Law Against Genocide Cosmopolitan Trials (Criminology)
Law Against Genocide Cosmopolitan Trials (Criminology)
Law Against Genocide Cosmopolitan Trials (Criminology)
GENOCIDE
Cosmopolitan Trials
David Hirsh
All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or
transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording,
scanning or otherwise, without the prior permission in writing of Cavendish Publishing Limited,
or as expressly permitted by law, or under the terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics
rights organisation. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the above should be
sent to the Rights Department, Cavendish Publishing Limited, at the address above.
You must not circulate this book in any other binding or cover
and you must impose the same condition on any acquirer.
British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data
Hirsh, David
Law against genocide: cosmopolitan trials
1 Genocide
I Title
341.7'78
Library of Congress Cataloguing in Publication Data
Data available
ISBN 1-90438-504-4
1 3 5 7 9 10 8 6 4 2
Printed and bound in Great Britain
Acknowledgments
Thank you to the people at the Sociological Review. They gave me their
fellowship of 200102 at Keele University, which supported me financially
while I wrote this book. The only thing they asked in return was that I use the
time to develop myself as a writer and to produce this work. Amazing that
such a thing still exists: academic funding for its own sake.
Thank you to Robert Fine, to whom I owe a considerable debt, both personal
and academic, for the help, inspiration, advice and support that he has given
me over many years. He ought to be more generally recognised as one of the
most profound contemporary social theorists. Everything good in this book
has something to do with Robert. Chapter Two was written jointly with him.
Thank you to Beverley Brown at GlassHouse. How much nicer to be found
by a publisher than to find a publisher. Her help and advice were much
appreciated, and made this a better book; also to Sanjeevi Perera, for her
detailed editing.
Thank you to Alison Diduck for reading an early draft and giving me the
confidence to finish it.
Thank you to Stephan Feuchtwang who, as well as teaching me at City
University, has subsequently been interested in my work and ideas, and has
taken time to discuss and clarify them with me.
Thank you to David Seymour for his encouragement, help and friendship;
Max Seymour too.
Thank you to Margaret Archer, Jim Beckford and Peter Wagner who taught
me at Warwick University, and to John Cowley who taught me at City
University. Thanks are also due to Gillian Rose who taught me at Warwick
while she was dying of cancer.
Thank you to Adam Keller and Beate Zilversmidt, who star in Chapter
One, for inspiration. It is not easy to fight for a cosmopolitan politics in Tel
Aviv. They produce The Other Israel, available from POB 2542, Holon 58125,
Israel ([email protected]).
Thank you to my mum and dad, Mirjam and Julian, and to my sisters,
Deborah and Judy, for their support and for making me who I am.
Thank you to Fella, Fischel, Rushka and Yidl, members of my family who
survived the Holocaust and told their stories.
Thank you, above all, to Alexandra, my wife, for her warmth, energy and
love. She has worked very hard so that I could write this book.
David Hirsh
March 2003
Contents
Acknowledgments
Abbreviations
Abbreviated cases
Introduction
v
ix
x
xi
CHAPTER ONE
COSMOPOLITAN LAW
1
7
13
17
20
23
24
27
31
33
35
38
39
43
49
57
57
64
66
70
CHAPTER FIVE
THE TRIALS OF BLASKIC AND TADIC AT THE ICTY
The trial of General Tihomir Blaskic
The trial of Dusko Tadic
CHAPTER SIX
THE SAWONIUK TRIAL:
A COSMOPOLITAN TRIAL UNDER NATIONAL LAW
79
79
84
94
96
103
112
123
CHAPTER SEVEN
IRVING v LIPSTADT AND THE LEGAL CONSTRUCTION
OF AUTHORITATIVE COSMOPOLITAN NARRATIVE
Irving v Lipstadt
The legal construction of cosmopolitan social memory
CHAPTER EIGHT
CONCLUSION
Bibliography
Index
130
131
138
151
161
169
Abbreviations
BNP
FLN
HV
HVO
ICJ
ICC
ICTR
ICTY
IMTFE
JNA
KGB
KLA
NA
National Alliance
NATO
NKVD
RSHA
SA
SDA
SDS
SS
TO
UN
United Nations
UNHCR
Abbreviated cases
Demjanjuk case
Eichmann case
Prosecutor v Kristic
Sawoniuk case
Zundel case
Introduction
On 28 January 2000, I was at the Royal Courts of Justice in the Strand, in
London. Outside the building was a large, angry, noisy demonstration
consisting mainly of Chileans, displaying hundreds of photographs of
individuals who had been murdered by the Pinochet regime. Augusto Pinochet
was attending an appeal by the Kingdom of Belgium against the British Home
Secretarys decision that, due to his poor health, the General was unfit to
stand trial for crimes against humanity. Upstairs in the same building, judges
were hearing the unsuccessful appeal of Andrei Sawoniuk against his
conviction for the murder of Jews in Belorus during the Holocaust. And in
Court 73 there was a gathering of Jews, historians, Nazis and journalists
watching the Irving v Lipstadt libel trial. In the Pinochet case the court confirmed
the principle of universal jurisdiction for crimes against humanity and torture.
In the Sawoniuk case the court upheld the conviction of a man for crimes
committed as part of a genocide in another country. In the Irving case the
court produced a long, closely argued judgment that placed the propaganda
of David Irving outside what may be properly referred to as historiography.
On that sunny winters day in London, it felt as though something interesting
was happening.
On the same day, there were crimes against humanity trials being routinely
heard by international courts in The Hague, in relation to ethnic cleansing in
the former Yugoslavia, and in Arusha, in relation to the genocide in Rwanda.
In recent years there have been trials, and campaigns for trials, in many
countries that were occupied by the Nazis; also in Cambodia in relation to the
genocide there; in South East Asia in relation to the organised mass rape of
the so called comfort women by Japanese soldiers during the Second World
War;1 and in East Timor in relation to the mass killings carried out by the
Indonesian regime. In the summer of 1998, 120 states agreed in Rome to set
up an International Criminal Court, extending the ad hoc tribunals for the
former Yugoslavia and Rwanda into a permanent institution. Slobodan
Milosevic, the man who many held would never face justice at The Hague, is
on trial.
There is much darkness in the world; genocide, racist ethnic cleansing,
torture, industrialised humiliation and the mass production of terror are
commonplace. Those who perpetrate such crueltiesthe ideological, the
greedy, the enraged victims of some previous injustice, the stupidly loyal, the
sadistsmove stealthily in their self-created dusk. On reflection, perhaps the
bright winter sunshine in London did not really work as a metaphor for the
business that was going on in the court. The image of enduring brilliant light
When the Japanese Prime Minister offered a letter of apology and monetary reparations to some 500
survivors of the 200,000 comfort women, only six of them accepted the offer. Some of the womenfrom
Korea, Taiwan, China, the Philippines, and Indonesiafound more gratification when the US Justice
Department placed the names of 16 Japanese individuals involved in enslaving the women for sex on a
watch list of suspected war criminals barred from entering the United States. Some argued that only
prosecutions by the Japanese Government would adequately express governmental contrition and redress
the abuse. Others supported treatment of the comfort women in school textbooks as a kind of reparation
through memory. Minow, 1998, p 105.
xii
penetrating all the shadows of totalitarianism was surely illusory. But there
have been flashes and sparks that have momentarily lit up the landscape.
This book focuses on those. It seeks to sketch some of the scenes that are
briefly illuminated by cosmopolitan criminal law, and to assess the significance
and trajectory of the fragments of cosmopolitan criminal law that find a fleeting
and tentative existence. Sparks and flashes are unreliable, unpredictable and
dangerous, but they create bright light nevertheless. The existence of these
fragments of light is the starting point of this work.
The term cosmopolitanderiving from the Greek cosmos (world)was first
used in this context by Immanuel Kant,2 who picked up a thread of classical
Greek thought3 when he set out his theory of cosmopolitan right in 1795. He
argued that the relationships between democratic republics must be regulated
by a framework which provides for the peaceful settlement of disputes between
states. But he went further, arguing that cosmopolitan law must set minimum
standards for the treatment of individuals, both citizens and foreigners.
Contemporary social theory is rediscovering and radicalising the concept
of cosmopolitanism and recognising cosmopolitan law as one of its key
actualisations. James Bohman and Matthius Lutz-Bachmann4 argue that Kants
framework for a universal community of all peoples is given new urgency by
the current development of globalisation. Steven Vertovec and Robin Cohen5
chart the possibilities of peaceful human co-existence using the framework of
a cosmopolitanism which focuses on human commonality. Ulrich Beck6 sees
the development of a cosmopolitan politics as a necessary response to
globalisation. For David Held,7 a democratic response to globalisation requires
a cosmopolitan law that can regulate the unbounded growth of capital and
other power structures. For Mary Kaldor,8 a cosmopolitan approach is
necessary because the nature of war is changing profoundly. Outdated
categories of sovereignty, national interest and international law do not provide
an adequate framework either to make sense of current conflicts or to challenge
their worst excesses. Robert Fine says that:
cosmopolitan social theory may be viewed as a multi-disciplinary attempt to
reconstruct the core concepts of the human sciencessociety, political community,
democracy, culture, sovereignty, etcin such a way as no longer to presuppose the
givenness or Generality of the nation state in their designation.9
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
Kant, 1991.
Nussbaum, 1997.
Bohman and Lutz-Bachmann, 1997.
Vertovec and Cohen, 2002.
Beck, 1999.
Held, 1995, 2002.
Kaldor, 1999.
Fine, 2002a.
Habermas, 2001.
Introduction
xiii
xiv
By May 1994, at least 200,000 people, nearly all Tutsi, had been killed in
Rwanda, but the US Government instructed its officials to refuse to call this a
genocide.11 This was because, even though a legal duty to act in defence of
those being killed does not flow directly from such a characterisation, a refusal
to use the term makes it easier not to act. The moral power of the term genocide,
which stems partly from its legal existence, is considerable. Why, if the basis of
international relations is power, does the US Government find itself playing
these word games in order to help it to deny the undeniable? Clearly, there are
factors at work other than naked power. This is a small example of how the
powerful find themselves having to take notice of moral and legal duties. It is a
small crack in the monolith of power; but cracks signify possibilities.
There is a large and comprehensive body of international humanitarian
law. There are treaties, conventions, charters; there is customary international
law and precedent. One key question that I am trying to answer in this book
is to what extent that body of law has attained a genuine existence outside
UN libraries and international law journals. It is clear enough that it does not
exist as a settled system of criminal law that routinely tracks down and puts
on trial those responsible for crimes against humanity, independently of where
they commit their crimes or at whose behest. It is also clear enough that
international criminal law is bogged down by power politics and the veto of
the permanent members of the UN Security Council. International
humanitarian law does not exist as a finished set of institutions and principles.
But to what extent does it exist in an embryonic and incomplete form? This is
the key question that I aim to answer in this work. If cosmopolitan criminal
trials are being carried out, if they are based on due process and human rights,
if they bring some justice to at least some perpetrators and some victims, then
what is the significance of the development of these possibilities?
A number of important legal precedents have established the fact that the
greatest violations of international humanitarian lawgenocide, ethnic
cleansing and tortureare subject to universal jurisdiction. Nuremberg, Tokyo,
the ad hoc tribunals, the Pinochet judgment: all have clearly established that
such crimes may be tried by international courts or by the national courts of
any state. A state may no longer argue that the principle of national sovereignty
disbars foreign courts from trying its nationals for such crimes or trying those
suspected of committing such crimes within its territory. The right of national
sovereignty is not absolute, but is related to other rights. Crimes against
humanity are the concern of humanity as a whole, irrespective of where and
under what jurisdiction they were committed. The principle of individual
legal responsibility for such crimes, no matter whether they were carried out
at the behest of states, by the leaders of states, or with the blessing of the legal
system of states, is also clearly established.
I do not attempt to privilege the development of cosmopolitan criminal
law as the most important antidote to totalitarianism, but as one weapon that
is levelled against it alongside others. Law does not put an end to the actions
that are designated as criminal. Laws against genocide, on their own, cannot
stop genocide any more than laws against burglary have stopped burglary.
Law is just one weapon. It is a complement to, not a substitute for, political
action, education and organisation against those social formations that seek
11 Cohen, 2001, p 162.
Introduction
xv
xvi
13 The Nuremberg process was the first formal recognition of a universal jurisdiction over certain heinous
crimes. Goldstone, 2000, p 75. Richard Goldstone notes that piracy and brigandage had been recognised
as crimes of universal jurisdiction, but that they were never authoritatively defined.
14 Bauman, 1993.
15 Chapter Two was written jointly by David Hirsh and Robert Fine.
Introduction
gnocidaires will be able to say we were only obeying orders. Following the
tribunals, the innovations at Nuremberg became clearly established precedents
in cosmopolitan law.
Chapter Three goes on to discuss the codification of the crime of genocide
in the Genocide Convention of 1948, and some of the ways in which social
scientists have looked at genocide since then, with the emergence of genocide
studies. The genocide studies scholars attempt to discover ever more accurate
definitions for key terms, ever more intricate traits common to genocides,
ever more numerous statistical correlations. In this way they attempt to
understand the social phenomena that they investigate. But they do not pay
much attention to the ways in which those phenomena are understood by the
structures and norms of society itself, that is to say, by developments in
cosmopolitan law. It is, I argue, more fruitful to focus on the structures that
develop organically within society than to attempt, as some social scientists
do, to impose an abstract understanding based only on their own critique.
In Chapter Four, I explore the ways in which the three goals of peace, justice
and security have been pursued in the former Yugoslavia by the international
community. In the war in Bosnia, security and justice were subordinated to a
vain quest for peace and the avoidance of conflict. The overriding wish to
avoid any disruption of the peace enabled the practice of ethnic cleansing to
be carried out with little hindrance. In Kosovo, the international community
focused on preventing and reversing the ethnic cleansing, yet with such a
blunt use of force that peace, security and justice all suffered. The priority
given by the intervening powers to avoiding putting their own soldiers at
risk had not changed since Bosnia, but the policy that flowed from it took a
very different form. The establishment of the International Criminal Tribunal
for the former Yugoslavia (ICTY) focuses on justice, yet it was established
under the UN Security Councils powers to pursue peace and security. I explore
the process by which the ICTY came to be set up and how it developed from
a token institution, with no prisoners and a tiny budget, into one capable of
putting Milosevic himself on trial.
In Chapter Five, I focus on the trials of a Croatian General, Tihomir Blaskic,
and a small-time Bosnian Serb political activist, Dusko Tadic. It is through
these two case studies that I investigate the actual working of a cosmopolitan
criminal court. The most striking thing about the ICTY is that it exists. There
is a courthouse in The Hague, protected by UN security personnel, displaying
UN flags and symbols, that is carrying out the routine business of putting
people on trial for crimes against humanity and genocide. Political,
philosophical and legal discourse about the possibility of cosmopolitan law
are confronted by this institution which quietly came into being during the
debate. There are a number of factors which make it more difficult and
complicated to organise fair trials here under cosmopolitan law than to
organise domestic criminal trials, while all of the difficulties usually associated
with criminal trials are also still present. These narratives are presented in
order to highlight some of the problems and the ways in which the court
seeks to overcome them. But these descriptions of the business of ethnic
cleansing, and the day-to-day functioning of the court which relates to it, are
also presented in order to concretise the often rather elevated theoretical
discussion of such social processes.
xvii
xviii
Introduction
Holocaust memoir was acted upon by the rules and norms of the legal
processes, particularly by the process of cross-examination and the sifting out
of evidence that was deemed inadmissible: the trial process always strove to
transform memoir into evidence. Blustein resisted the court and tried to retain
control over his own testimony. The court had difficulty in bounding the
extraordinary events and stories which were given to it within the normal
rules of criminal evidence. The jury was swayed both by evidence which the
court wished it to hear and also by influences which the court wished to
suppress. The trial was a struggle between witnesses, the defendant, the
lawyers and the judge for control over the information which the jury would
use to come to its verdict.
While cosmopolitan criminal trials are intended to bring criminals to justice
and to deter future crimes, Chapter Seven, which looks at the defamation
case of Irving v Lipstadt, focuses on another important aspect of such trials.
One of the strongest, most pervasive and widespread forms of collective
memory is that which creates and recreates myths of nationhood. Most of the
evidence that is presented to crimes against humanity trials is strongly coloured
by national social memories; the subject matter of such evidence is the most
extreme ethnic and national conflict. I argue that the cosmopolitan legal process
is like a machine whose data is input in a form heavily coloured by national
myth, yet whose output aims to be free from national particularity. The
institutions of cosmopolitan law, as well as the body of law, rules and precedent
on which they are based, are the mechanisms by which such cosmopolitan
judgments may be arrived at. Crimes against humanity trials aim to produce
authoritative narratives of the crimes, narratives given a particular form of
authority by the legal processes and norms by which they are created. I argue
that this is a part of the process of the evolution of a global collective memory
that can play a role in undermining myths of nationhood, particularly those
that have played their part in causing ethnic cleansing and genocide. The
Irving v Lipstadt libel case is discussed as an example of the ways in which
battles over narrative can be hosted by a trial process. Irvings revisionist
narrative clashed with the academic cosmopolitan discourse of Lipstadt. The
court necessarily took on some of the characteristics of a cosmopolitan court
and produced a legally authoritative narrative in the form of its 349-page
judgment.17 In Chapter Seven, I discuss the status and possibilities of such
narratives.
The particular shape of this book, though not the fundamental arguments
that it contains, is a little arbitrary. It is not a comprehensive survey of
developments in cosmopolitan criminal law, nor is it an account of all crimes
against humanity trials. It does not necessarily focus on the most important
cases, nor on the most interesting cases. The empirical heart of this work is
the observation of four trials; the Blaskic and Tadic cases in The Hague and the
Sawoniuk and Irving cases in London. These trials were within my reach,
geographically and temporally.
The trials at The Hague represent a sample of the early work of the Hague
Tribunal. This tribunal is, along with its sister tribunal in Arusha, among the
most interesting and important developments in cosmopolitan criminal legal
history, and I was fortunate to be able to observe some of its operation. Two of
17 Irving v Lipstadt judgment.
xix
xx
the cases taking place there while I was carrying out my research were the
Tactic and Blaskic cases. The Tadic case was the first ever to undergo a full trial
process by a UN court; and I chose the Blaskic case because of its contrast to
that case. Tadic was a small-time Bosnian Serb political leader; Blaskic was a
General in the Croatian army.
The selection of the Sawoniuk and Irving cases was more opportunistic on
my part. Yet their appearance at the right time for this work was not only a
matter of good fortune, since cosmopolitan law is, at the moment, enjoying a
limited but real renaissance. The Sawoniuk case was the trial of a man who
had become a British citizen after the Second World War, for crimes committed
in Belorus during that war as part of the Nazi genocide of the Jews. The case
exemplified many of the complexities and difficulties associated with
cosmopolitan criminal trials, such as the fact that the jurisdiction in which the
trial was taking place was different from that in which the crimes were
committed. It illustrated very clearly some of the difficulties involved in
assigning different kinds of standards and rules that render evidence
admissible or inadmissible, and it illustrated some of the ways in which
different nationalistic narratives are worked upon by a court to produce a
judgment. The Irving case was a libel trial in which David Irving sued Deborah
Lipstadt for calling him a Holocaust denier and a falsifier of history who had
neo-Nazi links. This case shows a contrasting way in which events that may
be characterised as crimes against humanity can be examined in a court of
law. As well as focusing on the ways in which a trial process can judge between
opposing narratives of such events and produce its own legally authoritative
narrative, this case also sheds light upon the ways in which the acceptance of
certain forms of evidence rather than others can skew the truth that the court
or the historian or the witness produces.
The central aim of the empirical investigation was to observe the actual
working of these trials. Much has been written and spoken about international
law by media commentators and politicians, and the law journals are full of
articles by lawyers about the theory of international law. I wanted to observe
the social phenomena of cosmopolitan trials as they actually happened. I
wanted to look more at how they happened than at how they were supposed,
theoretically, to happen. I wanted to come to a judgment not only about
whether they could be characterised as fair trials, but also about the substance
and character of cosmopolitan trials.
In the case of the ICTY, live sound (delayed by half an hour) from the three
courtrooms is broadcast over the internet; full transcripts are available on the
official website of all public proceedings; and the judgments that the tribunal
produces are of the highest quality: detailed, well written and authoritative.
The huge availability of this material is a methodological problem in itself:
each day, each courtroom produces something like an 80-page transcript. This
is simply an enormous amount of data for a researcher to handle. I still found
that being in the building and in the courtrooms themselves gave me an
incomparably fuller picture of the institutions and their proceedings. To be
able to watch the lawyers, the judges, the witnesses and the defendants, day
after day, and to be able to see the trial unfold, proved to be an absolutely
invaluable part of my work. This work of observation was important in
enriching the mountains of documentary data available.
Introduction
xxi
xxii
Irving case was less regimented and was much more a part of the courtroom;
it did, on the other hand, contain a small collection of Nazi sympathisers, as
well as Holocaust survivors, well known historians and students. In The
Hague, the public gallery is very close to the court, but is separated from it by
soundproof and bulletproof glass, giving an impression of intimacy mixed
with remoteness. Usually at The Hague, the public gallery was almost empty,
apart from one or two journalists and a few officials from the Bosnian or
Croatian embassies. As well as being clear about who the observer is and
what is being observed, the researcher is also conscious of the place from
where the observations are made.
The strength, for a researcher, of choosing a small number of detailed case
studies is that it is possible to achieve more depth. I could have attempted a
comprehensive survey of all crimes against humanity trials, obtaining
information from law reports, press reports, transcripts and other secondary
and mediated sources. My aim was different. It was to attempt to get a feel for
the cases; to understand the defendants and their crimes; to see exactly how
the volumes, treaties and precedents of international law are given life by
particular cosmopolitan institutions and particular lawyers and judges. I did
not only want to see that trials take place; I also wanted to see how they take
place, how unexpected events are dealt with by the process, and how the
rules of the institutions of law are worked upon by the individual agents at
work in the processdefendants, lawyers, judges, the press, the public. An
immediate relationship between the phenomenon and the researcher requires
attendance in court. The researcher makes sense of their own observations
first, before being subjected to the opinions of others and the shape given to
events by the media.
I did not observe these trials innocently. I did not go to any great lengths to
attempt to create some sort of scientific distance from events, that is, to hide
my particularity as an observer and as a social agent behind a faade of artificial
objectivity. In fact, I observed the trials with all the prejudices that the
experience of my life gives me. Observation is not only created by that which
is being observed; it is also created by the observer. It is necessary to keep in
mind the social context of the observation as well as that of the object. It is
necessary to retain some picture of who is observing, and of the interaction
between the observer and the observed. The difference between the
information that is available when you are an observer in court and that which
is available even from a complete transcript lies in the impressions of people
and events that are filtered through ones own personal experience, and also
impressions of structures, people and events outside the formal proceedings
of the institution. I will give three examples to illustrate what I mean.
There was an incident, which I describe in Chapter Four, when I was at the
ICTY and was approached by the chief security officer and interviewed by him.
I was, at the time, outside the building, sitting on the grass in the sunshine at
lunchtime. He approached me in order to ask me why I had been trying to
engage members of staff in conversation, what I was observing, and why. I was
surprised by the extent and the manner of the security. The incident added, in
a small way, to my impression of the institution as a whole. It bolstered a feeling
I had that the institution took itself seriously but in a civilised sort of way. It was
interesting that he chose an informal interview outside his territory rather
than in his (perhaps rather intimidating) office. It was interesting that he had a
Introduction
19 Burgess, 1993.
xxiii
xxiv
Chapter One
Cosmopolitan law
Classically, international law is the system that protects the right of sovereign
states to be free from external aggression, and sets out a framework by which
the relationships between states may be regulated. Following the experience
of Nazism, a need was felt to extend the scope of international law so that it
could protect the rights not only of states but of individuals, and also so that
it could hold individuals criminally responsible for the actions of states. It
was recognised that states could not always be relied upon to guarantee the
most basic rights of their citizens, and neither could they be relied upon to
hold those individuals committing the greatest crimes to account. Some crimes
are so huge and some rights so fundamental that they become the business
not just of the citizens of particular states but of humanity as a whole.
In this way, a new form of law began to emerge out of international law, a
form of law that has a logic that transcends international law and is in some
respects in contradiction to it. It seeks to limit state sovereignty, and lays down
minimum standards for the treatment of human beings by states. It claims
the right to put individuals on trial for certain crimes even against the will of
their state and the state in whose territory and in whose name the crime was
committed. In this chapter I argue that, even though this new form of law can
be understood simply as a development in international law, it is more
appropriately recognised as cosmopolitan law. Cosmopolitan law represents
a break from international law because it does not put the rights of states
above the rights of people. Its emergence is tentative and incomplete; it emerges
into a world dominated by forms of power that threaten to extinguish it or to
strip it of its radical content. But cosmopolitan law exists as an empirical fact,
in institutions such as the International Criminal Tribunal for the former
Yugoslavia (ICTY) as well as in treaties, conventions and charters that give
ammunition and courage to those struggling against state tyranny.
within its territory; and it reserves the right to act as a power outside its territory
in any way that it believes furthers its own national interests.
There was another parallel response to the Nazi genocide. That response,
which began to emerge at Nuremberg, understood the Holocaust not primarily
as a crime against Jews but as a crime against humanity as a whole. The
Holocaust was not understood as a campaign of genocidal antisemitism but
as a campaign of genocidal racism. That which must never happen again was
any genocide against any collectivity. This approach was based on a particular
notion of humanity; it was one that understood human beings to be of equal
value in at least a very basic and minimal sense.1 Human beings are bearers of
fundamental rights. The most basic right, perhaps, is the right to ones identity
as a human being. Those who commit genocide must first challenge the
universality of that right. The Nuremberg trials began to give a material realworld existence to the concept of human rights. They established the principle
that nobody, no state, no head of state, no soldier acting under apparently
legal orders, has the right to violate the most fundamental of human rights.
Those who had done so were tried as criminals. The trials were not held under
the authority of any sovereign power or national legal system, but under the
authority of international law.
An Israeli Colonel was interviewed on Israeli television during the current
intifada. He said:
We have entered Taumon in order to catch terrorists. The terrorists managed to
escape before our arrival, but we are going to give the townspeople hell, to teach
them not to harbour terrorists.2
Gush Shalom, an Israeli peace group, wrote a letter to this Colonel pointing
out that collective punishment is a violation of the Geneva Conventions, and
citing reports that 20 inhabitants of Taumon had already been wounded by
soldiers under his command, among them a 70-year-old imam of the local
mosque. The Colonel was warned that the evidence might in future be
presented to an Israeli or international court empowered to deal with war
crimes and violations of international law. The army responded by issuing a
new directive, forbidding soldiers and officers to give their full names when
interviewed by the media. The reason explicitly given was to prevent the
possibility of their being prosecuted at the Hague War Crimes Tribunal. Prime
Minister Sharon responded by instructing the Attorney General to look into
ways of prosecuting the Gush Shalom activists. Several other ministers who
spoke used the word treason, and so did nationalist Knesset Members and
newspaper columnists. An activist was asked on Israeli television: And would
you really inform upon a fellow Israeli, a fellow Jew, to a foreign court? Are
you that depraved?3
The two responses to the Holocaust, one of Jewish self-determination, the
other of cosmopolitan law, thus appear to be turning on each other. The
nationalists see an external threat to Jews; they see foreigners under the banner
of a new world order claiming to have the right to imprison and punish Jews
1
2
3
[O]ur species is one, and each of the individuals who compose it is entitled to equal moral consideration.
Human rights is the language that systematically embodies this intuition Ignatieff, 2001, pp 34.
Keller, 2002.
Keller, 2002.
Cosmopolitan law
against the legitimate sovereign will of the Jewish state. Those who argue for
the extension of a cosmopolitan criminal legal system see a Jewish army and a
Jewish state committing, or perhaps preparing to commit, war crimes or crimes
against humanity.
But it is not a surprise to see the principles of human rights and those of
national self-determination come into such severe conflict. It was precisely
the fact that individual Nazis were convicted of crimes under international
lawcrimes that were not considered as such under their own system of
rulesthat represented the novelty of the Nuremberg process.
Human rights are instruments that seek to limit the scope of state
sovereignty. They affirm that there are certain things that independent states
do not have the right to do. States may agree to enforce human rights; they
may incorporate this or that human rights principle or charter into their own
systems of law. But state national sovereignty is not the source of human rights.
It is a fundamental strand of the cosmopolitan argument that the incorporation
and enforcement of human rights is not something that states may choose to
do but is something that they are obligated to respect.
In the 18th century, the concept of the Rights of Man gave focus and
legitimacy to struggles against traditional political systems, which held that
some human beings were created with rights to rule over the others, who
were created with only the right to obey. The concept of rights was at the
heart of the post-revolutionary states in France and America. It was held to be
self-evident that all men were created equal; the new society was to be based
on liberty, equality and fraternity. These truths were then embedded into
national constitutions and imprinted on the coinage. These rights were
guaranteed to citizens by national states. As Hannah Arendt put it:
man had hardly appeared as a completely emancipated, completely isolated being
who carried his dignity within himself without reference to some larger
encompassing order, when he disappeared again into a member of a people.4
From the beginning, rights were tied to a national state that could guarantee
and enforce them. The Rights of Man were tied to rights of citizenship. The
classical conception of the nation state that emerged from the French
Revolution was an inclusive one: the nation was defined by the state and
citizenship was enjoyed by all inhabitants of the territory. Yet there was always
the danger that this relationship between the state and the nation could be
reversed: an ethnically defined nation could take control of the state and
exclude those whom it defined as not belonging.
But a larger concept of rights, specifically human rights, was to re-emerge
in the 20th century. Following the Holocaust and other horrors, it was, as Phil
Allot puts it, this timeinstalled not merely in the constitutions of national
societies but in the constitution of international society itself.5 The Nuremberg
process, and the wave of human rights conventions and declarations which
were generally accepted after the war by states, by international law and by
the new United Nations (UN), solidified human rights as a clear and agreed
principle of the international community.
The two principles, however, by which people seek to protect their collective
and individual existence and freedomnational self-determination and
4
5
Eg All members shall refrainfrom the use of force against thepolitical independence of any state
(UN Charter, Article 2(4)); Nothing contained in the present Charter shall authorize the United Nations to
intervene in matters which are essentially within the domestic jurisdiction of any state (Article 2(7)); see
fuller discussion below.
Eg Universal Declaration of Human Rights (1948); Convention on the Prevention and Punishment of the
Crime of Genocide (1948); Geneva Convention for the Amelioration of the Condition of the Wounded and
Sick in Armed Forces in the Field (1949). Hoog and Steinmetz, 1993.
Lauterpacht, 1950, pp 3637.
Cosmopolitan law
humanity and war was decisively broken; the prosecution of genocide, also,
requires no link to armed conflict.9 In the post-Second World War period,
there was much cross-pollination between humanitarian and human rights
law.10
Jean Pictet envisages the possibility of bringing the two forms of law
together under the common name of humane law.11 While humanitarian
law and human rights law do have different histories, principles and
purposes,12 it is clear that they often share the same objectives and goals; they
also share a common theoretical grounding in the discourse of human rights.
In 1982, at a time when the post-war innovations in international law
appeared to have been permanently frozen out in the context of the bipolar
power struggle of the Cold War, Leo Kuper wrote that:
[T]he sovereign territorial state claims, as an integral part of its sovereignty, the
right to commit genocide, or engage in genocidal massacres, against people under
its rule, andthe UN, for all practical purposes, defends this right.13
Twenty years later this expression of exasperation is not quite as true as it was
when it was written. The legacy of the post-war innovations has been defrosted
and re-examined following the end of the Cold War. It has been built upon by
social theorists,14 international lawyers15 and both legal and state practice. A
current has been emerging out of international law that vigorously challenges
the sovereign right to commit genocide. This current is developing into a new
form of law that a number of theorists have referred to as cosmopolitan law.
David Held, for example, sees a progression from the model of classical
sovereignty, the law of states, through a model of liberal international
sovereignty, in which the liberal concern for limited government is extended
into the international sphere, to the model of cosmopolitan sovereignty, the
law of peoples.16
For Mary Kaldor, the Yugoslavian wars of the 1990s typify the changing
nature of warfare. She argues that in new wars the classic distinctions between
internal and external, war and peace, aggression and repression are breaking
down. War is no longer controlled by sovereign states wielding legitimate
monopolies of violence; rather it is fought out between ethnically defined
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
The prohibition of genocide, derived from the concept of wartime crimes against humanity and later
enlarged to prohibit similar peacetime behaviour, can perhaps be seen as an example of the intersection of
human rights and humanitarian law, Provost, 2002, p 6.
The Universal Declaration of Human Rights was drafted in the aftermath of the Nuremberg process. It, in
turn, influenced the Geneva Conventions of 1949 and its additional protocols of 1977 which set down
standards for the treatment of prisoners of war and wounded soldiers. The progressive rejection of military
necessity as a valid justification for disregarding humanitarian law over the course of the last century can
also be linked to the development of individual human rights: Provost, 2002, p 6.
Humane law comprises the totality of the international legal provisions which ensure for the human
person respect and fulfilment. Pictet, 1985, p 3. Pictet, however, does not argue for such a merger between
the two forms of law.
Humanitarian law allows lawful killing, even on a large scale, of the enemy, in some circumstances even
including civilians; it authorizes various measures of deprivation of freedom which are not recognised by
human rights law: Meron, 1997, p 100.
Kuper, 1982, p 161.
Eg Habermas, 2001; Kaldor, 1999; Held, 1995; Archibugi and Held, 1995; Bohman and Lutz-Bachmann,
1997; Fine, 2002a.
Eg Bassiouni, 1999; Higgins, 1999.
Held, 2002.
Thus both Held and Kaldor attach their theories of cosmopolitan law to a
particular narrative of development that seems to give its emergence some
sort of historical inevitability. While this evolutionism is problematic, the central
insight is that a new body of law has emerged out of international law that is
sufficiently different from its classical form to make its recognition as a new
form appropriate. This is not an argument about names: it is an argument for
the recognition of the centrality of the development that is being made and
struggled for. Neither is it a celebration of the historical forces of progress that
are remaking the world. While proponents of cosmopolitan theory do point to
significant structural changes that are occurring in global relations, often
grouped under the heading of globalisation, the recognition of cosmopolitan
law is fundamentally an observation of human agency at work. It is the
recognition of a movement for a form of law that does not replicate that which
is being fought against. The current emergence of cosmopolitan law may turn
out to have been just a fleeting one; it is a movement that may be reversed and
politically defeated. But human rights have an unusual quality: once they have
been asserted, they exist for all time. Once Nazis and ethnic cleansers have
been put on trial under cosmopolitan law, that precedent remains.
Sometimes cosmopolitanism looks like a hopelessly radical and Utopian
project. It begins by asking how to prevent future genocide and it ends up
challenging every power structure, institution and principle: nationalism and
the nation state; the huge imbalances of power between strong states and
weak ones; the agonising gulf between rich and poor; the rule of global capital.
Yet sometimes cosmopolitanism looks like a hopelessly conservative project.
It is only necessary to make some fine adjustments to international institutions,
to take further reforms that are already being made because structural changes
in the world demand them; the rules of the UN Security Council must be
democratised, the US State Department must learn a few lessons from the
experiences of Somalia and of Srebrenica; the International Criminal Court
(ICC) must start hearing cases; problems of global inequality and poverty
must be addressed by agreements on social issues that can be woven into
agreements on free trade and all will be well. Sometimes those who argue for
cosmopolitanism appear to be both Utopian and conservative at the same
time. The emergence of cosmopolitan criminal law is neither. It is, as Robert
Fine put it, an expression of worldliness as the practical wisdom of those
who by hook and crook know how to construct a touch of humanity in the
most forbidding circumstances.18 It is one instrument that can make a
contribution to the fight against the most horrific forms of tyranny.
17 Kaldor, 1999, p 116.
18 Fine, 2001, p 162.
Cosmopolitan law
National sovereignty
Traditional natural law theory held that states were bound by moral
considerations when deciding whether to wage war. Augustine wrote about
war in terms of justice. He argued that states had a right and, in some
circumstances, a duty to take up arms in the cause of justice. Aquinas stressed
the point that a just war must be authorised by due authorities, that is, that it
must be a concern of the public at large, as distinct from a private quarrel.
Neutrality within the framework of traditional natural law could be a
dereliction of duty: if a state stood by and watched another being unjustly
conquered, it was morally in the wrong.19 The rise of the modern state and its
associated modern sovereignty put an end to the medieval recognition of the
(aristocratic) individual as a bearer of international rights and obligations,
except in cases where it was in the interests of states to hold individuals to
account for crimes such as piracy.20
The rise of the modern state also coincided with the generalisation of private
property that freed property owners from traditional obligations and duties.
Relations between individuals, all of whom were now potential property
owners, came to be understood as based on equality.21 In a parallel shift, states
rejected their moral duties and obligations to each other, and instead openly
followed their own self-interests, creating the doctrine of the sovereign equality
of nation states. Nation states, like citizens, and like property owners, were
now all equal before the law. Right replaced duty and ethics.
In the positivist era, argues Stephen Neff, the:
Ethical considerations had, in the real world, often been thin cover for the
material interests of those clerical authorities who assumed the right to make
ethical judgments. Such considerations were replaced by the freedom for
individuals and states to pursue their own interests in an enlightened way
and within a minimum legal framework.
