intrinsic to the very
structure of the Critique of Pure Reason is the notion that intuition is blind
In the same way, without the calendar the clock is incapable of telling
the time. For, as has already been noted, the ticking which marks the
26In the capitalist production of time, calendric temporality operates less as a marker of
astronomical cycles than it does as a dating system which distinguishes between past,
present and future. Astronomy, as we have seen, has taken on a secondary role since the
planetary revolutions are now measured by the ticking of the clock. Nevertheless, the calendar
is still used to index qualitative distinctions, (year, month, and day of the week), that are
inaccessible to clock-time and yet crucial to capitalist processes of production.
118
passage of hours, minutes and seconds can never, no matter how accurate it
becomes, calculate the day, month or year when something occurs. Thus,
clocks are 'blind' without the dates and the a. m. and p.m. markers which the
calendar provides. Telling the time is thus itself a synthetic operation which
combines the hour, minute and second with the calendric anchors of day,
In the Kantian system the two distinct parts of critique are joined
together through the schema. Hidden in the recesses of the imagination, the
secret of the schema takes the synthetic production of time to its highest
the Aesthetic with the Logic, joining the intuition of time together with the
of time reveals that the production of capitalist time operates, like the diagram
of the schema, to construct an abstract plane which can connect the two
sides of time-keeping with each other. Thus, rather than assuming that the
process of production which mobilizes both the time of the clock and the time
27The fact that 'the day for all the world, begins at Greenwich' shows that GMT is not, as it
may first appear, a standardized time based entirely on the clock. In fact, Greenwich time is a
synthesis between clock time and the calendric count.
119
of the calendar into a particular synthetic regime, and thus views this equation
production of time.
120
2.3 History and the Transcendental
reduce the transcendental to the status of the empirical, but rather to uncover
technical formations of the empirical world. The claim, then, is not that Kant's
writings are the result of the historical experience of capitalist time. For Kant's
underlie experience are not restricted - as Kant believed - to the eternal inner
workings of the human subject but are also found in the technical and cultural
the work of Karl Marx and Michel Foucault, two thinkers who maintain that
subject to change and transformation. That is, according to both Marx and
121
It soon becomes apparent, however, that Marx and Foucault differ
lines. At stake in this divergence is, as we will see, two drastically distinct
force in the generation of change, it creates the a priori through the power of
its own internal dynamics. Foucault's work, on the other hand, reveals that
there are certain empirical transformations that are so dramatic and sudden
that they can only be explained through the gaps and holes that break open in
maintains that rather than being produced inside history, the transformation of
/
the a priori impact history as a force of the outside.
In examining both these theories, the following pages explore the line
manage to effect the empirical domain of history and vice versa. The
Kantian revolution in the philosophy of time and the capitalist revolution in the
ultimately to the conclusion that there are certain events in the history of
122
the Marxist critique of Kant is well known. For throughout his texts Marx
than on philosophers, the attack he makes can be easily applied to Kant. For
presuppose what they should be explaining. "The 18th century individual, "
writes Marx, "the product on one side of the dissolution of the feudal forms of
society, on the other side of the new forces of production developed since the
they project into the past. ' (G, 83) By taking the individual "not as a historic
result but as history's point of departure" (G, 83) these economists miss the
real forces at work in capitalism. For they fail to see that the bourgeois
for Marx 'among the unimaginative conceits of the eighteenth century' (G, 83)
1 'For Marx, Engels and Lenin, Kant's theory of knowledge was defective in three
related
ways. First, it was held to be ahistorical in its account of the a priori contributions made by the
mind in the constitution of knowledge: for Kant these fundamental concepts were universal
properties of the mind whereas Marxists have tended to understand human cognitive powers
as subject to historical transformation and development. Connectedly, whereas Kantianism
locates the a priori conditions of objective knowledge in the faculties of the mind, Marxism
characteristically locates them in indispensable human social practices which have bodily as
well as mental aspects. Finally, Engels and Lenin argued that the boundary between the world
of knowable 'phenomena' and the unknowable 'things-in-themselves' was not, as Kantianism
required, fixed and absolute but was historically relative. The potential knowability of the world
as it is, independent and prior to the human subject, was seen as essential to the empirical
123
since it takes a contingent product of a particular time and place and treats it
knowledge should begin not with experience but with the constitutive forces
that produce that experience. However, the content of Marx's assertions can
doing to Hegel.
the eighteenth century' can be reread as follows: Kant is said to have asked
what are the necessary conditions that produce experience. His answer
turns this question around and asks 'what are the necessary conditions which
the notion that transcendental structures are ultimately produced through the
124
is a particular socio-economic arrangement that "is itself the product of a
or modes of production, the ancient, the feudal and the bourgeois. 2 These
three phases are related dialectally such that each successive mode of
production themselves have a logic of their own; that is to say, they change
workings. " (TGE, 13) Thus, according to Marxist philosophy, the ancient
necessarily gave way to the feudal, and the feudal necessarily gave way to
the bourgeois. Each stage is both historically and dialectically related to the
previous one such that "higher relations of production never appear before
the material conditions of their existence have matured in the womb of the old
society. " (CCPE, 12) It is this logical unfolding of history which is for Marx the
ultimate force of production, and the real agency of change. It generates both
2 Actually Marxism usually singles out four stages of development. Note the following from a
Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy. in broad outline we can designate the
Asiatic, the ancient, the feudal, and the modem bourgeois methods of production as so many
epochs in the progress of the economic formation of society! (CCPE, 13) Marx believed,
however, that the first of these, the Asiatic mode, existed outside the progressive development
of history. (See Karl Marx on Colonialism and Modernization: his dispatches and other writings
on China, India, Mexico, the Middle East and North Africa. Edited and introduced by Shlomo
'Ivineri. Garden City NY: Doubleday, 1968) The over-simplification of a history characterized
by these three rigid stages was questioned and complicated, even by Marx himself, in later
writings. Nevertheless, it is still considered to be the basic structure of historical materialism.
125
the capitalist system and its corresponding structures of knowledge. 3
philosophy of time should converge with changes in the technology and socio-
regardless of the fact that they occur in radically different spheres, are a
Transcendental and capitalist time coincide since both are the result of the
anticipate the Marxist contention that the discovery of the transcendental was
is insistent that the discovery of the transcendental could not have been
architectonic, or the "art of creating systems. " (CPR, 653) This requires the
reason" (CPR, 654). Once uncovered, this a priori schema, " writes Kant, is
capable of making "a system out of a mere aggregate of knowledge. " (CPR,
3 See in particular Karl Marx. German Ideology. New York: International Publishers, 1970.
126
653)
demonstration that the art of the architectonic exists. Yet, Kant is adamant
that this is an art which can never be learnt. For learning, according to Kant,
is based on the successive accumulation of facts. As such it can only add one
thing after the other, destined to remain at the level of the aggregate,
history.
Anyone, therefore who has learnt (in the strict sense of that term) a
system of philosophy... although he may have all its principles,
explanations, and proofs, together with the formal divisions of the
whole body of doctrine, in his head, and, so to speak, at his fingers'
ends, has no more than a complete historical knowledge of [that]
philosophy. (CPR, 656)
only in a historical fashion, " (CPR, 657) he nevertheless maintains that the art
For, as we have seen, Kant's is a revolution that does not occur in time but to
127
time.
and asserting that the a priori are ultimately a product of the a posteriori he
argued -in a Spinozistic sense - that Marx fails to take heed of his own
historical time, whose own production can never be explained. That is to say
governing everything from what people believe, to how bodies move, to the
128
way in which objects are produced. 4 Thus by investigating the transformations
in different regimes of power, (he focuses especially the shift from the
be in the hands of the despot. Rather than a 'privilege one might posses'
circulating everywhere within the social field. No longer the type of force
which lashes out from above, the micro-physics of disciplinary power inserts
itself directly into the body, subtly articulating its motions, posture, and
must be 'conceived not as a property but as a strategy. ' (DP, 26) Such a
rather than display itself in its murderous splendour. " (FR, 266)
Foucault introduces this new regime in the fist few pages of Discipline
scheduling and control of time. Foucault's work traces this new form of
129
control as it spreads from prisons to factories to schools. 5 To quote from an
exemplary passage:
Foucault insists, however, that this maniacal ordering of time was only
the first step in the new 'economy' of power. As the disciplinary regime
The principle that underlay the time-table in its traditional form was
essentially negative; it was the principle of nonidlenenss: it was
forbidden to waste time, which was counted by God and paid for by
men... Discipline, on the other hand, arranges a positive economy; it
poses the principle of a theoretically ever-growing use of time.
Exhaustion rather than use. (DP, 154)
Thus, the role of time became crucial not only for scheduling the days
activities but also for a sort of internal articulation of the body. "In the correct
use of the body, which makes possible a correct use of time, nothing must
remain idle or useless: everything must be called upon to form the support of
the act required. " (DP, 152) In the disciplinary regime, writes Foucault, "time
penetrates the body and with it all the meticulous controls of power. " (DPI 52)
130
This is the world of Taylorism, chronometric efficiency and time and
motion studies. ' world in which the bodies of soldiers, schoolchildren and
schema of behaviour. 'The act is broken down into its elements, the position
(DP, 152)
'extracting from time, ever more available moments, and from each moment,
ever more useful forces. "(DP, 154) In a regime in which time is equated with
money, power must develop "a new technique for making profit out of the
movement of passing time. " (DP, 157) The question of the disciplinary
regime, writes Foucault, is "how can one capitalize the time of individuals,
in
abilities, a way that is susceptible of use and control? How can one
institution, making them converge and function in a new way. (F, 26)
131
then, " writes Foucault in the opening section of the book, "a public execution
particular regime of power undergoes 'a global modification. '6 (PK 113)
Foucault makes use of the concept by repeatedly showing how, over the
course of history there have been moments when 'in the space of a few
"the intrusion of an outside. " (F, 87) Operating in an exterior relation to the
which our experience depends Thus for Foucault, as Deleuze writes, "things
the operations of power but also marks a heterogeneity intrinsic to the nature
6 "My problem, " he is quoted as saying, was to pose the question 'How is it that at certain
moments and in certain orders of knowledge, there are these sudden take-offs, these
hastenings of evolution, these transformations which fail to correspond to the calm, continuist
image that is normally accredited? " (PK, 54)
132
time itself. Contained within the sentence from Discipline and Punish that is
temporality, from the festive time of the torturous spectacle, through the
metric and quantitative time of the prisoners time table, to the time which
marks the passing of the century. These different time systems are radically
-
even transcendentally incommensurable. Even the supposed consistency of
historical time fails to tie them together (there is nothing in the continuity of
time (the century) that can account, for example, for the introduction of a new
133
Chapter 3: The Materialist Revolution: Time in Capitalism and
Schizophrenia
seasonal variation and the movement of day into night. What the preceding
chapters have sought to show is that - in what can loosely be called modernity
focussed on the fact that in both the philosophy of Immanuel Kant and in the
time-keeping practices that have emerged under capitalism, time has ceased
The question of this thesis is how an innovation such as this can occur
to the abstract nature of time. Or, to put it another way, how are we to explain
events which happen not only in time but to time? Our response, as we will
reformulation of the relation between time and change such that these
134
subordinated to a hierarchical relation - as in the modem conception but
-
rather coexist together on an immanent plane.
requires, first of all, a conception of time that is not been transcendently fixed.
economic system lies its unique ability to have transformed the nature of
time. '
We have seen in the previous chapter that the work of the key theorists of modern
capitalism, for example Mumford, Marx and Weber can all be formulated in this way.
