Being, Univocity and Logical Syntax - Adrian Moore
Being, Univocity and Logical Syntax - Adrian Moore
Being, Univocity and Logical Syntax - Adrian Moore
136th session
volume cxv
issue no. i
draft paper
w w w. a r i s t o t e l i a n s o c i e t y. o r g . u k
memberships | latest issues | podcasts | virtual issues | the joint session
issue no. 1
volume cxv
2014 / 2015
adrian moore
university of oxford
m o n d a y, 6 o c t o b e r 2 0 1 4
17.30 - 19.15
contact
[email protected]
www.aristoteliansociety.org.uk
biography
Adrian Moore is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Oxford,
where he is also a Tutorial Fellow at St Hughs College. He was an
undergraduate at Cambridge and a graduate at Oxford, where he wrote
his doctorate under the supervision of Michael Dummett. He is one
of Bernard Williams literary executors. His publications include The
Infinite; Points of View; Noble in Reason, Infinite in Faculty: Themes and
Variations in Kants Moral and Religious Philosophy; and, most recently,
The Evolution of Modern Metaphysics: Making Sense of Things.
This years Presidential Address marks the official inauguration of Adrian
Moore as the 107th President of the Aristotelian Society.
editorial note
The following paper is a draft version that can only be cited or quoted with
the authors permission. The final paper will be published in Proceedings of
the Aristotelian Society, Issue No. 1, Volume CXV (2015). Please visit the
Societys website for subscription information: www.aristoteliansociety.
org.uk.
i.
THERE are three strikingly different groups of philosophers with
whom a title such as this, a title in which mention of being or existence
is conjoined with mention of the broadly semantic or the broadly grammatical, is liable to resonate especially loudly: analytic metaphysicians;
historians of medieval philosophy; and students of post-structuralism, or
more specifically students of the work of Deleuze. I shall say a little in connection with all three. But I shall say most in connection with the first and
third, whose concerns I hope to illuminate by discussing them in tandem
with one another.
Prima facie their concerns are quite different. Analytic metaphysicians
have long been exercised by questions about what exists. Do mathematical entities exist, for example?and if not, how come there are infinitely
many primes? Do holes exist?or is it just that, among the physical things
that exist, some are perforated or porous or some such? The more analytic metaphysicians have grappled with these questions, the more selfconscious they have become about what they are up to. There is accordingly a thriving branch of analytic metaphysics, sometimes referred to as
metametaphysics, whose aim is to clarify what is at stake in addressing
such questions. How far is it a matter of ascertaining the human-independent constitution of reality and how far a matter of settling on a way of
speaking, perhaps even settling on an interpretation of the verb exist?1
In the predicate calculus, assigning a domain to a formal language with an existential
quantifier is part of interpreting the language. But that is not what is meant here by settling on an interpretation of the verb exist. What is meant here would cut across that
purely formal exercise by sanctioning the use of the verb exist for only some of the things
that could be part of any such domain. (Indeed some philosophers, of whom Quine is the
most notable example, would take exception to it on precisely those grounds: see Quine
(1960, 49).)
1
adrian moore
draft paper
adrian moore
draft paper
the things that exist. But if this inventory had to include things that were
absolutely transcendent, then there would be an issue about what it would
mean even to say that such things exist, and that issue would lie squarely in the analytic metaphysicians territory. Even so, prima facie at least,
there are two broadly different sets of concerns here.
What animates Deleuzes concerns? All manner of things. But he has
two projects in particular that deserve special mention. One of these is to
extend Heideggers work on being. Heidegger drew a distinction between
being and the entities that have it.3 The entities that have it are all the
things that we can be given or all the things of which we can make sense;
their being is their very giveability or intelligibility (1962, 2 and p. 228/p.
183 in the original German).4 By drawing this distinction Heidegger enabled being itself to become a distinct focus of attention, a privilege which
he argued traditional metaphysics had prevented it from enjoying. Not
only that; he also contributed a great deal to our understanding of being.