The signing of the Treaty of Westphalia (1648) is seen by many, both
cosmopolitan23 and more orthodox international relations24 theorists, as the
historical event around which this shift hinged. It is represented as the moment
when territorial sovereignty in Europe was entrenched and when the only
limit to the pursuit of state interest became state power. Some who still cling
to the principle of absolute state sovereignty see Westphalia as the birth of the
freedom of nations; some cosmopolitan theorists see it as the moment when
ethics disappeared from the discourse of global politics, a historic fall that
must be remedied; some European integrationists see it as a specifically
European settlement. Yet even if the significance of Westphalia is
overemphasised by those who wish to use it as a pivotal moment in their
particular narrative of history, it has come to represent the shift towards a
new set of principles.
The Thirty Years War (16188), which was ended by the Treaty of
Westphalia, was a complex set of conflicts, involving wars both between estates
within the Holy Roman Empire and with external states, particularly France
and Sweden. In fact, the distinction between states and estates, Staate and
Stnde, or ltat and les tats, was not yet clearly drawn. Indeed, the drawing
of these distinctions, the battle for sovereignty, or freedom from domination
by the empire or other states, was one of the aims of the war for many of the
participants. Some, like the Dutch States General, were successful, gaining
recognition of sovereignty in 1648, while others, such as the Estates of Bohemia
and the Protestant cities and noblemen of France, were forced to accept the
reduced status of subjects.25 The war was exceptionally long, bloody and
destructive.26 The bloodshed was ended by a settlement that provided a
framework for national and religious freedom from the Catholic Church.
The key elements of the model of Westphalia, encapsulating the principles
of relations between sovereign states, are as follows:
(a) The world consists of, and is divided by, sovereign states which
recognise no superior authority.
(b) The processes of law making, the settlement of disputes and law
enforcement are largely in the hands of individual states.
Cosmopolitan law
10
the central principle of classical sovereignty, that a state would not be subject
to outside interference in its affairs, remained central.
Following the First World War, and the collapse of the Ottoman and AustroHungarian empires, the system of independent nation states was greatly
expanded by the victorious powers in Europe. Anthony Giddens30 argues that
the external influence of the international system of states played an important
role in the generalisation of the sovereign nation state model. The international
system of nation states required the universalisation of national sovereignty,
exercised through the rapid proliferation of surveillance within territories and
reflexive monitoring between states. Developments as mundane as
international postal services required the existence of national postal
organisations that had full reach within their territories. Sovereign control of
the means of mass violence and the industrialisation and totalisation of war
strengthened the detailed control of territory and information that national
states were developing. Territorial definitions and the sovereignty of borders,
policed according to international agreements, similarly increased the necessity
for internal surveillance by states. The influence of the international system
of nation states and the requirement for international co-operation were,
according to Giddens, centrally important in the consolidation and
generalisation of the doctrine, the reality and the myth of national sovereignty.
However, Arendt highlights the increasing problem of the nation states
inability to guarantee a framework of rights for all. She focuses on this same
post-First World War period when the nation state form was being hurriedly
replicated.31 The form became a pattern to be copied everywhere in order to
fill the vacuum left by the breakup of the multinational empires. The great
powers wanted to impose the nation state form from above, through the peace
treaties and the League of Nations; powerful national groups seized on it in
order to win state power for themselves; and the requirements of the
international system also fuelled the process.
Arendt argues that the result was that, in large parts of Europe, exclusive
ethnic nationalism subverted the classical model of the all-inclusive civic state.
The nation state form became the universal form but the content, which had
classically guaranteed rights to all citizens, was new. In these new nation states
in central and eastern Europe, it was the pre-existing nation, defined
ethnically, that took state power, rather than the state as a set of civic institutions
defining a community of equal citizens as a nation. There was an all-out
struggle between nationalities and minorities for some kind of favourable
political settlement: Slovaks against Czechs, Croats against Serbs, Ukrainians
against Poles, everyone against Jews.32 Rights became increasingly dependent
on national independence, which could only be won at the expense of the
exclusion of others. Hence the settlements that the victorious powers tried to
impose through the League of Nations in fact encouraged and accelerated
the process of competition between national and ethnic groups for
independence and hegemony. Everyone became convinced that [t]rue
freedom, true emancipation, and true popular sovereignty could be attained
29
30
31
32
Cosmopolitan law
only with full national emancipation, that people without their own national
government were deprived of human rights.33 The appeal to human rights
became increasingly one only resorted to if all other rights were out of reach.
The Rights of Man had been dependent on common citizenship, a situation
to which the nation state could no longer even formally approximate.
The Nazis further subverted the classical model of citizenship, declaring
that citizenship of the Reich was dependent upon possession of the correct
blood. Arendt quotes the official SS newspaper (Schwarze Korps) in 1938: If
the world is not yet convinced that the Jews are the scum of the earth, it soon
will be when unidentifiable beggars, without nationality, without money, and
without passports cross their frontiers.34 The plight of this scum is not that
they are not equal before the law, but that no law exists for them; not that they
are oppressed but that nobody wants even to oppress them.35
The nation state could not guarantee the rights of its citizens, and the
unbounded, perpetually destructive ideological madness of Nazism certainly
could not. The logic of cosmopolitan law is to tie the idea of universal human
rights to a legal structure that can give those rights some concrete reality
independently of the state. The appeal to human rights had become a sign of
absolute desperation: cosmopolitan law is one strategy that aims to give the
appeal to human rights some muscle. If the movement for cosmopolitan law
could begin to offer the de facto stateless some kind of protection, this would
also undercut the force of the politics of nationalism, which scorns as Utopian
every politics that does not involve the carving out of nation states and the
exclusion as aliens of those who do not fit.
However, the foundation of the UN, which followed the Second World
War, did little to undermine the centrality of the doctrine of absolute national
sovereignty. Article 2(4) of the UN Charter (1945) states that:
All Members shall refrain in their international relations from the threat or use of
force against the territorial integrity or political independence of any state, or in
any other manner inconsistent with the Purposes of the United Nations.36
It is clear that the prohibition of the use of force by one state against another
was a principle that needed restating and emphasising in the post-war world.
Invasion and occupation of a sovereign state was already, and was more clearly
now, perhaps the most serious and clear contravention of international law.
But there is an assumption that lies behind this principle: there must be
some sense in which the state is seen to represent the people who live within
the territory of that state. This is why invasion and occupation is undesirable.
The principle of self-determination holds that the people of a territory have
the right to determine their own destiny, free from external intervention. So
what kind of relationship is assumed to exist between the state and the people
who live within its territory?
There are clear and agreed precedents and principles laid down in
international law concerning the recognition of states and governments by
other states, governments and international bodies. Emphatically, it is not a
33
34
35
36
11
12
Yet Chapter VII appears to offer little hope for people to expect protection
against their own states. Article 32 in that chapter states that:
The Security Council shall determine the existence of any threat to the peace, breach
of the peace, or act of aggression and shall make recommendations, or decide what
measures shall be takento maintain or restore international peace and security.38
Chapter VII seems to offer some possibility that the Security Council may
authorise the use of force against a sovereign state, but the charter is careful
to emphasise that this may only be done to maintain or restore international
peace and security. So if other sovereign states are at risk there is the possibility
of intervention; emphatically not, if the only risk is to the internal population
of the state.
It must be emphasised that, while these passages from the UN Charter do
make a prima facie case against the legality of humanitarian intervention, as
do other principles of international law, they are open to interpretation and
37 UN Charter, Chapter 1, Article 2(7).
38 UN Charter, Chapter 7, Article 32.
Cosmopolitan law
13
14
or for their comrades since they belong nowhere. Cosmopolitans are never
authentic since they have no genuine home, no genuine links to the soil and
no genuine culture. Roger Scruton defines cosmopolitan as follows:
The belief in, and the pursuit of a style of life which[shows] acquaintance with,
and an ability to incorporate the manners, habits, languages, and social customs of
cities throughout the world In this sense, the cosmopolitan is often seen as a
kind of parasite, who depends upon the quotidian lives of others to create the
various local flavours and identities in which he dabbles.41
Cosmopolitan law
LeBlanc, 1991, p 2.
Nussbaum, 1997.
Held, 1995, p 228.
Kant, 1991, p 103.
Held, 1995.
15
16
as a set of ideas and practices that are replacing the Westphalian system, both
because that outdated system is no longer capable of creating a stable framework
for a changed world, and also because cosmopolitanism is a better, more open
and more democratic paradigm. The rapid growth of aspects of life that
transcend national borders raises problems of democratic accountability.
The world is changing in such a way that it is increasingly diverging, both
theoretically and structurally, from existing politics that aim to keep democratic
accountability over it. People are increasingly finding that the key networks
of power that influence their lives have escaped from their control, and that
the powerful have liberated themselves from outdated political arrangements
that are increasingly ineffective. Held reworks the concept of sovereignty,
arguing for a layered theory in which sovereignty is sited on different levels:
local, regional, national, global. What is necessary, he argues, to bind the
disparate sites of power and sovereignty into a democratic framework is an
agreed set of minimum principles, a system of cosmopolitan democratic law.
He sees the first step in this journey as the reform of the United Nations.
This process could begin with the UN taking measures to implement, extend
and enforce the UN Rights Conventions. The UN could increase its role in the
settlement and prevention of inter-state conflict by requiring states to submit
to compulsory jurisdiction in the case of disputes falling within the ambit
covered by international law and UN resolutions. The institution of an
international criminal court could play a central role in policing serious
violations of human rights. The General Assembly could play a more legislative
role if a consensus (or near consensus) in that forum were recognised as a
legitimate source of international law. The veto arrangements in the Security
Council could be modified.
A key question is the degree to which a cosmopolitan global order is
becoming a reality or whether, on the other hand, Helds principles of
cosmopolitan democracy constitute little more than a Utopian yearning. It is
not clear whether these kinds of solutions are indeed emerging out of the
existing situation or whether, on the contrary, the voices calling for
cosmopolitan democratic reform are drowned out by the demands of
international capital and great power politics. Indeed, perhaps those liberal
voices are simply being incorporated by the great powers as a democratic
cover for the usual business of pursuing national interest with all the force
that can be mustered.
This book does not focus on cosmopolitanism in general, but on a single
manifestation of its narrative: cosmopolitan criminal law. Cosmopolitanism
is open to the charge that it may turn out to herald the appearance of a new
grand narrative of emancipation to be followed, perhaps, by a new
disillusionment with its inability to deliver.47 Cosmopolitan law, in contrast,
is a set of particular ideas that has achieved a limited but real institutional
existence. The project for cosmopolitan law has had successes and failures.
The Nuremberg and Tokyo tribunals, as well as many national successor
trials, established the principle of individual criminal responsibility for
international crimes and the offence of crimes against humanity. They tried
and punished many of those guilty of crimes during the Second World War.
Many conventions have enshrined rights and prohibitions of their violation
47 Fine, 2002a.
Cosmopolitan law
in international law.48 The tribunals in The Hague and at Arusha are currently,
routinely, applying international humanitarian law and punishing some of
those who are guilty of its contravention. The indictment of Slobodan Milosevic
by the tribunal, at a moment during the Kosovo conflict in 1999 when perhaps
NATO would have preferred it to remain diplomatically silent, is a small
demonstration of the fact that the tribunals do possess some degree of
autonomy in relation to the great powers that allowed them to come into
existence. The Spanish courts established the principle that a former head of
state like General Pinochet may be arrested anywhere in the world and held
accountable for his crimes, and this principle was endorsed by English law.
The ICC is now formally a reality, although it faces significant opposition
from the United States.
On the other hand, there are compelling reasons to be sceptical. Nuremberg
was, in many ways, a fundamentally flawed process of victors justice: the
four powers made every effort to limit and control the universal principles
that they had allowed the process to enshrine as precedent. Following the
post-war trials and the consolidation of much international humanitarian law
on paper, history since the war has repeatedly demonstrated that power
politics overrides paper law. Even in the former Yugoslavia, where perhaps
the most progress has been made, some of the key criminals are still enjoying
their freedom; the legal processes are slow, underfunded and badly publicised.
The success of cosmopolitan law here, where it has been most successful, is
still questionable. And in the former Yugoslavia it happens that the
implementation of this law is in the interests of at least some great powers,
and not against the interests of the others.
Whether or not this was true in 1887, it is not true now. There is an enormous
number of manifestations of international law that function routinely and
form a framework for a world in which people, capital and information move
more or less freely. There are binding and enforceable international laws that,
for example, prevent airliners from crashing into each other and ensure that
letters sent from one country to another have a good chance of arriving. There
are international laws and agreements regulating trade, telecommunications,
copyright, and numerous other spheres of social life.50 Article 38(1) of the
48 Eg Convention on the Prevention and Punishment of the Crime of Genocide (1948); Geneva Convention
for the Amelioration of the Condition of the Wounded and Sick in Armed Forces in the Field (1949);
Convention Concerning the Abolition of Forced Labour (1957); Convention against Torture and Other
Cruel, Inhumane or Degrading Treatment or Punishment (1984). Hoog and Steinmetz, 1993.
49 Koskenniemi, 2001, p 34.
50 The fact that they operate routinely does not mean that they are not controversial; the rules of international
trade, for example, and their institutional expression, the World Trade Organisation, are subject to much
criticism.
17
18
Statute of the International Court of Justice (1945) sets out a generally accepted
statement of the sources of international law:
(a) international conventionsestablishing rules expressly recognised by
the contesting states;
(b) international custom as evidence of a general practice accepted as law;
(c) the general principles of law as recognised by civilised nations;
(d) subject to the provisions of Article 59, judicial decisions and the
teachings of the most highly qualified publicists of the various nations,
as subsidiary means of determination of the rules of law.51
The first does not pose any problem for a narrow positivist conception of law
that understands state sovereignty as the only source of legitimate authority.
The others build a framework of obligation to which states may become subject.
Customary international law is a combination of two elements: state practice
and opinio juris. The actions concerned must amount to a settled practice, and
the states involved must carry them out as though they believe that this practice
is required by a rule of law. Customary law binds all states with the exception
of those who persistently object; failure to protest against an emerging practice
in circumstances where a reaction would be expected contributes to the
formation of a new custom. Rules originating in treaties between specific states
may pass into the general corpus of international law and become accepted
as such by opinio juris, so as to become binding even for countries that were
not parties to the original treaty. Equally, treaties may be taken as declaratory
of customary law that is already in force. Similarly, UN resolutions or
declarations may be understood either as recognising existing international
law or as signalling an intent to create a new one; but it is state practice
combined with opinio juris that actually defines the law.52 UN resolutions or
conventions only become law when it can be shown that states in fact treat
them as law. The general principles (Article 38(1)c) source is one that allows
courts to make use of fundamental principles that are common to different
legal systems. The highly qualified publicist (Article 38(1)c) source allows
courts to take into account legal argument of respected legal scholars.
Yet Salisburys denial seems to be more than a view that, empirically,
international law did not exist; it also suggests that he was quite happy for it
not to exist. Martti Koskenniemi comments that an empire is never an advocate
of an international law that can seem only an obstacle to its ambitions.53 On
the one hand, a strong state may be happy to operate in the world as nothing
but a power pursuing its own interest. But on the other hand, a strong state,
particularly a hegemonic state, may be in a position to wield an overwhelming
control over the content and functioning of international law. In that case, it
has an interest in bolstering an international legal framework that it can influence
both directly, through pressure, and indirectly, through using it to project its
own world view and values.54 It would appear that the strong win either way.
51
52
53
54
Cosmopolitan law
55
56
57
58
Higgins, 1999.
Higgins, 1999, p 5.
Higgins, 1999, p 4.
Higgins, 1999, p 4.
19
20
they reunite authority and power. It is noticeable, however, that the Nuremberg
and Tokyo tribunals brought together a great deal of power, that of occupying
armies and American political will, with a somewhat hastily and inadequately
constructed authoritative framework. In contrast, in the cases of the ICTR,
the ICTY and the ICC, the authority is more solidly constructed out of the
legal precedents already set by those post-war tribunals and the codification
that followed them, and also by their more genuinely international basis, but
the power that underwrites the contemporary tribunals is less reliable and
less committed. A more complete unity of authority and power is yet to be
embodied in a cosmopolitan tribunal.
Higgins argues that her understanding of international law allows for a wider
and more open debate as to the identification and articulation of the values to be
promoted, and that it allows space for claims and counterclaims, state practice,
decisions by a variety of authorised decision makers, and the use of past decisions
and rules to develop appropriate decisions for new situations. However, referring
back to Lord Salisburys dilemma, there is clearly huge scope in Higgins
conception of a dynamic and open process of law for powerful states to influence
decision making in their own interests. They can influence the appointment of
judges who will make decisions; they can imbue processes and institutions with
their own systems of value; they can exert pressure on subordinate states and
institutions. Koskenniemi argues that anti-formalistic approaches to international
law have had an agenda of justifying American dominance in the world. On the
other hand, he also recognises that formal rules are just as capable of co-existing
with injustice as informal principles.59 It is apparent that no legal-philosophical
fix is possible.A clear system of rules provides transparency insofar as it makes
decisions predictable but not insofar as its values are covered behind a veil of
impartiality. The worth of a dynamic system of decision making based on a set
of core values depends greatly on what the core values are and who is in control
of them. The debate between formalism and dynamism must therefore be one
of emphasis rather than one of absolutes. What is most important is that in relation
to crimes against humanity, genocide and ethnic cleansing, there has emerged a
significant body of international humanitarian law, and there is still the possibility
for further development.
Cosmopolitan law
But if the cleavage between the universalist values of cosmopolitanism and the
politics of more particularist identities is understood not as a product specifically
of the postmodern now, which supplants previous political cleavages, but is
instead understood as a thread that runs throughout the time frame of the
narrative,thenwedevelopaclearerandlessapocalypticpicture.Cosmopolitanism
is not a historical stage that arrives after and as a result of the increasing perception
of the deficiencies of the old order. The idea of cosmopolitan law does not follow
nationalism, but runs parallel to it. The narrative is more appropriately understood
both as one of intertwined development and one of acute competition. Immanuel
Kant did not develop his theory of cosmopolitan law after and as a result of the
generalisation of absolute state sovereignty. The Genocide Convention (1948)
was passed simultaneously with the foundation of the UN as a conference of
independent states. The Nuremberg trials did not take place as a response to the
failures of Israeli nationalism or against its interests or sensibilities. The tribunals
for Rwanda and Yugoslavia did not come into existence because the Security
Council became convinced that absolute state sovereignty was no longer a
principle worth defending. Many of the events that we can understand as
landmarks in the development of cosmopolitan law took place within, and not
in opposition to, the existing order of power and law. Part of what is at stake,
therefore, in the argument for the recognition of cosmopolitan law, is the degree
to which its principles and institutions are able to be brought to life as independent
entities. Can they attain sufficient authority, independence and power to threaten
some of the interests that brought them into being? If they can, cosmopolitan
law attains an existence not just as a set of ideas but as a new form of law.
60 Kaldor, 1999.
61 The new cosmopolitanism has a proclivity to turn the cosmopolitan into a fixed idea or abstract idealto
turn it into an ism and so divorce it from the social world of needs, passions and conflicts of which it is
part. The new cosmopolitanism, as I read it, is not only a way of thinking that recognises the validity of
cosmopolitan ideas in social theory; it also elevates the idea of the cosmopolitan to supreme status. Fine,
2002a.
62 Kaldor, 1999, p 6.
21
22
Chapter Two
Individual responsibility and
cosmopolitan law
Chapters Two and Three examine two central advances made at the
Nuremberg tribunals that followed the Second World War. The first is the
establishment of the legal responsibility of individuals for their parts in
violations of international humanitarian law committed by large state-like
formations. The second is the codification of crimes against humanity and
the establishment of universal jurisdiction for such crimes. These two
innovations can be seen as the foundational acts of cosmopolitan criminal
law. They constitute the subjects of cosmopolitan criminal law in individual
perpetrators and individual victims, and they define the scope of such law
with the concept of universal jurisdiction.
We were only obeying orders was not a valid defence at Nuremberg. Article
8 of the Charter of the International Military Tribunal at Nuremberg (1945)
stated:
The fact that the Defendant acted pursuant to order of his Government or of a
superior shall not free him from responsibility1
Conversely, for those giving the illegal orders, the charter allowed no Acts of
State defence:
The official position of defendants, whether as Heads of State or responsible officials
in Government Departments, shall not be considered as freeing them from
responsibility or mitigating punishment. (Article 7)
The tribunal added that a superior order would not serve even as a mitigating
factor unless it was given under circumstances that left a defendant with no
moral choice but to obey the order.2
The tribunal established a definite link between individuals and their
actions, by treating so called cogs in a murder machine as perpetrators,
refusing the excuse of service to the state. It presupposes that choices are
available to the perpetrators of such crimes. If no such choice is in fact available,
that is, if the situation is one of kill or be killed, then this would constitute a
legitimate defence or mitigation.
This insistence on the individual criminal responsibility of perpetrators
was one of the most important and far-reaching precedents that were set at
Nuremberg. It is a principle that since its establishment at Nuremberg is
necessarily at the heart of cosmopolitan criminal law. The Nuremberg
precedent has been followed and strengthened by the tribunals for Yugoslavia
and Rwanda.
The question we3 shall address in this chapter is how well this legal
assumption of choice and responsibility fits with the sociological reality of
1
2
3
24
the ways in which individuals make the decision to commit a crime against
humanity. Is the decision to commit such a crime one for which it is reasonable
to hold individuals to account?
The prevailing sociological explanation of such decisions in relation to the
Nazi genocide is that provided in Zygmunt Baumans Modernity and the
Holocaust (Bauman, 1993). Bauman himself may not think of his work precisely
in this way, but his basic proposition is that it is the dominance of rational
choice over moral response in the modern age that is the key to understanding
how ordinary men and women commit such extraordinary crimes. Conversely,
the key to overcoming this potentiality is seen to lie in the development of a
postmodern ethics that subordinates the imperatives of rational choice to a
reconfigured moral point of view. Bauman does not like a world structured
around rational choice, but he accepts that this is the actuality of our present
world; he looks to a way of thinking that overcomes the constraints of rational
choice and in its place revives our suppressed capacity to act in a moral rather
than rational way From this perspective, rational choice appears as a form
of human decision making that arises in the modern epoch and that has as its
consequence the exclusion of ethical concerns. And rational choice theory
appears as a form of reified consciousness that hypostasises rational choice as
a natural presupposition of social life and blinds us to its historical
preconditions and demoralising consequences.
We are not going to defend rational choice theory against this very sharp
line of criticism, but rather argue that this line of criticism is over-dependent
on the rational choice model that it attacks. We want to argue first, that the
reduction of modernity to the imperatives of an amoral and instrumental
rationality paints a one-sided picture of modernity that obscures the inner
connections between modernity and the development of moral consciousness
itself; secondly, that the reduction of reason to instrumental, technical or
technological rationality distorts the meaning of reason and severs its
connections with thinking, understanding, willing and judgment; thirdly, that
the decisions of individuals to participate in crimes against humanity
(including those synthesised under the name of the Holocaust) cannot be
adequately explained within this framework; and fourthly, that the moral
point of view itself is far from being a purely innocent or suppressed factor in
decisions to commit crimes against humanity. Most of all, although we
recognise that Bauman and those who think like him have undoubtedly
revealed something extremely important about the nature of organised
violence in the modern age, we must also be alert to the dangers of forcing
the empirical phenomena into an over-determined theoretical straitjacket.
regardless of their moral content. It also means the prioritising of selfadvancement or self-preservation regardless of moral cost. We become a new
type of bourgeois: not the Kantian who thinks and judges for himself, but the
mass man (to use a phrase borrowed from, among others, Hannah Arendt)
who can kill without passion or enmity, simply as a job or in service to the
state, because it is an efficient means to a given end or because he is
commanded so to do or because that is what everyone else is doing. The
making of merely rational choices, without regard for ethics, is the very mark
of this social type. It is, Bauman argues, through the combination of many
such rational choices that the Jews of Europe were rounded up and murdered.
As long as we remain within this rational template, we are destined to play
our part in the genocide.
The frighteningly domestic image through which Bauman portrays
modernity is that of a garden culture in which the extermination of weeds is
the necessarily destructive aspect of the gardeners productive and aesthetic
vision. A gardener has an image of how he wants his garden to be. He wants
it to be well ordered and to conform to his own dreams of beauty and serenity.
He likes certain plants and breeds them to fit in with his plan. He does not
like other plants, which he designates as weeds and poisons or incinerates. In
this scenario, the gardener sees the elements of nature instrumentally, in terms
of how they affect him and may be affected by him, rather than as things
endowed with an intrinsic value of which he is guardian.4 In modernity human
beings are themselves stripped of intrinsic value. Some are defined as weeds,
others are selectively bred. Genocide is a kind of social weeding, and Hitler
and Stalin were but the most consistent, uninhibited expressions of the spirit
of modernity.5
If the technologisation of conception is one aspect of the spirit of modernity,
the other is the technologisation of execution. In this reading of the situation,
it was the bureaucracy that executed the final solution, and even the political
master, Hitler, found himself in the position of the dilettante standing
opposite the expert and facing the trained official.6 There is no decision, as
such, to commit crimes against humanity, simply the normal functioning of a
bureaucratic state. In his discussion of Claude Lanzmanns Shoah,7 Bauman
tells us that by far the most shocking among Lanzmanns messages is the
rationality of evil (or was it the evil of rationality?).8 For the bureaucratic
form of administration that prevails in modern society has a machine-like
quality in which each bureaucrat follows detailed written rules unthinkingly
and without responsibility for what the machine is doing as a whole.
Bureaucracy is a machine for the exclusion of moral responsibility.
Bauman argues that the defining features of modern bureaucracy were not
only well established in Germany during the Holocaust, but made the
Holocaust possible. Government was conducted through a centralised,
hierarchical and bureaucratic state; respect was afforded to science, knowledge
4
5
6
7
8
25
26
and expertise; rational behaviour was valued over irrational behaviour; the
breaking down of tasks into small parts was prevalent; and the technology of
factories and railways was well established. The Nazi regime appears in this
reading as an extreme form of the modern state, and the administration that
carried out the Holocaust as but an extreme form of modern bureaucracy.
Even the choice of extermination was an effect of the earnest effort to find
rational solutions to successive problems, and at no point did the Holocaust
come into conflict with the principles of rationality:
The Final Solution did not clash at any stage with the rational pursuit of efficient,
optimal goal-implementation. On the contrary, it arose out of a genuinely rational
concern, and it was generated by bureaucracy true to its form and purpose.9
11 Rules are nothing without interpretation. Bureaucracies are machines made up of people, each of whom
takes decisions within given parameters. Weber writes: a system of rationally debatable reasons stands
behind every act of bureaucratic administration, that is, either subsumption under norms or a weighing of
ends and means. Gerth and Mills, 1991, p 220.
12 See also Alan Bullock: There was always more than one office operating in any field. A dozen different
agencies quarrelled over the direction of propaganda, of economic policy, and the intelligence services.
Before 1938 Hitler continually went behind the back of the Foreign Office to make use of Ribbentrops
special bureau or to get information through Party channels. The dualism of Party and State organisations,
each with one or more divisions for the same function, was deliberate. In the end this reduced efficiency,
but it strengthened Hitlers position by allowing him to play off one department against another. Bullock,
1983, p 381.
13 Arendt, 1994a, p 71. In September 1939, the Security Service of the SS, a party organisation, was
fused with the regular Security Police of the State, which included the Gestapo, to form the
Head Office for Reich Security (RSHA), commanded by Heydrich. The RSHA was one of 12
head offices in the SS, two others of which were the Head Office of the Order Police, which was
responsible for rounding up Jews, and the Head Office for Administration and Economy
(WVHA), which ran concentration camps and later the economic side of extermination. [cont]
27
28
knew your action, would approve it.14 This categorical imperative is the
opposite of clear, rational, written rules. The leader principle is not that of a
bureaucracy organised on the basis of formal rules within a structured
hierarchy, for the allegiance of the official is not owed to his or her immediate
superior but to the leader himself.
The individual responsibility of the official is arguably even greater under
the leader principle than in a regulated hierarchical bureaucracy in which
responsibility and authority are distributed according to plan. On the one
hand, to grasp the will of the Fhrer demands zeal and creativity far in excess
of the old fashioned plodding bureaucrat, and wide latitude is given to subleaders for the execution of policies. On the other hand, each holder of position
is held responsible for all the activities of his subordinates, even in cases of
disobedience and failure. The perpetrators were not generally forced into the
formations that implemented the Holocaust. Eichmann was keen to win
promotion on his particular front line, and the members of the murderous
police battalions (the Einsatzgruppen) were given the opportunity to withdraw
from the killing actions.15 When they accepted the authority of these outfits,
they chose to do so even if the parameters of their choices were limited.
Authority in the modern sense of the term is not the same as power. People
choose to defer to authority. To be sure, choices are never completely free; they
are made within the limits of what is possible and of what alternatives are
possible. There are always external constraints, yet rarely are those constraints
so rigid that there is no choice; rarely is the structure so dominating that it
removes all agency. Under the leader principle, authority works through the
will of every member to know and act in accordance with the will of the leader,
and to take responsibility for all the decisions taken in their field of operation.
Bauman was right to tie his analysis of responsibility to the actual ways in
which decision making was organised in the planning and execution of the
Holocaust, that is, not to remain exclusively at the level of political philosophy
or legal theory but to link such concerns with a sociology of decision making.
However, the presumption of rationality in the substance of his analysis
obliterates what Arendt called the horrible originality of totalitarian rule.
It is commonly noticed about the Holocaust that one of its most striking
features was its industrialisation of death. The Holocaust was of its time; it
used the methods of its time and, particularly important to Bauman, are the
methods of modern management through which the genocide was in part
carried out. We say in part lest the industrial image of Auschwitz overtake
our imagination of the Holocaust as a whole. We should remember that the
Nazis devised two basic strategies for the annihilation of Jews: mass shooting
and mass gassing. Special duty troops of the SSs (Schutzstaffel) Security Service
and Security Police, called Einsatzgruppen, were assigned to each of the German
armies invading the Soviet Union and were given the task of rounding up
Jews and killing them through crude and primitive methods of shooting. These
methods were the antithesis of Baumans image of clean and dispassionate
[cont] The RSHA contained Section IV, the Gestapo, divided into Section IV-A, dealing with opponents,
and Section IV-B, dealing with sects. The Higher SS and Police Leaders were in a different command
structure to the 12 offices of the RSHA, while the Einsatzgruppen were under the command of the RSHA,
but were not one of the 12 offices: Arendt, 1994a, p 70.
14 Arendt, 1994a, p 11.
15 Browning, 1993.
29
30
Bauman argues that the regime in power is always in control of the game in
such a way that the rational choice from the point of view of the subordinates
is also the preferred choice from the point of view of the regime. So it was that
the Jewish administrators and police of the ghettos were enticed to co-operate
with the Nazis in the deportation of Jews on the grounds that, however many
Jews they produced, they were saving or at least delaying the transport of the
rest. The Nazis were able to rely on the Jews to act rationally and thus
collaborate in their own extermination:
In [the world of Auschwitz], obedience was rational; rationality was obedience
Rational people will go quietly, meekly joyously into a gas chamber, if only they
are allowed to believe it is a bathroom18
18 Bauman, 1993, p 203. He adds: [T]here are no scientific methods to decide whether the well-off residents
of the Warsaw Ghetto could have done more to alleviate the lot of the poor dying in the streets of hunger
and hypothermia, or whether the German Jews could have rebelled against the deportation of the Ostjuden,
or the Jews with French citizenship could have done something to prevent incarceration of the nonFrench Jews. Bauman, 1993, p 205.
19 Bauman, 1993, p 13.
20 Bauman, 1993, p 170. Take the case, which Bauman cites, of Dr Arthur Gtt, the Head of the National
Hygiene Department in the Ministry of Interior who argued for selective breeding of human beings. Bauman
comments that Gtt had no doubt that the policy he envisaged of selection-cum-elimination was a logical
extension, if not culmination, of the advancement of modern science. But Bauman does not discuss whether
the theories of Dr Gtt actually constituted a logical extension of the work of the celebrated scientists, nor
indeed whether there was any scientific basis whatsoever for his theorising. Gtt and his colleagues may
have been recognised by the Nazis as genuine scientists, but that does not mean that we have to accept this
recognition. The problem with eugenics was not that it was scientific but that it was not scientific. Bauman
seems to accept that Nazi doctors are doctors: that their talk of hygiene, cleansing, blood and purification
were genuinely within a medical tradition. But this is to take rhetoric at its face value.
21 Browning, 1993.
31
32
in Bosnia, the group regularly drank large amounts of alcohol in the evenings
to blank out their days and avoid having to think about their actions.
The members of Police Battalion 101 seem to fit Baumans model better
than that controversially advanced by Daniel Goldhagen,22 that they were
driven by an antecedent and virulent antisemitism. They decided to commit
crimes against humanity under the influence of the command structure to
which they were subordinated. In private life, they were no more predisposed
to violence than any other randomly selected group. Yet this genocidal
formation was able without much difficulty to incorporate most of them and
use them as its agents. There was a role for deference to authority and for the
unthinking following of orders. The individuals were explicitly given a choice
and most of them made a positive choice to kill. Social factors, such as esprit
de corps, peer pressure and the wish not to stand out, were all present in the
making of these choices. However, the hands-on massacres in which these
men participated had nothing to do with social or technological distancing
from unseen and faceless victims.23
There seems to have been some sense in which killing became an adventure
for the members of the police battalion. They became caught up in an orgy of
drink and violence and togetherness. It was, perhaps, similar to the explanation
of Varnado Simpson for his behaviour at My Lai during the Vietnam War.
Suffering from post-traumatic stress syndrome, he later described the events
as follows:
But like I say, after I killed the child, my whole mind just went. It just went. And
once you start, its very easy to keep on. Once you start. The hardestthe part
thats hard is to kill, but once you kill, that becomes easier, to kill the next person
and the next one and the next one. Because I had no feelings or no emotions or no
nothing. No direction. I just killed. It can happen to anyone. Because, see, I wasnt
the only one that did it. Hung em, you knowall types of ways. Any type of way
you could kill someone, thats what they did. And it can happen.24
22 Goldhagen, 1996.
23 Bauman acknowledges this point. He writes: At the Einsatzgruppen stage, the rounded-up victims were
brought in front of machine guns and killed at point blank range. Though efforts were made to keep the
weapons at the longest possible distance from the ditches into which the murdered were to fall, it was
exceedingly difficult for the shooters to overlook the connection between shooting and killing. But Bauman
immediately goes on to claim that this was why the administrators of the Holocaust found the methods
inefficient and dangerous to morale: Other murder techniques were therefore soughtsuch as would
optically separate the killers from their victims. The search was successful and led to the invention ofgas
chambers; the latterreduced the role of the killer to that of the sanitation officer. (Bauman, 1993, p 26.)
It seems to me that this account misconstrues not only the order of succession between the face-to-face and
the distanced (what about the death marches at the end of the war?), but also the organisation of murder
in the camps (as if the executioners did not have face-to-face contact with those they humiliated, tortured
and killed). In the genocide in Rwanda in 1994, a rate of killing which exceeded that accomplished by the
Nazis was achieved, using mainly clubs and machetes. In both Rwanda and Bosnia, it was common for
perpetrators and victims to be well known to each other. The recent evidence does not show that either
technological or social distancing are important factors in perpetrating crimes against humanity.
24 Bilton and Sim, 1992, p 7.
33
34
dichotomised between our own absolute innocence and the unspeakable Nazi
beast. He was living proof of what Karl Jaspers and Hannah Arendt termed
the banality of evil, demonstrating that the perpetrators were endowed more
with prosaic triviality than with satanic greatness.31
On the face of it, the case of Eichmann offers a strong case for Baumans
rational choice argument. It also highlights, however, a major difficulty with
his formulation of the problem. Arendt mentions one moment in the trial
when Eichmann suddenly declared that he had lived his whole life according
to Kants moral precepts and especially according to a Kantian definition of
duty. Arendt comments that this was outrageous, since Kants philosophy
was bound up with the human faculty of judgment, with thinking for oneself,
and so rules out blind obedience. However, when pressed further, Eichmann
revealed that he had read Kants Critique of Practical Reason, and he came up
with a roughly correct version of the categorical imperative:
I meant by my remark about Kant that the principle of my will must always be
such that it can become the principle of general laws.32
Headdedthat,fromthemomenthewaschargedwithcarryingoutthefinalsolution,
he knowingly ceased to live according to Kantian principles. Arendt comments
that Eichmann did not merely cease to follow Kants categorical imperative but
ratherthathedistortedit inlinewithHansFranksformulation,whichismentioned
above: Act in such a way that the Fhrer, if he knew your action, would approve
it. This meant that duty was duty, a law was a law; there could be no exceptions,
not even for ones own friends. But when Eichmann said that he had given up on
Kant, this also meant in effect that he had put his own self-advancement before
any ethical concerns, and blind obedience to the leader before his own practical
reason and reflective judgment. In saying this, he must have recognised at some
level his own descent into thoughtlessness, lack of reflection, unreason.
This episode reveals the inversion of reason and passion in Baumans
reformulation of Kant. In place of Kants identification of practical reason
with larger moral concerns and passion with self-interest, self-advancement
and self-preservation, Bauman reverses this order of association. Reason is
now identified with self-interest, self-advancement and self-preservation, and
ethics is now identified with ones emotional response to the face of the
suffering other. In Kants hierarchy of reason and passion, passion is
subordinated to the demands of reason but is not denounced or damned.
Baumans hierarchy is more severe: it does denounce reason (that which
Kant calls passion) in favour of postmodern ethics (that which Kant calls
reason). The neo-Kantian turns out to be more Kantian than Kant. The effect
of this inversion is not only to accept the disconnection of rational choice
from ethics, but also to sever the relationship between thinking and
understanding on the one hand, and moral judgment and decision making
on the other.33 There are many moments in the text when Bauman writes of
the separation of reason and ethics under Nazism. This may well be true,
though we would continue to insist that the Holocaust had more to do with
31 Arendt and Jaspers, 1992, p 62.
32 Arendt, 1994a, p 136.
33 The interconnections of thinking, willing and judging, and the dangers inherent in the separation of thinking
from willing and judging, became the subject matter of Hannah Arendts later investigations in The Life of
the Mind: Arendt, 1978.