135
transcendental philosophy. The problem the thesis encounters then, is how to
synthesize its two sides and thereby establish a connection between the
= money) that constitute time in the capitalist world. Implicit in this problem -
material practice. This thesis has formulated this question in the terms set out
by the transcendental philosophy of time. In doing so, it sees the link between
keeping technologies and the cultural practices which surround them. The
establish this relation by way of a debate between the writings of Kant and
Marxist philosophy.
intuition' which Kant names 'the form of inner sense. ' It functions, in this role,
136
as a numerical synthesizer ordering and sequencing anything which happens
to fill it. A one dimensional linear succession which provides the underlying
occur in time "we can quite well think time as void of appearances. " (CPR,
75) This distinction between time and the changes which occur within it is
-
as has already been noted - what makes Kantian thought revolutionary. It
mistakes consequence for cause and remains blind to the primary processes
contention that philosophy is dependent upon its material conditions and that
Thus, for Marx, it is the changes which occur in time which are ultimately
2 Note the following from The German Ideology. "In direct contrast to German philosophy,
which descends from heaven to earth, here we ascend from earth to heaven. That is to say,
we do not set out from what men say, imagine, conceive, nor from men as narrated, thought
of, imagined, conceived, in order to arrive at men in the flesh. We set out from real, active
men, and on the basis of their real life process we demonstrate the development of the
ideological reflexes and echoes of this life process. The phantoms formed in the human brain
are also, necessarily sublimates of their material life process, which is empirically verifiable
and bound to material premises... Life is not determined by consciousness but consciousness
137
However sympathetic one might be to Marx's underlying intention, the
production and thus cannot account for innovation in the abstract construction
Aesthetic', since time "underlies all intuitions" (CPR, 75) "the actuality of
see time as a presupposition of the changes which occur within it, Marx
The problem, then, remains. For neither Kant nor Marx can account for
how an event which occurs in time (and is thus empirical) can effectuate
meant to designate the "rifts and instabilities" (OT )o iv) that operate to
by life. ' Quoted from 'Excerpts from The German Ideology' in Marx & Engels: Basic Writings
on Politics and Philosophy.
138
disrupt the apparent continuity of historical time. There is, then, in Foucault,
envelops it, according to the Nietzschean conception. " (F, 85) These forces
the rifts or cracks they break open, mark, above all, the incommensurability of
transcendental structures. Yet the actual process through which this doubling
of history takes place is left unclear. Foucault thus shows us the fact
themselves, nor of how they are able to connect with or act upon the
are to succeed in projecting a line that can connect the temporal machines of
3 In his book The Order of Things, Foucault himself admits that he focused on outlining
discontinuous change without examining either the causes of these changes or the
mechanisms through which they occur. To quote Foucault: it seemed to me it would not be
prudent for the moment to force a solution I felt incapable, I admit, of offering: the traditional
explanations - spirit of the time, technological or social changes, influences of various kinds -
struck me for the most part of being more magical than effective. In this work, then, I left the
problem of causes to one side; I chose instead to confining myself to the transformations
themselves, thinking that this would be an indispensable step if, one day, a theory of scientific
change and epistemological causality was to be constructed. (OT, xiii)
139
description which ensured that temporal change be regarded as belonging to
the realm of appearance and illusion. Despite its all encompassing nature,
From the beginning this thesis has viewed the Kantian and capitalist
though they are successful in transforming the nature of time both leave the
make the connection between Kant and capitalism, and thus develop a
reformulation - not only of our conception of time - but also of that which
work which - taken together - enable them to explain how cultural and
of idealist thought.
140
philosophy to call for a revolution 'this time materialist' which is aimed at
the synthetic processes of the transcendental. Yet, this time, the revolution
work dissolves the rigid distinction between matter and thought and is thus
to
events on a single plane. 5
141
2. A philosophy of time that replaces the notion of eternity with the
concept of Aeon.
revolution is a redefinition of time. This section will show that Capitalism and
one, and in the doctrine of the thing-in-itself it mirrors the classical conception
occurs in time and the production of time itself. These singularities - or Aeonic
occurrences - are not above, beyond, or segregated over and against time
but are rather flat with the production of time and constitute its immanent
142
Outside.
Through the concept of Aeon, they uncover the possibility of events that do
not break into time from a transcendent beyond, as is the case with eternity,
143
3.1 Transcendental Materialism: Capitalism & Schizophrenia's Critique
of Kant
familiar of these, the one that seems most common or easy to perceive, they
name the plane of organization and development. On this plane the world is
their substance and form. This is why the plane of organization has more in
common with an overall plan (the plan of divine creation) than it does with the
stratification (always placing one level on top of the other in accordance with
3
a strict code). Unable to account for its own immanent production, this
' These two planes are not dialectically opposed as thesis is to antithesis both because the
two planes are simultaneously and continuously under production and also because there is
always a series of complex passages between them. As Deleuze and Guattari write, "why
does the opposition between two kinds of planes lead to a still more abstract hypothesis?
Because one continuously passes from one to the other, by unnoticeable degrees and without
being aware of it, or one becomes aware of it only afterwards. ' (ATP, 269)
2 As Brian Massumi, the translator of A Thousand Plateaus points out, in french 'the word plan
designates both a 'plane' in the geometrical sense and a 'plan! (ATP, xviii)
144
1)." (ATP, 265) This is why, for Deleuze and Guattari, the strata are
conception of the plane. " (ATP, 266) Here, things escape the form,
Spinozistic conception of the plane4 in which bodies are defined by the power
communication and connectivity. In this way, it has more in common with the
heterogeneous multiplicity of the rhizome than with the organized unity of the
tree. 5 Like a rhizome, it is flat in that it spreads vertically rather than through
nothing above or beyond itself to act as the agent of its own production. As
Deleuze and Guattari write, "however many dimensions it may have, [the
145
transpires upon it." (ATP, 266) It is thus necessarily a force of destratification.
by the fact that without this as a reference point their take up of Kant can
often appear contradictory and confused. For it is never quite certain whether
Capitalism and Schizophrenia which seems to have more in common with the
Guattari emphasize rhythm and style? just as much as logical argument, and
work by extracting the refrains they can use rather than through the adoption
6It is in a text entitled 'To Be Done with the Judgments of God' where Antonin Artaud first
creates the concept of a 'body without organs'. 'Man is sick because he is badly constructed.
We must decide to strip him in order to scratch out this animalcule which makes him itch to
death, god, and with god his organs. For tie me down if you want to, but there is nothing more
useless than an organ. When you have given him a body without organs then you will have
delivered him from his automatisms and restored him his true liberty. "To be Done with the
Judgments of God' in Antonin Artaud. Four Texts, trans. Clayton Eshelman and Norman
Glass. Los Angeles: Panjandrum Books, 1982
8As Foucault writes in the introduction to Anti-Oedipus, "it would be a mistake to read Anti-
Oedipus as the new theoretical reference (you know that much-heralded theory that finally
146
sampling of Kant is subject to the most rigorous criteria. Their aim - as stated
will see, it is this method itself which insists that the realm of the
transcendental be liberated from the structure and plan of the organism and
Deleuze and Guattari advise, 9 and attempt to enumerate the various features
transcendental philosophy" with "a complete architectonic plan. " (CPR, 60)
"In this inquiry," writes Kant, "I have made completeness my chief aim, and I
venture to assert that there is not a single metaphysical problem which has
not been solved, or for the solution of which the key at least has not been
supplied. " (CPR, 10) So certain is he that nothing has escaped his all
inclusive structure, that Kant maintains the Critique "leaves no task for its
9'It is through a meticulous relation to the strata that one succeeds in freeing lines of flight. '
(ATP, 161)
147
successors save that of adapting it in a didactic manner according to their
own preferences, without being able add anything whatsoever to its content".
(CPR, 13-14)
belief in the systematic unity of critique. For Kant, the art of constructing
systems consists in the ability to unite the manifold of knowledge under one
idea. Ordered by this single identity, the system is likened to an animal body
which even as an embryo, contains all its parts within the whole. Conceived of
and should evolve like any other organism, "growing from within, and not by
concepts with intuition, and ensure that all our experiences are our own. It is,
in short, both the cause and creator of a priori synthesis and as such forms
148
only when thought of as an epistemological representation that the synthetic
structure, imposed on the world through the interiority of the knowing mind
that this isomorphy necessarily exists. As Kant writes, "the order and
nature itself that is ordered in this way but only the representations of the
mind. " (CPR, 147) Composed on the plane of organization, then, Kantian
philosophy is less concerned with what the world is really like than with how
that the Kantian system makes way for the judgments of God. Critique had
beyond this "land of truth" is a "wide and stormy sea. " (CPR, 257) Restricted
cannot help but to point to a realm beyond its borders. Kant names this the
thing-in itself and seeks to banish it from his system by insisting that because
philosophy. 10
Yet, with the distinction between what we know and the thing-in-itself,
149
Kant aligns himself with his classical predecessors. "Limiting all that
we can
theoretically know to mere appearances" (CPR, 29) he divides the world
for the idealism of Kantian thought, and is also what allows for an element of
doctrine of the thing-in-itself the synthetic structures of the I think are haunted
seeks to limit reason but only in order to leave room for faith.