Deleuze wants to enlarge that understanding. He thinks that Heidegger
has helped us towards a unified account of being. In particular, he thinks
that Heidegger has helped us towards an account of being which, though
it certainly acknowledges the many profound differences between entities,
and indeed the many profound differences between their ways of being,
does not cast any of them in the rle of the absolutely transcendent and
does not involve any Aristotelian polysemy. (Heidegger himself emphasized the magnitude of this task. At one point he put the pivotal question
as follows: Can there... be found any single unifying concept of being
in general that would justify calling these different ways of being ways
of being? (1982, p. 176, emphasis in original).5) Nevertheless Deleuze
thinks that Heideggers investigations are importantly incomplete. It is not
In Heidegger (1962) the translators register the former by using a capital B: see their
n. 1 on p. 19. I shall take the liberty of dropping the capitalization in all quotations from
this book and other books where the same practice is followed.
3
He says that entities include everything we talk about, everything we have in view,
everything towards which we comport ourselves in any way, (1962, p. 26/p. 6 in the
original German). But in drawing the distinction between being and entities he also says
that the being of entities is not itself an entity, (1962, p. 26/p. 6 in the original German). At the very end of this essay I shall say a little about the apparent tension between
these. (I have in mind the fact that precisely what seems to be required of us, for us to
be engaged in reflection of this sort, is that we talk about, have in view, or in some
way comport ourselves towards being. A similar problem afflicts the characterization of
entities that I ventured in the main text: all the things of which we can make sense. For
Heidegger is intent on making sense of being. Suffice to say, for now, that my references
to sense-making in the main text may all need to stand under some suitable tacit restriction; more specifically, they may all need to be understood in such a way as to exclude
certain sense-making that is characteristic of Heideggerian phenomenology.)
4
adrian moore
draft paper
Note: the Dostoevskian adage, though often attributed to Dostoevsky in the form cited,
does not in fact appear in that precise form anywhere in his corpus. The closest it comes
to doing so is in the mouth of Mitya Karamazov, in Dostoevsky (1982, Pt Four, Bk 11,
Ch. 4). There Karamazov says, Whats to become of man then? Without God and without a future life? Why, in that case, everything is allowed. You can do anything you like!
(p. 691).
7
adrian moore
draft paper
interpreted non-literally.8 But he did deny that it all does. That, for Duns
Scotus as for Deleuze, allows such talk too much free rein. It makes it
merely formulaic and means that we cannot have any real grasp of what
we are talking about when we indulge in it.9 In particular, this must apply
to our very talk of Gods being. Duns Scotus accordingly championed the
univocity of being (1987, pp. 19 20).10 Deleuze seeks to do likewise.
He considers two broad approaches to this problem, one that he finds
in Spinoza and one that he finds in Nietzsche. The first approach involves
viewing being as an entity in its own right. Any mention of the being of
any other entity is to be understood as a reference to this entity. I say any
mention of the being of any other entity. In fact, of course, any mention
of the being of being itself had better be included. Thus in Spinoza, whose
version of this approach Deleuze treats as more or less canonical, the rle
of being is assigned to an infinite substance in which everything that is, is;
and that includes this very substance, which is in itself (2002, Pt I, Def. 3,
Ax. 1, and Prop. 15).11 Spinoza works hard, on Deleuzes interpretation,
to keep all intimations of the absolute transcendence of this substance at
bay. He needs to work hard. The way in which he executes his project
This is important. It explains my continual use of the word absolute to qualify the
kind of transcendence that I am interested in. It is certainly possible for someone who
repudiates absolute transcendence to accede to a relative transcendence whereby we have
no way of making basic claims about a given entity in some of its aspects except by using
language that demands to be understood non-literally. Spinoza may be a case in point.
We shall be considering Spinozas non-absolutely-transcendent conception of God in due
course. But this conception did not, for instance, prevent Spinoza from both denying
that God loves anyone in any strict sense (2002, Pt V, Prop. 17, Corollary) and allowing
for a non-strict sense in which God does love us (2002, Pt V, Prop. 36, Corollary): the
difference is that Gods love, unlike love properly so-called, is not accompanied by the
idea of an external cause, (2002, Pt III, Definition of the Emotions, 6). Whether this
betokens relative transcendence or not depends partly on whether such claims about love
are suitably basic and partly on whether we have some other, literal way of expressing
what we mean when we say, God loves us. I shall not pursue that question here.