34 At a lecture Bauman gave at Warwick University on 19 February 2001, I was twice able to ask him what his
attitude was to crimes against humanity trials. I still do not know what his attitude is, since he seemed to
go to some lengths to avoid giving a straight answer.
35 Bauman, 1993, p 206.
36 Finkielkraut, 1992.
35
36
The reality is that not everyone was responsible for the Holocaust. Social
structures were in place that put considerable pressure on many individuals
to commit crimes against humanity. There was peer pressure; there was the
pressure to pursue personal success and advancement; there was pressure to
conform; there was pressure to submit to authority; there was pressure to
follow racist and genocidal ideology. There were risks, sometimes small,
sometimes large, but very rarely life-threatening, in resisting these pressures.
There were also more personal motives, such as killing as part of an adventure
or as an outlet for psychological frustration and anger, and such as simple
sadism or love of power. But whatever motives were to the fore in any
particular case, it is clear that individuals made choices; sometimes choice
was limited; sometimes other options were not attractive; sometimes they
were difficult and dangerous. But perpetrators are never merely the puppets
of the social structure within which they find themselves.
37
Chapter Three
Crimes against humanity:
the actualisation of a universal
Auschwitz has become the signature of an entire epochand it concerns all of us.
Something happened there that no one could previously have thought even possible.
It touched a deep layer of solidarity among all who have a human face.1
In this chapter I look at the Nuremberg process, the ways in which the charge
of crimes against humanity was used, and the codification of the term
genocide in the Genocide Convention (1948). I go on to look at the emerging
academic discipline of genocide studies and the ways in which it understands
and defines these concepts.
The Nuremberg process, in spite of its inadequacies and flaws, was the
beginning of the actualisation of the concept of cosmopolitan criminal law. It
was the point at which power first coincided with supra-national authority
in a successful legal response to mass killing. The acceptance of the new legal
charge of crimes against humanity heralded the recognition of the principle
that the most serious human rights abuses are the business of all human beings,
and that the prosecution of such crime is therefore a supra-national matter.
The development of cosmopolitan criminal law is a process that occurs within
the sphere of existing global politics and diplomacy, and within the sphere of
existing power relationships. It is a messy and uncertain development, always
beset by the grossest hypocrisy. It is diluted and perverted by those states and
heads of states who have reason to fear the consequences of universal
jurisdiction. It is the opposite of Utopian; it has a real existence and an organic
development. It is not just the assertion of an abstract universal by critics but
is the concrete development of a universal in the real world.
It was not a new problem that faced the four powers when they were
confronted with the prospect of victory in 1945. Whenever the overthrow of
an old regime is achieved, the problem is posed of how to deal with the old
leadership in order to neutralise them as a threat, hold them to account for
their actions, and build the foundations of the new regime in such a way as to
make its difference clear to all. When Charles I and Louis XVI were executed,
there was little doubt as to the legal irregularity of the institutions that decided
their fates. It could not have been otherwise, since under all existing law
regicide was the greatest crime. Otto Kirchheimer calls this trial by fiat of the
successor regime and the Nuremberg trial the most important successor
trial in modern history.2 Part of its importance was in putting up a barrier
1
2
between the past and the present. Experience shows that every successor
regime feels intensely that in condemnation of the predecessors practices lies
the key to humanitys future3 Post-war trials of Nazis, therefore, had clear
benefits for the four powers in terms of legitimation, both of themselves and
of the new regimes that they wanted to build.
However, as soon as they had allowed the genie of cosmopolitan law out
of the bottle, they went to great lengths to control it, limit it and peg it back.
The universality of the new form was perceived as threatening. No crimes
were to be considered that had been committed by any of the Allies, such as
the bombings of Dresden, Tokyo, Hiroshima or Nagasaki; the treatment of
German civilians by the Red Army; the Russian complicity in the invasion of
Poland; or French collaboration with the Nazis. The concept of crimes
against humanity at Nuremberg was tied to crimes against peace and to war
crimes, which were safer charges for the powers because they were more
concerned with familiar questions of inter-state relationships and
sovereignty.4 The Allied powers tried to avoid allowing the universality of
the crimes against humanity charge to set universal precedents. They did
this by particularising the charge. The offence of crimes against humanity
was linked to a particular nation, Germany, and a particular frame, that of
the Second World War.5 At Nuremberg, it was easy for the four powers to
keep significant control over much of the process. In the end a conclusion as
to the efficacy of international cosmopolitan law must focus on the question
of its ability to find an autonomous space for itself. If cosmopolitan criminal
law is able to attain a genuine life outside the control of the great powers,
then this autonomy is achieved; if it remains nothing more than a faade
erected for purposes of legitimation that remains forever under the control of
the powerful, then it is not.
3
4
5
6
39
40
While the prosecution argued that the offence of crimes against humanity
was in fact simply a distillation of existing law, the formulation and use of
that charge set an important precedent.
The London conference of the USA, the USSR, Britain and France took
place in summer 1945, and produced the charter of the tribunal. The trial of
the major war criminals started on 20 November 1945 and finished on 1
October 1946 with three acquittals, seven prison sentences and 12 death
sentences. There were eight members of the tribunal or judges, a senior and
an alternate from each of the four powers. There were notable absences from
the dock: Adolf Hitler, Josef Goebbels, Heinrich Himmler and Martin Bormann
were dead. Gustav Krupp was intended to represent German industrial might
in the dock, but was elderly and found by the court to be mentally incompetent.
However, all of the leading Nazis who had been arrested were on trial.
The prosecution at Nuremberg charged the defendants with four counts.
Count one, conspiracy, charged all 22 of the defendants with participation in
a common plan to prepare and execute the substantive crimes enumerated in
counts two, three and four:
At the trial of any individual member of any group or organisation the Tribunal
may declare (in connection with any act of which the individual may be convicted)
that the group or organisation of which the individual was a member was a criminal
organisation.7
Count one, charging defendants with conspiracy, is not outlined in the charter
as the other three counts are: the language of conspiracy is included in Article
6(a) in relation to crimes against peace, but not (b) or (c) in relation to war
crimes or crimes against humanity. The charter was the result of hurried
negotiations in London and showed the effects of much patching and
compromise. 8 Stanislaw Pomorski comments that one is at a loss to
understand why conspiracy to prepare an aggressive war should be a crime
per se while conspiracy to set up a death camp should not be.9 The ambiguity
and confusion of the charter left considerable law making powers in the hands
of the tribunal, and Jackson prepared the conspiracy count to include all the
other substantive crimes, arguing that the tribunal should accept this even
though it was not explicitly allowed by the charter itself. In the end the
judgment of the tribunal rejected Jacksons expansion of the conspiracy charge.
The conspiracy/criminal organisation plan was conceived by a young
lawyer from the American Department of War, Colonel Murray C Bernays,
and was set out in a memorandum dated 15 September 1944.10 Bernays
opposed an administrative solution to the problem of de-Nazification,
preferring a judicial one that was intended to grant due process. He proposed,
first, that a court should judge that the Nazi government, party and agencies
such as the SS (Schutzstaffel) and SA (Sturm Abteilung) were conspiracies to
commit murder and other crimes. The same court should then try individuals
considered to be representative of those organisations who would then be
found guilty of the same offences on the grounds of their membership of
these organisations alone. Once the conspiracy was established, each act of
7
8
9
10
every member thereof during its continuance and in furtherance of its purposes
would be imputable to all other members thereof.11 Thus any member of
these criminal organisations could then be arrested and found guilty simply
by virtue of their membership.
Jackson argued for the conspiracy/criminal organisation approach in
order to reach a great many of the equally guilty persons against whom
evidence of specific violent acts might be lacking although there is ample
proof that they participated in the common plan or enterprise or
conspiracy.12 Bernays plan was adopted by the Americans with a little
refinement and watering down.
Pomorski argues that the approach was important in that it allowed the
tribunal to find that Hitlerism, as a social phenomenon, was criminal:
If one perceives a deterrent and preventive function of criminal law in a broad
sense, if one views it as a consciousness-building factor, the idea of organisational
prosecution fulfilled its tasks very well.13
Renaud Donnedieu de Vabres, the French senior judge, set out his argument
against conspiracy in two deliberative s3essions (27 June and 14 August 1946)
and with two memoranda.14 First, conspiracy was, he argued, anAnglo-American
legal concept, unknown to both continental and international law. Secondly, the
prosecution had failed to prove the existence of a huge 25-year conspiracy
beginning in the early 1920s; it had failed to establish that there was a common
plan to prove that a group of people had, at a specific time and place, agreed on
definite criminal objectives and the criminal methods they intended to use to
attain them. Instead, the prosecution had merely gathered up various expressions
of Nazi principles such as passages from the party programme and quotations
from Mein Kampf, contending that these were the core of a fixed criminal plan.
He argued that there had been no master plan, but a development of policy.15
Thirdly, conspiracy was not a crime against international law at the time the acts
were committed so that any charges would be ex post facto. Fourthly, the London
charter had only listed three prosecutable crimes. At the end of Article 6, the
mysterious short paragraph had been added stating that all those who participated
in a common plan or conspiracy to commit any crimes would be responsible
for all the acts performed by any persons in execution of the plan.16 Donnedieu
deVabres argued that this paragraph was aimed at complicity and did not provide
for a specific general crime of conspiracy.17 Fifthly, he argued that conspiracy
required some degree of equality amongst the conspirators that did not exist in
this case due to the overpowering weight of the Fhrer compared to the other
actors. He wanted to convict for substantive crimes and, where necessary, also
to punish accomplices and accessories, but to drop the conspiracy charges.
Some German observers welcomed Donnedieu de Vabres opposition to
conspiracy charges, since they implied collective German guilt, but he himself
11
12
13
14
15
41
42
took the opposite position. He thought that to find the Nazi leadership guilty
of the conspiracy would too easily absolve those Germans not directly
involved. He was also worried that the Jewish conspiracy myth could be
replaced by blaming a small secret Nazi conspiracy for Germanys problems.
The case of Karl Doenitz illustrates the complexities involved in the idea of
conspiracy. He was Commander of the German submarine programme from
1935 until 1943, when he became Commander in Chief of the navy. He was
convicted at Nuremberg on counts two and threecrimes against peace and
war crimesand sentenced to 10 years in prison. There was much discussion in
his case about the attack on Norway, and whether this particular attack was
aggressive or defensive, since there was evidence that the British were also
planning to attack Norway. There was also much discussion about the waging
of submarine warfare, and whether Doenitz had been responsible for a policy of
failing to rescue or actively killing survivors of naval attacks. Biddle, theAmerican
judge, admitted that Germany waged a much cleaner [naval] war |than we
did.18 The case against Doenitz hung on things that were not centrally important,
and that might have been carried out by either side in the war, such as the attack
on Norway or the ruthlessness of submarine warfare. But was there not a case
for charging Doenitz with being a part of the Nazi machine that planned to rule
the world and commit crimes against humanity? There was a division of labour:
some ran death camps; others took the territory that was to be cleansed of Jews;
others patrolled the seas to keep them safe for Nazi shipping and dangerous for
enemy shipping. Irrespective of particular crimes committed by the U-boat fleet,
there was a good argument for finding that those who ran the U-boat fleet were
doing so as part of a greater Nazi plan. Crimes against humanity or genocide are
necessarily conspiracies. Though the court in general rejected the conspiracy
prosecution,itmaybearguedthattofinddefendantsguiltyoftheothersubstantive
crimes contained the necessary element of conspiracy in a different form.
Count two of the prosecution was crimes against peace:
All the defendants with divers other persons during the period of years preceding
8 May 1945 participated in the planning, preparation, initiation and waging of wars
of aggression that were also wars in violation of international treaties, agreements
and assurances.19
In 1927 the Assembly of the League of Nations had adopted the Declaration
on Aggressive War, which declared aggressive war to be an international crime:
All wars of aggression are, and shall always be, prohibited. Every pacific means
must be employed to settle disputes of every description that may arise between
states.20
In 1928 these propositions were incorporated into the Paris Pact for the
Renunciation of War as an Instrument of National Policy, signed by 15 states
and later adhered to by 48 others, converting it into a universal treaty. The
Kellogg-Briand Pact (1933), the Convention for the Definition of Aggression,
reaffirmed these principles. The t ribunal at Nuremberg held that the KelloggBriand Pact in particular constituted international law against the waging of
aggressive war. In its opinion, the renunciation of war:
18 Pomorski, 1990, p 261.
19 Smith, 1977, p 16.
20 Lukashuk, 1990, p 127.
The tribunal also noted thatArticle 227 of the Treaty of Versailles (1919) provided
for the establishment of a special international tribunal to try the former German
Emperor for a supreme offence against international morality and the sanctity
of treaties. Article 228 provided for the indictment of others accused of having
committed acts in violation of the laws and customs of war.22
Count three, war crimes, was the least controversial count since it relied on
the most precedent. It added together the sections of the Hague Rules of Land
Warfare and the Geneva Conventions that prohibited certain wartime actions,
such as acts of mistreatment of prisoners, murder and devastation not justified
by military necessity.23 These conventions and treaties became part of customary
international law that binds all states irrespective of whether or not they have
ratified this or that particular convention. Common war crimes evolve into
crimes against humanity if they are committed pursuant to orders drawn up
in advance, thereby assuming a state-organised character, and also have as
their objective the mass annihilation of people.24 States have the responsibility
to prosecute their own soldiers who commit war crimes. Clearly, when the
state itself is criminal the prosecutions must come from outside the state.
43
44
To the extent that the crimes committed by the Nazi regime, particularly
against the Jews, were unprecedented, the formulation of a law that was capable
of addressing the particular unprecedented characteristics was required. Crimes
against humanity are different from murder, not just quantitatively, but also
qualitatively. The Nazis were not simply unwilling to share Germany with the
Jews; they were unwilling to share the earth with them. State expulsions, murders
and persecutions were not unprecedented; in the context of international law,
expulsions had been considered as crimes against neighbouring states. Genocide
is qualitatively different; it is a criminal enterprise against the human
condition.29 As Hannah Arendt puts it, genocide is:
an attack upon human diversity as such, that is, upon a characteristic of the
human status without which the very words mankind or humanity would be
devoid of meaning.30
29
30
31
32
[cont] civilisation for their parts in the deportation of Armenians. Kemal was hanged, but there was much
nationalist opposition to the process and the Ottoman court freed many other prisoners without charge. In
the end the British were also forced by the triumph of the nationalists in 1921 to free their prisoners.
Constantinople is the Nuremberg that failed. What Constantinople shows, most of all, is that the enormous
political difficulties of mounting prosecutions against foreign war criminals can be so great that a tribunal
can crumble. Bass, 2000, p 106.
Edgar Faure, in Finkielkraut, 1992, p 28.
Arendt, 1994a, p 269.
Fine, 2000.
Jaspers, 2000.
45
46
name of humanity, against those sections of society that were held not to
recognise the existence of any fundamental human community. Heidegger
was against individuals being held criminally responsible at Nuremberg,
arguing that the legal subject was a fiction that forgets the historicality and
finite freedom of human existence and the homelessness of modern human
beings. He argued, and Zygmunt Bauman was later much influenced by his
argument, that the events of the Holocaust were the results of such a profound
malady of modern society that any attempt to scapegoat a few individuals in
a legal process would constitute nothing more than empty hypocrisy.
Fine argues, in summary, that the originality and strength of Arendts
understanding of the Nuremberg process was in the way she recognised the
limited justification of each of these understandings of the Nuremberg
processhumanist, realist and post-humanistand wove them into a more
critical and grounded cosmopolitan argument. What gives her discussions
their force is the recognition of the equivocation of law and her readiness to
embrace legal remedy in the knowledge of its risks.38
At the time of Nuremberg, Arendt wrote to Jaspers that the Nazi crimes
were such that no law could prosecute them, that no mundane criminal process
could achieve any sort of justice, or punish the perpetrators with anything
but an inadequate sentence. [T]his guilt, in contrast to all criminal guilt,
oversteps and shatters any and all legal systems. That is the reason why the
Nazis at Nuremberg are so smug.39 Yet 15 years later, in relation to the
Eichmann trial, it was Arendt who defended the trial against Jaspers
scepticism. For her, that trial represented missed opportunities to push the
bounds of cosmopolitan law, to institute an international court and to bolster
the offence of crimes against humanity. Nevertheless, she defended the right
of the Israelis to kidnap the indicted Nuremberg war criminal Eichmann from
a state with a bad record for extradition, and to put him on trial. This action
served the cause of justice, resulted in the punishment of Eichmann, gave
many victims their day in court, and allowed the story of the Holocaust to be
retold in an authoritative way to a new generation. Throughout her work,
Arendt is aware both of the importance of the cosmopolitan project of
international criminal law and of the many problems and shortcomings of its
actuality. She wrestles with the perplexities and contradictions. She avoids
what Fine40 refers to as cosmopolitan utopianism as well as realist cynicism
while engaging positively with the question of crimes against humanity
prosecutions.41
38
39
40
41
Fine, 2000.
Arendt and Jaspers, 1992.
Fine, 2000.
In a process which ran parallel to the Nuremberg tribunals, Allied military commissions condemned 920
Japanese to death and sentenced to prison terms 3,000 others who had been found guilty of crimes during
the Second World War. The International Military Tribunal sat in Tokyo from 1946 to 1948, trying the 25
most senior Japanese defendants. The International Military Tribunal for the Far East (IMTFE) was set up
by a special proclamation of General MacArthur, Supreme Commander for the Allied Powers in the
Pacific, with a charter similar to that for the Nuremberg tribunal. One important difference was that only
persons charged with crimes against peace could stand before the tribunal; all others were to be tried by
national or other courts. The Emperor of Japan, Hirohito, was not charged with any crimes. This seems to
have been simply a political decision made by the Americans; they wanted Hirohito to remain as Emperor
in their newly established regime. Political considerations, and the consolidation of a friendly and antiRussian regime, took precedence over cosmopolitan law: Piccigallo, 1979.
47
48
During the preparations for the main trial at Nuremberg, the Russians had
specifically wanted the inclusion of a charge relating to the massacre of Polish
officers in the Katyn forest. However, the Americans found evidence showing
that it was the Russians themselves who had committed the massacre. The
scandal was hushed up by the court.42 This incident, however, illustrates the
fact that the Cold War was, during the trials, rapidly beginning to freeze.
There had been a period of about a year when the interests of all the great
powers had converged around the prosecution of the Nazis. This remarkable
period, however, was short-lived. The struggle between the USSR and the
USA for global hegemony began to take precedence over the establishment of
a global legal order, and co-operation in the name of justice quickly crumbled.
The Cold War saw the emphatic re-emergence of particular interest as against
cosmopolitan order. The global bipolar struggle was everything. Both sides
held that victory in the global ideological and military struggle was the
prerequisite for any kind of justice.
During the American war in Vietnam, there was little question of any kind
of jurisdiction over crimes committed by combatants, but there was one notable
exception. A military court-martial tribunal found William L Calley guilty in
April 1971 of the murder of at least 22 Vietnamese civilians at My Lai on 16
March 1968. Between 8 am and noon on that day, 504 non-combatant
inhabitants of My Lai, everyone who was there, were killed by the American
soldiers of Charlie Company.43 Calley was, even before My Lai, a sadistic
killer. During a previous assault on a village, he had thrown a defenceless old
man down a well and shot him.44 At My Lai, he saw a baby crawling away
from a ditch that was already filled with dead and dying villagers; he seized
the child by the leg, threw it back into the pit, and shot it.45 Nobody else was
ever held legally responsible for the massacre: no other killers, no one higher
up the chain of command. No one else was found guilty of any war crime
during the entire Vietnam War. Calley was sentenced to life imprisonment
with hard labour. He served his sentence under comfortable conditions, and
was released on parole in 1974 by Judge Robert Elliott, who said: war is war,
and it is not unusual for innocent civilians such as the My Lai victims to be
killed.46
While there was a lack of official tribunals and legal accountability, it is
nevertheless true that during the Vietnam War one important weapon in the
armoury of the anti-war movement was the appeal to international law. The
war could legitimately be characterised as a crime against peace; there was
much behaviour that could be characterised as war crimes and crimes against
humanity. Bertrand Russell wrote a book entitled War Crimes in Vietnam,47 for
example, and Jean-Paul Sartre published a pamphlet48 with the same name,
arguing that the American war in Vietnam constituted genocide. In May 1967
in Stockholm, and November 1967 in Roskilde, Denmark, a tribunal was
organised to investigate whether the USA was guilty of crimes under
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
many millions were killed, and the death rate was about 40% of the population,
therewasnogenocidalideologyorintent.InthecaseofthekillingoftheArmenians
in Turkey in 1915, there was similarly no genocidal intent, but rather the killing
was the result of an over-zealous nationalism. The purpose was ethnic cleansing,
rather than killing. He makes a similar argument in the cases of the killing of the
Ibo in Nigeria and of the native Brazilians. The Gypsies were killed by the Nazis
but this did not constitute genocide:
The overall Nazi policy toward the Gypsies was different in kind from that toward
the Jews The Nazis did not ontologise the Gypsy into their metahistoric antithesis,
nor did they make the elimination of all Gypsies from history a primal part of
either their historic moral mission or their metaphysical mythos.54
Taylor, argued that the bombings of Hiroshima and Nagasaki did not constitute
genocide, as people were killed because they lived in enemy strongholds and
not because the Americans had the intention of killing them simply because
of their ethnicity.
Destexhe wants to keep the definition of genocide narrow in order to focus
attention on the most serious cases. He is worried about the dilution of the
term genocide, believing that a process of verbal inflation is diminishing its
power. When people campaign against a particular set of acts that they
consider evil, they often use the word genocide in order to highlight the
seriousness of their case. Racism against black people in the USA;59 the selling
of tobacco that causes millions to die of lung cancer; the abortion of millions
of foetuses; the refusal by governments to fund AIDS research sufficiently
all have been characterised as genocides.
The genocide studies scholars, on the other hand, want to keep the definition
broad in order to incorporate into their discipline all cases of mass killing:
[b]y genocide studies we mean attempts to expose, comprehend, and prevent
the phenomenon of genocidal killing as a subject in its own right and, ideally, in
comparative perspective.60
Helen Fein carried out a study of introductory sociology texts from 194777,
and showed that a minority of texts in all three decades defined and recognised
genocide; those in the middle decade (195767) were least likely to mention
genocide, while those published last (196877) were almost twice as likely to
recognise genocide as those in the decade after the Second World War.61 She
goes on to say that the beginning of professional social scientific interest in
genocide was in the 1970s, and that comparative research on genocide is
almost wholly generated by scholars educated in the USA and writing in
English.
These scholars reject the idea that the Holocaust was a profoundly unique
or holy event that defies analysis and understanding. They situate themselves
in a certain sociological and scientific methodological tradition that particularly
values comparative studies.
Michael Freeman62 formulates the rejection of the profound uniqueness
argument by making a critique of Elie Wiesels religious understanding of the
Shoah and of his insistence on the primacy of survivor testimony over social
scientific analysis. He quotes Wiesels three reasons for holding that the
Holocaust cannot be wholly explicable:
(1) The events obeyed no law and no law can be derived from them; (2) complete
understanding would require identification with all the victims and all the
executioners, which is impossible; (3) no language is sufficient to communicate the
Holocaust experience; the language of science, in particular, fails before the suffering
of the victims.
His answers to Wiesel are, first, that contemporary social scientific forms of
understanding are more sophisticated and flexible than simply the search for
laws of social behaviour; understanding can be derived from analysis, and
59
60
61
62
Weisbord, 1975.
Markusen and Kopf, 1995, p 5.
Fein, 1993, p 5.
Freeman, 1991, p 187.
51
52
that understanding does not need to aspire to a totalising quest for absolute
knowledge. Secondly, while empathy is necessary for an analysis of genocide, it
is also necessary to go beyond the subjective consciousness of victims and
perpetrators, and to investigate the social structures in which they find themselves
and which help to make them who they are, as well as simply focusing on their
agency. Thirdly, the problem of language is a general problem about the
representation of experience, which may be particularly acute in the case of the
Holocaust; but it would be a greater error for social science to ignore this challenge
than for it to attempt, sensitively and carefully, to confront it. Freeman also argues
that, since Wiesel considers the study of the Holocaust to be important in order to
prevent possible future genocides, then it is clear that past and future must have
important elements in common. The Holocaust may be unique in certain ways,
as is any event, but it also has features in common with other genocides, and
other possible future genocides.
Markusen and Kopf similarly criticise those whom they call, following Alan
Rosenberg and Evelyn Silverman,63 Holocaust absolutists, who hold that the
Holocaust was a profoundly unique event, outside history and outside the
possibility of representation or comparison. They prefer to call themselves
contextualists, which means that they see the Holocaust in its historical
context and that they assert the validity of comparison.
It is the rejection of the idea of the uniqueness of the Holocaust, and the
insistence that it is an event within, not outside, history, that allows genocide
studies to broaden its focus from the single event and look also at similar
social phenomena. Leo Kuper, one of the founders of the discipline, says that
he has been driven to this terrain by the realisation that genocide is all too
common in our own day, and that the organisation charged with its prevention
and punishment, the United Nations (UN), responds with indifference, if not
with condonation.64 A central concern, then, of the emerging discipline is not
the uniqueness, but the ordinariness of genocide. And, as Bauman argues,
sociologys traditional neglect of the field as a pathological condition of society,
rather than as an aspect of societys normal functioning, becomes untenable.
Israel W Charny argues as follows:
What is needed, I would argue, is a generic definition of genocide that does not
exclude or commit to indifference any case of mass murder of any human beings,
of whatever racial, national, ethnic, biological, cultural, religious, and political
definitions, or of totally mixed groupings of any and all of the above.
I propose that whenever large numbers of unarmed human beings are put to death
at the hands of their fellow human beings, we are talking about genocide.65
Frank Chalk argues that social scientists have a different set of objectives to
those of international lawyers. Lawyers are concerned with successful
prosecution, while sociologists are concerned with:
outlining the boundaries of a set of cases which they want to study for the
purpose of discovering their common elements and analysing the processes that
brought them about. Perhaps these differences in objectives account for the
differences in breadth and focus which one finds in the several definitions of
63 Rosenberg and Silverman, 1992.
64 Kuper, 1982, p 9.
65 Charny, 1994, p 74.
53
54
69
70
71
72
73
74
55
56
Chapter Four
Peace, security and justice
in the former Yugoslavia
In Chapters Four and Five, I look at three different approaches taken by the
international community towards the conflict in the former Yugoslavia. In
Srebrenica, security and justice were subordinated to a vain quest for peace
and the avoidance of conflict. The wish to avoid at all costs any disruption of
the peace ended in disaster for those who had understood that they were
being promised life-saving help by the UN. In Kosovo, the international
community in the form of the North Atlantic Treaty Organisation (NATO)
focused on preventing and reversing the ethnic cleansing, yet with such a
blunt use of force that peace, security and justice all suffered. The priority
given by the intervening powers to avoiding putting their own soldiers at
risk had not changed since Srebrenica, but the policy that flowed from it took
a very different form. The establishment of the International Criminal Tribunal
for the former Yugoslavia (ICTY) focused on justice, yet it was established
under the Security Councils powers to work for peace and security. While
the ICTY has been denounced from many different angles, I argue that its
most important achievement is its existence; it is an empirical fact.
Cosmopolitan criminal law exists, and in those three courtrooms in The Hague,
as well as in Arusha, it conducts the daily business of putting people on trial
for crimes against humanity and genocide. In Chapter Five, I look at two
cases at the ICTY in detail.
In July 1995, a crime against humanity was committed by Bosnian Serb forces
against the Muslims who lived in Srebrenica or who had fled there for safety.
This crime was committed under the noses of UN forces, who did little to
prevent it.
By the end of May 1992, Serb forces had occupied and ethnically cleansed
a large part of eastern and western Bosnia, and the front line that was
established then was essentially stable until the summer of 1995. There were,
however, Bosnian Muslim enclaves that they had failed to defeat: Bihac in the
west, and Gorazde, Zepa, and Srebrenica in the east. Refugees fled to these
enclaves, swelling their original populations.
Between May 1992 and January 1993, Bosniak forces from Srebrenica
attacked and destroyed Serb villages near the town. Serb forces responded
with a counter-offensive, capturing some villages and severing the link
between Srebrenica and Zepa.2 The Bosnian Government put pressure on the
1
2
58
It seems, however, that the world did not really notice this nice distinction. It
was understood that the UN was guaranteeing the safety of civilians who
lived within these enclaves. But the Security Council had only placed a duty
upon the Bosniaks and the Serbs to keep these areas safe; UNPROFORs role
would be to monitor the humanitarian situation.
3
4
5
6
7
The final Serb attack on the safe area of Srebrenica began on Tuesday 6 July
1995. There was much small arms fire and shelling recorded by the Dutch
from their observation posts that surrounded the town. One observation post
in particular came under attack, and the soldiers inside it surrendered to the
Serbs, who eventually allowed them to go back towards their comrades in
the town in their armoured car. On their way back, they encountered a Muslim
roadblock through which they drove without stopping. One soldier, Raviv
van Renssen, was shot in the head and killed. A second observation post was
attacked and overwhelmed by the Serb forces. The Serbs gave them a choice:
8 Yugoslav National Army.
9 Prosecutor v Kristic, para 28.
10 Prosecutor v Kristic, para 28.
59
60
they could either make their way back to their unit in Srebrenica or be taken
prisoner. The soldiers opted to be taken prisoner. The Dutch Lieutenant Colonel
Karremans did not yet understand that Srebrenica was in danger of falling to
the Serb forces. By Saturday, the Bosnian army was decisively outgunned;
they wanted NATO air strikes against Serb forces. Their strategy was to
manoeuvre the Dutch into the line of fire, so that they would be forced to call
for air support. They therefore made it difficult for the Dutch to withdraw
from their observation posts into the town. But the Dutch soldiers preferred
to surrender to the Serbs, who treated them well, than to remain in their
positions.
At 10 pm on Sunday, the most senior UN Commander in the former
Yugoslavia, French Lieutenant General Bernard Janvier, ordered the Dutch
battalion to position their armoured cars around Srebrenica in order to stop
the Serb advance. From Zagreb, Janvier and Yasushi Akashi, the UN Secretary
Generals special representative, sent an ultimatum to the Serbs: they were to
withdraw from Srebrenica and release the captured Dutch soldiers, or else air
support would be employed.
On Monday morning, there was increased shelling of the town, both of the
Muslim civilians and refugees and of the Dutch soldiers, followed by a relative
lull. By early evening, Serb soldiers were lining up above Srebrenica ready to
advance into the town. Muslim civilians began to flee from the town towards
the north. At 6.30 pm, the Serbs began to advance. Many Muslim civilians
streamed towards the Dutch compound at Potocari, just outside the town, for
protection, and broke into it. The Bosnian army was trying to stop civilians
from withdrawing from the town to the base; they still wanted to force the
Dutch to fight, and to call for air support. Most of the refugees remained in
Srebrenica during the night of 1011 July.
The Dutch requested air support at 7 pm during the Serb attack. Following
much discussion and delay, Janvier promised that NATO would be ready to
attack from the air by 6 am. The Dutch soldiers were informed that NATO
had given an ultimatum to the Serbs that if they did not withdraw they would
come under heavy air attack first thing in the morning. Janvier and Akashi,
however, had only agreed to the air attack if the Dutch troops were attacked
first.
Karremans announced to the Bosnian army and the civilian town council
that the Serbs had been warned to withdraw on the threat of NATO air strikes.
The Bosnians did not trust Karremans. Major Fahrudin Salihovic, of the
Bosnian army, twice asked Karremans if he could guarantee that the attack
would take place. Karremans twice answered dont shoot the piano player,
which was translated by the interpreter as dont trouble the bringer of good
tidings.
NATO aircraft were in the air from 6 am, ready to attack. All in Srebrenica
waited for the attack. UNPROFOR commanders were waiting to be contacted
by the Dutch if they were being attacked by the Serbs.
The NATO aircraft, which had been airborne since 6 am, were forced to
return to their base in Italy by 11.30 am. The Serb forces were made aware of
this from radar bases in Serbia. Shortly after 11 am, the Serb attack resumed.
The Dutch resumed the evacuation of refugees to their base. There were some
limited NATO air attacks that afternoon. The Serbs issued an ultimatum of
their own. If the air attacks were not stopped, the captured Dutch soldiers
would be killed and the refugees and Dutch battalion would be shelled. The
Dutch Government, Akashi and UNPROFOR quickly halted the air attacks.
The Dutch withdrew to their base, and Karremans opened ceasefire
negotiations with the Serb forces.
By the evening of 11 July, there were around 25,000 Muslim refugees, mostly
women and children, crowded into the Dutch base. The highly organised
and pre-planned Serb deportation operation began. Ratko Mladic himself
was in Srebrenica on 11 July, with a television camera crew, to organise the
cleansing of the town in order to make, as he told the cameras, a present to
the Serbian nation. His meeting with Karremans was filmed; Karremans raised
a glass to toast the Serb victory. He was ordered by Mladic to return with
representatives of the Muslim refugees in order to organise the deportations.
Conditions in and around the Dutch base were bad. At the trial at the ICTY
of Radislav Kristic, the Chief of Staff of the Drina corps of the Bosnian Serb
army, a resident of Srebrenica described the scene:
The baby had its pram, and we left our belongings in the pram or simply lay down
on the ground As we sat there, snipers would fire every now and then, and all
this throng would then move to one side or the other, screaming.11
Above them was the village of Pecista where the Serb soldiers were setting
houses on fire. At the sound of shelling, the whole crowd would simply dodge
to one side or the other with frightened cries, and that is how we spent the
night.12 The next day General Mladic appeared among the refugees with his
television crew and handed out sweets to the children.13 After the General
had left, Serb soldiers mingled with the crowd, harassing people and carrying
out some sporadic killings.14 That night, a Dutch medical orderly witnessed
two Serb soldiers raping a young woman. He testified that the rape was seen
by many refugees but that nobody could intervene because of the presence of
Serb soldiers.15 Other witnesses testified that they had seen women being
dragged away and that they could hear women screaming.16
The Serb forces organised buses to take the prisoners away. The Muslim
men were separated from the women. Witness DD at the Kristic trial recalled
seeing her young son for the last time as her family tried to board the buses:
one of their soldiers jumped out, and he spoke to my child. He told us to move to
the right side, and he told my son: young man, you should go to the left side. I
grabbed him by his hand And then I begged them, I pleaded with them. Why are
you taking him? He was born in 1981. But he repeated his order. And I held him so
hard, but he grabbed him And he took my sons hand, and he dragged him to the
left side. And he turned around, and then he told me, Mommy, please, can you get
that bag for me? Could you please get it for me? That was the last time I heard his
voice.17
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
61
62
Perhaps Srebrenica could have been saved if the Dutch battalion had been
willing to risk lives in a heroic stand; perhaps it could have been saved if
Janvier and Akashi had been more willing to offer air support; perhaps it
could have been saved if other states had offered more troops as the
Netherlands had done; but the UNs humiliation in Srebrenica was not an
isolated disaster. The UN stood by and watched the ethnic cleansing in
Srebrenica as it did in the rest of Bosnia; as it stood by and watched the genocide
in Rwanda. In both cases it had intelligence reports telling it what was likely
to happen, but it was unable or unwilling to protect people. In Rwanda, there
were television pictures showing thousands of desperate, frightened people
crowding around UN bases, and UN soldiers retreating, leaving those people
to their fate. Failure at Srebrenica, while not inevitable, mirrored failure
elsewhere. Most towns and villages in the Republica Srpska did not even
receive the token protection and the publicity that was afforded to Srebrenica,
but were cleansed unnoticed by the worlds news media.
Since the UN and the states who provide its forces were unwilling to risk
the lives of their soldiers in an operation to prevent it, ethnic cleansing was
carried out unhindered. There was much discussion at the time of the military
and political impossibility of putting an international force in Bosnia that was
capable of defending the victims of ethnic cleansing. There was also much
political obfuscation: politicians argued that there were evils on all sides in the
war. Douglas Hurd, the British Foreign Secretary, argued that it was impossible
to go into other peoples countries and run them: this was the lesson learned
from the British Empire. The Balkans were portrayed as an exotic and inherently
unstable place, and therefore, by implication, undeserving of help.
Given that a force to prevent ethnic cleansing was not forthcoming, the
role that the UN gave itself in Bosnia was one of observation and of attempting
to slow down and ameliorate the effects of ethnic cleansing. The UN forces
found themselves in the position of constantly having to negotiate at a number
of different levels. It was necessary to negotiate with leadership of the Bosnian
Serbs; it was also necessary to negotiate with each group of Chemiks at each
18 Honig, 1996, p 36.
19 Prosecutor v Kristic, para 67.
20 Prosecutor v Kristic, para 84.
roadblock. While the UN did have, as its trump card, the possibility of calling
in air support which was genuinely able to hurt the Serb forces, the Serbs
developed trump cards of their own. They were able to take UN soldiers as
hostages, and to threaten the increased shelling of civilians. The UN had no
answer to these threats.
A flavour of the kind of negotiations that were constantly taking place can
be obtained from a letter that Sir Michael Rose, the Commander of
UNPROFOR, sent to Mladic, the General in charge of Serbian ethnic cleansing
in Bosnia:21
Dear General,
Following your telephone conversation today with Brigadier General Brinkman
[General Roses Chief of Staff in Sarajevo], I would like to confirm that the UN
always regrets the need to use force in its peacekeeping mission. As Commander
B-H Command, I fully agree with you that we must in the future avoid all situations
which necessitate the use of force, whether it be applied from the ground or the air.