With its systematic unity, its strengthening of the subject, and its faith
exactitude to the stratified conception of the plane. Surely even God could not
organizing structure or a more stringent desire for unity. Yet, nonetheless, the
Kantian system too is composed of lines of flight. For despite the apparent
away from the form of the organism and the hierarchical structure of the plan.
150
and more as a systematic method. From this point of view, the critical project
turns away from its organization and development and aims instead to
on the practice of critique. "Our age", writes Kant "is, in especial degree, the
age of criticism, and to criticism everything must submit. " (CPR, 9) What is
nothing be granted that can not "sustain the test of free and open
revolution in that it is based on the practice of critique. Like Kant, Deleuze and
Guattari adopt the critical method in order to rid thought of the illusion of
immanent criteria. In this way - though it is far from the didactic analyses Kant
11This is why the French Revolution is often seen as the political equivalent to Kant's
philosophical revolution. See, for example, Heine's Religion and Philosophy in Germany p.
151
expected from his successors - Capitalism and Schizophrenia is a strictly
Kantian text. It soon becomes clear, however, that to follow through with the
critical method so that the thought of the transcendental can reach the plane
The time has come for the Kantian system itself to submit to critique.
principles, not by adding anything new to the system but rather through a
process of subtraction. Yet, though they use nothing but this simple arithmetic
effect. For what Deleuze and Guattari subtract is the identity and unity of the
architectonic plan.
project itself which requires that the system be dismantled in this way. For the
notion that the transcendental plane can be united under one idea is,
to that of the system considered. " (ATP, 8) Thus, unity must be subtracted
108
152
flattened onto an immanent plane.
priori are processes which occur inside the mind, Kant positions the subject,
seen. For according to Deleuze and Guattari, the subject is "the locus of an
illusion. ' (SPP, 19) Though it is merely a peripheral side effect of more
production "which now seem to emanate from it as a quasi-cause. " (AO, 10)
is a betrayal of the critical project. For the Kantian contention that we only
synthesis of reason. In this way Deleuze and Guattari's critique of the subject
12In Anti-Oedipus Deleuze and Guattari speak of the body of capital in the same way it falls
back on all production, constituting a surface over which the forces and agents of production
are distributed, thereby appropriating for itself all surplus production and arrogating to itself
both the whole and the parts of the process, which now seem to emanate from it as a quasi-
cause. Forces and agents come to represent a miraculous form of its own power they appear
to be `miraculated" by it. (AO, 10)
153
Spinozistic lens, Deleuze and Guattari release transcendental production
individual transcendental field" (LS, 102) they strip the Kantian system from
the "error of idealism" and detach the synthetic a priori from their
containment inside the mind. Capitalism and Schizophrenia thus treats the
synthesis of the first Critique not as the operations of conscious reasoning but
represent the real but operate instead as the abstract forces which constructs
14
it.
and Guattari, then, Kant's claim that his work is derived from the a priori
12In Anti-Oedipus Deleuze and Guattari describe the unconscious as a factory, a workshop.
(AO, 55) 'For the unconscious itself is no more structural than personal, it does not symbolize
any more than it imagines or represents; it engineers, it is machinic. Neither imaginary nor
symbolic, it is the Real in itself, the 'impossible real' and its production. (AO, 53)
13This is why the question posed by Capitalism and Schizophrenia is not'What does it
mean? ' but rather, 'How does it work? '
154
discovered when he gained access to the realm of the transcendental was not
common plane (what Deleuze and Guattari, following Artaud will call the body
without organs).
more, to quote Deleuze, as "the analogue of a great explorer. " (DR, 135)
Seen from this perspective, the Kantian texts cease to be the colorless
accounts from the law courts of reason and become instead the record of a
'stationary voyage' which unlocks realms beneath and between the empirical
less real for being abstract. In the Kantian system it is this transcendental
That Deleuze and Guattari have followed Kant on this voyage, and are
ones not figurative ones: machines driving other machines, machines being
155
To see the world in terms of a machinic production is not - as it may
Guattari replace the Kantian emphasis on the unity of the subject and its
ability to connect things together or drive things apart. They thus push
by transforming the Kantian plan onto a flat, intensive and immanent plane.
156
3.2 From Eternity to Aeon
From the point of view of the philosophy of time, Deleuze and Guattari
depart from Kant not so much by questioning his account of time but rather
through a critique of his notion of eternity. This critique - as we will see - involves
the revolutionary nature of Kantian thought, his notion of eternity varies little from
the view of the eternal developed in the western classical tradition. With Deleuze
different. Rather than an idealist construction (which it is for both Kant and Plato)
Deleuze and Guattari develop an account of the eternal which is fully materialist
discovery is of such importance that just as it has been said of Kant that "all the
discovery of an entirely new conception of time, " (KST 1) so too can it be said of
Deleuze and Guattari that all of their creations and novelties rest on an entirely
property of the intuition of time. According to Kant, time as intuition (or the form
157
of inner sense) is best thought of as an extensive arithmetic sequence whose
directions. Thus, in this first instance, it is the infinitude of time which constitutes
eternity.
unity of apperception. For it is the unity of this subject which ensures that the
everlasting series of time be brought under a single identity. United in this way,
the eternal, in this second case, is constructed as the whole of time conceived of
as one.
the doctrine of the thing-in-itself. Here, the eternal is evoked in opposition to the
fundamentally from all three of these aspects of the Kantian system. First of all,
because the kind of infinity which is aligned with the transcendental materialist
notion of eternity is not the extensive infinity of an everlasting series but rather
1To quote from the first critique: We represent the time-sequence by a line progressing to
158
continuum involves the whole of time, this is not because it is united under a
single subject. Instead, for Deleuze and Guattari the eternal is the mode of time
unchanging identity. Finally, though the intensive time of the plane of consistency
will see, eternity, for Deleuze and Guattari, is a body which constructs an
immanent outside.
What is this time which need not be infinite but only "infinitely
subdivisible?" It is the Aeon.
Deleuze, Logic of Sense, p. 61
magnitude is one whose parts are apprehended successively. That is to say, the
pure intuitions (space and time) are extensive in that they order the manifold of
things into parts and then gathering those parts into a whole. Thus, according to
infinity and we reason from the properties of this line to all the properties of time."(CPR, 77)
...
159
transcendental philosophy, to perceive something in space and time is to
synthesis of part to part in (the process of) its apprehension can it come to be
In the work of Deleuze and Guattari the Greek god Chronos provides the
moment to another" (CPR, 198) It marks the linear order of a purely metric time.
Composed entirely of "interlocking presents" (LS, 61) which follow one another
cardinal beats, which serve to enclose the multiplicity of the world in between its
Yet, as even Kant himself is aware, our perception of the world is not
section of the first Critique entitled the 'Anticipation of Perception' Kant makes
clear that there is something other than intuition that is at work in the
construction of appearances. Since space and time are never perceived directly
Kant calls the "matter of an object in general", the "real of sensation" or "realitas
160
phaenomenon" (CPR, 201) and insists that instead of extensive magnitudes it is
201)
perhaps most obvious in our perception of space since the same extensive
space can be filled with varying degrees of intensities. To quote from a lecture by
Deleuze, "the same space can be filled by a more or less intense red, the same
room can be filled with a more or less intense heat, the same volume can be
Deleuze and Guattari name this intensive time Aeon and throughout their work
uses to replace the classical disjunction between the appearance of time and the
essence of eternity.
through successive synthesis. Rather than "proceeding from parts to the whole"
161
(CPR, 203) intensities are instead apprehended in a single instant. To quote
Deleuze:
homogenous units. Rather than a temporal succession which unites the manifold
their elements changing in nature. " (ATP, 31) They thus create a diagonal line
which bypasses the stratic distinctions between constant and variable, quantity
and quality and produce a time of continuous variation whose elements can not
162
others, each of which marks a change in nature. (ATP 30-31)
Aeon does not share the infinity of Chronos. Yet, nonetheless, there is an Aeonic
infinity that is greater than the whole of Chronic time. This is because the instant
we have seen, to say that intensities are apprehended instantaneously does not
are composed of intensive rather than extensive parts. They divide, but only into
diminish to nothing (the void) through infinite gradations. " (CPR, 206) Thus the
"infinite subdivision of the abstract moment. (LS, 77) This occurs through a
and lesser rather than cardinal units. Thus, while extensive magnitudes are
-
cessation ('0'), towards which each "can diminish in its degree in infinitum. "
163
differences - or irreducible distances - from degree-zero. It is this virtual
continuum, immanent within each instant, that constitutes the infinity of Aeon. 2
As has already been noted, the infinity of extensive time is not the only
way in which the concept of eternity operates in the Kantian system. In fact, from
the point of view of the classical tradition, the infinitude of the 'Transcendental
Aesthetic' has more in common with the everlasting than it does with the eternal.
insisting that the intuition of time be united by the transcendental subject,3 Kant
conceived of as one.
2 This difference between the infinite series of Chronos and the infinitely subdivisible Aeon can
perhaps best be understood through the work of Georg Cantor, a 19th century mathematician
who specialized in the problem of infinity. Cantor's work shows that there are different types of
infinity. The first - and smallest kind - corresponds to Chronos in that it is characterized by any
number line extending infinitely in both directions. Cantor called this a 'countable infinity' or Aleph
null. Cantor realized, however, that there are infinitely more numbers in between two points on a
number line, if one includes the irrationals, then the infinite set of whole numbers. In other words,
there is an infinity greater than Aleph null which exists between any two points on the number line.
Cantor called this greater infinity C for continuum. It is continuum that corresponds to the intensive
infinity of Aeon.