We can only do this through closer liaison and co-operation. As you know
UNPROFORis in B-H to help return this country to peace through peaceful means.
It is not part of our mission to impose any solution by force of arms. We are neither
mandated nor deployed for such a mission.
However, you will understand that everyone has the right of self-defence. If our troops
are deliberately engaged by fire, then we have to respond, no matter who it was that
opened fire. I am sure that as a soldier you will understand this point of view.
I believe that we must now return to the status quo ante in terms of the relationship
between UNPROFOR and the Bosnian Serb army. These are difficult times for
everyone, and we must not allow local tactical-level incidents to undermine the
road to peace. I urge you now to give orders accordingly.
Yours Sincerely,
Michael Rose.
Rose, the brave SAS hero, defended his stance in a letter to The Times on the
same day that they published his letter to Mladic. It isnt his fault, he argues;
he is merely carrying out the orders of his political masters:
The mandate, and therefore the mission, is principally one of peacekeeping, not
peace enforcement. The primary mission of the UN in Bosnia remains that of
assisting UNHCR and other humanitarian agencies to sustain the lives of millions
of suffering people in the midst of a war
It is not within the mandate of capability of UNPROFOR to impose a military
solution on the country. Injudicious use of force would take the mission across the
line which divides peace from war
If this happened, the enclaves of eastern Bosnia would fall, Sarajevo would return
to the horrors of the last two winters, and the future of the Croat Muslim Federation
would be put in doubt22
During late summer 1995, all sides in the conflict made significant gains. The
Serbs took and cleansed the safe areas of Bihac, Srebrenica, Zepa and Gorazde.
The Croats took the Krajina from the Serbs, and there committed one of the
biggest acts of ethnic cleansing of the whole war. The Bosnian army retook
21 (1994) The Times, 2 November, p 15.
22 (1994) The Times, 2 November, p 19.
63
64
some territory in central Bosnia. The Americans sensed that the new situation
could be transformed into some sort of equilibrium, and, for the first time in
the war, NATO launched a serious and sustained assault from the air against
Serb forces.
In November 1995, the Americans organised the final negotiations at an
air force base in Dayton, Ohio. They refused to deal with the indicted Mladic
and Karadzic, preferring to negotiate with the real Serbian leader, Slobodan
Milosevic. The Dayton deal was agreed on 12 November. On the one hand,
Milosevic came under severe American military and diplomatic pressure to
make the deal; on the other hand, the deal allowed the Serbs to keep the
territory of Bosnia that they had cleansed, and allowed Croatia to keep the
Krajina. Dayton ended the war, but on the basis of accepting the reality of the
ethnic cleansing of a large proportion of Bosnia.
There were cosmopolitan institutions and forces positioned in Srebrenica
and in the rest of Bosnia to which the victims of the ethnic cleansing and the
outside world looked to stop the killing and the terror. There were armies and
air forces; blue helmets and red crosses; diplomats, politicians and military
leaders; there were promises and guarantees. Yet in this case, the cosmopolitan
institutions were nothing more than a form that disguised an old fashioned
realist content. In this case, the radical critique of cosmopolitanism looks
persuasive. Cosmopolitanism was the form of appearance of the great powers.
The policies followed by them were based on little more than calculations of
self-interest; there was no political will to defend human rights, nor to stop or
reverse the huge injustices that were perpetrated against the Muslims of Bosnia.
The policies of the great powers were hidden behind a faade of cosmopolitan
forms and institutions. Even with the preponderance of the appearances and
forms of cosmopolitanism, there were no sparks or flashes of genuinely
cosmopolitan response. In Bosnia, what happened, contrary to appearances,
was ordinary power politics.
65
66
was unsuccessful; the Kosovars were allowed to go back to their homes with
some guarantees of safety. But the cost was enormous; to the Kosovars, who
had to endure the most appalling campaign of ethnic cleansing before the
Serb forces finally conceded defeat, and to the 500 Serb and Kosovar civilians
who died during the 78 days of bombing, as well as the presumably higher
number who were wounded.28
While there was some component of cosmopolitan motivation in the
Western response to the ethnic cleansing of Kosovo, there was also a large
component of self-interest, particularly the wish to avoid domino
destabilisation and mass movements of refugees towards the West. The
overriding concern to avoid any risk to Western soldiers undermined the
effectiveness of what was possible in terms of protecting populations from
the ethnic cleansers. In Kosovo the great powers used less cosmopolitan forms
than they had used in BosniaNATO rather than the UN, aerial bombing
rather than peacekeeping forcesbut the content of the policy was more
effective in aiding the victims of ethnic cleansing.
from the canteen or the latrines, all the time. The guards used clubs, thick
electrical cable, rifle butts, fists, boots, brass knuckle-dusters, iron rods.
Prisoners were tortured into false confessions: a doctor who had no cellar
was forced to admit that he stole drugs from his clinic and hid them in his
cellar; a man who was widely known to suffer from progressive blindness
admitted that he had been a sniper.31 The sounds of these torture sessions
were heard daily from the dormitories. In the hot summer, the prisoners were
kept thirsty; the guards would throw small bottles of water into the dormitories
because the frantic struggle between the prisoners amused them. The prisoners
were routinely forced to sing Chetnik songs.
When somebody took a leak, the others gathered around to cup their hands and
catch the urine, wetting their chapped lips with it and even drinking it.32
67
68
He tells of many more brutal tortures and deaths, always humiliating and
unimaginably painful. It is clear that at Omarska murder and torture were
routine. Bodies were regularly taken away in yellow trucks.
Djemo was taken from Omarska on a crowded, thirsty bus journey to a
camp called Manjaca. Here there were also terrible, crowded conditions, hunger,
thirst, and lice; but brutality, while it still existed, was less tolerated by the
Commander in Chief of the camp, who interrupted a beating with the words:
Enough. Thats the kind of thing you were supposed to do in Omarska, but
you cant do it here.38 There were visits from the Red Cross, who provided
diesel for the collection of water, but the prisoners still got little and dirty water.
In the end, Djemo was released in an exchange of prisoners organised by
the Red Cross and UNPROFOR. He and his fellow prisoners alighted from
the buses into a scrum of the worlds press and TV reporters, and then went
into exile.
Ed Vulliamy was a journalist who was in the first group of any outsiders
press, Red Cross or United Nations (UN)to see Omarska, on 5 August 1992.
He quotes a witness, Nedzad Jacupovic, who survived the White House, as
follows:
They would bring people from the big red hut at eight in the evening, 40 of them
each night, to the White House. There, they would beat them until they were dead;
it could take a day, three days or five days, ripping clothes off with knives, cutting
people and then just kicking and beating them to death over a period of days. Then
they would arrive with lists of others in the White House who were not yet dead,
for execution. They would record the mens details, take them out, one every 15
minutes, towards the Red House, where they were butchered. I was counting the
numbers; sometimes 18, 20 or 30; the record was 42. They were killed just in front
of my windows.39
Vulliamy quotes another survivor of the White House, Sakib R, who calculated
that 612 men disappeared from the hut during 12 days in July 1992:
I saw people loading the dead onto lorries and they were dropping bodies down
the mine shaft. On one occasion, 12 Croats were taken out to the toilet. I went in
there, and saw bits of their bodies on the floor.40
Vulliamy says that [t]he testimonies are willing and endless, but the evidence
these two men submit is typical, cogent and can be corroborated.41 One
survivorestimates that he was personally forced to help deposit 600 bodies
down the mine shaft at Omarska.42 Vulliamy estimates that something like
6,000 men were at Omarska at any one time, and several thousand of them
were brutally murdered. He adds that there were other similarly brutal camps,
for example one at Kereterm, established at a disused tile factory on the edge
of Prijedor and known as Room Three, and the Luka camp outside Brcko.
Here, a university lecturer called Mirsad was held and he told the following
story:
38
39
40
41
42
Hukanovic describes how one day all the prisoners, including the beaten and
the sick, were taken out onto the tarmac and stood against a building. There
were, he estimates, about 3,000 of them:
The soldiers positioned themselves around the prisoners, ready to fire. One guard,
known for never parting from his machine gun for even a second, climbed to the
roof of the building across the way and began loading the magazine of his gun
with cartridgeshe aimed the barrel at the runway and lay down next to it, taking
aim at the menthe guards kept their guns trained on the prisoners for over an
hour. Then they were all taken back to the dormitories.44
Omarska was utterly different from Zygmunt Baumans picture of the genocide
of the Jews, the picture of the principles of scientific rationality coldly and
dispassionately designating the goal of extermination, and a bureaucratically
and technologically efficient execution of the plan. At Omarska, killing was
passionate and inefficient. Many of the guards knew personally many of the
victims. It often took hours or days to kill a single prisoner.
Hukanovic tells us that:
On weekends regular troops from Banja Luka came to the camp. The guards called
them specialists, and they were indeed specialists at breaking arms and legs, tearing
out organs, and smashing skulls against walls. The weekends at Omarska were
orgies of blood. One dayone of the regulars said, loudly, so everyone could hear:
Today is my 25th birthday, and Ive only killed 23 Muslims.45
Regular soldiers came to Omarska at the weekends to torture and kill Muslims.
Was this a way to wind down after a hard week at the front?
The main objective of the concentration camps, especially Omarska, but
also Kereterm, according to a UN commission of experts:
seems to have been to eliminate the non-Serbian leadership. Political leaders,
officials from the courts and administration, academics and other intellectuals,
religious leaders, key business people and artiststhe backbone of the Muslim
and Croatian communitieswere removed, apparently with the intention that the
removal be permanent. Similarly, law enforcement and military personnel were
targeted for destruction.46
When Djemo was being taken to freedom, one exchange of prisoners failed to
take place. The prisoners were taken to a cell block in the prison of a military
barracks. Their guards went off to sleep, leaving the prisoners in the hands of
the locals, the Knin Boys. They were left in the hands of this gang for a day
and a night, who tortured them, humiliated them and forced them to sing
43
44
45
46
69
70
Chetnik songs. The gang was allowed to amuse themselves with a bunch of
Muslims while they were in town, while the guards rested.
Vulliamys story about the young woman torturer reinforces this picture of
killing and beating for recreation. In very many of the testimonies of brutality
the perpetrators are drunk and laughing, enjoying themselves. They amuse
themselves by forcing prisoners to sing for them, and by haranguing them
with witty and ironic comments while they are murdering them.
There is an abundance of sexual torture, one prisoner sometimes being
forced to torture another. One prisoner was forced to bite another prisoners
testicles off.
On 7 May 1997, Dusko Tadic was found guilty of crimes against humanity.
He was found to have played a part in almost all of the assaults on prisoners
described by [Omarska] survivors during the one-year trial.47 The detailed
judgment upholds the view of Omarska that I have summarised from Vulliamy
and Hukanovic. The judges said that women who were held at Omarska
were routinely called out of their rooms at night and raped. One woman was
taken out five times and after each rape she was beaten.48
David Forsythe agrees, arguing that the tribunal was set up fundamentally to
placate public opinion, and lacked the support from those states that set it up
that it required in order to be successful. Britain and other states failed to give
this support since it might have interfered with diplomatic efforts to end the
conflict.50 But he does concede that it may not be entirely useless: The
equivalents of Goering and Eichmann, much less Hitler, will not be tried, but
neither will they be free to visit Disney land on vacation.51
However, social structures have emergent properties, and they are shaped
by social agents; they have possibilities that are different from those intended;
they have the possibility of growing and developing. Institutions do not always
become what those who conceived of them had hoped. The ad hoc ICTY was
set up with a certain degree of autonomy from the UN Security Council. This
was inevitable, since it was set up as a court of law in the Western tradition,
and such courts necessarily have a degree of independence from the powers
in whose name they operate. The separation of powers between the executive,
47
48
49
50
51
the legislators and the judiciary are deeply ingrained principles, even if there
are many mechanisms by which the separation can, in practice, be eroded or
diminished. Even if the ICTY was set up by the great powers in order to feign a
concern for justice, that does not necessarily restrict the existing institution to
remaining a token gesture. The Nuremberg process was given life by the young
idealistic lawyers who made it work, and who, as far as was possible, strove to
use it to leave a set of precedents of cosmopolitan criminal law in place.52
Both the prosecutors at the ICTY and the judges have a belief in the
importance of the work they are doing, and they do it with commitment and
energy. Many of the central actors, for example Antonio Cassese and Cherif
Bassiouni, are well renowned legal scholars, people who have been writing,
almost since Nuremberg, about the possibility and necessity of international
criminal law. They were brought in from an academic wilderness and given
an institution to build. What the judges lack in actual trial experience they
make up for in enthusiasm and vision.
At the Tadic appeal, there was an instructive little exchange. Defending
Tadic was a British barrister, William Clegg, the same man who had defended
Sawoniuk.53 He was presenting an argument about what constitutes an
international conflict. He made an analogy with lend-lease during the Second
World War and said, rather clumsily, the Americans lent us armaments and
money but this didnt necessarily mean that they were themselves participants
in the conflict. Judge Shahabuddeen pulled him up immediately, saying that
he should speak more clearly: he should not say us, but Britain; he should
remember that people will be reading these transcripts in 50 years time, and
he should express himself in such a way as to make himself intelligible to
those future students of international law. Shahabuddeen was aware that the
discussion in the Tadic case regarding the definition of an international conflict
was ground-breaking; the court was making law for the future. Even if the
ICTY was set up by the Security Council as an empty gesture, those involved
were determined to make it work. Even if it was to end in failure, they were
thinking about future generations of lawyers and students who might be
reading those transcripts. The same can be said for the prosecutors: What
Richard Goldstone and his successorhave demonstrated is the optimistic
fact that enterprises of this sort have a tendency to develop a momentum of
their own.54 Cosmopolitan law is not simply an expression of the will of the
great powers. It can be influenced, limited or corrupted by them; but it is a
sphere of social life that necessarily has some degree of autonomy from the
particular interests of the powerful.
Yugoslavia broke up in the summer of 1991. Croatia and Slovenia declared
independence and fighting broke out between Croats and Serbs in Croatia.
Serbia sent arms, supplies, and the JNA to Croatia. In October 1991, Bosnia
held a referendum on independence but the Bosnian Serbs took control of
52 Franz Neumann, Otto Kirchheimer and Herbert Marcuse, for example, were all members of the prosecution
team at Nuremberg: Salter, 2000.
53 See Chapter Six.
54 Robertson, 1999, p 267.
71
72
their territory in Bosnia. During the spring and summer of 1992, the Serbs
began the process of ethnic cleansing against the Muslims in Bosnia.
In February 1992, the UN Security Council adopted Resolution 721,
authorising a special peacekeeping force, UNPROFOR, for Bosnia. The
Commission on Human Rights convened the first exceptional session ever
on 13 August 1992 to discuss the ethnic cleansing. A special Rapporteur was
appointed in August 1992, who subsequently issued four reports to the General
Assembly and the Security Council.55
The first report, on 28 August 1992, confirmed that ethnic cleansing had
been pursued throughout Bosnia by Serbs, that there had been torture and
systematic execution and that 3,000 Muslims had disappeared after the fall of
Vukovar. The second report, in October 1992, following a visit by the Rapporteur
to Bosnia, stated that Muslims had clearly become victims of aggression and
ethnic cleansing. Displaced persons were in a desperate situation, especially
in the Travnik area; before their arrival in Travnik, many had been taken to
the front lines, subjected to beatings, robbery, rape and sometimes shooting.
There had also been ethnic cleansing in Pijavija, Prikepolje, and Proboj. On 6
October, the Security Council voted to establish a commission of experts to
gather evidence of war crimes in the former Yugoslavia.56 The third report of
the Rapporteur, on 17 November 1992, highlighted violations of the various
parties legal obligations under international law. Ethnic cleansing, it argued,
followed the political objective of the Serbian nationalists of the creation of a
Greater Serbia. It concluded that one and a half million out of four million
Bosnians had become refugees, 75% of these refugees being children and
elderly. The fourth report, the most comprehensive, concluded that the serious
and large scale violations of human rights and international humanitarian
law were not by-products of war but were deliberate policies of the Serbs. It
also reported that there was discrimination against Serbian civilians in Croatia,
and against Albanians in Kosovo.
Dame Ann Warburton was sent by the European Community to Yugoslavia
in December 1992 and January 1993, and she reported on 3 February 1993 to
the UN Secretary General. She found that the rape of Muslim women had
been perpetrated on a wide scale and in such a systematic way as to be
considered part of an intentional war strategy. She estimated that there had
been 20,000 rapes, but said that it could be between 10,000 and 60,000, with
about 1,000 pregnancies. She reported testimony that a repeated feature of
Serbian attacks on Muslim towns and villages was the use of rape, often in
public, or the threat of rape, as a weapon of war to force the population to
leave their homes.57
The Security Councils commission of experts was slow, academic and
stuffed with old fogeys.58 It was chaired by Frits Kalshoven, a retired professor
73
74
set up under a section of the UN Charter that was clearly never intended to
empower the Security Council to institute a court. Yet the Security Council
discovered a mechanism for doing what it wanted to do. Perhaps the
Nuremberg tribunal suffered from significant flaws; perhaps it was vulnerable
to the tu quoque argument, and perhaps also to the retrospective justice
argument. However, after Nuremberg, the Nuremberg process itself constitutes
a clear unambiguous precedent. Innovation is necessarily unprecedented.
Similarly, the ICTY was perhaps created on the basis of a piece of legal trickery.
Once created, however, it constitutes a precedent.
The structure of the tribunal consists of three principal organs: the chambers,
the prosecutor, and the registry. The chambers comprises three-member trial
chambers and a five-member appeals chamber charged with adjudicating
cases. The prosecutor investigates allegations and prepares indictments for
cases to be prosecuted. The registry assists both the prosecutor and the
chambers, in addition to performing other administrative duties, such as
requesting governments to provide information on the identity of the accused,
to serve documents and to extradite the accused.
The tribunal retains concurrent jurisdiction with the national courts of states
that have emerged from Yugoslavia since its collapse. States have the right to
put a suspect on trial, but the tribunal has the power to retry such a suspect.
Article 210 of the statute prohibits trials in absentia.
Today, as we watch the trial of Milosevic himself unfold, the tribunal can
appear to be a successful manifestation of Western, or American, power and
resolve. It is not true, however, that there was a policy decision at an early
stage by the Western leadership to create such a tribunal. When the tribunal
was first constituted by the Security Council it was done so ambivalently. It is
impossible to know exactly what the intent of Western leadership was when
the court was set up, to know exactly how components of different motivations
were balanced. There was a wish to pursue justice; there was a wish for the
appearance of justice to cover an unjust policy; there was a wish for an
instrument of apparently legitimate power that could punish the enemies of
the West. And then there is no such thing as an intent of the Western
leadership, but rather a coalition of individual approaches by states with
different amounts of influence, and by individuals within regimes also with
differing amounts of influence. Western policy swung wildly from the
humiliation in the Sudan, to the timidity in Bosnia and Rwanda, to the
thunderous response in Kosovo; the uses the West wished to make of the
ICTY must also have swung wildly during this period, a period also of
transition from Bush to Clinton to Bush, and from Major to Blair. Policy
towards the court also became more favourable when Yugoslavia became more
stable and when the possible threat to the fragile equilibrium held in place by
NATO troops decreased; in other words, when the risk to stability and to the
lives of NATO soldiers decreased.
One thing is clear: that the ICTY was first established without the resources or
the power necessary to succeed in bringing to justice those primarily responsible
for ethnic cleansing in the former Yugoslavia. Its growth into such a body was the
result of a combination of factors. There was the work and vision of the
prosecutorsandjudgeswhobuilttheinstitutionbecausetheybelievedinit.There
were the developments in the former Yugoslavia, such as fall of the Milosevic
regime and the liberalisation of the Tudjman regime after his death. There was
75
76
the increasing reliance by NATO on human rights rhetoric during the Kosovo
conflict. There was the good luck of the ICTY in obtaining defendants, from the
chance arrest of Tadic in Germany to the extradition of Milosevic, following his
overthrow, encouraged by the promise of dollars to the new Serbian regime.
In November 1993, the 11 judges took office in The Hague. Antonio Cassese
later said that the Security Council had thought that the tribunal would never
become operational. We had no budget, we had nothing. Zero.70 The selection
of a prosecutor was a protracted and politicised process, since the prosecutor
would have control over the indictments of the court. In July 1994, the Security
Council appointed Richard Goldstone. In 199394, the UN proposed a budget
of $562,300 for investigations, including witness travel, interviews with
refugees, forensic experts, translators and protection,71 although in the end
the General Assembly gave the tribunal $5.6 million for the first half of 1994
and $5.4 million for the second half. By 1999, in comparison, the budget had
risen to $94 million.72 In those early days morale and confidence at the ICTY
were low, and there was a danger that the whole process might fold. A member
of Goldstones staff is quoted by Gary Bass: A, you can indict Milosevic and
be shut down, or B, you can do low level [indictments] and do a few trials.73
Even the indictments of Mladic and Karadzic, issued on 25 July 1995, were
bold moves by Goldstone, who said: it was really done as, if you like, an
academic exercise. Because our duty was clear. We werent going to be
dissuaded from doing it by any prognosticationsgood or badas to what
effect it would have.74 The autonomy of the prosecutor and of the court was,
perhaps, not seen as a problem by the West since its power was very small.
The morale and sense of purpose at the ICTY strengthened greatly. It
developed from a body whose central actors felt that it existed only to fail in
1993, to a body capable of indicting the (almost) top perpetrators of ethnic
cleansing as an academic exercise in 1995, to a body capable of convicting
Tadic in 1997. After the Tadic conviction there was a different feeling around
the court. There were three courtrooms trying cases and a queue of defendants
waiting in the cells. By 1999 the court was ready to indict Milosevic himself,
and by June 2001 it held him prisoner. This trajectory of development would
have astounded everyone in 1992 when the Security Council constituted the
court. The relentless increase in leadership, competence and self-confidence
within the institution has been mirrored by a gradual change in policy by the
Western leadership in its favour.
The ICTY is an empirical fact; it exists. The court building is opposite the
main conference centre on the edge of Den Haag, a couple of miles away
from the seafront at Scheveningen. The brown stone 1950s-style building is
surrounded by a metal fence, behind which UN security staff can be seen
patrolling from time to time. Their uniforms are reminiscent of American police
uniforms, but UN pale blue. They carry guns on their belts. They are recruited
from police forces and armies around the world, but are not working for those
forces; they work for and owe their allegiance directly to the UN and to the
court. I spoke to guards from Nigeria, Scotland, Italy and Venezuela.
70
71
72
73
74
There is airport-style security on entering the building. There are armed guards
in the foyer and in the public galleries. They sit on either side of the defendants
at all times behind the bulletproof glass separating the court from the public.
The building feels like an international court. It flies blue UN flags outside; it
has blue UN flags and insignia behind and above the judges. Daily, it proceeds
with the business of conducting trials. It conducts slow and long trials, but
trials nevertheless. Cosmopolitan criminal law is not some Utopian concept; it
exists in this building in The Hague, even if only in an embryonic form.
On a routine day in the court, when there is no verdict to be announced, no
new indictment, nothing dramatic happening, there are not many visitors.
Even for the Milosevic trial, the public gallery is typically less than half full.
There is a small press room, a handful of journalists. There is a young man in
the press room whose job it is to feed the television pictures of the trials onto
the internet. Proceedings in each of the three courts can be watched, with a
half hour delay, from anywhere in the world.
I arrived at the court shortly after the end of the Sawoniuk trial in London.
There, I had become accustomed to gossiping about the progress of the case
with the others in the public gallery between sessions; there were the few who
followed the case throughout, and the ones who came to look, occasionally,
or just for a day or two. On my first morning at The Hague, I was watching
the Blaskic trial. During the break, I approached one of the few other observers.
I asked how the trial was going, what were her impressions. She looked at
me with disdain, and said, shortly, that she was not about to explain the whole
complex case to me, and walked off. A while later, I approached three men
who were there, and attempted, a little more subtly, to talk to them. They
looked at me with suspicion. They asked me who I was, what I was doing
there, and why they had seen me talking to a Croatian journalist. I suddenly
became aware that the whole atmosphere at The Hague was different from
that of the Old Bailey. The woman had been a Croatian, covering the trial of
Blaskic for a Zagreb paper; the three men, I noticed later, left the courthouse
every day in a large black BMW with Bosnian diplomatic number plates. The
events dealt with here were much more current and fresh than at the London
trial. There was an atmosphere of suspicion. There were supporters of all
sides present; those who had direct experience of being cleansed and those
whose profession it was to deny and lie about ethnic cleansing. A small part
of the war was still being fought, here, in the court building. The buildup to
the NATO bombing in Kosovo was happening at that time.
The three Bosniak men told me that they were spies like James Bond.
They watched the trials, taking long and detailed notes. I spent some time
trying to gain their confidence, hoping that perhaps I would be able to
interview them. They became more friendly, and a little less suspicious, but
they had their work to do; they answered questions either in riddles, or with
the official Bosnian Government line.
The staff who work in the building speak mainly English as they sit in the
foyer near the coffee machine. I spoke to Americans, Canadians, British, Dutch,
French, Germans, South Africans, and others. They are lawyers, ex-cops,
translators, clerical workers, students doing internships. Being a sociologist, I
attempted to strike up conversations with people, to find out what they had
to say, to build up an impression of them and how they were thinking; to
form an idea of the general morale of the staff and the institution; to do a little
77
78
Chapter Five
The trials of Blaskic and Tadic at the
ICTY
In this chapter, I present outlines of two trials from the International Criminal
Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia (ICTY) based on my own observations at
The Hague, on internet broadcasts of the trials, and on the trial transcripts
and judgments. Tihomir Blaskic, a Croatian General, presented himself as a
professional soldier, and at the time of his conviction was the highest ranking
person to have been convicted at the ICTY. Dusko Tadic, an ideologue and
torturer in a small town, was the first person who pleaded not guilty to be
found guilty at the ICTY. Cosmopolitan criminal law is not an abstract ideal
but a developing reality. It is important to anchor discussion of theoretical
debates in the actuality of events: first, events that constitute the subject matter
of cosmopolitan criminal law, in these two cases ethnic cleansing itself;
secondly, events that constitute the substance of cosmopolitan criminal law,
the extraction of individuals from machines of terror, the designation of their
acts as crimes and the routine business of their prosecution. It is important to
look at trials not only as legal cases but in a more rounded way as social
processes. These discussions of trials are intended to give an insight into the
mechanics of the processes of cosmopolitan criminal law. The concepts of
cosmopolitan right, supra-national authority and due process attain their
worldly actuality in the quotidian professional business of lawyers, judges,
investigators, translators, security officers and journalists. As was shown in
the last chapter, cosmopolitan forms do not necessarily coincide with genuine
cosmopolitan content. The relationship between the lofty concepts and their
worldly actuality is therefore a fundamental point of investigation.
80
The HVO was the army of Croatians in Bosnia; the HV was the army of the Republic of Croatia.
In early 1992 Blaskic was in Vienna, having left the Yugoslav army (the
JNA). In February 1992, the municipal council of Kiseljak, the town in which
Blaskic had been born, invited him to organise the defence of the municipality
against the Serbs. This was initially organised with both Croat and Muslim
participation. On 6 April 1992, the Republic of Bosnia-Herzegovina declared
its independence, and it was formally recognised by Croatia the next day. The
UN Security Council called for external forces to leave the territory of Bosnia.
It demanded that the JNA and Croatian army units withdraw, place themselves
under the authority of the Bosnian Government, or be disbanded. But the
now Serbian JNA was nearby, at Jajce, and was also advancing towards the
Lasva Valley from the south east. The Croatian nationalists, with the backing
of Zagreb, gained the leadership of the HVO, the Croatian Defence Council
in Bosnia, against the wishes of those Croatians who supported multi-ethnicity,
or cohabitation, with the Muslims. The Bosnian Territorial Defence (the TO)
was formed on 9 April 1992 and was outlawed the next day by the President
of the Croatian community in Bosnia, Mate Boban. The Croatian General Anto
Roso confirmed this in an order on 8 May, and on 11 May Tihomir Blaskic
implemented that order by pronouncing the TO unlawful in the territory of
Kiseljak. The joint Muslim and Croatian defence of the Lasva Valley, therefore,
was only ever notional, and was quickly replaced by a Croatian nationalist
leadership that planned a campaign of ethnic cleansing against the Muslims
in the area. They were not prepared to allow Muslims to participate in the
defence against the Serbs since it would have been necessary to allow them
access to weapons.
Blaskics defence contained a number of strands but centrally he argued that
he was in charge of a poorly trained, hurriedly mustered force; he was under
siege from the Serbs, communications between himself and his forces were
difficult, and there were many Croatian paramilitary and police outfits operating
in the area over which he had no authority. There were atrocities committed of
which he did not approve and over which he had no control. He further argued
that some of the atrocities committed against Muslims were in fact either
committed by Serbs or by Muslims themselves. He argued that Muslims were
committing atrocities against Croats, and that it was not surprising if Croat
forces beyond his control retaliated in a similar manner. His defence argued
that he had repeatedly issued written orders that his forces should respect
humanitarian law. And the defence maintained that the use of work teams
made up of prisoners to dig trenches was legal at the time of the conflict.
Blaskic presented himself in court as an experienced and meticulous army
officer. He was always courteous. He played the part of an isolated professional
soldier trying valiantly but unsuccessfully to discipline his untrained civilians
into a modern and professional army. During his cross-examination, Kehoe
would always greet him with a gruff good morning, General. Blaskic would
answer with good morning, Mr Prosecutor. And they would get down to
business. Kehoe would introduce a document, maybe a copy of an order that
Blaskic had received or issued. Blaskic would require 10 minutes to read the
order. Kehoe would ask him what the order meant. Blaskic would take five
minutes to explain in great detail the meaning of the order, explaining everything
in it except for the part that was relevant. It became increasingly clear under
cross-examination that his professional attention to detail and rules was a screen
behind which Blaskic was hiding the reality of his job in the Lasva Valley. He
81
82
Prosecutor v Blaskic.
led by Colonel Bob Stewart, who gave evidence at the trial, found the bodies
of many people. Stewart was interviewed at the time on television news. His
anger, disgust and frustration at the scene his men had found in Ahmici
penetrated his English and military reserve. The interview was moving and
memorable. No soldier in the HVO, the military or paramilitary police units
was ever punished for the events at Ahmici by the Croatian authorities. This
reaction can be contrasted with the fact that on 16 April, the very day of the
attack on Ahmici, Blaskic sent a protest to UNPROFOR because a United
Nations (UN) armoured vehicle had knocked down a church fence. Many
other villages in the Lasva Valley met the same fate on 16April and the following
few days. Inhabitants were taken prisoner, forced to flee or murdered. There
were attacks on Muslims all through the spring and summer of 1993 that
constituted the campaign to Croatise the territory.
The prosecution contested Blaskics two central lines of defence, which
were that he had difficulty in communicating with his troops3 and that the
crimes were committed by paramilitary units that were not under his control.
The judges found that Blaskic had been successful in setting up a solid chain
of command throughout the territories for which he was responsible. That
chain of command incorporated paramilitary and police outfits that were not
part of the HVO but that were shown during the trial to have operated under
the authority and direction of Blaskic.
The HVO was not simply an army, but also had a civilian structure. The
distinction between the military leadership and the civilian or political
leadership was not sharp. Blaskic often appeared in public meetings, alongside
Mate Boban, Dario Kordic,4 Anto Valenta and other political leaders, who
sometimes wore military uniforms; he was part of the leadership of the HVO,
and was clearly aware of the fact that the programme of the HVO was one of
Croatisation and the ethnic cleansing of Muslim people, places of worship
and businesses.
Much time was spent during the trial by the prosecution to show that the
conflict was an international one, and not simply a conflict between Croats
and Muslims within Bosnia. This was relevant for two reasons. First, some of
the laws and customs of war, particularly the Geneva Conventions, only apply
to international conflict, so that it was necessary to prove the existence of an
international conflict in order to convict Blaskic of breaking those laws.
Secondly, it was shown during the trial that the HVO and Blaskic were carrying
out the policy of the Republic of Croatia in working towards the dream of a
Greater Croatia. Franjo Tudjman had met with Slobodan Milosevic in March
1991 to discuss the sharing of Bosnia between themselves. The chain of
command was shown, in the trial, not only to be strong from Blaskic
downwards to the troops on the ground carrying out the ethnic cleansing,
but also upwards, all the way to Tudjman. A fiction of HVO independence
3
4
In fact, it was shown that cellular phones were working in the area at the time.
At the time of the cross-examination of Blaskic, the trial of Kordic was beginning in the courtroom upstairs.
Kordic, the political leader of the Croats in the Lasva Valley at the time, was found guilty on 26 February
2001 for his part in the ethnic cleansing of the territory, and particularly for ordering the attack on Ahmici
and other villages in April 1993. He was not found to be a prime mover or an architect of the overall
campaign, but was found to be an important politician in the area. At the time of his conviction, Kordic
was the most senior political leader to have been found guilty at the ICTY. Prosecutor v Kordic and Cerkez.
83
84
from Croatia was maintained, but it did not constitute a reality. Many HV
personnel operated within the HVO, and documents produced during the
trial show that they were ordered to change their insignia to those of the HVO.
Later, Blaskic himself was transferred from the HVO to the HV on the orders
of President Tudjman. It is true that Croatia, initially at least, gave some aid to
Bosnia, but its links with the HVO were much closer, involving the interchange
of personnel and the donation of a million Deutschemarks a day.
Fundamentally, the Republic of Croatia was involved in a cross-border military
campaign with the eventual aim of annexing parts of Bosnia.
The trial of Blaskic took over two years, heard 158 witnesses and received
nearly 1,500 exhibits. It is perhaps a measure of the novelty and immaturity of
the system of international criminal law that this trial, which was not
fundamentally very complex, took so much time, money and resources. It is
possible that with increasing self-confidence and experience the ICTY will be
able to try cases more quickly and efficiently. William Clegg, the barrister who
defended Tadic at his appeal, and who also defended Andrei Sawoniuk,
expressed the opinion in an interview5 that it should be possible to try a case
such as this in six weeks. He argued that it would be better for the prosecution
to pick its five or six clearest incidents with which to prove its charges, instead
of attempting to prove every single allegation. It is also true that these first few
trials have been concerned to prove larger issues than the guilt or innocence of
the accused. For example, in the Blaskic and Tadic trials, much time was spent
proving the complicity of Croatia and Serbia in the conflict in Bosnia and proving
that genocide and crimes against humanity were being committed. Such issues,
it is to be hoped, need only to be proven comprehensively once.
Following many pre-trial hearings about rules, procedure and other technical
matters, the trial of Dusko Tadic began on 7 May 1996.
Mira Tadic gave evidence to the tribunal. She had married Dusko in 1979,
after living with him for a year. At the time that she gave evidence she was 35.
She was a nurse; Dusko only had secondary school level qualifications.
Between 1980 and 1986 Tadic worked in a factory, assembling electrical
equipment. In 1986 Mira got a job as a nurse in Libya and Dusko went with
her. They were divorced in 1987 because, she explained, she wanted to get
work in Switzerland as a nurse, and it was easier for single people to get such
work than for married people. While they continued to live together, however,
she never got the job in Switzerland. In 1987 Tadic formed a construction
company which got some work in Croatia, but the business ended in the
summer of 1989. Next, Tadic spent time working on his own house, with
some periods in Germany working for his brothers construction company in
Munich. Tadic opened a caf in early 1991. Mira told of a letter that they had
received from Muslims that was threatening, saying that we should leave
Kozarac and if we did not leave Kozarac within three months that we would
be killed, and it was signed by the Young Muslims from Kozarac, that is the
party of SDA. On two occasions the shop window was broken, and at one
time the caf was broken into and burgled. Mira Tadic gave evidence as follows:
Kay: As we enter 1992 and some five months before the conflict in Kozarac,
what was the state of relations like in the town amongst the different
ethnic groups?
Mira Tadic: The relations were tense. Apparently, we would say hello
and talk, but there were no close contacts or visits. Everybody was just
minding their own business.
K: What was causing this tension?
MT: Because people were simply afraid of one another.
K: Were you or your husband adding to this tension? Were you or your
husband adding to this climate?
MT: We could not add to it because we were a minority. We were more or
less the only ones there
K: Why did you leave on 1 April 1992?
MT: Because at that time in Kozarac it was not safe any more. We were in
a minority. The Muslim people became organised. They had their barracks,
they wore uniforms, held arms. I was afraid for my life and for the life of
my children, and that is why I left Kozarac.6
The presentation of the prosecution case lasted for 47 sitting days and ended
on 15 August 1996. During this period 76 witnesses gave evidence and 346
prosecution exhibits were admitted, including video tapes of the region and a
model of the Omarska camp, together with a further 40 exhibits from the
defence. The defence case began on 10 September 1996, ending on 30 October.
Forty witnesses were presented and 75 exhibits admitted. Tadic testified for
three days from 25 October 1996.
The judgment produced by the tribunal in the Tadic case was about 120,000
words long. It is a comprehensive account of the trial and of the events for
85
86
which he was on trial. It spends many pages giving an outline of the history
of Yugoslavia and its political breakup, focusing on the growth of the idea of
the Greater Serbia and the development of ethnic cleansing as an instrument
of national policy. It is a self-conscious attempt to provide an objective,
authoritative and impartial narrative concerning the breakup of Yugoslavia,
ethnic cleansing in Bosnia and of the small part played by Dusko Tadic.
Tadic was born on 1 October 1955. His mother had been deported during
the Second World War to Jasenovac, the notorious concentration camp run by
Croat Ustasa forces in alliance with the Nazi regime. This son of a concentration
camp survivor was to become a gnocidaire and torturer himself. He came
from a prominent Serb family in the small town of Kozarac. His father was a
decorated Second World War hero. Tadic taught karate and was the father of
two daughters. Ninety per cent of the inhabitants of Kozarac were Muslims
prior to the conflict. Tadic testified that most of his friends had been Muslim.
He joined the SDS, the Bosnian Serb political party, in 1990. A witness
testified that Tadics caf became a centre for Serb nationalists, who were
becoming increasingly racist against Muslims and who used to gather there,
singing Chetnik songs. Tadics brothers ex-wife testified that Tadic admired
Milosevic, and had said that if his next child was a boy he would call him
Slobodan. After the ethnic cleansing of Kozarac had been accomplished, Tadic
became the political leader of Kozarac, was elected president of the local board
of the SDS, and was appointed as acting secretary of the local commune in
September 1992, also becoming its representative to the Prijedor Municipal
Assembly.
Tadic began service as a reserve traffic police officer at the Orlovci
checkpoint on 16 June 1992, and was thereafter assigned duties as a reserve
policeman in Prijedor. He went to some lengths to resist being drafted for
military service; when, after more than one attempt, he was successfully
drafted to the war zone, he escaped the following day and went into hiding.
He was arrested several times during the ensuing months for desertion but
always managed to escape. In August 1993 Tadic travelled to Nuremberg,
then to Munich, where he stayed with his brother, who operated a club there,
and was reunited with his wife. He was arrested by German police on 12
February 1994.
One of the central charges against Tadic was that he was involved in killing,
sexual torture and rape at Omarska. The incidents of sexual torture, as
described in the previous chapter from the account of Rezak Hukanovic, were
widely reported. In the trading of atrocity stories that surrounded the conflict
in Bosnia, the story of one prisoner being forced to bite off anothers testicle
attained a certain centrality. The tribunal found that the beatings of the five
named prisoners and of Senad Muslimovic did take place at Omarska and
that witnesses G and H at the trial, whose identities were protected, had been
compelled to and did take part in the sexual assault on Fikret Harambasic,
and that G was compelled to sexually mutilate him by biting off one of his
testicles. These events took place on 18 June 1992. The judgment describes the
assaults and the beatings in detail, relying on a large body of witness testimony.
Tadic was identified by the witnesses as being involved in the beatings.
One witness knew Tadic before they met in Omarska and also identified him
in court. Another witness had previously identified him from a photospread
procedure, an identification accepted by the tribunal. Witness Senad
Muslimovic said that Tadic was among those kicking him severely when he
was tied to a large tyre, and that Tadic threatened his eyes with a knife,
threatened to cut his throat and to cut off his ear, and he testified that Tadic in
fact stabbed him twice in the shoulder. Tadic was seen by nine witnesses on
the day of 18 June, calling prisoners out, beating prisoners, and torturing
prisoners. The judgment gives details of this testimony, with names of
witnesses and victims. Tadics defence in relation to these allegations was
that he was not present at Omarska. He said that he had never visited Omarska,
and that on that day he was working as a traffic policeman. The judges were
satisfied that Tadic did take part in the beatings and that he was present at,
but not necessarily a participant in, the sexual mutilation.
Hase Icic testified in great detail to events at Omarska on 78 July 1992. He
had known Tadic at school and had also played football with Tadics brother.
He testified that Tadic was present when he was taken into a room, a noose
was tightened around his neck, and he was beaten unconscious with iron
bars, whips made out of heavy electric cable and other weapons. The trial
chamber accepted Icics evidence. Sefik Sivac testified that he had once been
good friends with Tadic until there was an incident when he had thrown
Tadic out of his caf. He threw him out because he had been saying that there
would be a Greater Serbia, it would be theirs and that we, Muslims, will not
be there, that there will be no place for them.
Sometimes the judgment describes conflicts of evidence, places where the
evidence of different witnesses was incompatible. The judgment details the
conflicts and states clearly on which version the judges rely, if any, giving
reasons for the preference, and giving the logical process by which the tribunal
reached its conclusions. The judgment details each incident described by the
witnesses, the alleged role of the defendant, the defence argument, and then
its conclusions as to fact. Elvir Grozdanic testified that he had known Tadic
for 10 years before the war, and that he had taken weekly karate lessons from
him. He told of many abuses in Omarska, including Muslims being forced to
chew grass and grunt as pigs do and also to drink water from the ground as
dogs do. He told how he had seen a prisoner pushing an apparently lifeless
body in a wheelbarrow, and how he had seen Tadic insert the hose from a fire
extinguisher into the mouth of the body.
The defence evidence once again consisted of Tadics alibi that he was on
duty as a traffic policeman, and his claim that he had never visited Omarska.
The defence produced witnesses to say that he had often been seen at the
checkpoint, and that his superior officer had often checked to make sure he
was on duty; they testified that Tadic did not have the right to use the police
car for his own purposes, and so could not have travelled to Omarska. They
also argued that, since it is not known whether the body in the wheelbarrow
was alive or dead, then it was not necessarily an offence to insert a fire
extinguisher hose into its mouth. A number of witnesses testified that they
had seen Tadic at the Trnopolje camp. Tadic admitted having visited Trnopolje
on five occasions for innocent reasons, usually accompanying Red Cross visitors.
The judgment discusses in some detail the charge that the motivation for
the behaviour of the accused was discrimination on the grounds of race and
of politics, and was part of a plan to build a Greater Serbia without a
significant Muslim population. Tadic had been one of the early members of
the SDS, whose policy it was to cleanse the Republica Srpska. He was a
87
88
in one single grave. Subsequently all the houses of Jaskici were burnt, leaving
only ruins.
There were five witnesses, four of whom already knew Tadic, who saw
him in Sivci or Jaskici on 14 June in spite of the fact that he claims not to have
left Banja Luka. The tribunal was satisfied that Tadic was amongst the armed
men who entered these two villages. One witness, who had known Tadic,
described him beating men from the village with a stick, and pouring water
over those who had fainted in order to revive them. She also described Tadic
beating her father. She has never seen the men of her family since that day,
although she has made efforts to trace them. This witnesss sister described
Tadic beating men with a rifle butt. Both witnesses independently described
Tadic as having a beard and wearing a camouflage uniform. The other
witnesses identified Tadic, and described him taking part in classical ethnic
cleansing behaviour, beating, threatening and terrorising people out of their
houses.
Though there were some inconsistencies in the detail of the evidencefor
example in their descriptions of Tadics uniform and the uniforms of the other
armed men with himthe tribunal was satisfied that Tadic had been an active
participant in the ethnic cleansing of the two villages, but the tribunal was
not satisfied that the five men had been murdered by Tadic or the armed men
with him.
The next incident that Tadic was alleged to have been involved in was the
attack on Kozarac and the surrounding hamlets on 2427 May 1992. Witness
Q worked at the hospital in Kozarac. On the way home from the hospital on
24 May he saw Tadic with another man jumping over a fence into some
gardens. Moments later he saw a flare being launched from the vicinity of the
gardens, illuminating the hospital so that the Serbian artillery and tanks could
shell it and seriously damage it. The defence showed that witness Q had
previously given a different sequence of events in his witness statement, that
he had said that he was on his way to the hospital, not on the way home. He
explained the discrepancy by saying that he had not thought the details were
important when he gave his statement and that the account he now gave to
the tribunal was full and authoritative. The tribunal accepted Q as a reliable
witness. Other witnesses testified that they had seen Tadic in Kozarac during
the time of the attack and participating in the attack. One witness testified
that Tadic had said to him that Kozarac was going to be part of a Greater
Serbia, saying that he had liberated Kozarac and nobody is going to take
anything out of Kozarac, only over my dead body.
The judgment discusses a number of issues regarding the nature of the
evidence at the tribunal, and possible problems with it. This was the first
contested case before the ICTY. The rules of evidence and of procedure were
being developed by the tribunal and the appeals chamber during this and
following cases, aiming to draw on best practice from the worlds legal
systems.
The first problem discussed concerned difficulties regarding access to
evidence. Both parties encountered problems due mainly to the fact that the
authorities in the Republica Srpska were unwilling to co-operate with the
tribunal. Most prosecution witnesses were living in western Europe, whereas
most defence witnesses were resident in the Republica Srpska. At the trial,
use was made of video conferencing to link the courtroom with the Republica
89
90
91
92
campaign against Muslims, still enjoy their freedom. Tudjman, the architect of
the campaign of Croatisation in Bosnia and the Krajina, died peacefully in his
bed. The court in The Hague, say the sceptics, was set up by the ethical
imperialists9 who fought for hegemony in the Balkans under the cover of the
language of human rights; it was set up spuriously by the great powers in the
Security Council under the law authorising them to take measures to protect
world peace and security. The court is bureaucratic and slow. The system gives
great power to a politically motivated set of judges who are allowed to base
their decision on many kinds of evidence that would usually be deemed by
national criminal courts to be inadmissible, including hearsay, contaminated
identifications and anonymous witnesses. This sceptical argument has been
dealt a blow by the arrest of the big boss himself, Slobodan Milosevic. Many
sceptics had felt that it was impossible for the ICTY to try the real leaders, that
they would always be given de facto immunity by the great powers. The
argument, however, has simply slipped a little, and now portrays the man who
gave a million Kosovars hours to leave their country as an unfortunate scapegoat.
Alternatively, it is possible to see the ICTY as a step in an inevitable process
towards international order and human rights. The story of humanitarian
law and human rights is one of constant progress, banishing the darkness of
inhumanity from the bright new modern cosmopolitan civilisation. The law
has been written; it is in place. Finally, the world is in a position to deal with
those who seek to deny others the status of human beings.
The evidence from The Hague does not really show either of these views
to be true; or, perhaps, it shows them both to be true. The most important
thing about the court is that it exists as an empirical fact. Cosmopolitan law
cannot any longer be regarded as some sort of dream, but demands to be
recognised as a reality. It has demonstrated that it is possible for an
international court to hold trials under the universal jurisdiction of
international criminal law. There is something enduring in this demonstration.
We know that people can walk on the moon; we know that an international
criminal court is a possibility. Once these things are demonstrated to be
possible, they are possible forever.
Tudjmans successors in Croatia have grudgingly accepted the jurisdiction
of the court and its legitimacy. Mladic and Karadzic had no place at the
negotiations at Dayton, and were subsequently removed from power in the
Republica Srpska. Karadzics successor, Biljana Plavsic, now lives in a cell in
The Hague as she awaits her trial, and Milosevic is being tried. The fact that
Milosevic was indicted as a criminal must have been a significant boost to
those fighting to depose him. Even if the Serbian opposition was more
interested in his crimes against Serbs than his crimes against humanity, it
must have helped that he was officially accused by the international
community of being a criminal. It is not insignificant that these people could
not travel abroad: they could not make a living on the lecture circuit, nor
could they come to Harley Street for medical attention in their old age. It is
not trivial to be indicted as a war criminal. And the ICTY is having more
success than had seemed likely at one point in making significant arrests.
What of the charges against the court related to its flawed predecessor, the
Nuremberg tribunal? What is to be said about the tribunals foundation in a
9
Coates, 1999.
legal trick by the Security Council? What can we say about its own efficiency
or fairness as a court? These problems bring us back to the central point: that
of its existence. The court has a clear set of rules that it enforces. The provenance
of its existence and its rules may be questionable; there are answers to those
questions, however, and its existence is no longer in doubt. Neither are the
central precedents of Nuremberg any longer in doubt. Individuals are
responsible in law for their crimes, even if obeying orders, even if committed
as head of state. Crimes against humanity and genocide are criminal offences
that may be tried under universal jurisdiction. No principles in law are clearer
now than these, even if they were open to dispute in 1945.
There are some questions that may be asked about the fairness of the court.
For example, Geoffrey Robertson is worried about the lack of a clear
demonstrable physical and political separation between the prosecution and
the judges.10 We may also cite the incident of Dragan Opacic when he gave
anonymous evidence which was only discovered to be false at the last minute.
As Caroline Buisman argues, the inequality of resources available to the
defence and the prosecution, and the liberal rules of evidence, which are selfpoliced by the judges, are also possible sources of problems.11 It is an empirical
finding of this book, however, that the trials that I have observed and studied
have been relatively fair trials; that is to say, they have been unfair only to the
extent that ordinary criminal trials may be judged unfair. There is a clear body
of law and rules upon which the ICTY operates; there is the opportunity for
defendants to conduct a defence; there are opportunities to appeal against
decisions made by the judges to a separate appeals chamber; there is due
process; there are opportunities to cross-examine witnesses; there are honest
and competent judges. Of course, the fact that trials are fair and that
cosmopolitan law is clear does not tell us that there is a settled and just system
of cosmopolitan criminal law in place. But it does tell us that cosmopolitan
criminal law is possible and that it is not simply utopian.
10 Robertson, 1999.
11 Buisman, 2001.
93
Chapter Six
The Sawoniuk trial:
a cosmopolitan trial under national law
In Chapters Six and Seven, I look at two court cases that took place at the very
end of the 20th century. Both cases were concerned with one of its defining
events!, the Holocaust. One was the trial of Andrei Sawoniuk, a man who
had been involved in carrying out the genocide in a small town in Belorus.
The other was a defamation trial, in which David Irving, a British revisionist
historian, sued Deborah Lipstadt, an American academic, for calling him a
Holocaust denier. Both cases were looking back at the event from the distance
of more than half a century. Both courts, therefore, found themselves writing
the history of the Holocaust as well as judging more specific issues. Both were
judging men who had chosen to allow the genocide to define who they were,
who had been seduced by the glory and power of the Nazis, yet who were
not exactly Nazis themselves. Both trials were in Britain, perhaps the country
in Europe least touched by the events themselves.
A central task of both trials was to tell a story, or a history, of what had
happened, and to assign responsibility: to reproduce a narrative of muchnarrated events. But the courts were charged with producing narrative with a
unique form of authority. When courts make judgments they have the power
to enforce those judgments; they have at their disposal the power to award
damages as well as a monopoly on legitimate violence. Their judgments,
therefore, claim a particular authenticity; legal processes claim to be, and hope
to be recognised as, producers of impartial judgments. These cases were both
concerned with events that happened outside the territory of the UK; events,
in fact, that happened outside any particular national territory. But the
Holocaust was not only cosmopolitan in the sense that it happened throughout
Europe: it was also cosmopolitan in a whole range of other senses, which I
have discussed in this book. It was the business of the whole of humanity. So
when it is the task of courts to make judgments concerning the Holocaust,
they find themselves having to judge cosmopolitan events from a cosmopolitan
point of view: that is, from an impartial, and therefore not from a national,
point of view. These two cases had many of the characteristics of cosmopolitan
trials but were held in British courts under English law.
The main trial at Nuremberg was only the spearhead of the international
process of judging those responsible for the Nazi crimes. As well as the 12
other trials organised by the international tribunal, there were many national
post-Nuremberg trials organised by the successor regimes in countries that
had been occupied, such as Poland, Hungary, Yugoslavia, Greece, Russia and
France. These trials prosecuted those whose crimes could be localised in
particular jurisdictions.
The trial of Adolf Eichmann in 1962 was fundamentally one of these national
post-Nuremberg trials, although it had a number of peculiarities. Eichmanns
crimes could not be localised in a particular jurisdiction, since his job was in
the organisation of the genocide of the Jews across Europe. Yet he had not
been considered an important enough criminal to be included, even in absentia,
at the time of the main trial at Nuremberg. Thus, the trial of Eichmann in
Israel follows the pattern of the other national trials. His crimes were against
Jews, and so he was tried by the national courts of the Jewish state: not because
he had committed his crimes there, but because, retrospectively, he had
committed his crimes against its citizens. The Jews, in the absence of an
international criminal court, argues Hannah Arendt, had as much right to sit
in judgment on the crimes committed against their people as the Poles had to
judge crimes committed in Poland.1
The trial of Klaus Barbie in 1987 for crimes against Jews in France, and also
crimes against the French resistance during the war, was more
straightforwardly a national trial, even though the charge was actually crimes
against humanity. Barbie had been the head of the Gestapo in Lyon, and so it
was France that assumed the right to extradite him from Bolivia and put him
on trial.
These post-Nuremberg trials have contained a strange mixture of national
and cosmopolitan law. They followed the legal precedents set by the
Nuremberg process, and they convicted for the cosmopolitan offence of crimes
against humanity. But the courts were national criminal courts and relied on
the normal processes and institutions of criminal justice. There was always a
tendency for the trials to drift back from a cosmopolitan to a national
perspective. Arendt was critical of the Eichmann trial when it drifted away
from its central concerns with Eichmann and the Holocaust towards issues
more concerned with Israeli nationalism and the legitimacy of the state of
Israel, and when it glossed over issues concerned with Jewish collaboration
with the Nazis.2 Alain Finkielkraut, similarly, was critical of the Barbie trial
when it drifted away from its cosmopolitan focus towards the needs of French
nationalism and the continuation of the French national myth of resistance to
Nazism.3
The trial of Andrei Sawoniuk in 1999 may also be seen as a Nuremberg
successor trial. It was, however, carried out in Britain, not because the crimes
were committed in Britain or against British citizens, but because Sawoniuk
himself had settled in Britain and had British citizenship.
Since the Nuremberg trials, it has been an accepted norm of international
law that jurisdiction over war crimes and crimes against humanity is universal.
Such crimes, like those involving slavery and piracy, are understood in
international law as an attack not only on the particular state in which they
were committed but also on the international order. Any state, therefore, has
the right to try a suspect for such crimes under the universality principle.
However, when the British Home Secretary, Douglas Hurd, was faced with
calls for the prosecution of suspected war criminals living in Britain in February
1998, he summarised his position as follows:
We would normally deal with alleged crimes in foreign countries by way of
extradition. However, all the cases in question relate to crimes committed in
territories now controlled by the Soviet Union, with whom we have no extradition
treaty. Nor do the courts in the United Kingdom at present have jurisdiction to
1
2
3
95
96
4
5
Hansard, 1988.
[T]o enact legislation in this country to give the British courts jurisdiction over murder and manslaughter
committed as violations of the laws and customs of war would not be to create an offence retrospectively.
It would be making an offence triable in British courts to an extent which international law had recognised
and permitted at a time before the alleged offences in question had been committed. Report of the War
Crimes Inquiry, 1989, p 97, para 9.27.
The report argues that any attempt to legislate to provide for prosecutions with respect to acts of genocide
allegedly committed during the Second World War would be retrospective, since genocide was not defined
as an offence in international law until 1948. Report of the War Crimes Inquiry, 1989, p 96, para 9.23.
[T]o this day, crimes against humanity have not been incorporated into the federal law of the United
States. Instead, the INS sought to deport resident aliens or naturalised citizensnot as war criminals, but
as persons who lied on their emigration forms and thus never should have been permitted to enter the
country in the first place. Douglas, 2001, p 197.
Dodd, 2000.
in a blazer, creased trousers, and shiny shoes, like the old Polish soldier and
British Rail ticket collector that he was. He limped, and used a stick, but did
not seem particularly fragile. He seemed to be a man who knew how to look
after himself. He sat in court next to his solicitors, not in the dock, since he
was on bail. He followed the transcript of the proceedings as it appeared on
the laptop computer in front of him. He occasionally whispered, rather loudly,
perhaps because of his partial deafness, to his solicitors. They seemed friendly
and called him Tony. Not once in the whole trial did Sawoniuk look to his
right towards the press gallery, or to the public gallery above it.
He was born in Domachevo, a small, ordinary town that is currently in
Belorus, near Brest-Litovsk, and that was just inside the Polish border of the
old Soviet Union. When he was born there on 7 March 1921, it was in Poland.
Domachevos main business was tourism. It had a spa and some hotels and
guest houses. Domachevo conformed to the strange ethnic division of labour
that was common in eastern Europe. The town itself was almost entirely
Jewish, while the surrounding villages where the peasants cultivated the land
were almost entirely non-Jewish. The Jews supplied goods and services to
the farmers, as well as to visitors. The farmers sold their produce to the Jews
in the market. Everyone who testified at the trial, the non-Jewish witnesses
and Ben-Zion Blustein, one of the very few surviving Jews from Domachevo,
said that the two populations lived together in harmony. As well as the Russian
Orthodox church in Domachevo there was a Catholic church, where those
who considered themselves Polish worshipped. Domachevo was a town like
many hundreds of others that was soon to be engulfed by the Shoah in an
entirely typical way.
Sawoniuk himself was born, and lived his childhood, outside the
established division of labour, or perhaps underneath it. His family did not
have land to tend, and so they lived in the town itself. His mother made a
meagre living by doing laundry and other casual work for Jews, and when he
was old enough he also worked for Jews, doing odd jobs where he could find
them. He never knew his father, and his mother died when he was a child. He
was regularly called a bastard and was subjected to a certain amount of
bullying on that account. After his mother died he lived with his grandmother
and his brother Nikolai, or Kola. For these reasons he must have experienced
a certain amount of alienation from the society in which he lived and in which
he did not really have an established place. He left school at the age of 14. He
was known by everyone in Domachevo simply as Andrusha, a diminutive of
Andrei; Little Andy. He was still known by this diminutive when he was the
commandant of the local Nazi-organised police force.
The German invasion of Russia started on midsummer night 1941, and
within hours had swept well past Domachevo, which was one of the first
small towns it encountered. Within a very few days, the Germans had
organised a local police force that Sawoniuk and a handful of other local men
joined enthusiastically. He was 20 years old and had experienced two very
difficult years under Russian occupation. For the first time in his life he had a
job, and a place in the world.
Sawoniuk has lived in Britain since 1946. He moved around a little, mainly
on the south coast, before settling in London, just off the Old Kent Road. He
worked for British Rail, and retired in 1986. He married twice after the war,
both short marriages, and had a son with his second wife, but they parted
97
98
shortly after his birth. In Britain he has been, as the police testified, of good
character.
On 9 March 1999, he appeared in court 12 at the Old Bailey. In many ways
it was a routine trial. The defendants in the courts next door were accused,
one of rape, and the other of murder. There was no bulletproof glass screen to
protect him from assassination. There was no simultaneous translation
apparatus in the courtroom. It was the usual English courtroom. The barristers
wore wigs. The judge sat underneath the large royal crest on the front wall in
his rather grander wig. Sawoniuk was not accused of anything exotic or unBritish like genocide or crimes against humanity. He was accused of four counts
of murder contrary to the common law under the conditions specified in the
War Crimes Act 1991. The ad hoc tribunals for the former Yugoslavia and for
Rwanda have recently convicted for both genocide and crimes against
humanity;9 and Belgium has shown that it is possible for national courts to
make convictions for genocide.10 The fact that Sawoniuk was simply charged
with murder, albeit with conditions attached, added to the impression that
this was an ordinary Old Bailey trial.
For the individuals involved in the rape and murder trials in the
neighbouring courts, however, those cases were in no way routine or mundane.
They concerned events that must have made profound changes to the lives of
those affected. Criminal trials give extraordinary events a routine form: they
abstract them, shape them and civilise them. The rapist and the murderer, as
well as Sawoniuk, both wore shiny shoes and well pressed suits. Their counsel
spoke for them eloquently and persuasively. The judges politely offered them
drinks of water. If the Sawoniuk trial was made to look routine, that is partly
because that is a general function of a criminal trial. But the contrast between
the businesslike quality of the trial and the horror of the events that it concerned
was greater, because the events were extraordinary in a more profound sense
than an ordinary rape or murder.
There are many senses in which this trial was entirely extraordinary. It was
the first and only trial to be completed in Britain of someone accused of taking
part in the Nazi genocide of the Jews. It was the only prosecution under the
War Crimes Act 1991. It was the only time that a British court has sat in
judgment of crimes committed outside Britain, and the only time a British
court has travelled outside Britain. The trial happened 57 years after the crimes
in question. The crimes were part of the Holocaust, which is perhaps the
biggest and most extraordinary crime yet committed.
This juxtaposition between the ordinary and the extraordinary is a theme
that runs throughout this particular trial, and it echoes a similar dialectic that
many have detected within the Shoah itself. Claude Lanzmann11 is fascinated
by the ordinariness of the trains that transported so many to their deaths.
Zygmunt Bauman12 focuses on the bureaucratic individuals and procedures
that organised the mass killing. Karl Jaspers13 and Hannah Arendt14 wrote
about the banality of evil.
9
10
11
12
13
14
Eg Prosecutor v Kristic.
Le Monde, 8 June 2001.
Lanzmann, 1985.
Bauman, 1993.
Arendt and Jaspers, 1992.
Arendt, 1994a.
Sawoniuk was an ordinary kid, a nobody who joined the police force in
order to become a somebody When the real function of the police force became
clear, some, including his brother, left; he chose to stay. When the Einsatzgruppe
came to town to kill the Jews on Yom Kippur 1942, Sawoniuk helped. The Nazis
left to kill the Jews in the next town, and the local police were left the job of
hunting and killing those who had escaped the main massacre. Sawoniuk took
a central part in this hunt and kill operation for a few months until it was
complete. He killed maybe 50 or 100 or 200 Jews at this time, and he did so with
more enthusiasm than most. There must have been many tens of thousands
like him. They were a necessary part of the machine that committed the genocide.
It was the locally recruited police forces who knew the Jews, and who knew
where they might be hiding, much better than the invaders did. When it was all
over, he found a life for himself in Britain, and lived it. On 21 March 1996, he
was arrested by Metropolitan Police detectives, interviewed, and put on trial.
It was William Clegg, Sawoniuks barrister, who raised the question of
Sawoniuks ordinariness. One of Cleggs central strategies was to try to make
the prosecution look ridiculous and far-fetched. He often employed an ironic
and satirical tone, and with some success; he is a warm, witty man with a
sense of comic timing. The prosecution presented the enormous tragedy of
the Holocaust. The barrister for the Crown, Sir John Nutting, a stereotype of
an English establishment figure, tall, with an antiquated upper class accent,
slow and methodical, had begun his case. He had used Christopher Browning
as an expert witness to paint an outline of the Nazi plan to kill the Jews, of its
development and execution. He had followed Browning with a succession of
elderly witnesses. All these witnesses told the same background story, about
Sawoniuk, about the German invasion, the setting up of the local police force
and the ghetto, and most had added a particular testament to particular
atrocities committed by Sawoniuk. Clegg constantly had to try to change the
mood of proceedings for the jury He had to pull their attention away from the
greatest crime in human history and towards the specific charges made against
his particular client. He pleaded with the jury, as follows:
Lets be realistic and sensible. It was a ramshackle defence unit. He was just an
ordinary policeman. He was no decision maker. There was nobody of lower rank
than him. He was 20 or 21 years old. You may have felt that theres been an attempt
to elevate his position. What has Brownings evidence about Hitler and Himmler
to do with him? Hitler didnt have a hot-line from Berlin to his hut in Domachevo.
Its like comparing Churchill to Pike in Dads Army!15
99
100
Inevitably, the trial raised the question of responsibility for the genocide. Who
was responsible? Who can be responsible for a crime so huge that it can only
be perpetrated by the mobilisation of the resources of a whole state? Daniel
Goldhagen17 argues that the responsibility for the Holocaust rests firmly with
Germany, the German people, and their political institutions. They are the
ones who are responsible. They were Hitlers willing executioners. Indeed,
Nutting made use of Goldhagens phrase in his summing up:
the defendant played an effective part in the search and kill operation after 20
September 1942. Hitler needed willing executioners. The Crowns case is that the
defendant in one town and with the killing of a limited number of Jews played a
part, however small, in carrying out this policy.18
Goldhagen wrote his book in order to prove German collective guilt, and
thereby everyone elses collective innocence, yet Sawoniuk was not German.
In Domachevo, the main massacre of the Jews was carried out by a unit of
Einsatzgruppe men, who were German. They were assisted by a number of
Ukrainians, and also by the local police. It is inconceivable that Sawoniuk
was not present, since he was an important member of the local police, and
this was the biggest event requiring policing. He claimed that, by chance, he
went away for the weekend to visit friends. (I cant remember the name of
their village, I cant remember the names of the friends.) Yet the central
perpetrators of the main massacre were indeed German. This was a theme
that Clegg touched on more than once: the Germans killed the Jews; the local
police carried out normal police duties and the war against the partisans.
This, however, was not true. Germans led the killing of the Jews of Domachevo,
perpetrated the massacre, but relied on Ukrainian and local support both for
the main massacre itself and also for the subsequent search and kill operation.
It is the function of the court of law to extract Sawoniuk from the enormous
machine of the Third Reich. The Nazi movement committed the crime, but in
a court the individuals who were part of that movement are transformed
from footsoldiers and bureaucrats back into responsible human beings. The
extraordinary history of Europe in the middle of the 20th century had
transformed Sawoniuk as a young man from an ordinary human being into a
sadistic killer. He had succeeded in transforming himself back into an
unremarkable railway worker after the war. But the court demanded more of
him. It demanded that he take responsibility for those crimes he had committed
during the time when he was part of the genocide machine.
At one point during his cross-examination Sawoniuk lost his temper. He
shouted at the jury:
Andrusha Andrusha Andrusha. They say only Andrusha Andrusha. No one else
killed no one. Only Andrusha. Everyone else just watches and claps. Only they
pick on me.19
Nutting might have replied: No, Mr Sawoniuk, it isnt fair, is it? So many
were guilty and it is only Andrusha who stands trial. There must be many
thousands of old men in Europe who committed crimes worse than those
committed by Sawoniuk. Some of the members of the Einsatzgruppe who
17 Goldhagen, 1996.
18 24 March 1999.
19 22 March 1999.
Each count related to an incident of murder, and each was alleged by a different
witness.
Following the testimony of the expert witness, the whole court travelled to
Domachevo: the judge, the lawyers, the jury, the stenographers, court officials
and the press. The court list at the Old Bailey in London read Court sitting in
Domachevo. During his opening statement, Nutting had given the jury many
photographs of Domachevo and had taken much time going through them,
explaining each one. There were aerial photographs, including one taken by
Allied bombers during the war, photographs of the town as it is today, and
photographs of the paths travelled by the witnesses who alleged counts of
murder. During the trip to Domachevo, the court followed the paths travelled
by the witnesses and gained an overview of the town. Fedor Zan, a central
witness, had been sworn in before the trip, and showed the jury where he
had seen Sawoniuk shooting people.
Domachevo was under snow at the time of the visit. Much effort seems to
have been made to keep the jury away from contact with the press and the
locals. A newspaper report tells that the jury were held virtual prisoners in
the Intourist Hotel, a hostelry exuding all the charm of a tax office while the
prosecution and defence teams enjoyed the hospitality of the only Indian
restaurant between Warsaw and Moscow. The same report tells us that during
the tour of Domachevo, Nutting strode about in the manner of a grand
Shakespearean actor-manager, puffing on his pipe; the judge wore a pointed
red hat with ear-flaps as though it were an Arctic-grade judicial wig, and
Clegg made do with a brightly patterned Austrian ski jacket.21
20 Cesarini, 1999.
21 Hamilton, 1999.
101
102
24 Levi, 1987.
103
104
It seemed to me that Blustein was one of those Israelis who feels that the only
safe place for Jews is Israel, more particularly that Israel is the only safe place for
him. Being a witness in this court, and undergoing cross-examination, must have
been, and indeed appeared to be, an unpleasant and uncomfortable job for him.
Dan Stone writes about Holocaust memoir, and the ways in which many
historians of the Holocaust have undervalued survivor testimony in relation
to more solid types of evidence such as documentation.25 Jean-Franois
Lyotard has argued that a part of the enormity of the crime of the Shoah was
that it eradicated the witnesses and the evidence, making it impossible to
reconstruct or represent the events exactly. Stone quotes Lyotard as follows:
The perfect crime does not consist in killing the victim or the witnessesbut rather
in obtaining the silence of the witnesses, the deafness of the judges, and the
inconsistency (insanity) of the testimony.26
Stone argues that survivor testimonies, full of both traumatic truth and factual
inaccuracies, transcend traditional forms of writing histories, that:
testimonies make more clear than other evidence why the excess of the Holocaust
breaks the bounds of normal philosophy of historyand that this is the primary
reason why historians tend to shy away from testimonies28
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32 According to the Report of the War Crimes Inquiry, 1989, it was common practice for men who had been in
auxiliary police or militia units in the occupied territories to be recruited into the Waffen SS, rather than
the Wehrmacht, when the Germans retreated (p 90, para 9.2). Some fighting units were designated SS
units, but were used simply as part of an army. (p 3, para 1.13.) It is only possible to imagine what
connotations the words Waffen SS had for the jury, especially when it became clear that they were not
really supposed to have heard them.
33 Anglo-American adversary procedure organises the trial as a battle of wits between the prosecution and
defence, with the judge acting as their referee, constantly deciding what line of questioning and what
material should be allowed to enter the minds of the jury. Yet the judges authority in this respect may be
more official than real: a skilful lawyer will be able to make his point before his adversary can open his
mouth to object. The resulting wrangling on admissibility and the judges ritual exhortation in summing
up what points to disregardfor example, the political loyalties of the defendant in an espionage trial
only make the forbidden fruit more tempting to the jury than all the rest. Kirchheimer, 1969, p 342.
105
106
107
108
35 24 February 1999.
Clegg: Can you tell me about the police uniforms. Did they have uniforms
in the first few days after the German invasion. Wasnt it later?
Blustein: This thing didnt interest me and I didnt know about it. I still
think they had uniforms very soon after the invasion.
C: Do you remember giving evidence last year in the magistrates court?
B: Yes.
C: What did you say about police uniforms?
B: I dont know.
C: You said They eventually had a uniform. Remember?
B: No.
C: Do you accept thats what you said?
B: Yes. But it makes no difference.
C: Thats not what you said yesterday.
B: It is not my duty to know about uniforms.
36 24 February 1999.
37 24 February 1999.
109
110
from the story that he told in court 55 years later. Much of the difference was
easily explainable: Blustein admitted that he lied to the NKVD because he
was afraid of them. Yet much of his story in the NKVD statement was different.
He had told them that he and his family had hidden in the woods, not in the
cellar, that they had hidden for three days, not for nine, and that his mother
had been caught and shot. Why was his story so different?
Clegg: Can you confirm that is what you said in 1944?
Blustein: Mostly.
C: Lets go through it sentence by sentence. [He does so, at length.] Did you
give a wholly different account to the Russians in 1944 from what you
say today?
B: Not completely.
C: You would have had a motive for lying about your work as a telephone
engineer under German occupation before the massacre, so that you
couldnt be accused of collaboration. You would have had no motive for
lying about where you hid?
B: The NKVD official wrote what he wanted. I was waiting for him to
finish and let me go.
C: You read and signed it?
B: I cant remember. I would have signed anything.
C: Why did you lie about hiding in the woods rather than the ghetto?
B: I didnt want to get into an argument with him. Maybe he was drunk.
Who knows?
C: Was he unsteady on his feet?
B: I dont know. He was sitting down.
C: Were his eyes glazed? Was his speech slurred?
B: I cant remember.
C: You have no motive for giving a different account to the Russians?
B: My evidence was the same as Ive said here. What he wrote was up to
him. I wanted him to finish so I could leave. It didnt make any difference
to me what he wrote.38
Blusteins strategy was to be entirely indifferent. He was not used to being
asked such impertinent questions. His answers seem to be those that would
satisfy a group listening to the story of a survivor-hero. Maybe the Russian
was drunk? Of course! Everyone knows that Russians are always drunk. But
in the court, it is different. Blusteins story is that he told the NKVD man his
correct version, the man wrote whatever he wished to write, and Blustein
signed it in order to get away from the NKVD quickly and unscathed. It is
perfectly plausible. But why would the NKVD man have changed three days
to nine? And why would he have changed the cellar into the wood? And
Blusteins reply is, of course, who cares?. He is not interested in that; he is
interested in telling the world that everyone he knew was killed on Yom Kippur
1942, and that Sawoniuk was involved.
Blustein claimed too much. He claimed that his evidence was infallible in
every respect. He used the word holy to describe it. He did not trust the
38 25 February 1999.
court to assess his evidence fairly, to use its judgment in interpreting his
honesty. So he claimed that every single word was exactly true. Clegg had
little difficulty in comparing his words at the Old Bailey with his words the
year before in the magistrates court, his original statement to the British police,
his testimony to Yad Vashem, his book and his NKVD statement, and
discovering small but definite differences in each account.
This was the cross-examination that related directly to the killing of Mir
Barlas, count four:
Clegg: Turning to Mir Barlas. You couldnt see which way they went on
the Borisy Road, could you?
Blustein: They turned right. They could have gone to the forest or to
Domachevo.
C: You dont know where he went, or when or where he was killed, do you?
B: How could I know?
C: The conversation you say you had with Andrusha about Mir Barlas.
Did Andrusha say to you that he had killed Mir Barlas?
B: Yes.
C: Not that Mir Barlas had been killed by somebody?
B: No.
C: He said I killed him?
B: He said: He was very courageous before I killed him. We will see each other
in the world to come. No, thats wrong. He said before I liquidated him.
C: At the magistrates court you said that Andrusha did not say I killed
him. You said the opposite.
B: What did I say?
[Clegg reads it out again: there is no direct confession.]
B: Even if he did not say to me I liquidated him this was the biggest
proof that he did it.
C: But before, you said that he had said I liquidated him.
B: Yes, he said that.
C: You decided that Mir Barlas had been killed by Andrusha. That is
different from a confession In your evidence to Yad Vashem, transcribed
from a tape machine, you didnt mention the incident with Mir Barlas at
all. Can you confirm this?
B: I dont remember.