3'There can be in us no modes of knowledge, no connection or unity of one mode of knowledge
with another, without that unity of consciousness which precedes all data of intuitions, and by
relation to which representation of objects is alone possible."(CPR, 136)
164
According to the Kantian system it is a necessary and universal principle
that the everlasting series of time belongs under the transcendental unity of
apperception. This is a result of the fact that for Kant, time is ultimately nothing
transcendentally ideal. "(CPR, 78) That it is to say "when abstracted from its
defined as nothing other than the constant synthesis of time. For despite the fact
one. (CPR, 136) For Kant then, the I is an empty slot - defined as nothing other
than its ability to remain the same. Conceived of in this manner, the subject - as
has already been noted - becomes inextricably bound to the production of time.
First, because it is only time (which functions both as the form of inner sense and
as the secret of the schematism) which is abstract enough to organize and unite
from Deleuze "I is an act which constantly carries out the synthesis of time. "
165
(KCP, viii)
time. It is this unity of time which ensures that the multiplicity of the
itself.
the point of view of critical thought. This is not to say that the production of unity
is not materially instantiated.; The power of the strata is real. Rather, it is to claim
that the unity of the transcendental subject, which Kant considers a necessary
then, the unified subject is a stratified mode of individuation which does not
Deleuze and Guattari's critique of unity has important implications for the
166
according to Deleuze and Guattari, the notion of a subject who unites the whole
of time under a single identity is not eternally given but is rather produced on the
extensive plane of Chronic time. "Chronos, " they write, is "the time of measure
that situates things and persons, develops a form, and determines a subject. "
(ATP, 262) Thus, rather than emanating from a presupposed identity, for
subjects and structure their formations. Always at work dividing things into parts
and arranging those parts into wholes Chronos, as the time proper to the plane
into parts, it cannot be unified into wholes. Thus as the time of immanence or
Aeon operates with a mode of individuation that has nothing to do with unified
167
Instead of being determined by the higher unity of subjects or things,
singularity has more in common with the destratified nature of Spinozistic modes
than it does with the structure and form of identity. In Aeon, writes Deleuze and
axis of this composition - the longitude and lattitude of the plane. Drawing on
Spinoza, they discover that these two axis can be characterized first by relations
the corresponding capacity for affecting and being affected (latitude). (ATP, 507)
axis which define the individuality of a body on the immanent plane of Aeon. 4
Spinozistic sense are not individuals that remain consistent throughout time.
Rather they are events or Aeonic occurrences that are themselves immanent to
the very nature of time. They are becomings not beings. Comprised of
4 In short, if we are Spinozists we will not define a thing by its form, nor by its organs and its
functions, nor as a substance or a subject. Borrowing terms from the Middle Ages, or from
geography we will define it as a longitude or latitude....The longitudes and latitudes together
constitute Nature, the plane of immanence or consistency, which is always variable and is
168
changing in nature, these events are in a process of "continuous variations,
which go beyond constants and variables. They are becomings which have
These becomings or intensive events are eternal in the sense that they
involve the whole of time, not by uniting it under a single identity but rather by
flat multiplicities composed on a single undivided plane, intensities fill the whole
between the constant structure of time and the changes which occur inside it.
from that which it gives rise. Aeonic events do not occur in time, not because
they belong to a transcendent outside but because they are flat with the single
plane of immanence which collapses the distinction between time and that which
populates it. Equally immanent within any given moment of Chronos, in Aeon
that is incommensurable to the order of Chronos they cannot help but scramble
constantly being altered, composed or recomposed, by individuals and collectivities. (SPP, 128)
5 For a good pulp fiction account of Aeon see Stephen King's book The Shining which is based
on
Jack Torrence's encounters with the Aeonic singularities that haunt the Overlook Hotel. King,
Stephen. The Shining New York: Doubleday, 1993.
169
The identity of Chronos knows the world as a perpetual present. For
though the plane of organization segments time into past, present and future,
nevertheless "in accordance with Chronos, only the present exists in time. " (LS,
162) Past, present and future are known only as the present that has been, the
present that is and the present that will be. As Schopenhauer says "No man has
lived in the past and none will ever live in the future, the present alone is the form
other hand, "forever sidesteps the present. " (LS, 77) Enveloping the whole of
time without unifying it, Aeon is, "already past and yet in the future, at once more
and less, always the day before and the day after"6 (LS 77) As the "indefinite
Chronic time.
space, time, causality belong not to the thing-in-itself but only to the
6'Aeon: the indefinite time of the event, the floating line that knows only speeds and continually
divides that which transpires into an already-there that is at the same time not-yet-here, a
simultaneous too-late and too-early, a something that is both going to happen and has just
happened.' (ATP, 262)
170
phenomenon, that they are only the forms of our knowledge, not qualities of the
thing-in-itself, which constitutes the idealism of Kantian thought. It is also, for this
reason, the element of the Kantian system which comes closest to the notion of
the world that we know and the thing-in-itself, Kant reproduces the classical
eternity. For, implied in the doctrine of the thing-in-itself is that beyond the
structures of the knowing subject, outside the representation of the mind, and
exterior to the world of phenomena, is another hidden plane of which time is not
a part.
of critique. It thus operates in the Kantian system as the relic of an older tradition
contradicts the explicit aims of the critical project, Kant attempts to banish all
questions pertaining to the thing-in-itself by insisting that they are beyond the
7 To quote Schopenhauer "Whatever the thing-in-itself may be, Kant rightly concluded that time,
space, causality...could not be its properties, but could come to it only after, and in so far as, it has
become representation." (WWR1,120)
171
scope of transcendental thought. Yet, from the point of view of the philosophy of
time it is already too late. Kantianism has collapsed into a Platonic vision in
which time is seen as a trap or enclosure, and eternity its transcendent outside.
starkly apparent. For as should now be clear, Deleuze and Guattari replace the
opposition between our capture in the phenomenon of time and the exterior
essence of the eternal with two different planes of production, governed by two
which produces the interiority of time, and the immanence of Aeon which is its
outside. 8
the Kantian theory of intensities. The reason they give so much weight to this
8 In this sense the difference between Aeon and Chronos corresponds to the Kantian distinction
between the transcendental production of time and the empirical changes in time. Aeon, however,
can only be equated with transcendental time if the transcendental is conceived in the terms set
out by Deleuze and Guattari's materialist revolution. For Aeon, as we will see, corresponds to the
172
sensation' intensive quantities are directly effective, not representational. As
even Kant himself writes, they have a direct "degree of influence on the
senses. " (CPR, 202) A production of the real that stems neither from concepts
nor from the forms of our perception, intensities are what is left when intuition
absolute reality of the thing-in-itself. Deleuze and Guattari call this abstraction
The BwO causes intensities to pass; it produces them and distributes them
in a spatium that is itself intensive, lacking extension. It is not space, nor is it
in space; it is matter that occupies space to a given degree-to the degree
corresponding to the intensities produced. It is nonstratified, unformed,
intense matter, the matrix of intensity, intensity V; but there is nothing
negative about that zero, there is no negative or opposite intensities. Matter
equals energy. Production of the real as an intensive magnitude starting at
zero... (ATP 153)
As Deleuze and Guattari write: You never reach the Body without Organs, you can't reach it, you
173
Since an intensity is nothing but a virtual descent to zero - which
instantiates the distance, difference, or degree which it is - the zero degree body
circuit of production which accounts for both the exteriority and immanence of
the BwO. Intensities make their own plane, which nevertheless intrinsically
exceeds them, and since this plane is untranscended it can be subject to a time
The preceding pages have sought to show that despite the revolutionary
retains the classical notion of eternity. For with Kant, just as with Plato, unity,
identity, being, and transcendence are all aligned with a conception of the eternal
is
which opposed to the phenomenon of time.
With the concept of Aeon, Deleuze and Guattari overturn this classical
understanding of the It
eternal. would be wrong, however, to assume that in
174
ridding the transcendental of its classical ties to eternity, Deleuze and Guattari
demons, sorcerers, werewolves, and traffic with the other side. Rather than a
sad and disillusioned atheism which would discard the eternal archetype in order
to insist that only time exists and there is no outside, Deleuze and Guattari
replace the classical disjunction of time versus eternity with "two readings of
time" - time as Aeon and time as Chronos. In substituting Aeon for eternity,
however, they discard the traditional associations of unity, being, and identity
which belong to a transcendent realm exterior to time and replace it with the
Yet though these two notions - Aeon and eternity - are in many ways
lamented our birth into the phenomenal world of restless matter and temporal
change. Entangled in the multiplicity of becoming the human soul is seen to have
been separated from its real eternal essence by the illusory movement of time.
Thus, the philosophical and religious quest is aimed at transcending the body
and matter, escaping the ever changing illusion of time, and reaching the truth of
eternity.
175
It is clear from their continuous refrain to treat theory as creation,
as assemblages that the work of Deleuze and Guattari is to be used and not
warns the reader that they will find neither a theory nor a philosophy in the pages
which follow. Instead, he writes, "I would say that Anti Oedipus (may the author
forgive me) is a book of ethics. " (AO, xiii) Like Spinoza's Ethics" then,
Foucault says, as a manual or guide to everyday life" (AO xiii)12 The aim of this
guide is to develop a set of practices which construct lines of flight that can
escape sequential order and the interiority of Chronos and make contact with the
13
outside, not so as to transcend matter into the world of spirit but rather to
access the destratified, unformed "Matter of the Plane" (ATP, 72), the body
" Spinoza's Ethics is a purely practical text in that its aim is to lay down concrete rules for freeing
oneself from 'sad passions' and to thereby map a path to an increase in power (or joyful
encounters). It is for this reason that Deleuze and Guattari's writings on Spinoza concentrate not
so much on the philosophical argument but rather on how one can 'live in a Spinozist manner."
(SPP, 123)
12On the same theme, Foucault writes: "I think Anti Oedipus can best be read as an art in the
sense that is conveyed by the term erotic art..." (AO-xii)
13 It is this accounts for the strong gothic component that runs through Capitalism and
Schizophrenia, a text that is teeming with references to secrets, sorcery, animal becomings,
werewolves, vampires, blind doubles, and Things from the 'Other Side'.
176
Chapter 4: The Aeonic Occurence
And believe me, friend Infernal racket! The greatest events they are not our
-
noisiest but our stillest hours.