C: In your book One of the Sheep
B: I didnt write it. I told it to a woman from Yad Vashem. She wrote it.
C: Not one word about Mir Barlas?
B: It may be so.
[Clegg refers to Blusteins May 1995 statement to the British police.]
C: Not one mention about Mir Barlas or Andrusha confessing to his
murder?
B: They asked me to remember names of policemen. I remembered
Andrusha.
C: Is it true that you made no mention of Mir Barlas?
111
112
B: I dont remember.
C: Will you accept it from me?
B: It could be.
C: You described other peoples fate. Nothing about Mir Barlas. You were
asked: What can you tell me about Andrusha? Why didnt you tell them
about his confession?
B: I told them about tens or hundreds that he killed. For me it held no
special meaning. I could even now give you more names of people he
killed that I havent mentioned39
It seems likely that the truth was that Sawoniuk had said something to Blustein
along the lines that he gave in his first examination by Nutting, something
like Mir Barlas was very courageous before he was shot. This was the story
Blustein had given to the British police, to the magistrates court and to Nutting.
In this cross-examination he changed his story, claiming that Andrusha had
used the words I liquidated him. Blustein was trying to make sure Sawoniuk
was convicted by claiming that he had said those particular words. And
Blustein also claimed that he remembered the phrase exactly, word for word.
Judge Potts accepted Cleggs argument. He judged that, since Blustein had
given a different story in his evidence-in-chief and in his cross-examination
concerning Sawoniuks confession, this evidence could not be relied on to
make a safe conviction. It is interesting that in his many accounts of events in
Domachevo, Blustein had never mentioned the fact that Andrusha had
confessed to the murder of Mir Barlas. Is it possible that Blustein invented
this incident after he knew who the defendant was? That was Cleggs
implication in cross-examination. And Blusteins answer: who cares? I could
even now give you more names of people he killed that I havent mentioned.
The jury, in a murder trial, heard this accusation. It was entirely inadmissible,
entirely prejudicial, and probably also entirely true.
113
114
40 2 March 1999.
to do it; we Nazis are doing it for you. The killing of the Jews was not a secret.
It was not supposed to be a secret. It was not a crime committed on the quiet
or in the shadows. It was done in front of an audience. In Lublin, the
concentration camp was on the outskirts of the town and the railway station
in the centre of the town; Jews were marched from the railway station to the
camp, past the local population. The Nazis had a taste for the dramatic; for a
public drama of death.
Pushkina had little more to say about Sawoniuk himself. She did not see
him kill or mistreat anybody, but she was aware of his reputation as a man of
power, a man to be afraid of.
All the other prosecution witnesses spoke Belorussian, and were from
Borisy, a tiny hamlet near Domachevo. They were small farmers and their
religion was Russian Orthodox.
The first was Mrs Fedora Yakimuk, aged 73. She was the most peasantlike of all the witnesses, small, wrinkled, old, tough and stubborn. Clegg
entirely broke her down under cross-examination and made her admit that
all her evidence against Sawoniuk was gleaned from village gossip. Yet,
strangely, this did not affect her credibility. Clegg made her look ridiculous in
cross-examination primarily because she was uneducated, unintelligent, and
in a wholly foreign country and setting; but not necessarily because she was a
liar. The godmother of Yakimuks nephew, her sisters baby was Sawoniuks
first wife, Anna Maslova.
Yakimuk told the following dramatic story:
Nutting: Did you used to use a sickle when you worked in the fields?
Yakimuk: Yes.
N: Did you injure yourself?
Y: Yes. I cut my shoulder one day.
N: How did you treat the cut?
Y: My mother bound it up. She put iodine on it. The iodine came through
the bandage on my arm as a yellow stain. Andrusha saw me and shouted
Jude, Jude to make me stop. Andrusha and some Germans dragged me
away to be shot. I was crying, begging, kissing their feet. I was on my
knees explaining I was not a Jew and pleading for my life. Andrusha
knew me very well but he didnt protect me. The German pulled off the
bandage and saw the wound. He let me go. This was one week after the
massacre.41
It is a great story, and the press loved it. The headline in The Times was
Sawoniuk stood by as I begged for life.42 Undoubtedly it could be true, and
for this reason it is a powerful story Yet it is just as possible that it was only
partly true. Maybe it did really happen to her, but Sawoniuk wasnt actually
there? Maybe it really happened, but to somebody else, and Yakimuk was
telling it because it was true in a sense, and she wanted to be involved, she
wanted the trips to London, and she wanted the bad guy Sawoniuk put behind
41 2 March 1999.
42 Jones, 1998.
115
116
bars. Fifty-seven years is a long time. Mrs Yakimuk did not do well under
cross-examination:
Clegg: You never saw Andrusha commit any act of violence against
anyone, did you?
Yakimuk: His behaviour to everyone was violent.
C: Yes or no?
Y: Yes, but we werent allowed to see it. People did see acts of violence
but we werent allowed to go there.
C: Look at your statement of 12 February 1997 Is it a copy of your
statement to Scotland Yard?
Y: Yes.
C: Turn to page five. I never personally witnessed any acts of violence
during the German occupation. Did you say that?
Y: I did not say that.
C: [Repeats the quote.] Today youve told us you saw Sawoniuk beat people.
You didnt say that to the police, did you?
Y: I did see him herd people towards the sand hills but I couldnt be close.
C: You are changing your evidence to fit in with other peoples stories.
Y: Im telling you what I saw.
C: You have twice travelled here to give evidence in the company of other
people from Domachevo People in Domachevo are talking about this trial
Y: Yes.
C: Everybodys talking about Andrusha?
Y: Yes.
C: It is in the papers?
Y: Yes.
C: And on the TV?
Y: Yes.
C: Everyone is saying what Andrusha did in the war. But the truth is you
never saw anything in the war, isnt it?
Y: We werent allowed to go there.
C: Its untrue that you saw him beat people, isnt it?
Y: People werent allowed to see.
C: You said 10 minutes ago that you saw him beat people. Youve just
been caught out saying something that you never saw, havent you? Why
did you tell us that you saw Andrusha beat people?
Y: I didnt say that.
C: You said it a few minutes ago. Youre coming here and repeating a lot
of gossip, arent you?
Y: I did see people being driven towards the sand hills.
C: I suggest youre repeating gossip.
Y: I would see people being led away while I was queuing for bread.
C: When you said that you saw acts of violence, thats what others have
told you?
Y: Yes. I saw them led away but I was too afraid to go myself.
C: What you were telling me earlier was what others had told you.
117
118
43 2 March 1999.
44 3 March 1999.
119
120
B: No.
N: Where did you first see the Jews?
B: They were standing by a hole that had been dug out. There were three
Jews, two men and one woman. Andrusha ordered them to undress. The
men were about 40. They undressed. The woman, about 28, was reluctant
to take her pants off. Andrusha insisted. Andrusha threatened her with a
beating. The Jews were emaciated and unshaven. Andrusha shot the Jews
in the back of the head.
[Baglay explains that he and his friend were told to bury the bodies, and told that
they could take the clothes.]
N: Who shot the Jews?
B: Andrusha.
N: With what?
B: With the pistol, in the back of the head.
N: Did they fall into the pit?
B: Yes. One after the other.
N: Where was Andrusha?
B: Standing behind each.46
The next witness was Ivan Stepaniuk. Stepaniuk told of the death of Shlemko,
which related to count two of the indictment. Stepaniuk had known Shlemko
before the war when he had worked for him in his team on the railway.
Stepaniuk had seen Shlemko being taken away by Andrusha towards the
massacre site a few days after the main massacre. Andrusha was beating
Shlemko:
Nutting: What was Shlemkos reaction?
Stepaniuk: He was picked up, beaten again, picked up again The other
policeman held his right arm.
N: For how long did they remain in your sight?
S: Two to five minutes. No more.
N: Where were they going to?
S: Towards the woods.
N: You said he was killed. What happened after you lost sight of them?
Did you hear anything?
S: I heard the sound of gunfire.
N: When he was being hit was he doing anything to protect himself?
S: No.
N: How did he appear?
S: I cant describe him. How can I describe him?
N: What sort of spirits did he appear to be in?
S: How should he feel when he was being led away to his death? He was
quite insensitive.
46 5 March 1999.
121
122
he says he saw Sawoniuk shooting the women. The defence and the
prosecution agreed that the distance was 127 or 128 paces. The jury had to
decide whether an identification at that distance was safe. In the end they
decided that it was, and found Sawoniuk guilty on this count. By the time the
jury considered this count, they had reason enough to want to find Sawoniuk
guilty; but an identification at such a distance and such a length of time after
the event must, surely, be open to some reasonable doubt.
This was, perhaps, an echo of an argument he had had long ago with his
brother about leaving the police. He was his own man. He wasnt going to be
told by anyone else what was right and wrong. He would make his own
decisions:
Sawoniuk: I wasnt ready.
Nutting: You knew you could leave at any time?
S: Yes.
N: Some did leave?
S: I wouldnt know.
N: Didnt your brother leave?
S: He left soon after he joined.
50 22 March 1999.
123
124
S: If hed been ordered to kill Jews hed have done it else hed be dead. He
never discussed with me anything. He was only a half brother. We didnt
have good relations.
N: What you have done is to lift a corner of the truth. I suggest that what
you have told us about your brother leaving the police, that your brother
didnt like having to kill Jews, was true.51
Sometimes Sawoniuks testimony was so bizarre and incoherent that it was
not even incriminating. The one issue that made him really lose his temper
was the accusation that he had been a member of the SS after he left
Domachevo. He told a long and certainly fictional story about how he travelled
from Domachevo to France to join the Free Polish army. In fact he had travelled
from Domachevo to France with the German army as a member of the
Belorussian section of the SS. Nutting was able to confront him with his Polish
army document but it was only of use to the prosecution if Sawoniuk could
be enticed into authenticating it himself.
Nutting: Were you serving in the German army?
Sawoniuk: I never ever joined the German army.
N: Weve had that document translated. What it says is 1 August to 11
November 1944, German army according to his own statement.
S: [angry] Prove it me in black and white. Rubbish.
N: Why does it say so?
S: You are lying in front of the jury, everybody. I hope the jury doesnt
believe you.
N: Look at exhibit seven. Did you ever join the Waffen Border Regiment
of the SS number 76, 1st Battalion?
S: [very angry] You call me liar twice. I call you liar.
Judge: Yes, but did you or didnt you?
S: Never. Dont talk to me about German army. I wont answer no more
questions about German army.
N: Were you transferred from Warsaw to France in that regiment?
S: No.
N: Does the document give your surname, Sawoniuk? Is that you? Does
it give your date of birth?
S: Yes. 7 March 1921. Thats correct.
N: Place of birth, Domachevo?
S: Yes sir.
N: Against the German for place of birth does it say Domachevo?
S: I was born in Domachevo, yes.
N: Does the document say that?
S: Yes. I see it.
N: That is German isnt it?
S: What you putting German for?
51 22 March 1999.
125
126
only crucial questions. Perhaps if Sawoniuk had been charged with the crime
of genocide, or crimes against humanity, the court would have been more easily
able to take into account the whole story that emerged about his conduct during
the war. It would not have been necessary to focus exclusively on the two
murders, and it would have been possible to take into consideration other
evidence that added to the picture of Sawoniuk as a Nazi killer. And perhaps,
even if it had proved impossible to convict him of the two specific murders, it
might still have been possible to convict him of being part of the common plan
or criminal conspiracy to kill the Jews of Europe. But in this trial, the charge
was simply murder, and so the two particular counts were all-important.
Cleggs closing speech was interesting and, given that by this time Sawoniuk
seemed to have very little case left, surprisingly compelling. He noticed that
all the important witnesses, all the witnesses who testified to having seen
Sawoniuk committing atrocities, came from Borisy. The witnesses who came
from Domachevo itself, while providing background information, did not
tell of having seen Sawoniuk actually commit any crimes. But every single
person from Borisy who was alive during the war, said Clegg, and who is still
alive today, gave evidence of particular crimes carried out by Andrusha.53
Clegg argued that this was too much of a coincidence. Therefore, there must
have been either some sort of conspiracy in Borisy, or some sort of communal
action that was based on the Borisy collective memory, or gossip, of wartime
and of Andrushas involvement.
Clegg went on to give a reason why Sawoniuk would be particularly hated
in Borisy, a hamlet consisting of no more than 30 houses. Borisy was a partisan
village, and Sawoniuk freely admitted to having killed partisans. He even
recalled the incident where Zans uncle, aunt and cousins were killed. Also,
Clegg pointed out, Yakimuk, Melaniuk, and Alexander Baglay had not
mentioned important parts of the stories they told about Andrusha in court
at the time of the first British police interviews, so they gave new and important
information only when they knew who the suspect was. And further still,
there was much media interest in Domachevo concerning Sawoniuk, and
much talk about Sawoniuks guilt. Zan had given interviews to both British
and Russian television journalists about Sawoniuk. It is certainly possible that
by the time of the trial it was well known in Borisy, as well as Domachevo,
that Sawoniuk was guilty, and that it was important for him to be found guilty.
It might be the case, however, that the jury had already tacitly agreed upon
their verdicts before Cleggs closing address but after Nuttings, since it was
at this lunchtime that most of them were seen for the first time in the pub
across the road from the Old Bailey enjoying alcoholic refreshment.
The jury were certainly convinced of the general guilt of Andrei Sawoniuk,
and the two counts, based on the evidence of Alexander Baglay and Fedor
Zan, enabled them to convict him, which they did. Since he was found guilty
of murder, he was sentencedthe judge having no discretionto life
imprisonment.
The trial of Sawoniuk was, at least partly, a cosmopolitan trial. It dealt with
events in Belorus, organised by German Nazis as part of their attempt to kill
the Jews and take over the world. Perhaps, then, it would have been most
53 This, Clegg admitted at Sawoniuks appeal, was a littlebut not muchof an exaggeration.
127
128
appropriate to have held the trial in an international criminal court, and for the
defendant to have been charged with crimes against humanity. In the absence
of the existence of such a court, the trial was held in London under English law
and so took a transitional form between national and cosmopolitan.
The court dealt with evidence that was 56 years old and that had been
compromised by fading memories, by the telling and retelling of stories, by the
cross-contamination of evidence, and by the reconfiguration of old enmities.
The particular form of evidence that was demanded by English law was quite
specific, that of immediate oral testimony, subjected to cross-examination.
Other forms that might have shed light on the case, such as documentary
evidence, were excluded. Evidence offered in the form of Holocaust memoir
and of nationalistic narrative was aggressively transformed by the processes of
the court into its preferred forms. The court acted to legitimate survivor
testimony by locating it in the sacred space of law, but simultaneously to
delegitimate it by trying to remove control of the narrative from the hands of
witnesses and by contesting the value of much of the testimony.
A complex picture of Andrei Sawoniuk emerged from the process. The
contrast of ordinariness and extraordinariness in his story was striking.
Sawoniuk would surely not have become a killer if he had not found himself
in a situation where killing was expected and sanctioned by authority; yet
neither was he forced into it. Some aspects of Sawoniuks transformation into
a mass killer are in tune with Baumans framework, but others are in
contradiction to it. It is true that, believing the Nazis were destined to win the
war, his strategy of becoming a policeman and behaving in such a way as to
be trusted and promoted by the occupying power had a certain logic from the
point of view of his own narrow self-interest. It gave him a job, a living, power
and the possibility of promotion.
It is stretching the facts, however, to suggest that Sawoniuks decision to
become a gnocidaire was simply an example of rational decision making. First,
since his brother chose to leave the police force, and is still living quite happily
just across the river from Domachevo, it is clear that Sawoniuk could have
made the same choice if he had wanted to. He chose a different course, and it
was a free and conscious decision. He had an argument with his brother; he
chose to kill Jews and his brother chose to take his chances outside the police
force. Secondly, a decision such as whether or not to become a mass killer
must involve factors other than rational choice. It is only possible to speculate
about Sawoniuks early life and what kind of person he was when he chose to
become a killer. It is clear enough that he was not brought up in a loving
family and that he was poor. It also seems that he suffered as a child from
some bullying. None of this, of course, can explain how a person becomes a
brutal mass murderer, but it is not irrelevant that he was an excluded, alienated,
unloved young man. He found a way to improve his social prospects and
also, perhaps, an outlet for his anger. But Sawoniuk was in no way a Weberian
bureaucrat who just obeyed orders and carried out professional duties. He
chose to become a killer and he chose to kill and beat with more brutality
than the efficient pursuit of a bureaucratic goal could possibly require.
When they gave evidence, both Blustein and Sawoniuk had attempted to
wrest control of their stories from the court. Blustein was mistrustful of the
court and its rules; he did not trust the court to hear his evidence fairly or to
believe him. He wanted to be in control of the story he told, to tell what he
wanted to tell, rather than be confined and guided by the adversarial system.
He did not want to play the game of cross-examination; rather he wanted to
be believed. He did not mind if the court was unhappy with one true story;
he could tell another true story. It didnt matter to him. Sawoniuk felt that he
was cleverer than the court, and cleverer than his own lawyers; if only he
could have a chance to tell his story to the jury, they would believe him. He
thought that he could talk his way out of the Old Bailey, as he had, presumably,
talked his way out of many a tight spot before.
Both of the men, the one who as a young man had seen everybody he
knew killed, and the one who as a young man had taken part in that killing,
felt that they could circumvent the rules and norms of the court. They both
wanted to talk straight to the jury and they did find ways of doing so. They
might have done better if they had trusted the court more, if they had
attempted to use the rules of the court in their favour rather than attempting
to rise above those rules. Blustein might have avoided having the count that
was based on his testimony thrown out if he had trusted the court to believe
his original evidence of an indirect confession; it was because he did not trust
the court to do so that he embellished it with his claim that Sawoniuk made a
direct confession. Sawoniuk would have avoided showing himself so clearly
to be a liar. On more than one occasion during his cross-examination, Nutting
was happy to allow Sawoniuk to speak directly to the jury without
intervention. Sawoniuk would have had more chance of success by exercising
the right to silence, which was offered to him by the law, than by following
his strategy of trying to communicate in an unmediated way with the jury.
On the other hand, it might be that the jury was swayed as much by evidence
that was inadmissible or prejudicial as it was by the evidence upon which it
was supposed to come to a decision. The witnesses found ways to talk to the
jury that were non-legal, outside the formal rules of the court. Blustein
presented the jury with his emotional and moving Holocaust memoir. He
challenged them to accept it in spite of Cleggs smart cross-examination and
the judges earnest directions. The existence of the jury and the privacy of the
jurys discussions are also within the rules and norms of the criminal trial,
not outside them. Evidence is given in the presence of the jury so that they
can assess non-verbal messages from witnesses. They must be able to see the
witnesses giving evidence, and enduring the pressure of cross-examination,
in order to come to a judgment as to their truthfulness. The rules and norms
of law insist that the jury make its judgment not only from the words spoken
by the witnesses but also from the ways in which they are spoken. Embedded
within the norms and rules of the criminal trial are the mechanisms by which
the rules and norms of evidence may be subverted. The extraordinariness of
the events with which this trial was concerned accentuated the difficulties
that the trial process has with abstracting and shaping events in the world so
that they can be judged in the courtroom.
129
Chapter Seven
Irving v Lipstadt and the legal construction
of authoritative cosmopolitan narrative
The Irving v Lipstadt libel trial was a different kind of trial from the criminal
trials examined so far. It was centrally concerned with assessing the
parameters, rules and norms of academic historiographical methodology. It
was asked to decide whether the work of David Irving, which questions and
denies central facts about the Holocaust, fell within or without those
parameters; or, at least, whether someone who says that Irving is a Holocaust
denier rather than a historian should be stopped by the law from publishing.
Inevitably, this decision necessitated some investigation into the actual events
in question as well as into the accuracy, limits and legitimacy of the
historiography that has mapped them. Thus, the trial was judging the events
of a particular set of crimes against humanity in a different way from a criminal
trial. Instead of asking whether a particular defendant shared a legal
responsibility for them, it was asked to make a judgment about the two
different forms of narrative that claimed to chart them: the academic form of
Deborah Lipstadt and the revisionist form of David Irving. The court was
being asked to produce a form of narrative of its own.
Two forms of narrative, then, were given to the court as inputs: an academic
form and a revisionist form. The court had to produce a cosmopolitan and
legally authoritative output by working on those inputs according to its own
procedures, rules and norms. Even though the court was a national one, its
task was to give an impartial, that is, not nationally particular, verdict regarding
a profoundly supra-national event. The judgment consisted of a 349-page
document that sketched the central events and facts of the Holocaust, and
showed how Irvings writing could not be rightly understood as even an
eccentric or dissident attempt at honest historiography.1
The judgment was a cosmopolitan narrative. The second half of this chapter
discusses the significance of this kind of legal production of cosmopolitan
narrative. It draws on other cases from this book and elsewhere. I argue that
cosmopolitan trials are in a particularly strong position to produce
authoritative descriptions of highly contested sets of events; events that are
the subject of shaping and reshaping by competing mythologies of nationalism.
Cosmopolitan courts contain mechanisms that aim to free their judgments of
national particularity. They require evidence to be scrutinised in rigorous ways;
they can hear different forms of evidence, evidence from different countries
and different points of view. The narratives produced by cosmopolitan courts
are produced with the authority of an established body of international
humanitarian and human rights law.
Irving v Lipstadt
I was in the queue outside the courtroom where the case was being heard. A
man behind me was explaining the issues very loudly to his companion. Why
doesnt Irving have the balls to tell the truth? he asked:
He knows as well as we do that no Jews were ever killed, there were no gas chambers.
So why does he admit that some existed but not others? Hes just trying to please
the judge. But we all know that hes made his mind up already. All they have to do
is go to Auschwitz, dig up the rubble, and find that theres no holes in the roof.2
Then theyd know there were no gas chambers. But they wont do it. Because then
the whole game would be up
I turn round to watch and listen, not knowing what to do. Should I attack
him? Argue with him? I just continue to watch and listen, keeping eye contact
with him. He enjoys the attention. His self-righteous little monologue puffs
up, becoming louder and more confident. He is aware that he has an audience
to shock. He covers many important issues, the flood of asylum seekers, the
weakness and hypocrisy of the Labour government: If they continue to
come over here, then perhaps Ill leave the country. I, and those near me in
the queue, listen for about five minutes, until the courtroom is opened and
we are allowed to file in, making every effort not to have to sit next to the
Nazi for the entire morning.3
The Irving case was in some ways more unpleasant and shocking to observe
than the crimes against humanity trials. There was always a sprinkling of
Nazis in the audience, ready to laugh at Irvings witticisms and marvel at his
cleverness. Irving himself was not being asked to answer for any Nazi crimes
in court. On the contrary, his performance in court actually constituted his
political activity. We were not observing the consequences of his activity, but
the activity itself, that of a racist intellectual who had made it his business to
defend Hitler and to ridicule Holocaust survivors.
Deborah Lipstadt first published her book, Denying the Holocaust: The
Growing Assault on Truth and Memory, in 1993. It was an academic study that
sought to expose the methods, strategies and political agendas of those who
deny the Holocaust. It mentioned David Irving 16 times. She called Irving
one of the most dangerous spokespersons for Holocaust denial. Familiar
with historical evidence, she wrote, he bends it until it conforms with his
ideological leanings and political agenda.4
Irving sued Lipstadt and Penguin Books for libel but he presented himself
as a victim. In court he was alone, representing himself. On the other side of
the room was barrister Richard Rampton and the late Princess Dianas divorce
lawyer, Anthony Julius, accompanied by a team of about 10 busy, scurrying
young lawyers; they were able to elicit the testimony of five eminent academics,
backed up by long reports prepared with the help of their research assistants;
they had the financial backing of the Penguin corporation. Outside the
courtroom was the entire world Jewish conspiracy trying to silence Irving.
But the truth, sometimes overlooked by the commentators on the trial, was
2
3
The holes he meant were the ones through which the gas was introduced.
Kate Taylor says: On most days, assembled at the back of the courtroom were a motley crew of Irving
supporters. At least three were known members of the BNP, Bob Gertner, Arthur Flinders and Ron Smith.
Taylor, 2000, p 30. I dont know if this Nazi was one of these.
Lipstadt, 1994, p 181.
131
132
that it was Irving who was trying to silence Lipstadt; it was he who instigated
the trial; it was she who was forced to spend five years of her life defending
her right to publish. It was David Irving who had nothing to lose.
At the beginning of the trial it was agreed by both sides, and Judge Charles
Gray, that there would be no jury. Anthony Julius explained later5 that the
Lipstadt sides motivation for agreeing to this was that it would simplify and
shorten the trial. He denied that they would have been more worried about
the outcome of the case had it been tried by a jury. He also argued, with
hindsight, that the greatest benefit of having no jury was that the judge
produced a large, comprehensive and closely argued written judgment that
vindicated Lipstadt in detail, and that also concluded that Irving was a liar
motivated by racism. A jury would only have been able to produce a guilty or
not guilty verdict.
Julius also explained why they never called eye witnesses of the Holocaust
to give evidence against Irving. Some survivors had been unhappy at this
decision, arguing that they spoke with a unique authority, and felt marginalised
because they were not allowed to be central in rebutting Irvings case
themselves. Julius argued that the Lipstadt legal team had a moral objection:
they did not want to expose survivors to days of cross-examination by the
belligerent anti-Semite. They also had a forensic objection: they wanted to
run the case as if it was their case, to take the initiative in the trial. They wanted
to show that Irving was corrupt; that his history was full of lies and distortions.
The best way to do this, they decided, was to call historians to speak for the
historical documents. They wanted to put Irving on the defensive, to run the
case like a history seminar with Irving as a rather bad student.6 Lipstadt, too,
did not give evidence. Her team felt that her evidence was in her book. They
wanted to focus the case on Irving and his books, not on Lipstadt.
In the case, Irving denied three central things: that Jews were killed in gas
chambers at Auschwitz; that Hitler directly ordered their slaughter; and that
there was any systematic plan to destroy European Jewry. Irving claimed that
the well known pictures of bodies taken in concentration camps were victims
of typhus, of death by natural causes. Why were they all so thin, he asks, if
Jews were taken straight off the trains and killed? He boasted that Auschwitz
was the flagship of the Holocaust legend; if that were sunk, as it would be
within six weeks, the whole legend would crumble. In this case Auschwitz
became a substitute for the whole genocide; and the gas chamber Birkenau II
became a substitute for Auschwitz.
The first expert witness for Lipstadt was, therefore, Robert Jan van Pelt, an
architectural historian who has done some of the most interesting and
authoritative research on Auschwitz.7 He had spent a number of years in the
archives there, reconstructing the architectural history of the camp and
particularly of the gas chambers. Van Pelts report said that the overwhelming
evidence showed that a million Jews were murdered at Auschwitz. He said
that the convergence of testimony made it a moral certainty that the gas
chambers were the main instrument of murder between summer 1942 and
1944. Van Pelt cited eye witness evidence that had been given by prisoners
5
6
7
Julius, 2000.
Julius, 2000.
van Pelt and Dwork, 1996.
I discovered plenty of evidence in the archives indicating that Julius Schaub was one of Hitlers most loyal
followers. He had joined the Nazi Party in the early 1920s, taken part in the failed Putsch of 1923and
been decorated with various prestigious Nazi awards After the war he did his best to exonerate Hitler
from responsibility for the crimes of Nazism, claiming he had cursed the war and was always for peace.
He was not a very trustworthy witness, therefore. Evans, 2002, pp 6263.
9 Guttenplan, 2002, p 181.
10 Guttenplan, 2002, p 181.
133
134
He said that they recorded only very small traces of cyanide in the gas
chamber remains and relatively large traces in the delousing chamber remains;
therefore the gas chambers were never in fact gas chambers.11 The report was
flawed rubbish, said Rampton, Lipstadts barrister. It was pioneering work,
even though it has been superseded. Leuchter was barking up the right tree,
said Irving. Van Pelt said that the residues were different in the different types
of gas chamber due to differences of heat and humidity levels when gassing
people and clothing. The Leuchter report was, indeed, an amateurish report
produced by a man with no expertise, either historical or forensic.12 Irving
admitted that it was fatally flawed, but he insisted that Leuchter was
nevertheless right in his conclusions.
In his cross-examination, Irving grilled van Pelt on one document in
particular, questioning its authenticity. He rattled off questions: about a serial
number out of sequence, an incorrect rank for the signing officer, the initials
of the typist (which Irving said existed on no other document), even the precise
location of the margin. All these discrepancies, bragged Irving, suggested a
forgery. This is where Irving is happiest, rolling around in swastika-embossed
paper. He knows their mannerisms. On this terrain, Irving can be frighteningly
convincing.13 In fact, after two days research, van Pelt was able to authenticate
the document, and to give satisfactory explanations for Irvings anomalies.
One of the strategies of the defence was to present documents deliberately
ignored by Irving that showed things that he wished to deny. Irving responded
either by calling them forgeries, or by claiming that he had never seen them
and therefore could not be guilty of distorting them. This was not
fundamentally a trial about the truth of the historical account of the Holocaust;
it was a trial about David Irvings distortion. Thus Irving had to deny having
read books that he owned, and even ones that he had commented upon in
public, if they contained evidence that he claimed never to have known about.
The other expert reports produced by the defence were written by
Christopher Browning, by Peter Longerich, whose account detailed evidence
concerning the Holocaust outside Auschwitz, by Jaho Funke, whose report
examined Irvings contemporary links with neo-Nazis in Germany, and by
Richard Evans, whose report examined Irvings historiographical
methodology.
Browning said that the total number of Jewish victims in the Holocaust
was between five and six million. A good approximation could be made for
the numbers from Poland and westwards, but there is more uncertainty about
the figure in the Soviet Union, since records, both Russian prewar records
and Nazi records during the war, were not as accurate as in Europe. Irving
spent much time in cross-examination of Browning trying to dispute these
figures. He tried to suggest to Browning that the Madagascar plan (to send all
the Jews from the Reich to Madagascar) might have been a good one. Browning
11 Shapiro, 1990.
12 Leuchter had taken great chunks out of the wall instead of scrapings off the surface, thus greatly diluting
whatever residues were to be found there. Even more crass, he had also ignored the fact that the
concentration of cyanide gas needed to kill humans was far lower than that needed to kill lice in clothing,
and so failed to understand that, far from disproving the existence of the gas chamber as an instrument of
murder, his findings actually tended to confirm it. Evans, 2002, p 133.
13 Freedland, 2000.
argued that it could have been attempted only if the British had been defeated,
so that the Nazis could use shipping safely. Anyway, argued Browning, it was
only ever a bizarre fantasy; the results would have been disastrous, and a
large percentage of the people would have perished in an SS-run state. Irving
replied: I think the Jews are a very sturdy people. Irving argued that there
had been no explicit reference to killing at the Wannsee conference; Browning
argued that there were a number of passages whose meaning was viewed by
most people as transparent.
Richard Evans was not a Holocaust specialist, but a specialist in German
political history and in historiographical methodology. Evans claims that he
began the investigation into Irvings work with an open mind; he was paid
by the hour, he said, and not for his conclusions.14 Irving based his books on
primary sources; he is proud not to rely on the work of other historians. On a
first reading, said Evans, Irvings books appear entirely plausible. However,
he and his research students had carried out a most detailed and painstaking
investigation into Irvings sources. They followed up each reference, found
the documents to which they referred, and checked them. Evans found that
every piece of Irvings work that they examined in this way, not just those
that referred to the Holocaust but others that they examined as a control,
turned out to be a tissue of small manipulations rendering his entire output
absolutely worthless. An example Evans gave was drawn from Irvings
account of the main trial at Nuremberg. Irving claimed that Biddle, a judge at
Nuremberg, had commented about a witness in his diary, all this I do not
believe. So in Irvings work all the testimony of this witness was invalidated.
When the reference was checked by Evans, he found that the truth was that
Biddle had in fact said this I do not believe, clearly referring to a particular
piece of the witnesss testimony, and emphatically not to the rest, which he
certainly did believe. Irving had inserted the word all and changed the entire
meaning of the original.
Another example of Irvings distortion of the historical record was his
treatment of a document known as the Schlegelberger memorandum. Irving
used it in the 1991 edition of Hitlers War to show that Hitler could not have
ordered a policy of genocide against the Jews.15 The document included the
apparently startling information that the Fhrer had repeatedly explained
that he wanted the solution of the Jewish Question put back until after the
war.16 This undated and unsigned document was found in a file that had
been put together from Ministry of Justice papers after the war. Evans showed
how the accepted explanation for this document amongst historians was that
it was part of a discussion being held after the Wannsee Conference about the
fate of half-Jews and Jews in mixed marriages. This explanation fits well
with other documents from the same file, and with a meeting between Franz
Schlegelberger and Hans Heinrich Lammers which took place on 10 April
1942. It may, on the other hand, argued Evans, date from the summer of 1941,
when no fixed plan had yet been made for the final solution and when the
end of the war was thought to be only weeks away. Irving was pretending to
14 Evans, 2002.
15 As discussed in Evans, 2002, p 89.
16 Evans, 2002, p 89.
135
136
his readers that this document proved Hitlers lack of culpability for the
genocide, while he knew full well that it had in fact long been regarded by
professional historians as [proving] nothing of the kind.17
After the trial, Evans presented an interesting point of view in relation to
the often repeated argument in the press that a courtroom is no place to be
discussing and judging academic debate. Evans said that the rules and facilities
of the courtroom were, in fact, very helpful. In court, time was unlimited. If
Evans wanted to dispute the meaning of the precise placing of a full stop in a
document with Irving, for example, then he could do it; and he could do it for
hours, until he had made his point. This, Evans, remarked, was not always
possible in an academic seminar. Also, he said, the transcripting process in
the court was invaluable. It created an accurate record of what had been said.
If someone claimed they had not said something that they had in fact said, if
they changed their story subtly, then this could easily be shown in the
transcript. The court had resources of time, people and money that are not
usually available to academics.
Evans concluded that Irvings methodology is informed by the fact that
Irving thinks that he already knows the real truth; given this fact, the
documents may be manipulated a little in order that they should show this
true picture. Irvings work could not be regarded as history because it
consistently asserted things that the documents did not allow as possibilities.
There is vast space for debate and disagreement within the parameters of
what the historical evidence allows as possibilities; but Irving was not at all
constrained by the documents that he knew so well.
The defence spent some time showing Irvings motivation. Evans, Browning
and van Pelt had shown how he consistently lied about the historical evidence;
the defence now showed that the reason he did this was that he was a racist, and
was motivated by a wish to exculpate the Nazi regime and specifically Adolf
Hitler. His political project was to deny that the Nazis carried out the genocide,
and to show that, in any case, Hitler had not ordered one. This is the first step in
the rehabilitation of the Fhrer and his ideas. The defence found many examples
of Irvings racism. One of the most striking perhaps was from a passage in Irvings
diary in which he says that he sang a rhyme to his nine-month-old baby daughter
Jessica when half-breed children were wheeled past them in their prams:
I am a baby Aryan
Not Jewish or sectarian
I have no plans to marry an
Ape or Rastafarian.
Another example of Irvings racism was gleaned from a transcript of a speech
that he had made to his friends in the Clarendon Club. He regretted that
newsreaders at the BBC no longer wore dinner jackets when they read the
news. He suggested that on the BBC, in future, a newsreader in a dinner jacket
should read the serious news, then a lady should read the less important
news, the gossip about showbusiness and so on, and then Trevor McDonald18
should present the latest news about muggings and drug busts. I wish I could
go to Heathrow and get on a plane and land back in England as it was when
17 Evans, 2002, p 94.
18 Trevor McDonald is a well known black newsreader.
I was born in 1938, he mused in a speech. He feels queasy because there are
black cricketers in the England team:
I was speaking about what a pity it is we have to have blacks on the team and they
are better than our whites. I say its a pity because I am English I call it patriotism
patriotism is pride in a country that has been handed to you by your fathers. I
dont think there is anything despicable or disreputable about patriotism
The defence spent two days at the trial cross-examining Irving over his racist
speeches and writings. Irving laughed it all off as fun, or as patriotism.
One of the most telling pieces of evidence against Irving was a video
recording of a speech that he made in Tampa, Florida, in October 1995. It was
organised by the National Alliance, an American Nazi group. Jaho Funke
testified that Irving had spoken at eight of their events between 1990 and
1998. Irving denied knowing who had organised the meeting, even though
there was a very large National Alliance symbol visible close to him, and the
meeting had been introduced by a man who welcomed the audience to the
National Alliance event. The speech contained many unpleasant examples of
Holocaust denial, racism and antisemitism. But the recording of the speech
also showed, quite clearly, that David Irving considers himself to be part of
the movement. He uses the word we often. We are making progress; we are
beginning to cast doubt on the Holocaust legend; we are engaged in a heroic
struggle for truth. Irving was speaking to his comrades.
Funke, a political scientist from the Free University of Berlin, wrote a 140page report for the defence about Irvings links with neo-Nazis in Germany.
Using video clips of footage of Irving speaking in German at far right events,
Funke identified an assortment of leading extremists and neo-Nazis who had
also been present. Skinheads in boots were shown marching to a rally in Halle
in 1991, where Irving was one of the speakers. When he spoke they were heard
to shout Sieg Hell. Did you see me put my hand up to tell them to stop? Irving
queried. He went on to suggest that he had been shocked by some of his
audience. Did you get the impression that I was overjoyed? Was I happy? he
asked. Funke retorted that Irving had known the character of the event.
Funkes report said that Irving had strong and consistent connections with
many German neo-Nazi organisations between 1990 and 1993. Some groups
were subsequently banned for inciting racial hatred. How could I have
anticipatedthat they would be banned? asked Irving. As an intelligent
man who knows German, you could have known, replied Funke.
Funke told the court that Irving had said at a press conference in Berlin
that it is a defamation of the German people if one talks of extermination
camps or death camps. Irving said he was misquoted. Funke said that Mr
Irving committed himself wholeheartedly to the cause of revisionism, and
thus neo-Nazism, in Germany. For 10 years, until he was banned from
Germany in 1993, he was in a political alliance with the German Peoples
Union, an antisemitic party, and its leader Gerhard Frey.
Irving denied joining a toast to a certain statesman to mark what would
have been his 101st birthday at a 1990 Munich dinner. I had no glass as I
dont drink. If one has no glass and one doesnt drink, how can one toast? A
characteristic example of the arrogance of Irving; he uses this childish logical
trick and assumes that everyone is forced, against their will, to the conclusion
that nothing can be proved against him.
137
138
Irving claimed in the case that many Jews died while working and were
not murdered; he asked why there were doctors and hospitals at Auschwitz if
it was an extermination camp. Peter Longerich replied that the policy of
extermination through work was illustrated by the death auditsmaintained
by the camp authorities. The duty of Nazi doctors was not to keep inmates
alive but to keep their effectiveness as a workforce as high as possible.
Speaking later,19 Anthony Julius downplayed the importance of the Irving
case; no new knowledge or insight came out of it; his side had not wanted
the case to happen at all; it was important only to Irvings side. Therefore
the case would have been very important if Irving had won it. Julius also
argued that the written judgment, a 334-page document, gave the case some
importance because of its clarity, detail and authority. From his point of
view, something good came out of the case in the end. What he felt had
been achieved was this newly authoritative narrative that gave the truth of
the events of the Holocaust, and of David Irvings distortions, to the world
and to future generations.20
19 Julius, 2000.
20 There was a strange parallel to the Lipstadt v Irving case being heard in the same building at the same time.
Independent Television News (ITN) was suing the magazine Living Marxism for libel. Living Marxism had
published an article about the breaking of the story of Omarska and Trnopolje in the Western news media.
ITN journalist Penny Marshall and her cameraman, Jeremy Irvin, accompanied by Channel 4 journalist
Ian Williams and Ed Vulliamy from The Guardian, had been the first journalists to see and report on the
camps. The journalists had shot some videotape on 5 August 1992 from which was reproduced a well
known picture showing an emaciated Muslim prisoner at Trnopolje, called Fikret Alic, behind a barbed
wire fence. The media made much of this picture because of its obvious similarities to images of emaciated
prisoners from Nazi concentration camps. The barbed wire in the picture is not around the Bosnian Muslims;
it is around the cameraman and the journalists, wrote Thomas Deichmann in Living Marxism. The article
went on to argue that the picture and the account of the camps had been invented by the journalists in
order to propagate the myth of Serbian concentration camps in Bosnia. This case of left wing denial of the
Serbian campaign of ethnic cleansing and terror was shorter and simpler than the Irving case, and received
much less publicity. ITN and the journalists wanted to defend their reputations, and to defend the truth of
their scoop. Their story, indeed, had been a profoundly important one for the public understanding of
the war and for public pressure on the UN. The case was heard before a jury and was won by the journalists.
The damages that were awarded bankrupted Living Marxism.
Yet these criteria are fuzzy, shifting and ambiguous,23 and it is easy to think
of examples of nations that lack one or more of these criteria. This difficulty
of defining the objective existence of the referent of the world nation focuses
attention back onto nationalism as an ideology, and onto the nation state.
There is agreement in the sociological writing on nationalism that nations
and nation states are modern phenomena, no more than one or two centuries
old; this finding is, of course, starkly at odds with the claim of all nationalisms
to be age-old communities that stretch back into the mists of time. Moreover,
nations are more the creation of states than the other way round; the
emergence of groups of people who feel a national belonging with each other
was in fact the result of, not the cause of, the development of the modern state.
Benedict Andersons24 anthropological approach to the question emphasises
the fact that the nation state is bound together by the telling and retelling of
myth. The use of the term myth in this context highlights the sacred or
pseudo-sacred nature of the narratives. They are narratives that social actors,
consciously and unconsciously, have succeeded in imbuing with that sacred
quality. Nations are imagined communities, first because they are based on
myths of foundation and of common history, and secondly because they are
so large that the relationship of one citizen with others can only be mediated
by ritual, by printed communication and through the mass media. A nation
21
22
23
24
Gellner, 1983.
Cited in Hobsbawm, 1995, p 5.
Hobsbawm, 1995, p 6.
Anderson, 1995.
139
140
forges an identity through telling itself stories. Stories give a sense of direction
and continuity, and therefore identity and community.
Kevin Foster uses the term myth:
to describe a chain of associated concepts, usually rendered as a narrative, by
which individuals and communities mediate their personal and collective anxieties
and through which they are able to understand, express and communicate to
themselves and others a sense of their identity as members of specific social, cultural
and national groups.25
Foster discusses the forging of myth in relation to the Falklands War and British
identity. He argues that accounts of the war assumed a classically mythic form,
in Roland Barthes terms, by making a historical intention a natural justification,
and [making] contingency appear eternal. The decision to go to war and the
conduct of the war were presented as an expression of the essential character of
the British nation: there had been no other possibilities. The Britain that turned
defeat into victory at Dunkirk and that developed the Blitz spirit could only
have gone to war in the Falklands, and could only have emerged victorious.
The image of the heroic, modest but invincible British soldier is not only derived
from myths of Britishness but also bolsters those myths. Foster focuses on the
Falklands War as a struggle for ideological rather than physical terrain.26
Given that nation states are the ubiquitous form of political community in
our time, and that nationalism relies heavily on the creation of myths of
nationhood, then much of the writing about social memory focuses on its
nationalistic character. Narratives of nationhood are one of the pillars upon
which nation states are built and maintained. While the narratives speak of
timeless community, stretching back into the mists of history, the narratives
themselves, like the nations they constitute, are much more flexible than they
appear. Which narratives are to be told, which are to be heard, which are to be
accepted as national truth; these are questions of the utmost political
importance. There is always political controversy about how history and
religion are taught in schools; how are narratives of nationhood to be taught
to the next generation?
Norman Cigar27 argues that the processes of narrative creation occurred
very quickly in the former Yugoslavia at the end of the 1980s. It was the
conscious strategy of the nationalists to create and recreate ancient myths of
nationhood, to rewrite and retell the glorious history of Serbia or of Croatia.
Cigar argues that, contrary to the widely accepted myths that so quickly came
to be regarded as common sense in the late 1980s, Islamic-Christian coexistence, not genocide against the Serbs, was the rule during the 500 years of
Ottoman presence.28 In the 1980s, the Serbian nationalists brought the myth
of heroic Serbian martyrdom to the fore; Serbia had been the victim of many
centuries of Islamic domination. The idea of a Greater Serbia, as the only way
for Serbs to avoid this continuing domination, had been a core idea of the
Serbian nationalists since the 19th century. Now, the Serbian nationalists were
on the rise, and an important part of their work was to imbue Serbs with a
25
26
27
28
Foster, 1999, p 2.
Foster, 1999.
Cigar, 1995.
Cigar, 1995, p 12.
particular narrative of their past. In 1986, the Serbian Academy of Arts and
Sciences, an organisation of Serbias leading intellectuals, produced the
Serbian memorandum, which argued that the Serbian people had been
denied their destiny of a Greater Serbia following the Second World War by
the communists; Greater Serbia was a democratic right, and was the only
political programme for freedom. The Serbian nationalists wove narratives
of ancient victories and defeats, of Ottoman, and therefore Turkish, Muslim,
domination.
In 1989, Milosevic went to Kosovo, and with much rhetoric concerning the
battle of Kosovo of 1389, 500 years earlier, he proclaimed the end of Kosovar
domination over the Serbs. Similarly, the nationalists focused on remembrance
of the pro-Nazi Croatian Ustasa atrocities during the Second World War. The
wars in the former Yugoslavia have often been presented in the Western media
as the result of age-old conflict in the Balkans. Yet, as Cigar shows, it was in
fact a conscious reconfiguration and repopularisation of the narratives of ageold conflict in the late 1980s by the nationalists that helped to energise the
people for the wars of conquest and ethnic cleansing. Timeless myth can be
changed very quickly by purposive political action. The project of imbuing
particular social memories with a sacred and eternal quality is central to the
political work of nationalists.
Crimes against humanity, ethnic cleansing and genocide are inevitably
preceded by this political work of creating and consolidating timeless
narratives. How can these genocidal and mythical social memories be replaced,
fought against, or superseded?
In this book I have been surveying a facet of the tentative emergence of
cosmopolitan law. There is emerging a body of law and a set of institutions
that is developing the ability to try those responsible for violations of
international humanitarian law, crimes against humanity, ethnic cleansing
and genocide. Such trials are important in themselves, in order to hold to
account those who commit such crimes, and to deter others from committing
them. But in order to do this, a trial has first to establish a true picture of the
events under investigation. This function of finding truth is a particularly
important one in the field of crimes against humanity. One of the central
purposes of the Nuremberg tribunals was, particularly within Germany, to
publicise the truth about what the Nazis had done;29 similarly the International
Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia (ICTY) aims to show clearly what
the nature of the genocide and the ethnic cleansing was. The Tadic judgment
is a long and closely argued document showing how the war started in Bosnia,
how the politics of the communities evolved, how ethnic cleansing and
genocide was possible, how it was carried out, and who was responsible. The
29 [At Nuremberg] Justice was served, but, above everything else, in a strange way, in a dark poetic way, it
was memory that was confronted and celebrated at Nuremberg. When hundreds and hundreds of witnesses
emerged to piece together a storya story that we all must remember, although our memory and our
mind and our soul are too small to comprehend it, to take it all in. Our sanity was at stake. If we remembered
everything, we would lose our minds. But then, if we dont remember everything, we also lose our minds.
Nuremberg, therefore, was the repository of testimony. Hundreds, thousands, hundreds of thousands of
documents were introduced in evidence in Nuremberg. Thus, it was an important and meaningful event.
For the first time, I think, it gave memory such an exposure. Now we know that if there is one word among
others that also symbolised the dark years of that tragedy that has no pertinent name, it is Memory. Elie
Wiesel, Inaugural Raoul Wallenberg Lecture: Cotler, 1995, pp 1516.
141
142
trial was about more than Tadic. It was about producing a version of the truth
of what happened; a version that claims authority because it is produced by
an impartial cosmopolitan court according to the rules, methods and traditions
of international law.
Legal processes of finding truth claim a particular authority since they have
the right to impose sanctions on those who are found guilty. Their decisions
are implemented by the use or threat of legitimated violence. The process
that we can see happening in the emergence of cosmopolitan law is also in
part a process of the development of a cosmopolitan social collective memory.
Courts receive particular and contradictory testimony; they act upon this
according to their own rules, and produce a single narrative. Cosmopolitan
courts receive nationally particularistic narratives as testimony that they
transform into an authoritative cosmopolitan social memory.
The Sawoniuk trial demonstrates this process very clearly. The narratives
that the witnesses brought to the court were all heavily influenced by their
own national social memories. The subject matter that was under investigation
by the court, the Holocaust and the Second World War, is centrally important
to the national myths of Israel, Belorus, Poland, Britain, Germany, the USSR
and Russia. All the nation states involved in the trial have different tellings of
the story of the war and the Holocaust, and these tellings are central to the
ways in which they produce and reproduce their national identities. To have
an identity is to have a story; a story that gives a sense of direction and a sense
of continuity. The way in which a nation involved in these events understands
its role in the Second World War and the Holocaust is one of the most crucial
determinants of its national identity. These stories were told and developed
for 56 years before the trial; and then the witnesses, imbued with their own
national versions of the big picture, came to court to give evidence on matters
intimately connected to central myths of their own nationhood.
When Ben-Zion Blustein tells his personal story, he is also telling the
founding myth of the state of Israel. His childhood was spent in an uneasy
coexistence with the majority community, which tolerated him but which was
always liable to intolerance; his family, and almost every Jew he knew, was
murdered by the invaders with the complicity of that majority community;
by a combination of great toughness, good luck, bravery, stubbornness, guile
and intelligence he managed to survive the genocide. After the genocide,
Blustein was one of those pioneers who built the homeland; a land where
Jews could be genuinely free, where they could make the desert bloom
Sawoniuk was born in poor but proud Poland. During his childhood it
was invaded first by the USSR; they closed down all private businesses and
shops; they caused Sawoniuk, and Poland, increased hardship and hunger;
and in place of food and prosperity they provided party men and propaganda.
The Germans invaded briefly in 1939, only to withdraw from that part of
Poland and allow the Russians to reoccupy. They invaded again after two
years of terrible poverty and terror under Stalinist rule. Poland was a plaything
in the hands of the Great Powers across its borders. Sawoniuk joined the police
in order to protect his town and his country from communist and Jewish
enemies who wanted to kill, exploit and enslave ordinary people like himself;
enemies who in fact killed his first wife in a raid on the police station.
Sawoniuks story was prevented from becoming central to the official collective
memory of Poland because of the military defeat of the Nazis; it was prevented
partly by the Nuremberg tribunals themselves, and also by the successor trials,
the latest of which was the one in London.
Belorus is a small nation that emerged out of the old USSR. It has a history
of occupation by Russia, Poland and Germany. During the last German
occupation there was a proud and heroic resistance that fought against the
brutal occupiers; Sawoniuk was a collaborator with those occupiers,
implementing their indiscriminate and bloody suppression of the popular
partisan movement. Fedor Zans uncle, aunt and cousins were murdered in a
raid in which Sawoniuk participated. Borisy, where the Belorussian witnesses
came from, was a partisan village. This spirit of Belorussian patriotism was
subsumed under Soviet domination until 1989, when the independent nation
re-emerged, one which was finding a voice of its own in the international
community.
Perhaps an additional nationalist mythology that impacted on the Sawoniuk
trial was a British one. The wood-panelled courtroom; the wigs of the court
officials; the impeccable manners of John Nutting and William Clegg; the
history of the Old Bailey: these all told of British fair play, understatedness
and reasonableness. English law allowed only charges of murder against the
common law; nothing continental or ideological like crimes against humanity
or genocide. Britain did not allow itself to be invaded during the war; and it
was central in the defeat of Nazi Germany. However, notwithstanding the
heroic role that it played, Britain is not a place for show trials
Another form of narrative presented to the court was that given by Chris
Browning; a narrative created by the norms and rules of academic
historiography. This tradition aims to take all the available evidence,
documents, eye witness testimony, trial transcripts, other historiography, and,
carefully, methodically and disinterestedly, to build up the best picture of the
truth that the evidence allows.
It was the task of the court to hear testimony that was necessarily informed
by these differing narratives, to process it and work on it according to its own
legal rules and norms, and to produce a judgment that was free of these
contradictory nationalist influences. It is as if a cosmopolitan court is a machine
whose inputs are national narratives, but whose output is a single
cosmopolitan one. The hardware of the machine is a set of developing
cosmopolitan institutions; the software is the developing body of cosmopolitan
law and the increasingly clear and precise body of rules, procedures and
precedents that are being produced by the institutions.
Crimes against humanity are exactly the kinds of events which national
social memories make, and of which they are made. In order for them to
occur in the first place, there are inevitably sophisticated and widely held
narratives that tell why the other group needs to be disposed of. The Jews
have, through the ages, been the cause of Germanys defeats and problems;
the Muslims in Bosnia have, through the ages, been collaborators with the
invaders against the Serbs; the Tutsi in Rwanda have been, through the ages,
the oppressors of the Hutu. This is one of the central reasons why international
courts are necessary. It is necessary to create institutions to deal with these
crimes that have some chance of raising themselves out of myths of nationhood
and ethnic superiority. When a group or a nation has survived such severe
disasters as genocide and ethnic cleansing, it weaves the narratives of these
disasters into its own tapestry of identity. When a court comes to address
143
144
30 Prosecutor v Kristic.
145
146
that was where Irving thought he had the greatest chance of success. The
expert witnesses were American, Dutch, English and German. Many factors,
therefore, contributed to the British court taking on some of the characteristics
of a supra-national one.
But we are left with a paradox. Is not legal discourse itself, and the narratives
that it produces, equally susceptible to deconstruction? In this book we have
already examined examples of the insensitivity and the arbitrariness of legal
discourse. In the Sawoniuk case much relevant evidence, including some
survivor testimony and some documents, was ruled inadmissible by the judge
who closed the ears of the jury to it. At the ICTY the judges, to an extent, selfconsciously create the rules as they go along. In the Irving case, Irving was
alone while Lipstadt had the backing of a large corporation, an extensive legal
team, five leading academics and their research assistants. The charge is that
the legal discourse, and the rules that govern trials, create only a different
method of producing narrative, not necessarily a better one.
Law is not outside or above society, even if its own rhetoric requires that it
appear to be so. Legal language, argues Peter Goodrich, like any other language
usage, is a social practice andits texts will necessarily bear the imprint of
such practice or organisational background. He goes on to say that we should
treat legal discourse as an accessible and answerable discourse, as a discourse
that is inevitably responsible for its place and role within the ethical, political
and sexual commitments of its times.33 Certainly the narratives produced by
cosmopolitan courts are not, in some absolute sense, the truth. But neither,
in fact, do they claim to be. They claim to be judgments.
There are many ways of producing truth: law, fiction, journalism, art,
memoir, historiography, religion, science, astrology. All have their own rules,
methods and norms, but also their own claims and purposes. If we understand
these different approaches to truth-finding as social processes, then we do
not have to judge that one is authentic and the others fake; but nor do we
have to judge that they are all equally valid. While they overlap, they all have
distinct objectives and ways of operating.
Reiko Tachibana makes use of Michel Foucaults concept of countermemory, which Foucault puts forward as an alternative to [t]he traditional
devices for constructing a comprehensive view of history and for retracing
the past as a patient and continuous development, a view that must be
systematically dismantled.34 Tachibana focuses on the work of post-war
German and Japanese authors who write counter-memory: who do not seek
to create all-embracing historical narratives, but who instead write de-centred
and incomplete accounts that emphasise the subjectivity and selective nature
of any record of events. Such writing, continues Tachibana, seeks a liberation
of the reader from a dogmatic perspective on, or blindness towards, the legacies
of the Second World War, aiming instead at provocation towards an active
participation in history.35 Tachibana is interested in the ways in which authors
such as Gnter Grass and e Kenzabur have produced work that seeks to
tell truths of histories of mass brutality in micro rather than macro voices.
Tachibana tells how, in a letter Grass wrote to e in 1995, he recollects the fact
33 Goodrich, 1987, p 2.
34 Foucault cited in Tachibana, 1998, p 1.
35 Tachibana, 1998, p 2.
that 20,000 deserters from Hitlers armies were executed during the war. They
were hanged from trees with boards around their necks reading I am a
coward. These men, for Grass, should be remembered as the truly courageous
heroes of Germany.36 e praised the Japanese writers who had been producing
counter-memory in the post-war period:
In the history of modern Japanese literature, the writers most sincere in their
awareness of a mission were the post-war school of writers who came onto the
literary scene deeply wounded by the catastrophe of war yet full of hope for a
rebirth. They tried with great pain to make up for the atrocities committed by
Japanese military forces in Asia, as well as to bridge the profound gaps that existed
not only between the developed nations of the West and Japan but also between
African and Latin American countries and Japan. Only by doing so did they think
that they could seek with some humility reconciliation with the rest of the world.37
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
Tachibana, 1998, p 6.
e Kenzabur in his Nobel Prize acceptance speech in Stockholm in 1994: quoted in Tachibana, 1998, p 250.
Prosecutor v Kristic.
Irving v Lipstadt judgment.
Levi, 1987.
Wiesel, 1981.
Lanzmann, 1985.
147
148
Lawrence Douglas43 is critical of Hannah Arendt44 for arguing that the main
business of the Eichmann trialthe weighing of charges brought against the
accused, the rendering of judgment and the meting out of due punishment
was in danger of being undermined by the courts wish to accomplish other
purposes as well, such as education, the writing of history and the creation of
a forum to host survivor testimony45 Douglas argues that Holocaust trials
have rightly been concerned with these broader issues as well as focusing on
the particular guilt or innocence of the accused. This dispute is apparently
about the weight that the two writers assign to the different functions of the
trials. But Arendt, in fact, certainly did appreciate the Eichmann trial as a
forum for setting out an authoritative narrative of the events of the final
solution: most of her book on the trial is taken up with a repeated presentation
of the evidence presented in Jerusalem of the detailed picture of the genocide
across Europe. And Douglas certainly does admit that the primary
responsibility of a criminal trial is to resolve questions of guilt in a procedurally
fair manner.46 For Arendt, it is the foundation of the fair procedure, designed
to resolve questions of guilt, upon which the value of the narrative produced
is based. For Douglas, the aim of doing justice to the defendant seems to be
parallel to the other aims, rather than one upon which the subsidiary functions
rest. The Eichmann trial, he says, even more explicitly than Nuremberg,
was staged to teach history and shape collective memory This mindfulness
of the past was meant, in turn, to support the Zionist politics of the present.47
The question becomes not whether it is a legitimate function for a trial to
have a role in shaping collective memory, but what kind of collective memory
it shapes. Arendts disquiet about the Eichmann trial was not about whether or
not it had a function in educating people about the Holocaust. Rather it was
about the tension that ran throughout the trial due to the courts constitution as
a hybrid or transitional form between national and cosmopolitan. She defends
Israels right to kidnap and try Eichmann because a trial based on more
cosmopolitan principles and institutions was not on the agenda. She criticises
the prosecutor, Gideon Hausner, and the Prime Minister, David Ben Gurion,
for trying to build the trial into the foundation of the nationalist collective
memory of the state of Israel. She praises the judges for standing against that
project and for limiting the court to the task of trying Adolf Eichmann. The
methods that cosmopolitan trials use to come to their judgments are ones that
seek to produce a narrative free from national particularity. But the Eichmann
trial was also a national trial, dealing with a subject matter that was central to
Israeli national identity. Arendt was not critical of the trials function of producing
authoritative narrative of the Holocaust; she was critical when Hausner tried
to use it to tell an Israeli nationalist narrative about the foundation of the state.
By 1987, the Israeli legal system was ready to subordinate entirely the
requirements of a fair trial to the requirements of restaging national drama.
John Demjanjuk was accused of being Ivan the Terrible, a gas chamber
operator at Treblinka. The trial turned into a drama of collective unburdening,
43
44
45
46
47
Douglas, 2001, p 2.
Arendt, 1994a.
This discussion of the Eichmann trial is indebted to Robert Fines conference paper: Fine, 2002b.
Douglas, 2001, p 2.
Douglas, 2001, p 3.
a public rehashing of both the history of the Holocaust and the horrific tales
of the survivors.48 But they had the wrong man. Demjanjuk was accused on
the basis of a questionable identity card49 that allegedly linked him to Sobibor;
it was Treblinka survivors, however, who identified him as Ivan on the basis
of photospread identification procedures in which his photograph was about
twice as large as the others and significantly clearer.50
Willem Wagenaar, a Dutch psychologist who had previously testified as
an expert witness on the subject of memory at 40 trials, gave evidence for the
defence, telling the court that the photospreads conducted in the Demjanjuk
case lacked any evidential value.51 Later he wrote that he knows of no other
case in which so many deviations from procedures internationally accepted
as desirable occurred.52 The court allowed spectators in the theatre where the
trial was held to shout abuse at the defence lawyers and the defendant.
Demjanjuk was convicted and sentenced to hang, but on appeal the conviction
was overturned. Evidence from the crumbling Eastern Bloc, which the US
Justice Departments Office of Special Investigations had known about at the
time of the trial, showed that Ivan the Terrible was, indeed, another man.
The production of authoritative narrative is a by-product of procedurally and
substantially fair trials; if the production of narrative is the central goal of a
trial and justice is subordinated to it, then there can be no authoritative
narrative.
There are two cosmopolitan tribunals, for Yugoslavia and Rwanda; the
International Criminal Court is facing substantial opposition from the United
States. In contrast, national legal systems are well developed across the world.
There can be no question of waiting until some notional point in the future at
which cosmopolitan courts become institutionally mature before proceeding
with the business of conducting cosmopolitan trials. In this book I have
discussed a number of examples of cosmopolitan trials being organised under
national legal systems: the cases of Irving, Sawoniuk, Eichmann and Demjanjuk.
Many other significant cosmopolitan cases53 have also been tried in national
courts. If Osama Bin Laden was captured, there would be no reason to oppose
in principle a trial in the United States for crimes committed in New York and
Washington DC. The key aspect of cosmopolitan trials is not the particular
institutional shape that they take but the fact that they happen and they happen
fairly, that they actualise the principles of cosmopolitan law. In the Eichmann
case, the court successfully resisted pressure to bend towards the needs of
Israeli nationalism; in the Demjanjuk case it did not. A supra-national
cosmopolitan court is necessary to try cases where national legal systems are
unable or unwilling to hold fair trials.
Whether actualised within the framework of a national or an international
court, cosmopolitan law has the particular advantage of containing within
149
150
Chapter Eight
Conclusion
Costas Douzinas tells how Spanish soldiers, in response to the Napoleonic
invasion, unfurled banners that read Down With Freedom. He suggests that
the oppressed may soon be ready to raise the slogan Down With Human
Rights.1 He understands the current supremacy of the rhetoric of universal
rights to signify their weakness as a means by which ordinary people can
seek to limit the power of state sovereignty For Douzinas, the concept of human
rights is at its strongest when it is understood as a contemporary form of
natural law, sharing a common tradition of resistance and dissent from
exploitation and degradation and a concern with a political and ethical utopia,
the epiphany of which will never occur but whose principle can stand in
judgment of the present law.2 He connects the triumph of human rights to
the post-Cold War idea of the end of history3 that posits pragmatism as the
only legitimate political framework and rejects ideology or utopia as nave,
dangerous and discredited. The end of human rights comes when they lose
their Utopian end.4
Human rights may be useful for fighting tyranny and for conceiving of a
better world, but for Douzinas those positives are greatly outweighed by the
negative and destructive forces that are mobilised under their banner. The postSecond World War codification and institutionalisation of human rights in
tribunals and charters is opposed by Douzinas to the self-organisation of those
whose lives have been blighted by oppression or exploitation. He proposes to
leave the UN and their diplomats to their standard setting and their lunches
and return to the state or the community, the only territory where human rights
are violated or protected.5 He follows Arendt in focusing on the plight of
refugees who are denied even the right to have rights by virtue of their expulsion
from their particular communities and the refusal of other communities to allow
them to join. He re-emphasises the centrality of state sovereignty as the centrally
important terrain for the battle over rights in a globalised world.
Douzinas does see clearly that the problem of exclusion is at the heart of
the concept and the history of national communities and of a polity based on
the rights of citizenship.6 Yet he is unwilling to embrace a project of anchoring
human rights, which do not have a foundation in the exclusion of non-citizens,
in supra-national institutions which have some power to enforce them. The
1
2
3
4
5
6
Douzinas, 2002.
Douzinas, 2000, p 380. Also: Human rights are the necessary and impossible claim of law to justice. (Also
from p 380.)
Fukuyama, 1992.
Douzinas, 2000, p 380.
Douzinas, 2000, p 145.
the modern subject reaches her humanity by acquiring political rights which guarantee her admission
to the universal human nature, by excluding from that status those who do not have such rights. It is the
law of the nation state which defines the alien as alien and the refugee as refugee. The alien is not a citizen.
She does not have rights because she is not part of the state and she is a lesser human being because she is
not a citizen To have citizens we must have aliens, to have a home or a home country others must not
share it Douzinas, 2000, p 142.
152
more that human right gains an institutional and worldly existence, the less
he likes it, since in that case it moves away from its utopian form as a measure
of the existing world and into the compromised terrain of actuality.
Just as Arendt told us that the Rights of Man was compromised from its
inception, due to its necessary realisation as the right of the citizen, so Douzinas
tells us that human rights were always compromised by precisely the same link,
that of rights with national sovereignty. The major powers, in the period of the
post-war codification of human rights, he tells us, unanimously agreed that
these rights could not be used to pierce the shield of national sovereignty. The
new body of human rights and humanitarian law, and the possibility of its
institutional actualisation, was a promise made by the victorious powers not to
replicate the crimes of the Nazis. It was a statement that they accepted that there
was at least a basic minimum of human community. They needed to make that
promise for purposes of legitimation, to draw a line under the old regime.Again,
after 1989, the major powers renewed their commitment to the rhetoric of human
rights in order to legitimate their victory over communism. Douzinas says:
The contradictory principles of human rights and national sovereignty,
schizophrenically both paramount in post-war international law, served two
separate agendas for the great powers: the need to legitimate the new order through
its commitment to rights, without exposing the victorious states to scrutiny and
criticism about their own flagrant violations Once again human rights were a
main way for underpinning the power of states.7
For Douzinas, the use to which the great powers put the concept of human
rights expresses the central truth of human rights. Their existence as cover for
the ambitions of the powerful carries more weight than any other; their
existence as an updated form of natural law against which we can measure
the actual world is important, but only to the extent that it is kept clean, out of
the compromised actuality of international law.
The thesis I have been arguing in this book is rather different. It is that the
great powers, for purposes of legitimation, have allowed cosmopolitan law
to emerge and have allowed it a certain institutional existence; they have
always attempted to keep control of it and prevent it from attaining an
independent existence; they will not always succeed in thus controlling it
because that to which they are forced to agree for purposes of legitimation is
precisely that which makes it possible for cosmopolitan law and its institutions
to gain a life of their own.
The concept of crimes against humanity is powerful. Its acceptance by the
major powers as a central part of international humanitarian law constitutes
an acceptance that such crimes are the business of humanity as a whole. It is
a recognition that there is no sovereign right to commit such crimes and that
the claim made by cosmopolitan law, that it has jurisdiction within all
sovereign states in relation to such crimes, is legitimate. The actuality of
international tribunals competent to prosecute crimes against humanity
underlines the validity and legitimacy of the concept.
The reason that cosmopolitan law cannot simply be wheeled out for
purposes of legitimation and then pushed back when it interferes with the
business of government is that it attains an independent existence from the
7
Conclusion
153
154
10 There must be a new international framework which will organise intervention independently of the
interests of the powerful states; the role of governments and governmental organisations such as NATO
should be minimised; non-governmental organisations should be actively involved in decision making;
the aims and methods of the intervention should be removed from the power games of presidents, prime
ministers and generals and focus on protecting individuals; the military should be in close contact with
local democratic organisations and observers and should aim to enable them to protect civilians and help
them overthrow the murderous regime; a clear set of guidelines should regulate the conduct of war and
minimise casualties on all sides; such a war should aim to rescue the victims and prevent putting more
people at risk and not to engage another government. Douzinas, 2000, pp 14041.
Conclusion
between the two. And the Kosovo intervention was not the Vietnam War,
was not the Gulf War, was not the Second World War: it was itself.
Milosevics claim that the campaign against the Kosovars was carried out
for the protection of the community in Kosovo is currently being tested in
court. It is a false claim; as is Douzinas apparent claim that the conflict was
more appropriately characterised as an equal fight between two fratricidal
nationalisms11 than as a campaign of ethnic cleansing by a Serbian state
machine which had previously carried out other such campaigns and which
had been brutally running Kosovo as a colony for 10 years.12 And NATOs
claim that the intervention was carried out for humanitarian reasons is in
part credible. Undoubtedly, it was also motivated by a number of interests;
an interest in stability; in preventing a huge refugee crisis spilling over borders
and destabilising neighbouring states; in thwarting Greater Serbian expansion;
in developing, testing and showing off military power and technology; in
diverting domestic electorates from domestic politics. NATOs strategy was
also influenced by interests; centrally, the interest in not seeing NATO body
bags arriving back home. In its decision to intervene, there was a component
of self-interest and a component of political will to prevent a repetition of
Bosnia and Srebrenica. It is necessary to judge each claim. Universals are
necessarily particularised.
This book has considered exactly that process which compromises universal
values: their actualisation in the world as it exists plunges them into arenas of
competing powers and interests that often overwhelm them. This book is not
a general defence of universal values but an effort to trace one set of their
particularisations. I have argued that in cosmopolitan criminal law it is possible
for universal values to find a worldly existence that is not wholly subverted
by power and interest.
It is not enough to set out a list of conditions for humanitarian intervention
or for humanitarian law which can never be met but which would, in an
imaginary world, allow us to support such interventions. It is necessary to
find ways of intervening to prevent genocide and ethnic cleansing in the world
as it exists and not in the world as we would like it to exist. It is necessary to
find ways of holding criminals like Milosevic to account in this world and not
in the next. It is also necessary to find ways of holding to account individuals
like Saddam and Sharon, Putin and Kissinger, Xiang Zemin and Pinochet.
But principled opposition to all existing possibilities is not a serious way to
relate to actual developments. We cannot stand aside from the world as it is
in order to keep ourselves and our ideas pure:
To recognise reason as the rose in the cross of the present and thereby to delight in
the presentthis rational insight is the reconciliation with actuality which
philosophy grants to those who have received the inner call to comprehend13
155
156
political support. I do not want to reheat the old brew of cynical critique, nor
do I want to weave utopian dreams of a world made safe by good policemen
and judges; I have focused on existing developments, and searched for the
rose in the cross of the present. There is a seed within the compromised present
that is as radical and exciting as the dreams of the utopians; there are also
trends, potentialities and events that are as dark and terrifying as the
nightmares of the cynics.
The strongest critique of the existing cosmopolitan courts is that the process
that decides who will be tried is entirely problematic. It is a critique not of the
universalist values of the process but of the aspect in which it fails to be universal.
The International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia (ICTY) is possible
because it does not threaten the interests of any of the great powers. There have
been no trials of Americans for the Vietnam War, no trials of Russians for
Chechnya, no trials of Chinese for Tibet. Is it possible for cosmopolitan courts
to have any genuine independence from the great powers?
At the moment, there is not much independence, but there is some. The
great powers, with their vetoes in the Security Council, are in control of where
and when ad hoc tribunals are set up, and under the International Criminal
Court (ICC) treaty they will be in control of where and when the ICC
prosecutors will be allowed to investigate. However, that control is never
absolute or guaranteed by the powers. Social institutions have emergent
properties; they are never absolutely closed. Bourgeois domination of social
life, in contrast to totalitarian domination, allows space and relative freedom
for social institutions to change, develop and live. Even if human rights and
due process were only rhetoric, the rhetoric itself would grant some space
and autonomy to the institutions that are based upon it. It is clear that the
judges and the prosecutors have a certain independence of action and decision.
The judges are not told how to find. The chief prosecutor showed herself able
to indict Milosevic at a moment during the Kosovo conflict when it might
have been inconvenient for NATO. As Otto Kirchheimer14 argues in relation
to Nuremberg, one method available to the great powers of reacting to
genocide is due process. The great powers allowed the ad hoc tribunals to
administer a small part of their power by prosecuting some of those responsible
for crimes against humanity. An event can be both a manifestation of power
and a legal trial at the same time. It may be a means of asserting power, but
not arbitrary power.
Can it be rightly argued that cosmopolitan law is nothing more than a
means for pushing Western values onto the rest of the world? It is particularly
hard to make this criticism stick when discussing crimes against humanity.
As far as I am aware, there is no one who argues that genocide is traditional
in a particular culture, and that therefore the imperialist West has no right to
march in and thrust its own values onto those for whom genocide is an ageold and legitimate way of life. If human rights mean anything, they mean
that there is universal agreement that a social formation, a group of people,
must not be allowed to murder entire populations. The argument that human
rights are just the values of the rich does not fare much better with less extreme
examples of threats than genocide, since human rights abuses are perpetrated
14 Kirchheimer, 1969.
Conclusion
by the powerful against the powerless. And the argument that human rights
abuses are traditional within particular cultures, and should therefore not be
criticised, leaves the voices for freedom within those cultures isolated and
unsupported. Such an argument is often, anyway, a misrepresentation of the
actual traditions of the culture in question. It may be true that human rights
are more likely to be enforced when they have powerful backers; it may also
be true that many atrocities have been committed in the name of human rights;
but these facts do not strip human rights of their legitimacy, nor do they show
that human rights cannot act as powerful mobilising principles for the
powerless.
Would people in imminent danger of genocide be better off relying on their
own self-organisation than on the international community and cosmopolitan
law? Would someone being mugged on the street be better off attempting to
defend themselves, or waiting for the police or a criminal trial for their
assailant? Certainly, there is a right to self-defence, and self-defence, if it is
possible, must be legitimate. Crimes, however, are committed against people
or groups who are unable to defend themselves, who are unable to stop the
crimes being committed. If self-defence were always possible then law would
be redundant. Conversely, if law were always effective, then self-defence
would rarely be needed. There is no necessary conflict between international
intervention from above and self-defence from below; a conflict is possible,
but not inevitable.
There was a conflict in Bosnia between outside help and self-defence. For
example, in Srebrenica the UN forces actively persuaded the Muslims to stay
in their homes, and brokered an agreement of which it was a condition that
the Muslims should disarm if they were to receive outside help. Similarly in
Kosovo, those at risk of genocide were forced to disarm and give up their
claims to statehood before international help was forthcoming. At the time of
the war in Bosnia, there was some disagreement between the Americans, who
leaned towards a policy of arming the Bosniaks so that they themselves would
not need to intervene, and the Europeans, who wanted to keep the arms
embargo in force as a price for their own help, thus disempowering the
Muslims in particular, since the Serb forces were already well armed. Thus, it
is not an argument that suggests that the international community should
refrain from intervention on behalf of those at risk from the greatest imaginable
crime, for fear that it might inhibit the efforts of the victims to defend
themselves; neither is it an argument that suggests that when self-defence
has been unsuccessful, the perpetrators of the crime should not be brought to
justice. This experience warns people at risk to be mistrustful of those who
suggest that they should sacrifice self-defence in order to encourage outside
help. And it means that in some situations, such as that in Bosnia, the
international community must be clearer about who is attacking whom and
who is at risk of genocide from whom.