Friedrich Nietzsche, Thus Spoke Zarathustra, p. 153
In the biblical tradition eternity comes at the beginning and the end of
history. The ongoing passage of time is thus framed, on one side, by the
the Book of Revelations "I am Alpha and Omega, the beginning and the ending,
the first and the last.' (Rev 22: 13) Between these twin limits of time, the eternal
interrupts the order of time through miracles and divine revelation. In the popular
religious understanding of the West these punctual moments have long since
ceased. The world now waits for the eternal in the form of the apocalypse, which
'
will bring about the end of time. Though most people leave the anticipation of
such a moment to fanatic cults and fiction, at the end of the second millennium a
End of time apocalyptic scenarios which feed the current cultural imagination include: nuclear
war, ecological collapse, asteroid impact, alien invasion, and nanotech or genetically engineered
177
temporal event, brought on by a computer bug known as Y2K, brought the
As is now well known, when understood technically Y2K stems from the
fact that until only recently computers were programmed to read only
the last two digits of the year -assuming the prefix 19. This programming
convention dates back to the early days of the computer industry when memory
2
was scarce and expensive and each line of code was a precious resource. At
that time a space saving protocol called for dates to be recorded with 6 digits
register the year 2000. Instead of treating the stroke of midnight December 31
clocks to return to year zero (99 +1' 00). Incapable of recognizing the
difference between the year 1900 and the year 20003 cyberspace needed to be
3 Since 19 is the systems cipher the year 00 is treated as 1900 and not 2000.
178
Though no one could predict the exact consequences if this "glitch" was
not dealt with in time, the fact that it was deeply embedded in a globalized
years, Y2K was the cause of widespread concern - even panic. The ubiquity of
existing code) resulted in the fact that the target area of Y2K was practically
unlimited. As zero hour approached, it became clear that the vulnerable areas
lines.4 At its most extreme this two digit error in programming code threatened to
shut down planetary networks, erase large chunks of data and severely disrupt
The fact that this threat coincided with the dawn of a new millennium led
4 In the final stage of panic concern extended to embedded chips, which control everything from
microwaves to elevators.
which Y2K ceased to be a mere programming error and became instead the
technical mechanism which would bring about the biblical Armageddon. Thus,
rather than a simple glitch which would occur within the evolutionary structure of
history, Y2K came to be associated with catastrophic empirical events that would
signal history's very ends On the intemet Y2K was designated by another
acronymic term that could capture this apocalyptic aspect of the millennium. The
end of the twentieth century was renamed TEOTWOKI (or the end of the world
as we know it).
made its way across the time-zones. Yet, no matter where, when it was midnight
gestures and elaborate firework displays, celebrations heralding the arrival of the
Yes, yes - 2000 times yes! The Economist Oct 4th-10th 1997
6 Everyone is by now familiar with the most apocalyptic scenarios which included nuclear
accidents, plane crashes, major disturbances in communication and transportation lines,
shortages of food and other basic resources. These various disasters - so the story went - would
result in spirals of panic which would feed on themselves, leading to riots, martial law and general
social collapse. However farfetched, this basic narrative incited an expansion of survivalist
movements, especially in America, where many have people sold their homes in the cities and
moved to the hills with a stockpile of food, fire wood and weapons.
180
anticipated date in history was a non-event. In the days and weeks that followed
7
a sense of almost euphoric relief was mixed with a strange anger, even
contempt. Y2K, (or `apocalypse not') is now believed to have been nothing but a
serves to connect this singular temporal event with the philosophy of Deleuze
and Guattari. The fact that Y2K disappointed those awaiting an inauguration of
date. Though these dates correspond to singular events (e.g. the origin of the
state, the death of Genghis Khan etc.. ) they are not to be mistaken for punctual
moments. For Deleuze and Guattari, dates do not specify points in time but
rather tag plateaus. "A plateau, " they write, "is always in the middle not at the
beginning or the end." (ATP, 21) Defined as "self vibrating region of intensities
whose development avoids any orientation toward a culmination point" (ATP, 22)
Some maintain that the immediate post-millennium market drop was a result, not of scepticism,
but of an increasing faith, (the idea being that with nothing to stop it the economy would grow too
fast resulting in an increase of interest rates).
181
operate in an exterior relation to the linear sequence of Chronic time.
Like the plateaus singled out by Deleuze and Guattari, Y2K is dated in
-
its case precisely so - and yet, as the pervasive sense of anticlimax made clear,
question 'When did Y2K occur? ' is inevitably met with a certain degree of
unconscious origins and by the fact that it is unclear whether it ever existed as
anything other than hype. The question 'when did it happen? ' thus slides into
more nebulous questions such as `what happened? '10 or 'did it actually occur? '
8 "Bateson cites Balinese culture as an example [of plateaus]: mother-child sexual games, and
even quarrels among men, undergo this bizarre intensive stabilization. Some sort of continuing
plateau of intensity is substituted for [sexual] climax, , war, or a culmination point. It is a
regrettable characteristic of the Western mind to relate expressions and actions to exterior or
transcendent ends, instead of evaluating them on a plane of consistency on the basis of their
intrinsic valuation.' (ATP, 22)
9 The attempt to locate Y2K in time leads to a series of contradictory impulses. On the one hand, it
is tempting to argue that Y2K, as an event, took place - long before anyone was conscious of it -
in the early days of computing when the two digit dating convention was first introduced. At the
time, of course, no one was aware that this mundane bit of programming code would result in an
end of the millennium catastrophe. If given any thought at all it was assumed - in accordance with
the science fiction visions of the 1950's - that the computer systems that were then being
programmed - would no longer be in use by the year 2000. It is just as plausible, however, to date
Y2K to the more recent past - around the early 1990's - when the world began to awaken to the
problem this dating convention would pose for the millennium and financial institutions, military,
security and traffic control, and companies of various kinds began to realize that the problem had
to be fixed. Yet, another possibility is to claim that Y2K - as an event - took place in 1999 when
media coverage, panic intensity and apocalyptic hype was at its strongest. Finally, it may be the
case that Y2K will only make sense as a significant occurrence in the future when 21 Stcentury
historians use it as an index for changes that are still now unclear.
10Deleuze and Guattari write of the question 'what happened' in relation to the peculiar
temporality of the novella, suggesting that the question itself is an index of Aeonic events. See
'1874:Three Novellas, or What Happened?' in A Thousand Plateaus.
182
fact that -as we will later see is the name for a machinic multiplicity. As
-Y2K
waves of the capitalist economy. At the most extreme one could view Y2K as
temporality which exists outside the successive instants that constitute Chronic
time. Like every intensive singularity, Y2K occupies the whole of time to a greater
or lesser degree.
Y2K will never be anything other than a virtual catastrophe. Though it has
exteriority of Aeon.
11Y2K has obvious connections with Paul Virilio's theory of the accident. To quote Virilio: "For the
Philosopher, substance is absolute and necessary, whereas the accident is relative and
contingent. So the accident is what happens unexpectedly to the substance, the product of the
recently invented technical object-In fact, if no substance can exist in the absence of an accident,
then no technical object can be developed without in turn generating 'its' specific accident: ship'
shipwreck, plane' plane crash etc. The accident is thus the hidden face of technical and scientific
progress.' Paul Virillio. Politics of the Very Worst. New York: Semiotext(e), 1999 p. 92 The
argument of this chapter, namely that Y2K corresponds to the virtual time of Aeon rather than the
transcendence of eternity, is also in some ways convergent with Virilio's notion of the accident "as
an inverted miracle, a secular miracle, a revelation" (PVW, 90)
183
4.1 Time-Mutations
Throughout this thesis it has been argued that the modern conception of
and the historical variations which occur inside it. In previous social regimes,
when calendars were dominant and temporality was inseparable from the
movements of astronomy, this distinction did not exist, and time was itself
inherently connected with the qualitative changes now associated with history.
time from its age old subordination to movement. Unhinged from the cardinal
points which it had been so long destined to measure, time became autonomous
from the cyclical patterns of astronomy. There thus emerged a formal time
separate and distinct from the'historical content which happened to fill it.
new form of time. This temporal regime - or the capitalist production of time - can
184
Though sun dials, water clocks and hour glasses have been in use
throughout the long history of time-keeping' it was not until the modern period
that these devices gained any degree of technical or social autonomy. Previous
to this, the practice of time-keeping, like the philosophy of time, had been
on the calendar. Starting from as early as the 14th century, however, with the
ubiquity of the clock has ensured that clock time achieve a certain independence
order to tell the time, the division of the day into hours, minutes and seconds
must be synthesized with the days of the week and the months of the year. In
order to function time-keeping systems require both a beat and a count. Thus,
the ticking of the clock must be combined with the counting system prescribed by
the calendar.
purely arbitrary one. Capitalism requires only that the world agree on a
See Chapter2 'The Divisionof the Dayand Time-Keepingin Antiquity'in Historyof the Hour.
185
standardized convention. As a global system from the start ,2 capitalism operates
have seen, this regime was initially created through an international agreement
which divided the planet into a series of standardized time zones, placing the
Gregorian Calendar. With these two things in place capitalism was able to
synthesize the ever increasing precision of clocks with a unified dating system
across the planet, formal time is capable of being rigorously quantified. This
allows time (and in particular duration) to be directly converted into money. This
including, most famously, Weber's notion of the protestant ethic, and the labour
2 This claim is supported by the work of historian Fernand Braudel and by world system theory.
See in particular Braudel, Fernand. Civilization and Capitalism 15"' -181hcentury. London: Collins,
1981-1984, and the work of Immanuel Wallerstein.
186
economist Bohm-Bawerk, crucial to phenomena such as interest and credit, two
features that are essential to the capitalist economy and its mode of production.
These characteristic features of formal time are not static, but are rather
the result of an ongoing machinic process that produce the formalization of time.
In the capitalist regime it appears that this process (the machinic production of
instantiated by the digitization of both time and money that takes place in
cyberspace.
clocks and calendars in such a way that the length of calendric intervals are no
longer determined by the revolutions of the planets but are governed instead by
the ticking of the clock. Cut off from astronomical movements, calendars are a
pure counting convention that can be programmed into a digital system from the
start. With the digitization of time, clocks and calendars have thus become part
of the same technical machine. In cyberspace, the beat and the count, the two
187
thought to be spared) is evidence of the ever-increasing importance of the global
web makes the demand for a standardized time that accompanied previous
technological grids even more urgent. For cyberspace, like the capitalist system
never anything other than digital code - are continuously subjected to virtual
transactions that are sensitive to minute variations in time. As digital code, time
and money have converged on a single numerical and technical plane making
the conversion between the two ever more immediate and immanent.
All this is to say that the constitution of formal time is a continuing process
constructed in conjunction with its own historical development which it itself 'falls
back upon'. This history, however involves only a very limited conception of
upward curve of technological progress. The history of the clock, for example,
188
tells the story of an evolutionary growth that progresses from the mechanical
only occurs to heighten the accuracy and efficiency of the same basic device.4
Capitalism's construction of historical progress is much more than a
This is primarily due to the time-lag that is inherent in capitalist production. This
that capitalism treat history as a smooth upward curves6 For it is only with a story
4 This progressive history of technology has reached unprecedented heights with the development
of Information Technology. As everyone is all too aware, the cycles of obsolescence maintained
by the computer industry happen at an ever increasing speed. The trajectory of smaller and
smaller machines capable of processing more and more data for increasingly diminishing costs
seems itself to be continuously intensifying. For example, Moore's Law which states that
processing speeds will double every eighteenth months is itself now outdated.
5 That is to
say that the 'myth' of historical progress is not constructed in order to fool the masses
or as a mystification of underlying real value.
6 The most absurd
examples of the prevalent notion that as time passes things remain basically
the same were evident around the time of the millennium when newspapers and magazines were
filled with predictions of how are lives would be improved by a series of technical inventions
-
intelligent clothes, robotic vacuum cleaners etc - that would undoubtedly be in place for the year
189
such as this that the difference between the present and the future can remain
however, is that it hides the fact that capitalist history is discontinuous, based
capitalism, a sort of rule of the game, that it thrives on change, drawing strength
from it". (CC, 620) Capitalism, then, produces the appearance of a continuous
mutations. '
For Deleuze and Guattari social formations are defined not by modes of
production but by'machinic processes', (ATP, 435) and machines work, " they
write, "only by breaking down. "(AO, 8) Crises, ruptures, accidents and anxieties
are misunderstood when one regards them as threats. In order for a machine to
function "it must not function well". (AO, 151) Abandoning the rigid form of the
finely tuned, well oiled, mechanisms of a previous age, Deleuze and Guattari - as
3000. Surely Bill Joy, the CEO of Sun Microsystems is much closer to the mark when he wams of
the inevatibility of unpredictable mutations arising from a convergence of Artificial Intelligence,
nanotechnology and genetic engineering.
7 As Deleuze writes: 'Those
who continue to have recourse to History and protest against the
indetermination of a concept such as 'mutation' should bear in mind the perplexity of real
historians when they have to explain why capitalism arose at such a time and such a place when
so many factors could have made it equally possible at another time and place ."[F, 21]
190
we have seen - define machines through the principles of a post cybernetic
distinguished parts, cybernetic machines learn and adapt through their mistakes.
Feeding on their own misfirings, they "operate only by fits and starts, by grinding
intelligent social machine, has learnt this rule. As Deleuze and Guattari write,
"The more it breaks down, the more it schizophrenizes, the better it works, the
Yet these accidents, ruptures and mutations are more than just breaks in
the linear order of developmental history. For as we have seen in our discussion
of Foucault, real discontinuities are mutations not only in time but to time.
singular, ironic, and critical' version of "universal history" (AO, 140) in which the
great social formations - the primitive machine, the state, and capitalism itself -
do not evolve in time but coexist together as Aeonic virtualities. Each formation
191
8
strategies of anticipation and warding off. The linear narrative that bases itself
replaced with a story of flows and their blockages, convergent waves and
Plateaus:
Physics and biology present us with reverse causalities that are without
finality but testify nonetheless to an action of the future on the present, or
the present on the past, for example the convergent wave and the
anticipated potential, which imply an inversion of time. More than breaks
and zigzags, it is these reverse causalities that shatter evolution. (ATP,
431)
successively from one moment to the next. Yet this successive, extensive
'In a sense,' write Deleuze and Guattari, capitalism has haunted all forms of society, but it
haunts them as their terrifying nightmare, it is the dread they feel of a flow that would elude their
codes.' (ATP, 431)
9According to Deleuze
and Guattari, 'history is always written from the sedentary point of view
and in the name of a unitary State apparatus... ' (ATP. 23) In A Thousand Plateaus they oppose
this state centred narrative to a'nomadology, the opposite of a history. " (ATP, 23) Though this
topic relates to many of the themes of the thesis it is far too complex to be dealt with in detail here.
For a complete discussion see '1227: Treatise on Nomadology: -The War Machine' and '7000 BC:
Apparatus of Capture' in A Thousand Plateaus.
192
developmental structure of history, then, like the plane to which it belongs,
system in extension is bom of the intensive conditions that make it possible, but
it reacts on them, cancels them, represses them, and allows them no more than
generated through the capture of Aeon. "All history does", they write, Is to
Nietzsche called "the vaporous region of the unhistorical" (UM, 63) - constitute,
events that populate, and mutually draw the plane of consistency. It is on this
plane - however suppressed - that histories take place and extend themselves.
History is made only by those who oppose history (not by those who insert
themselves into it, or even reshape it)... The dividing line passes not
between history and memory but between punctual 'history-memory'
193
systems and diagonal or multilinear assemblages, which are in no way
eternal; they have to do with becoming; they are a bit of becoming in the
pure state; they are transhistorical. There is no act of creation that is not
transhistorical and does not come up from behind or proceed by way of a
liberated line. Nietzsche opposes history not to the eternal but to the
subhistorical or superhistorical; The Untimely which is another word for
haecceity, becoming, the innocence of becoming (in other words, forgetting
as opposed to memory, geography as opposed to history, the map as
opposed to the tracing, the rhizome as opposed to arborescence). "The
unhistorical is like an atmosphere within which alone life can germinate
and with the destruction of which it must vanish... What deed would man be
capable of if he had not first that vaporous region of the unhistorical? "
Creations are like mutant abstract lines that have detached themselves
from the task of representing the world, precisely because they assemble a
new type of reality that history can only recontain or relocate in punctual
systems ... (ATP, 296)
time, it was necessary to present Y2K not as a mutation but rather as a glitch, an
error, an accident, a bug. In the post-millennial period even this has been
questioned. Yet, while history may remember Y2K as nothing but an over hyped
mistake, on the plane that underlies history Y2K has always been much more.
break was itself a temporal event made even more powerful by the fact that
Deleuze and Guattari evoke, it operated on the virtual plane that haunts history,
empirically realized as a future that acts on the present and a present that acts
on the past.
194
In so far as it was ever present, Y2K manifested itself most strongly in the
years and months leading up to the millennium. Yet even at that time, Y2K was
-
at least when understood abstractly - primarily a challenge to the past. An act of
time. Yet, though it contested the past, it functioned most effectively when it was
by the dominance of a particular region, culture or ideology but rather by the fact
that is enveloped under a single and standardized time. This global temporal
standard is, as we have seen, a synthesis between clock time and the world-
10 Put most
simply, the problem with Y2K was that it threatened to replace the year 2000AD with
the year 00. This threat, though ultimately unrealized, was an unprecedented challenge to the
authority of the Gregorian calendar. For, as year 00, Y2K indexes the fact that cyberspace, rather
than reinforcing the temporal regime of modem capitalism, had surreptitiously installed a calendar
of its own. Thus, while human culture and nation states had all agreed on the Gregorian calendar
as a secular convention, until it was'fixed' cyberspace had not. It is the discrepancy between
cyberspace's own calendar and the calendar developed by Pope Gregory XIII reforms that is
signaled by the sign Y2K. From the point of view of a radical calendrics, then, the attempt to
achieve 'millennium compliance' was not merely the reversal of a technical glitch but a geo-
political strategy aimed at the imposition of the Gregorian calendar on cyberspace. Fixing' Y2K
required the abandonment of an existing calendar, one that had worked successfully around the
globe for half a century.
195
operating - however imperceptibly - with a calendar which challenged this
parodied in Conrad's Secret Agent. A timer so perfected that the timer is the
bomb, it operates as if aware that the vulnerability of the system comes from its
- Y2K not only exemplified an effect of the present upon the past, but also -
and even more starkly - an operation of the future on the present. This is most
evident in the instability it introduces into the equation of time and money, an
equation `time = money' is inevitably associated with duration. The cost of Y2K,
however, was only indirectly determined by how long it would take to fix. For the
measured against the potential cost which would result from an error or
discrepancy in the semiotic system which marks the date. By revealing that a
time-keeping practices are regularly converted into the Gregorian count. In this way the production
of capitalist time concretely implements the Kantian assertion that *different times are but parts of
one and the same time" (CPR, 75)
196
date - even as a virtuality - has immense economic consequences Y2K indexes
something that is apparently new in the economy of formal time. For what is
crucial in the convergence of time and money on the digital plane is not only the
Thus, far from operating as a transcendent grid, Y2K makes clear that the
As early as 1997 it was clear that Y2K was going to be "the single most
expensive accident of all time. " 12irrespective of what did or did not occur on
midnight December 31 1999. What makes this so critical for the abstract
production of capitalist time is not only how much money was spent but the fact
that it was spent on 'fixing' the date. For in introducing the date as an accident -
or positive force - in the capitalist production of time Y2K constitutes itself, not
197
4.2 Dates and the Semiotic of Aeon
tight mesh between calendric convention and cultural tradition. Far from a
why they have been traditionally managed by the priests and by the guardians
of the state. For unlike clock time, all the elements of calendrics - the type of
numeracy involved, the length and structure of the cyclical patterns, the
which are ritualized and the determination of when to start the count -
religion to claim the date 2000AD as their own. Yet, though this attempt was
confusions. For though it is true that Pope Gregory's reforms emerged from
of December 31st 1999 does not coincide with any particular festival, has no
specific commemorative relevance and does not (as Gregorian year MM)
1This is evident, for example, by the case of the religious section in London's 'millennium
dome' which, though it was primarily funded by a Hindu family, nevertheless took pains to
emphasize the Christian religion.