A policy of neutrality between criminal and victim will not do; neither will
one that seeks to prevent unarmed victims from arming themselves in selfdefence. At the same time, it is true that self-defence against a perceived threat
of genocide will often take the form of nationalism, and that the most
dangerous, exclusive and ethnic nationalisms always present themselves as
being at a special and imminent risk of eradication from outside; aggression
is often presented as self-defence. These points do not bolster an argument
157
158
15 [The UK Foreign Secretary] had earlier announced that he would support the suspension of international
sanctions placed on Libya by the United Nations as soon as the [suspects] were handed over for trial.
Colonel Gaddafi would have sought assurancesthat sanctions would not be reimposed at a later date,
even if any testimony was offered during the trial suggesting a direct link between the bombing of Pan Am
Flight 103 and the Libyan regime. Wallis, 2001.
Conclusion
Against those who argue that international relations are only determined
by power, I have argued that processes of decision making that rely on the
authority and due process of law can also have influence.
Against those who argue that the only legitimate sovereign is the national
state, I have argued that crimes against humanity have been recognised as
the business of all human beings and therefore global institutions may develop
that have jurisdiction within all states to prosecute such crimes.
Against those who argue that individual criminal responsibility for these
crimes is just a legal fiction, I have argued that those who perpetrate crimes
against humanity have had alternatives and that, while their alternatives may
have been severely constrained, they still made free choices.
Against those who argue that cosmopolitan law is Utopian, I have shown
that in the ICTY and the ICTR, as well as in national courts, it is coming into
being.
Against those who argue that the practical difficulties of organising fair
trials for such crimes are insurmountable, I have presented evidence that fair
trials are indeed being held.
Against those who argue that cosmopolitanism cannot hope to pull people
away from their own sacred myths of nationhood, I have shown one
mechanism by which a cosmopolitan social memory is being forged.
In the introduction to this book I asked whether there were sparks and
flashes of cosmopolitanism in the darkness of totalitarianism; if they exist,
what do they illuminate, and what is their significance? I have argued that in
cosmopolitan criminal law, we can see coming into being one new way of
challenging totalitarian horror. Rather than a smooth and institutional process
of civilisation, I have argued that it is more appropriate to understand these
trials as shards of light in the darkness. We do not know how things will
develop; whether processes such as the Nuremberg tribunals, the ICTY and
the International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda will appear to history as the
beginning of the coming of age of a new form of human regulation, or as
compromised, isolated sparks in the darkness. But even if they do remain
nothing more than historically isolated examples of flawed cosmopolitanism,
their existence will still have been remarkable and profound, even if the sparks
were unable to ignite a more enduring flame.
159
Bibliography
Adorno, TW, Negative Dialectics, 1973, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul
Allot, P, Eunomia: New Order for a New World, 2001, Oxford: OUP
Anderson, B, Imagined Communities, 1995, London: Verso
Anderson, DL, Facing My LaiMoving Beyond the Massacre, 1998, Kansas: University
Press of Kansas
Archibugi, D and Held, D (eds), Cosmopolitan Democracy: An Agenda for a New World
Order, 1995, Cambridge: Polity
Arendt, H, Eichmann in Jerusalem: A Report on the Banality of Evil, 1994a, Harmondsworth:
Penguin
Arendt, H, Understanding and polities, in Essays in Understanding, 1994b, New York:
Harcourt Brace
Arendt, H, The Life of the Mind, 1978, New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich
Arendt, H, The Origins of Totalitarianism, 1975, San Diego: Harvest
Arendt, H and Jaspers, K, Correspondence 19261969, 1992, New York: Harcourt Brace
Jovanovich
Asch, RG, The Thirty Years War: The Holy Roman Empire and Europe, 16181648, 1997,
Basingstoke: Macmillan
Baldwin, J, Research on the criminal courts, in Kin, RD and Wincup, E (eds), Doing
Research on Crime and Justice, 2000, Oxford: OUP
Bass, GJ, Stay the Hand of Vengeance, 2000, Princeton: Princeton UP
Bassiouni, MC, Crimes against Humanity in International Criminal Law, 1999, The Hague:
Kluwer Law International
Bauman, Z, Postmodern Ethics, 1996, Oxford: Blackwell
Bauman, Z, Modernity and the Holocaust, 1993, Cambridge: Polity
Beck, U, What is Globalization?, 1999, Cambridge: Polity
Berk-Seligson, S, The Bilingual Courtroom, 1990, Chicago: Chicago UP
Bernard-Donals, M and Glejzer, R, Between Witness and Testimony: The Holocaust and the
Limits of Representation, 2001, Albany: State University of New York Press
Bilton, M and Sim, K, Four Hours in My Lai, 1992, London: Penguin
Bland, MA, An analysis of the United Nations international tribunal to adjudicate
war crimes committed in the former Yugoslavia: parallels, problems, prospects
(1994) 2(1) Indiana Journal of Global Studies 1
Bohman, J and Lutz-Bachmann, M (eds), Perpetual Peace: Essays on Kants Cosmopolitan
Ideal, 1997, Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press
Browning, C, Ordinary Men, 1993, New York: HarperCollins
Bullock, A, Hitler: A Study in Tyranny, 1983, Harmondsworth: Penguin
Burgess, RG, In the Field: An Introduction to Field Research, 1993, London: Routledge
Cargas, HJ, In Conversation with Elie Wiesel, 1976, New York: Paulist
Chalk, F, Redefining genocide, in Andreopoulos, GJ (ed), Genocide, 1994, Philadelphia:
University of Pennsylvania Press
Chandler, D, From Kosovo to Kabul, 2002, London: Pluto
162
Bibliography
Fuller, LL, The Morality of Law, 1969, New Haven: Yale UP
Gellner, E, Conditions of Liberty, 1994, London: Hamish Hamilton
Gellner, E, Nations and Nationalism, 1983, Oxford: Blackwell
Gerth, HH and Mills, CW (eds), Max WeberEssays in Sociology, 1991, London:
Routledge
Giddens, A, The Nation State and Violence, 1985, Cambridge: Polity
Ginsburgs, G and Kudriavtsev, VN (eds), The Nuremberg Trial and International Law,
1990, Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff
Goldhagen, DJ, Hitlers Willing Executioners, 1996, London: Little, Brown
Goldstone, RJ, For Humanity, 2000, New Haven: Yale UP
Goodrich, P, Legal Discourse, 1987, London: Macmillan
Gutman, R, A Witness to Genocide: The First Inside Account of the Horrors of Ethnic
Cleansing in Bosnia, 1993, Shaftesbury, Dorset: Element
Guttenplan, DD, The Holocaust on Trial, 2002, London: Granta
Habermas, J, The Postnational Constellation: Political Essays, 2001, Cambridge: Polity
Habermas, J, Historical consciousness and post-traditional identity, in The New
Conservatism, 1991, Cambridge: Polity
Habermas, J, The Theory of Communicative Action, Vol 2: Critique of Functionalist Reason,
1987, Cambridge: Polity
Havel, V, Anti-political polities, in Keane, J (ed), Civil Society and the State, 1993, London:
Verso
Hegel, GWF, Elements of the Philosophy of Right, Wood, AW (ed), Nisbet, HB (trans),
1991, Cambridge: CUP
Held, D, Law of states, law of peoples: three models of sovereignty (2002) 2 Legal
Theory 1
Held, D, Democracy and the Global Order, 1995, Cambridge: Polity
Higgins, R, Problems and Process: International Law and How We Use It, 1999, Oxford:
OUP
Hirsh, D, The trial of Andrei Sawoniuk: Holocaust testimony under cross-examination
(2001) 10(4) Social and Legal Studies 529
Hobsbawm, EJ, Nations and Nationalism since 1780: Programme, Myth, Reality, 1995,
Cambridge: CUP
Hoffman, S, Foreword, in Bull, H, The Anarchical Society, 2nd edn, 1995, Basingstoke:
Macmillan
Honig, JW and Both, N, Srebrenica: Record of a War Crime, 1996, Harmondsworth:
Penguin
Hoog, G and Steinmetz, A, International Conventions on Protection of Humanity and
Environment, 1993, Berlin: Walter de Gruyter
Hukanovic, R, The Tenth Circle of Hell, 1997, London: Little, Brown
Ignatieff, M, Human Rights as Politics and Idolatry, 2001, Princeton: Princeton UP
Irving, D, Hitlers War, 1977, 1st edn, New York: Viking; 2nd edn, 1991, London:
Macmillan
Jackson, RH, International Conference on Military Trials, 1949, Washington DC:
Department of State Publication 3080
Jaspers, K, The Question of German Guilt, 2000, Fordham: Fordham UP
163
164
Bibliography
Nussbaum, N, Kant and cosmopolitanism, in Bohman, J and Lutz-Bachmann, M (eds),
Perpetual Peace: Essays on Kants Cosmopolitan Ideal, 1997, Cambridge, Mass: MIT
Press
OShea, B, Crisis at Bihac: Bosnias Bloody Battlefield, 1998, Stroud, Gloucestershire: Sutton
Piccigallo, PR, The Japanese on Trial, 1979, Austin: University of Texas Press
Pictet, J, Development and Principles of International Humanitarian Law, 1985, Dordrecht:
Martinus Nijhoff
Pomorski, S, Conspiracy and criminal organization, in Ginsburgs, G and Kudriavtsev,
VN (eds), The Nuremberg Trial and International Law, 1990, Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff
Provost, R, International Human Rights and Humanitarian Law, 2002, Cambridge: CUP
Reshetov, A, International law and crimes against the laws and customs of war, in
Ginsburgs, G and Kudriavtsev, VN (eds), The Nuremberg Trial and International Law,
1990, Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff
Robertson, G, Crimes against Humanity, 1999, London: Penguin
Rosenberg, A and Silverman, E, The issue of the Holocaust as a unique event, in
Dobkowski, M and Wallimann, I (eds), Genocide in Our Time, 1992, Ann Arbor: Pierian
Press
Russell, B, War Crimes in Vietnam, 1967, London: Allen & Unwin
Salter, M, The visibility of the Holocaust: Franz Neumann and the Nuremberg trials,
in Fine, R and Turner, C (eds), Social Theory after the Holocaust, 2000, Liverpool:
Liverpool UP
Sartre, J-P, War Crimes in Vietnam, 1970, Nottingham: Bertrand Russell Peace Foundation
Scruton, R, A Dictionary of Political Thought, 1982, London: Macmillan
Shapiro, S (ed), Truth Prevails: Demolishing Holocaust Denial: The End of The Leuchter
Report, 1990, New York: Beate Klarsfeld Foundation and Holocaust Survivors &
Friends in Pursuit of Justice
Sheftel, Y, Show Trial: The Conspiracy to Convict John Demjanjuk as Ivan the Terrible,
1998, London: Gollancz
Smith, BF, Reaching Judgement at Nuremberg, 1977, London: Andr Deutsch
Stone, D, Holocaust testimony and the challenge to the philosophy of history, in
Fine, R and Turner, C (eds), Social Theory after the Holocaust, 2000, Liverpool: Liverpool
UP
Tachibana, R, Narrative as Counter-Memory, 1998, Albany: State University of New York
Press
Taylor, K, Irving in denial: the trial, in Taylor, K (ed), Holocaust Denial: The David
Irving Trial and International Revisionism, 2000, London: Searchlight Educational Trust
van Pelt, RJ and Dwork, D, Auschwitz, 1270 to the Present, 1996, New Haven: Yale UP
Vertovec, S and Cohen, R (eds), Conceiving Cosmopolitanism, 2002, Oxford: OUP
Vulliamy, E, Seasons in Hell: Understanding Bosnias War, 1994, London: Simon & Schuster
Wagenaar, W, Identifying Ivan: A Case Study in Legal Psychology, 1988, London: Harvester
Wheatsheaf
Wallis, R, Lockerbie: The Story and the Lessons, 2001, Westport, Connecticut: Praeger
Weisbord, RG, Genocide? Birth Control and the Black American, 1975, Westport,
Connecticut: Greenwood Press
165
166
Newspaper articles
Cesarini, D, At home with hatred (1999) The Sunday Times, 4 April
Dodd, V, Deportation, not trial, for Nazi war crimes suspect (2000) The Guardian, 4
January
Freedland, J, Court 73where history is on trial (2000) The Guardian, 5 February
Genocide rwandais: les quatre accusus reconnus coupables (2001) Le Monde, 8 June
Hamilton, A, Jurys journey to a world between past and present (1999) The Times, 2
April
Jones, T, Sawoniuk stood by as I begged for life (1998) The Times, 3 March
Keller, A (ed), (2002) Nos 1034, The Other Israel, July-August
Message to Mladic (1994) The Times, 2 November, p 15
Bibliography
Prime mission of UN in Bosnia; Letter (1994) The Times, 2 November, p 19
Traynor, I, War crimes trial finds Bosnian Serb guilty (1997) The Guardian, 8 May
Film
Lanzmann, C, Shoah, Les Films Aleph, Paris, 1985
Television programmes
A Bosnian betrayal, Dispatches, Channel 4, 1996
Newsnight, BBC2, 12 April 2000
The killing of Kosovo, Panorama, BBC1, 28 April 1999
Official publications
Hansard, House of Commons Debates, Vol 127, 8 February 1988, London: HMSO
Hetherington, T (Sir), Report of the War Crimes Inquiry, 16 June 1989, London: HMSO
167
Index
Abortion 51
Academics 131, 136
Admissibility of evidence xviiixix,
105, 129, 146
Adorno, Theodor 104
Afghanistan 154
Agency/structure36
Ahmici village 8283
AIDS research funding 51
Akashi, Yasushi 60, 61, 62
Albania 65
Albanians 64
Albright, Madeleine 65
Alic, Fikret 138n20
Allied powers 39, 145
Allot, Phil 3
Alterity 26
American native peoples, North
and South 4950
American Revolution 3
Anderson, Benedict 139
Antisemitism 30, 32, 137
Anti-war movement 4849
Aquinas, Saint Thomas 7
Arendt, Hannah
banality of evil 34, 98
Douglas on 148
Eichmann 33, 95, 148
final solution xxiv
genocide 44
Jews/citizenship 11
mass man 25, 26, 33
nation state 10
Nuremberg tribunals 47
The Origins of Totalitarianism 27
refugees 151
Rights of Man 3, 152
self-determination 12
totalitarianism xv, 27, 28
Armenians 43, 49, 50
Arusha tribunal xi, xix, 17, 22
Asia, South East xi
Atrocities 32, 36, 141, 147, 157
Augustine, Saint 7
Auschwitz 29, 38, 54, 131, 13233
Austin, John 19
Authority 28, 37, 38
Autonomy
ICTY 7071, 76
Kosovo 65
Baglay, Alexander 11920, 127
Baglay, Ivan 11819
Banality of evil 34, 54, 98
Banja Luka 69, 89
Barbie, Klaus 33n30, 35, 95, 149n53
Barlas, Mir 108, 11112
Barthes, Roland 140
Bass, Gary 44n28, 76
Bassiouni, Cherif 71, 73
Bauman, Zygmunt
bureaucracy 98
crimes against humanity 35n34
Eichmann 33, 34
final solution 26
genocide 25, 52, 69
genocide studies 55
Heidegger 47
industrialisation of death 2829
mass killing 98
Modernity and the Holocaust 24
Nazi doctors 31n20
rational choice 2426, 2930
responsibility xvi, 28
shooting of victims 32n23
totalitarianism 35
Beck, Ulrich xii
Belgium xi, 98
Belorus 101, 142, 143
Belorussian witnesses 11223, 127
Belzec camp 29
Ben Gurion, David 148
Berk-Seligson, Susan 102n23
Berlin Protocol 39n4
Bernays, Murray C 4041
Bey, Kemal 4344n28
Bey, Tevfik 4344n28
Biddle, Judge 42, 135
Bihac 57, 63
Bin Laden, Osama 149
170
identity 140
national myth 142
British National Party 131n3
Broad, Pery 133
Browning, Christopher
Irving trial 13435, 136, 143
Ordinary Men 3031
Sawoniuk trial 99, 10405
Brutality xviii, 29, 6670
See also Torture
Buisman, Caroline 93
Bullock, Alan 27n12
Bureaucracy
Bauman 98
distancing 53
final solution 25, 27
Germany 2526
Holocaust 26, 27, 29
moral response 25
Nazis 26, 27
rational choice 3031
Weber 26, 27
Burgess, Bob xxiii
Bush, George 22, 75
Busovaca 80
Bystanders xvi
See also Complicity
Calamay, Edmund 8n26
Calley, William L 48
Cambodia xi
Canada
soldiers 59
Zundel case 13334, 145
Canadian soldiers 59
Capitalism 21
Cassese, Antonio 71, 76
Catholic Church 8, 11415
Chalk, Frank 52
Channel 4 138n20
Charles I38
Charny, Israel W 52
Chechnya 156
Chelmno 29, 147
Chemiks 6263
Chilean protesters xi
China 156
Cigar, Norman 1401
Citizenship
cosmopolitanism 14
foreigners xii
human rights 15152
Jews 11
nation state 3
Index
nations 13940
Nazis 11
Rights of Man 3
See also Non-citizens
Civilian-killings 63, 6465, 82
Clarendon Club speech 136
Clegg, William
international conflict 71
Sawoniuk 84, 99, 102, 10709
Tadic 71
Yakimuk 11518
Clinton, Bill 75
Co-existence 81, 140
Cohen, Robin xii
Cold War
aftermath 101
cosmopolitanism 15, 48
end of history 151
Genocide Convention 14
international law 5
international relations xiii
Collective action 3132
Colonialism 154
Comfort women xi
Commission of experts, UN Security
Council 7273
Commission on Human Rights, UN 72
Community humanity 154
imagined 13940
international 57
Complicity 26, 36, 84
Concentration camps 2728n13, 2829,
6670
Conception 25
Conflict
armed 21
international 71, 83, 91
see also War
Conformity 26, 31, 36, 37
Conspiracy charge 4042
See also Jewish conspiracy myth
Convention for the Definition of
Aggression 4243
Co-operation, international 10
Cosmopolitan law xiixiii, xiv, xvii, 5,
15859
Allies 39
citizens/foreigners xii
emergent properties xv, 141, 142, 153
ethnic cleansing 79
Held 15
humanitarian intervention 154
ICTY 1, 93
international law xvxvi
Israeli state 23
legitimation 15253
mass killing 38
modernity 22
narratives 130, 139
national law 95, 128, 14950, 158
Nuremberg tribunals 22, 38
power regimes 7
realpolitik 15556
supra-national court 14950
totalitarianism xiixiii, xiv, 147
universality 11, 39, 155
utopian 159
Cosmopolitanism xv, 1314, 21n61, 79
citizenship 14
Cold War 15, 48
globalisation 21
Held 1516
Holocaust 94
ICTY 77
Kaldor 21
politics 154
self-interest 64
social life 153
social theory xii
totalitarianism 159
utopian 6, 16, 47
Counter-memory 14647
Courts
academics 136
criminal xxi, 98
judgments 94
legal discourse 146
narratives 139, 147
Crimes 1617, 4647
Crimes against humanity 93
Barbie 33n30
Bauman 35n34
Berlin Protocol 39n4
Bosnian Serbs 57
as criminal offence 93
dehumanisation 44
evidence xix
The Hague trials xi
Holocaust 2
international humanitarian law 152
national social memory 143
Nazis 44
Nuremberg tribunals 23, 38, 49n49
precedent 40
rape 72n57
responsibility xiv, xvi
Turkey 43
USA 96n7
171
172
Index
Eye-witness testimony xviiixix, 10506
Fair play, British 143
Falklands War 140
Fein, Helen 51, 5354, 55
Final solution
Arendt xxiv
Bauman 26
bureaucracy 25, 27
Domachevo 100, 114
Eichmann 34, 148
Evans 13536
Fine, Robert xii, 6, 4445, 46, 47
Finkelstein, Norman 55
Finkielkraut, Alain 33n30, 35, 95
First World War 10
Flinders, Arthur 131n3
FLN prisoners 38n2
Forced Labour, Abolition of 17n48
Foreigners xii
See also Non-citizens
Forsythe, David 70
Foster, Kevin 140
Foucault, Michel 46, 146
France
FLN prisoners 38n2
French resistance 95
French Revolution 3, 46
Thirty Years War 8
Frank, Hans 2728, 34
Freeman, Michael 5152
Frey, Gerhard 137
Fuller, Lon 46n36
Funke, Jaho 134, 137
Gaddafi, Muammar 158nl5
Garden culture 25
Gas chambers 13234
Gellner, Ernest 139
Geneva Convention 4n7, 17n48, 43n23
international conflict 83
Tadic 91
treatment of prisoners 43
Universal Declaration of Human
Rights 5n10
Geneva Protocol 43n23
Geneva Regulations on the Treatment
of Prisoners of War 43n23
Gnocidaire xvixvii, xviii, 55
Genocide xivxv, 4956, 93
Arendt 44
banality of evil 54
Bauman 25, 52, 69
bombing 5354
Bosnia 157
Cambodia xi
Destexhe 49, 50, 51
ICTY 141
intentionality 50, 56
Katz 4950
Kuper 5051, 54
lawyers/sociologists 5253
modernity 30
Nazis 12, 14, 49
Nuremberg trials xvixvii
responsibility 4445
Rwanda xi, xiv, 32n23, 62
sovereignty 4
Srebrenica 144
Turkey 4344n28, 49, 50
Vietnam War 489
War 5n9
See also Holocaust
Genocide Convention xvii, 17n48,
21, 38
Cold War 14
cosmopolitan law 49
Kuper 5051
USA 15
Genocide studies xvii, 38, 49, 5153,
5556
Geras, Norman 55
German Peoples Union 137
Germany
bureaucracy 2526
invasion of Russia 97
Jews 143
national myth 142
neo-Nazis 134, 137
post-Second World War 14647
responsibility 100
See also Nazis
Gertner, Bob 131n3
Giddens, Anthony 10
Globalisation xii, 21
Goebbels, Josef 40
Goldhagen, Daniel 32, 100
Goldstone, Richard 76, 84
Goodrich, Peter 146
Gorazde 57, 63
Grass, Gnter 14647
Gray, Charles 132
Griffiths, Detective Sergeant 12122
Grozdanic, Elvir 87
The Guardian 138n20
Guilt 31, 4112, 100, 142
Gulf War 58
Gush Shalom 2
173
174
atrocities 157
citizenship 15152
NATO 7576
natural law 151
non-citizens 153
Nuremberg trials 3
political will 64
self-determination 34
sovereignty xv, 3, 4, 151, 15253
Human rights law 5, 6, 130, 151
Human Rights Watch 65n27
Human shields 80, 82
Humane law 5
Humanism 4647
Humanitarian intervention 1213, 154
Humanitarian law 5n12
armed conflict 4
Blaskic 81
human rights law 5, 6
Nuremberg tribunals 4, 1920
violations 73
See also International humanitarian
law
Humanity/community 154
Humanity concept 44, 46, 151n6
Hurd, Douglas 62, 9596
Hussein, Saddam 155
Hutus 49, 143
HV (Army of the Republic of
Croatia) 80n1, 84
HVO (Army of Bosnian Croats) 80n1,
81, 8283, 84
Ibo 50
Icic, Hase 87
Idel, Shaya 107
Identification 90, 121, 123, 149
Identity 140, 142, 148, 153
Imperialism xiii, 92
Independent Television News
138n20
Individuals
accountability 155
international law 1
responsibility xvi, 16, 2324, 26, 3537
scapegoating 158
society 35
Institutions
emergent properties 7071, 156
legal system 14344
social 156
supra-national xiii, 152
Instrumental rationality xvi, 24,
3031, 36
Index
Intentionality 50, 56
International community 57
International Court of Justice 15
Article 38(1) of Statute 18
International Criminal Court 6, 7, 19
precedents 20
treaty xiii, 156
US opposition 17
International Criminal Tribunal for
Rwanda (ICTR) 20
International Criminal Tribunal
for the former Yugoslavia
(ICTY) xvii, xx, xxiixxiii, 156
autonomy 7071, 76
Blaskic case 7984
cosmopolitan law 1, 93
cosmopolitan narrative 130, 144
cosmopolitanism 77
criticisms 92
ethnic cleansing 141
genocide 141
The Hague xvii, 76
judges 80
justice xvii, 57
Kristic 61
precedents 20
prosecutors 71, 80
public gallery 77
rape charges 43n25
successes 9293
Tadic case 8491
tu quoque argument 46
UN Charter 7475
UN security staff 7678
International humanitarian law xiv, 17,
91, 130, 152
International law xii
Cold War 5
cosmopolitan law xvxvi
customary xiv, 18, 43, 91
formalism/dynamism 19, 20
individuals 1
legal positivism 910
Salisbury 17
Sawoniuk 96
social life 17
sovereignty 1
state 1112, 1819
International Military Tribunal for
the Far East 47n41
International relations xiii
International relations theory 13
Interpreters 102, 107
Intimidation of witnesses 102
175
176
Lauterpacht, Hersh 4
Lawyers 5253
Leader principle 28, 34, 36
League of Nations 10, 19
Declaration on Aggressive War 42
Legal discourse 146
Legal positivism 910
Legal processes 142, 147
Legal system
institutions 14344
myths of nationhood 13839
Legislative power 71
Lemkin, Raphal 50, 53
Lend-lease, Second World War 71
Lenin, VI 13
Leuchter, Fred 13334
Levi, Primo 103, 147
Libya 158
Lipstadt, Deborah xx, 94, 130, 145
Denying the Holocaust 131
Living Marxism 138n20
Lockerbie trial 158
Longerich, Peter 134, 138
Louis XVI 38
Loyalty 53
Lubatov, Rabbi of 106
Lublin camp 115
Luka camp 68
Lutz-Bachmann, Matthius xii
Lyotard, Jean-Franois 104
MacArthur, Douglas 47n41
McDonald, Trevor 136
Macedonia 65
Madagascar plan 13435
Majdanek camp 29
Major, John 75
Manjaca camp 68
Mao Zedong 50
Marcuse, Herbert 71n52
Markusen, Eric 52, 53, 54
Marshall, Penny 138n20
Mass graves 62, 106
Mass killing
Bauman 98
cosmopolitan law 38
genocide studies 51
Hamburg 3132
social factors 32
states 53
structure/agency 36
Mass man 25, 26, 33
May, Judge xviii
Media coverage 90, 138n20, 13940, 158
Index
Melaniuk 127
Memoir 6667
See also Holocaust memoirs
Memory collective xix, 142, 148
cosmopolitan 142
counter-memory 14647
Nuremberg tribunals 141n29
social xix, 140, 143
Wagenaar 149
Meron, Theodor 73
Millart, Kazic 99
Milosevic, Slobodan
arrest 92
Dayton 64
ethnic cleansing xviii
extradition 76
fall of regime 75
indictment 17, 76, 156
international disunity 65n27
Kosovo 65, 141, 155
NATO 156
trial xi, xvii, xviii, 7, 77
Tudjman 8384
UN 73
Mirsad, camp inmate 6869
Mladic, Ratko
Dutch soldiers 59
indictment 64, 76
NATO 70
Srebrenica 61, 92
UNPROFOR 63
Modernity
cosmopolitan law 22
dehumanisation 25
genocide 30
instrumental rationality xvi, 24
moral choice xvi
sovereignty 7, 20
Moral choice xvi, 24, 25, 37, 153
Morillon, General 58
Mosques 82
Murder 101, 143
Muslimovic, Senad 86, 87
Muslims
Bosnia 50, 57, 143
coexistence 81
disarming 59, 82
ethnic cleansing 72, 81
executed 62, 72
Kosovo 50
Omarska 87
rape of 72, 82
refugees 61
Serbs 57, 143
UN relief 59
witnesses 88
My Lai 32, 48
Myth
Croatia 14041
Jewish conspiracy 13132, 133
narrative 140, 150
nationalism 130, 138, 142
nationhood xix, 3839, 159
politics 141
Serbia 14041
Nadioci 82
Nagasaki 51
Narratives
cosmopolitan 130, 144
cosmopolitan law 130, 139
courts of law 139, 147
historiography 143
Irving case 14445
judgment 144
myth 140, 150
nationhood 140
Sawoniuk case 1423
testimony 143
witnesses xviiixix
Yugoslavia (former) 14041
Nation/identity 140, 142, 148
Nation state xv, 3, 10, 139, 153
National Alliance 137
National interest xii
National law/cosmopolitan law 95,
128, 14950, 158
National sovereignty xiv, 4, 7
Nationalism 138
competing 139
ethnic 10
mythology 130, 138, 140
racism 145
self-defence 15758
Serbian 14041
Sharon regime 12
Nationhood xix, 1380, 159
NATO (North Atlantic Treaty
Organisation)
human rights 7576
intervention 154
Karadzic 70
Kosovo 17, 57, 65, 66
Milosevic 156
Mladic 70
Serbs 60, 64, 65
Srebrenica 6061, 155
Yugoslavia (former) 75
177
178
Index
Power
abuses 15657
authority 28, 38
cosmopolitan law 7
ethics 2021
executive/legislators/judiciary 71
politics xiv, 13, 64
Pragmatism 151
Precedents xiv, 20, 40, 71
Press galleries of courts xxixxii
Prijedor 6670, 86
Prikepolje 72
Proboj 72
Property ownership 7
Prosecutors, ICTY 71, 80
Public galleries of courts xxixxii, 77
Punishment, collective 2
Pushkina, Gallina 11215
Puskar, Abdullah 67
Putin, V 155
R, Sakib 68
Racak village 6465
Racism historiography 132
Irving 13637
nationalism 145
patriotism 137
self-interest 56
USA 51
Rambouillet talks 65
Rampton, Richard 131, 134
Rape comfort women xi
crimes against humanity 72n57
ICTY 43n25
Muslim women 72, 82
Omarska 70
Serbs 61
Rapporteur, UN 72
Rational choice 2426, 2931, 3335, 53
Rationality
evil 25
Hegel 155, 156
instrumental xvi, 24, 3031, 36
Jews 30
value 36
Realpolitik 15556, 158
Reason:
See Rationality
Red Cross 68
Refugees 57, 6061, 65, 151
Regicide 38
Regime change 3839
Renssen, Raviv van 59
Renunciation of War as an Instrument of
National Policy 42
179
180
JNA 59
Kosovo 64
Muslims 57, 143
NATO 60, 64, 65
rape 61
Srebrenica 5961
Shahabuddeen, Judge 71
Sharon, Ariel 12, 155
Shlemko, death of 12021
Shoah xxiv, 51, 97, 98, 104
Shoah (Lanzmann) 25, 104, 147
Silverman, Evelyn 52
Simpson, Varnado 32
Sivac, Sefik 87
Sivci 88, 89, 91
Slavery, sexual 72n57
Slovaks 10
Slovenia 7172
Smith, Ron 131n3
Sobibor 29
Social life 17, 26, 153, 156
Social structures 7071, 79
Social theory xii
Society/individuals 35
Sociologists 5253
Somalia 6
Sovereignty xii, 5
borders 10
ethnic cleansing 4
genocide 4
Held 16
human rights xv, 3, 4, 151, 15253
international law 1
inter-state relationships 39
Lenin 13
liberal international 5
modernity 7, 20
national xiv
state xv, 1, 3, 7, 89, 20
territorial 8
USA 15
Yugoslavia (former) 13
Soviet Union:
See USSR
Spielberg, Steven 104
Srebnik, Simon 147
Srebrenica
Bosniak forces 5758
Canadian soldiers 59
Dutch base 61
Dutch soldiers 59
ethnic cleansing 63, 92
genocide 144
Kristic judgment 147
Index
Mass graves 62
Mladic 61, 92
NATO 6061, 155
Refugees 6061
safe area designation 58
Serbs 5758, 5961
UN 57, 157
UNHCR report 58
UNPROFOR 58, 59, 61
US State Department 6
Srpska, Republic of 88, 8990, 91, 92
Stalin, Joseph 25, 46, 50, 139
Stalinism 13, 154
State
estate 8
international law 1112, 1819
mass killing 53
sovereignty xv, 1, 3, 89, 20
See also Nation state
State practice 18
Statute of the International
Tribunal 74, 91
Article5 91
Article 210 75
Statute of the International Military
Tribunal Article 7 23
Article 8 23
Stepaniuk, Ivan 12021
Stewart, Bob 83
Stoics 15
Stone, Dan 104
Structure/agency 36
Successors, regime change 3839
Sudan 75
Supra-national institutions xiii,
14950, 153
Survivor testimony 51, 6870, 104
Sweden 8
Tachibana, Reiko 146
Tadic, Dusko
appeal 71
arrest 76
background 86
conviction 158
ICTY 8491
international conflict 71, 91
judgment 8586
Omarska 8487
plea 8485
SDS 86
trial xvii, xx, 70, 79, 8493, 14142
witnesses 8687
Tadic, Mira 85
Tauber, Henryk 133
Taumon 2
Taylor, Kate 131n3
Taylor, Maxwell 5051
Technology 25
Territoriality 8, 10, 11
Terrorist attacks xiii, 22, 158
Testimony
academics 131
Blustein 10312, 147
evidence 10304, 106, 107
eye-witness xviiixix, 10506
narratives 143
survivors 51, 6870, 104
witnesses 10405
Thirty Years War 8
Tibet 156
The Times 63, 115
TO (Bosnian Territorial Defence) 81
Tobacco sales 51
Tokyo tribunal xiv, 16, 1920, 47n41
Torture
Bosnia 72
complicity 36
Omarska 6670, 84
for recreation 6970
sexual 70, 86
Torture, Convention against 17n48
Totalitarianism xii, xv, 153
Arendt xv, 27, 28
Bauman 35
cosmopolitan law xiixiii, xiv, 147
cosmopolitanism 159
instrumental rationality 36
Neumann 27
social life 156
Traitors 145
Translation problems 102n23
See also Interpreters
Trapp, Wilhelm 31
Travnik 72
Treblinka 29, 14849
Trials xxi, 75, 79, 105n33
Tribunals, ad hoc xiv, 13, 7374
Yugoslavia and Rwanda xiii, 13, 19, 21,
55, 7374, 98
Trnopolje camp 84, 87, 138n20
Truman, Harry S 15
Truth 142, 146, 147
Tu quoque argument 4546, 75, 102
Tudjman, Franjo 75, 8384, 92, 158
Turkey 4344n28, 49, 50
Tutsis xiv, 49, 143
Tvrtko 82
181
182
Ukranians 10
United Nations
Bosnia 6263, 75
Commission on Human Rights 72
Convention on the Prevention
and Punishment of the
Crime of Genocide 4n7
ethnic cleansing 59, 62
General Assembly 16
The Hague institutions 77
human rights 3
ICTY xvii, 7678
Karadzic 73
Milosevic 73
Muslims 59
peacekeeping 63
Rapporteur 72
reforms 16
Rights Conventions 16
Rwanda 75
security staff 7678
Srebrenica 57, 157
United Nations Charter 7475
Article 2(4) 4n6, 11
Article 2(7) 4n6, 12
Article 32 12
Article 48(1) 73
United Nations High Commission
for Refugees (UNHCR) 58, 63
United Nations Protection Force
(UNPROFOR)
Blaskic 83
Bosnia 72
Mladic 63
Omarska prisoners 68
Rose 63
Srebrenica 58, 59, 61
United Nations Security Council ad hoc
tribunals 13
Article 24(1) 74
Bosnia 81
commission of experts 7273
Hague Tribunal 70
International Tribunals 7374
Resolutions
721 72
808 73
827 73
955 73
rules 6
sovereignty 12
veto powers xiv, 16, 156
war crimes 72
United States of America
American Revolution 3
Bosnia 157
crimes against humanity 96n7
genocide 4849
International Criminal Court 17
interventions 154
Justice Department xi(n1), 149
Kosovo 154
racism 51
Rwanda xiv
Secretary of State 65
sovereignty 15
State Department 6
terrorist attacks xiii, 22, 158
USSR 48
Vietnam War 156
Universal Declaration of Human
Rights 4, 5n10
Universality
cosmopolitan law 11, 39, 155
moral choice 153
USSR 48, 142
Ustasa atrocities 141
Utopian ideals 6, 16, 47, 159
Valenta, Anto 83
Value judgments 56
Value rationality 36
Van Pelt, Robert Jan 13233, 134, 136
Vance-Owen plan 82
Vashem, Yad 111
Venezuela 50
Versailles, Treaty of
Article 227 43
Article 228 43
Vertovec, Steven xii
Victims
Holocaust 13435
perpetrators 32n23, 5354, 69
shooting of 32n23
Victors justice xiii
Vietnam War 32, 4849, 154, 156
Vitez 80, 82
Vukovic, Zoran 72n57
Vulliamy, Ed 68, 138n20
Wagenaar, Willem 149
Wannsee conference 135
War 56, 7, 10
War crimes
conventions against 43n23
crimes against humanity 45, 43
deportations 96
UN Security Council 72
Yugoslavia
72
Index
War Crimes Act 96, 98, 101
War Crimes Unit 121
Warburton, Ann 72
Warsaw Ghetto uprising 30
Weber, Max 26, 27
Westphalia, Peace of 9
Westphalia, Treaty of 89, 13
Wiesel, Elie 49, 5152, 141n29, 147
Williams, Ian 138n20
Witnesses Belorussians 11223, 127
Blustein 106
intimidation 102
Muslims 88
narrative xviiixix
partisanship 127
political/national allegiances xviii,
158
Tadic 8687
testimony 10405
uncorroborated 90
World Trade Organisation 17n50
Xiang Zemin 155
Yakimuk, Fedora 11518, 127
183