198
fuse the end of the twentieth century with Christianity involved as we have
-
seen - treating Y2K as the mechanism through which the prophecies foretold
This latter signifies an eternal battle at the end of time when Satan is chained
and sealed in the Abyss and Christ is able to rule on earth for a period of a
thousand years. (Rev-XX). Needless to say, the idea that Y2K is the sign of
2000AD.
between religion and the date by insisting that the millennium was a
commemorative sign for Jesus 2000 year birthday. Though many people the
to
world over seemed accept this as a valid assertion it has no historical,
calendric or religious legitimacy. For even if one accepts the dubious claim
that Jesus birth coincides with the starting point of the Gregorian calendarz,
still the only defensible date for the two thousandth anniversary of Christ's
2There is a great deal of debate over the exact year of Jesus birth. The dates that are most
commonly accepted, however, is either. 04 B.C., or 12 B.C.
199
because they follow each other so closely in time. The Christian religion,
move to place January Ist as the first day of the year was amongst the
accuracy and precision of the Julian calendar. Yet these gains in accuracy
calendar, that New Years is a much more commemorative date since it falls
More serious, however than the confusion between New Years and
Christmas is that to celebrate the year 2000AD as the dawn of the second
function. Lacking a year zero, the Gregorian calendar moves directly from I
1st 2001 (MMI). The current system of dating which synthesizes the
is
Gregorian count with elements of decimal numeracy4 relatively recent. '
The decimal aspects of the contemporary use of the Gregorian calendar include the adoption
200
European culture and in particular the church was extremely resistant to
precision, accuracy and efficiency that they were finally, reluctantly, absorbed
by the western world. 6 More than anything else, it is this adoption of the
millennialist beliefs, between New Years Day and Christmas, and between
the Roman and Hindu-Arab number systems - suggest that the massive
investment in the millennium was more about the date as such than it was
about anything that the date was purportedly meant to represent. As Y2K
starkly dramatized, the sign 2000AD had much more to do with the techno-
social apparatus involved in the global standardization of time than it did with
All this is to say that what many believed to be a celebration of the date
as representative sign - in this case one that signals the apocalyptic end of
of the Hindu-Arab numerals, and the emphasis on decades, centuries and millennium.
5 The Arabs had introduced decimal numeracy to Europe as early as the ninth century. The
development of the Gregorian calendar, however, makes clear that up until as late as the
sixteenth century the church still preferred to use the - much less efficient - numeracy of
Rome. See The Universal History of Numbers p. 537-543
6 Ifrah writes how resistance to Hindu-Arab numeracy was based on a class dynamic. For the
'infinitely complicated use of the classical (Roman) counter abacus' (UHN, 577) allowed
knowledge of arithmetic to be confined to a privileged class who could afford the long and
intricate training necessary to master such a baroque numerical system. Faced with a number
system that could not fail to make arithmetic more democratic, the ruling classes derided it as
a diabolical heresy and refused to engage with it for centuries. See The Universal History of
Numbers pp 571- 581
7The threat of Y2K was completely indifferent to any specific cultural belief or time-keeping
practice. Any given nation or state could insist on their distance from the Gregorian calendar
but this made no impact on their immunity to the danger of Y2K. Cyberspace thus ensured
201
history - served to mask an unconscious cultural investment in the date as
number.
made clear, the libidinal energy that accompanied the millennium was
excitement, then, had less to do with the Gregorian calendar or the religious
events prescribed by the Christian tradition than it did with a decimal delirium
indifferent to creed. What was celebrated at 00hrs. 01/01/00 was the instant
Issue":
Many cultures celebrated despite the fact that most follow completely
different calendars, and despite the fact that too many people were
pointing out that the millennium doesn't really start until next year and
that our system is all messed up anyway, because Jesus was born
2,004 years ago. They celebrated because the most famous
odometer mankind has ever created was displaying three zeroes. It's
exciting enough when it happens to your own car; when it happens to
the world, it makes you downright giddy. (Time. January 1 2000, p 26)
singular occurrences are, for them, marked by a very specific use of signs.
Two of the most crucial components of this semiotic are the proper name and
the date. 8There is, of course an 'extensive usage' of names which belongs
202
to the plane of organization and development. On this plane, names function
(ATP, 27) On the plane of consistency, on the other hand, names function
temporality. Yet, as we have seen, this is only when they have already been
captured by Chronic time. In relation to Aeon, on the other hand, dates are
the intensive markers for threshold events or singular becomings, and thus do
intensity. 10
semiotic' 11that is at once both a proper name and a date. What this sign
6 The other components are the indefinite article and the infinitive verb. The latter is
particularly relevant because, as Deleuze and Guattari write, it "expresses the floating,
nonpulsed time proper to Aeon, in other words the time of the pure event or becoming, which
articulates relative speeds and slownesses independently of the chronometric or chronological
values that time assumes in the other modes. (ATP, 263)
9 'It is the military men and meteorologists, write Deleuze and Guattari, who hold the
secret
of proper names, when they give them to a strategic operation or a hurricane. The proper
name is not the subject of a tense but the agent of an infinitive. "(ATP, 264)
10In this way, they act as nomad numbers which populate a smooth space without dividing or
segmenting it.
11In the plateau'587 B.C. D. On Several Regime of Signs' Deleuze and Guattari speak
-A. of
the coutersignifying semiotic which `proceeds by arithmetic and numeration. " (ATP, 118) as
the semiotic system of the nomad war machine.
203
designates is an event that is neither technical nor culturalt2 but machinic.
Singular and immanent, virtual but not at all vague, abstract and creative,
here and now, real yet nonconcrete, actual yet noneffectuated, A (ATP, 511)
transformation and the effect the transformation produces; that is why [these
machines] are precisely dated, to the hour, minute, and second and take
effect the moment they are dated. (ATP, 81) "The abstract machine does not
function to represent, even something real, but rather constructs a real that is
not stand outside history but is instead always 'prior to' history. " (ATP, 142)
This is why - as Deleuze and Guattari write, - 'history will never be rid of
12Y2K has both a technical and cultural dimension in the sense that, on the one hand, it
concerned the incompatibility of calendric systems (a purely cultural concern), and, on the
other, a technical glitch in computing code. It is It is for this reason that Y2K should be
considered as a machinic syndrome, a term which is precisely meant to avoid the
segmentation between technical and cultural systems.
13Abstract, singular and creative, here and now, real yet nonconcrete, actual yet
noneffectuated -that is why abstract machines are dated and named (the Einstein abstract
machine, the Webern abstract machine, but also the Galileo, the Bach, or the Beethoven,
etc. ). Not that they refer to people or to effectuating moments; on the contrary it is the names
and dates that refer to the singularities of the machines and to what they effectuate (ATP, 511)
204
As an abstract machine, Y2K puts a (virtual) end to the arbitrariness of
date. 14 Y2K thus brings an end to the assumption that the numbers which
' It can be argued that the importance of Y2K stems from the fact that it indexes the 'year
zero' of cyberspace time (a claim whose legitimacy can only be tested in the future). It seems
plausible, however, that Y2K will be remembered as a time-marking index of this kind, both
because in the years leading up to the millennium when Y2K hype was at its strongest
- -
there was a huge expansion in the world -wide use of the Internet, and also because Y2K was
directly responsible in ensuring that billions of dollars were spent in the pre
-millennium years
to ensure that cyberspace - and in particular cyberspace time- was fully in order for the dawn
of the new millennium.
The most obvious characteristic of cyberspace time is its speed or miniaturization.
For just as the clock divides the day (the smallest unit of the calendric time) into hours,
minutes, and seconds, so the computer divides the second (the smallest unit measured by the
clock) into a series of gradations (the nano- second, the pico-second etc... ) that are - at least
potentially - infinitely subdivisible.
Yet, just as it would be a mistake to reduce the distinction between calendric-time and
clock-time to a difference in scale so too would it be inaccurate to presume that cyberspace
time is no different from clock-time with the exception of being more finely articulated. For, as
we have seen, on the intensive plane where time is produced changes in size do not occur
without simultaneous changes in nature.
It thus becomes possible to say, that Y2K inaugurated - what will later be seen - as a
fundamentally new regime in the production of time. However, as Foucault maintains, radical
discontinuities are necessary accompanied by a certain degree of blindness. For there is an
inevitable failure to see that which is conditioning one's own experience of the world. For this
reason it is unavoidable that a degree of uncertainty surround questions of what cyberspace
time is and what it will eventually become. Any outline of the contours of this new'postmodem'
time, however, must take into account following characteristics:
First, cyberspace time can no longer be considered in any way human. For not only
does it follow the clock in ceasing to measure 'natural' rhythms of the organisms, but it also
operates with speeds that are below the level of human perception. It is for this reason that
cyberspace time appears instantaneous.
Second, cyberspace time has less to do with a clockwork universe and more to do
with machines of simulation. (It is because of its power to simulate other devices that Turing
called the computer the 'universal machine'). This link between simulation and time has
already led to some surprising experimentation. For example, in the summer of 1999 a group
of international financial institutions simulated time-travel -a practice that until then existed only
in the realm of science fiction - in order to arrive in the future and ensure that their systems
were millennium compliant.
Third, since cyberspace is nonlocalizable, cyberspace time must be considered as
transglobal or. postglobal rather than as operating with a globalized standard which co-
ordinates various localities in space.
Fourth, cyberspace time constitutes an immanent machinic culture in which time
measures nothing outside its own inner workings. (Crucial to this is the correspondence
between processing speeds - measured in Hertz or cycles per second - and the ever-
205
mark the time are nothing but an empty representation. A statement no
different from its effect, Y2K marks a singular occurrence which operates on
time and the events which happen to fill it has been dissolved. No longer an
which eradicates the difference between quantity and quality, content and
206
PAGE
NUMBERING
AS ORIGINAL
S. Conclusion
on the convergence between, on the one hand, one of the most abstruse areas
abstraction which is drawn primarily from the work of Deleuze and Guattari. This
theory about matter but rather due to its practical or pragmatic orientation which
208
Kant's Critique of Pure Reason. It seeks to show how, through the discovery of
which is freed from its ties to variation and movement. Time thus becomes a
invention of the mechanical clock. It does this by mapping the Kantian notion of
formal time onto the quantitative and homogenous time of the clock, a time
opposition which results in each side seeking to envelop the other by way of its
own superior unity (which on one side is constituted by the transcendental unity
of the subject and on the other the unity of the historical process)'. Linking them
together, thus always seems to occur at the expense of one side or the other,
1 For Marx this unity culminates in the universality of proletarian class consciousness.
209
variation or vice versa).
revolution, which occurs not in time but to time. Thus, though they appear as
revolutions in history, they are not in themselves historical. For in altering time
itself, both have accessed an abstract realm which conditions experience, and
which impacts the smooth succession of history only from the outside. Thus, the
In the classical western tradition the only thing capable of changing the
very nature of time, was the exterior and transcendent power of the eternal.
changes in the nature of time - if they were ever possible - could only be
changes were a matter of faith not reason. For they occurred only as the
divine revelation.2
apocalyptic or miraculous events which accompany
transcendent impositions. Though they push aside any explicit engagement with
the question of eternity, they nevertheless reject this classical conception of the
2 In Christianity the intrusion of the eternal in history is ultimately realized through the incarnation
of Jesus, or the idea of the Word made flesh.
210
exteriority. Operating with consistent circuits of abstract and effective production
in transcendent creation.
variations which occur in time, neither Kant nor the social history of capitalist
time can provide the conceptual immanence which their principles require. In
retaining the notion that the interiority of temporal variation is constituted by the
intrinsic unity of a higher and more primary structure, they dismantle the
and that abstract synthesis are consistent with the multiplicity and becomings of
material innovation, they deny the very possibility of time mutation. Blind to the
implications of their own respective revolutions they thus conceal the intensive
3 Capitalism's tendency to monetarize power differentiates it from other social systems, in which
power is based primarily on coded and territorial structures of organization. According to Deleuze
and Guattari capitalism is defined by these processes of decoding and deterritorialization, and it is
this which is responsible for its great affinity with immanence.
4 As has already been noted, stratification acts as double pincer, operates through double
articulation, and constitutes the world through binary distinction. (See A Thousand Plateaus esp
p. 40)
211
plane on which time is immanently produced.
In order to uncover this plane, the thesis turns to the writings of Deleuze
and Guattari whose work Capitalism and Schizophrenia calls for a materialist
cease to locate these syntheses inside the mind of the knowing subject and see
them instead as the operations of abstract machines. Deleuze and Guattari thus
discover a plane of consistency on which the nature of time is flat with the
have seen, not only a reformulation of the nature of time but also of the relation
between time and eternity. To reach the plane of consistency the implicit faith in
outside. Deleuze and Guattari thus substitute the division between time and
eternity with the difference between two modes of temporality; the extensive time
of Chronos and the intensive time of Aeon. While Chronos corresponds to the
stratified nature of time (with its division between structure and change), the
multiplicities and singular events which do not differentiate between the abstract
212
production of time and material innovation (which is generally considered to
occur in time).
transcend, interrupt or break into time in the same way that eternity does.
Rather, as we have seen, it constitutes the virtual field upon which Chronos is
abstraction of Aeon can only be accessed through the singular events out of
which it is composed. The final chapter of this thesis thus explores the concept
of Aeon by focusing on one such singular event, the dawn of the third
socio-technical apparatus. This event has come to be known by the sign Y2K.
in
were reported - even such crucial areas as stock exchanges, transportation
networks, emergency services, and credit card companies - each of these was
easily dealt with on an individual basis and did not seem to add up to anything
significant (certainly it was nothing like the global catastrophe that was
213
very existence has been retrospectively called into question. After all, despite
months and even years of anticipation January 1st2000 seems to have been just
another day.
The real nature of Y2K still remains a puzzle. No one is sure whether the
hundreds of billions of dollars spent were wasted or whether they were crucial in
the prevention of a catastrophe. While some maintain that the risk was wildly
exaggerated, the few 'glitches' that did occur are sufficient to give evidence that
there was indeed a problem. Yet, the fact that countries which appeared to do so
little to fight the bug (i. e. Russia and China) encountered no more disturbances
than countries like United States and Britain which reacted early and poured
huge resources into ensuring 'millennium compliance' makes the conclusion that
the problem was fixed highly improbable. The alternative, however, that Y2K was
The confusion which - even now -surrounds Y2K is a result of the fact that
- though entirely real - it was an event that never seemed to actualize. Y2K was,
and always will be, a virtual catastrophe, a pure potentiality, a non-event. The
final chapter of this thesis argues that the virtual nature of Y2K - which allowed it
Chronos. Rather, Y2K is a sign - which operates as both a name and a date -
for an event composed on the intensive plane of Aeon. This, as we have seen is
214
its disorganization of linear succession, and its dissolution of such stratified
the distinction between time and the materiality of time-keeping systems. For this
reason, Y2K has been used as an exemplary event in addressing the central
was a crucial event in the history of capitalist time. For though it acted only as a
date that marked the end of the second millennium into the most expensive
215
The way people talk about abstraction is absolutely amazing, they have
absolutely no idea what it is. Philosophy has a kind of technique or
terminology like mathematics. Generally the word abstract is used for
things in which there is no abstraction. The problem of abstraction is how
can I make two things out of what only exists as one in my
representations. It's not difficult to make a thing into two when I have two
representations, but when I say the back of the piece of paper, I am not
abstracting at all since the back is given to me in a representation which
itself exists. When I say a length without thickness, there I am abstracting
because I am separating two things which are necessarily given in each
other in my representation. (TLK, 5)
digits from the date. Through this subtraction, it serves to extract the decade,
making it autonomous from the interiority of the century. It thus separates out
two things from what - until then - had appeared only as one (rupturing the
fracturing the semiotic expression of dated time, it abstracts a scale of time from
the history within which it is previously embedded (the year 00, for instance,
only confirms its nature as an abstract event, through which time has escaped
its inception - has been affined with the transcendental in its trend towards the
establishing the autonomy of the clock in relation to the calendar). In this respect
216
extracts an abstract temporality from dates themselves. With Y2K, dates cease
unity. Instead they are activated as numerical indices for pure - or Aeonic -
that "true lived experience is an absolutely abstract thing... once you have
reached lived experience, you reach the most fully living core of the abstract. "
"Nobody, Deleuze continues, "has ever lived anything but the abstract. " (SLK, 5)
investigate the abstract nature of time. What it has discovered, is that this most
economic practices of contemporary life. For the nature of time is not some
eternal given that has descended from above, but is rather a process that is itself
217
Appendix
Table I
Table 2
218
Bibliography
[KMCS] Boehm-Bawark. Karl Marx and the Close of His System & Boehm-
Bawerk's Criticism of Marx by Rudolf Hilferding ed. Paul Sweezy New York:
Augustus M Kelley, 1975
[BT] The Book of Time. ed. John Grant. London: Westbridge Books, 1980
[LDIK] DeQuincy, Thomas. ,"The Last Days of Immanuel Kant. ' in The
Collected Writings of Thomas De Quincy Vol. IV. London: A&C Black, 1897
[AO] Deleuze, Gilles and Felix Guattari. Anti-Oedipus. London: Athlone Press,
1984
[DR] Deleuze, Gilles. Difference and Repetition. London: Athlone Press, 1994
219
[KSTJ Deleuze, Gilles. Kant, Synthesis and Time. 14 March 1978. Trans.
Mellissa McMahon. Published on the Internet.
www. imaginet. fr/deleuze/TXT/ENG/140378. html
[LS] Deleuze, Gilles. Logic of Sense. Trans. Mark Lester and Charles Stivale.
New York: Columbia University Press, 1990
[TLK] Deleuze, Gilles. Third Lesson on Kant 28 March 1978. Trans. Melissa
McMahon. Published on the Internet.
www. imaginet. fr/deleuze/TXT/ENG/280378. html
[ATP] Deleuze, Gilles and Felix Guattari. A Thousand Plateaus. Trans. Brian
Massumi. Minneapolis. University of Minnesota Press, 1987
[HH] Dohm-van Rossum, Gerhard. History of the Hour. Clocks and the
Modem Temporal Orders. Trans. Thomas Dunlap. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1996
[C] David Ewing Duncan. Calendar. New York: Avon Books, 1998
[DP] Foucault, Michel. Discipline and Punish. Trans Allen Lane. London:
Penguin Books, 1975
[OT] Foucault, Michel. The Order of Things. New York: Vintage Books, 1973
[FR] The Foucault Reader. Ed. Paul Rabinow. New York: Pantheon Books,
1984
220
[U] Freud, Sigmund. 'The Unconscious" in The Freud Reader. ed. Peter Gay.
New York: WW Norton & Company, 1989
[UHN] Ifrah, Georges. The Universal History of Numbers. Trans. David Betlos,
E.F. Harding, Sophie Woods, and Ian Monk. New York: John Wiley & Sons,
2000
[CPR] Kant, Immanuel. The Critique of Pure Reason. Trans. Norman Kemp
Smith. London: Macmillan Press, 1982
[RT] Landes, David S. Revolution in Time: Clocks and the Making of the
Modem World. Cambridge, Mass. Harvrad University Press, 1983
[MT/CT] Le Goff, Jack. "Merchant's Time and Church Time" in Time, Work
and Culture in the Middle Ages. Trans. Arthur Goldhammer. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1974
[Cl] Marx, Karl. Capital Volume 1. New York: International Publishers, 1967
[CM] Marx, Karl. Communist Manifesto. New York Monthly Review Press,
1964
[TC] Mumford, Lewis. Technics and Civilization. London: Routledge & Sons,
1934
221
[T] Plato 'Timeaus' in Plato: The Collected Dialogues. Ed. Edith Hamilton
and Huntington Cairns. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1961
[E] Spinoza, Baruch. Ethics and Selected Letters. Trans Samuel Shirley. Ed.
Seymour Feldman. Indianapolis: Hacket Publishers Co, *1982
[PESC] Weber, Max. Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism. Trans.
Talcolt Parsons. London: Unwin Hyman, 1930
[FMW] From Max Weber. Essays in Sociology. ed H.H. Gerth and C Wright.
Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1946
[ES] Weber, Max. Economy and Society. ed Guenther Roth and Claus
Wittich. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1978
Whitrow, G.J. Time in History.- Views of Time From Prehistory to the Present
Day. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989
222