8
10
11
adrian moore
draft paper
means that this substance is radically different in kind from any other
entity. Its infinitude, if not its transcendence, is absolute (2002, Pt I, Def.
6)which means, among other things, that its infinitude is unique to it
(2002, Pt I, Props 14 and 15). But Spinoza achieves his goal, at least on
Deleuzes interpretation, by not only allowing his substance to express
itself through its attributes (notably through thought and extension, the
two of its attributes of which we are aware), but by allowing it to do so
in just the same sense as any other entitythat is, in just the same sense
as any of its modeseach of which likewise expresses the essence of this
substance through one of the substances attributes (2002, Pt I, Defs 3, 4,
and 5, and Pt II, Def. 1). Spinoza is not only able to say that his substance
is extended, for example. He is able to say that it is extended in just the
same sense in which Mount Everest is extended.12 There is no hint of absolute transcendence here.
It is a further question, however, whether there is complete univocity
of being, as Deleuze claims. The doctrine that any mention of the being
of a thing is to be understood as a reference to one particular entity is already to be found in Aristotle. All that is, Aristotle writes, is related
to one central point, (1941c, Bk IV, Ch. 2, 1003a32 33) and he goes on
to insist that any mention of the being of a thing is to be understood as a
reference to this point (1941c, Bk IV, Ch. 2, 1003b6 7). Yet for Aristotle, this doctrine, so far from showing that there is a single sense of being,
precisely corroborates his view that there are different senses of being. He
likens it to the doctrine that any mention of the healthiness of a thing is
to be understood as a reference to health, where that, he urges, betokens
different senses of healthiness: a healthy diet is a diet that is conducive to
health, a healthy complexion a complexion that is symptomatic of health,
a healthy person a person who enjoys health, and so on. The common
reference to health in each of these cases shows only that the differences of
sense are not brute ambiguities. They remain differences for all that. In a
distinction that Aristotle draws, the term healthy applies in all these cases
not kath hen, in virtue of one thing, but pros hen, with reference to one
thing. Similarly, on Aristotles view, in the case of the term being (1941c,
Bk IV, Ch. 2, 1003a32 ff.).13 So what makes Aristotle and Spinoza, who
both accept that any mention of the being of a thing is to be understood
as a reference to one particular entity, arrive at such different conclusions?
For Aristotle, it is pretty much axiomatic that certain differences between things are great enough, in themselves, to preclude a single sense of
being in application to those things. Spinoza, by contrastat least on Deleuzes reading of himis prepared to understand all differences between
12
13
adrian moore
draft paper
15
See Deleuze (1990a, Ch. XI). And cf. some of the metaphors on the very last page, p.
304, of Deleuze (1994).
16
17
See n. 4.
18
10
adrian moore
draft paper
This is the second of the two approaches that Deleuze considers, the
one that he finds in Nietzsche (2006, esp. Ch. 5, and more esp. 10
13, but see also 1994, pp. 35 42). There is a famous sentence on the
final page of Deleuzes Difference and Repetition where he summarizes his
thinking by saying, All that Spinozism needed to do for the univocal to
become an object of pure affirmation [i.e. affirmation that is affirmation
of itself] was to make substance turn around the modes, and then refers
to Nietzsches doctrine of eternal return which he interprets as providing
the wherewithal to do precisely that (1994, p. 304).19
It is the Nietzschean approach that Deleuze favours. But on what
grounds? On what grounds, for that matter, does he favour Spinozas original preparedness to understand all differences as constituting the character of being in defiance of Aristotles unpreparedness to do so? Nothing
that I have said so far in this essay appears to forestall a simple stand-off
between Spinoza and Aristotle; nor, perhaps, between Nietzsche and Spinoza.
It is natural to look for arguments here. And relevant arguments are
to be found.20 Nevertheless, they are not my primary concern in this essay.
My primary concern is not with how the univocity of being can be established. It is with something more basic. It is with how the univocity of
being can even be properly thought.21 I hope that some of what I have said
so far has helped in this respect. In the second section of this essay I want
to recapitulate this material, but in a different form, a form that relates it
back to some of the concerns of analytic metaphysiciansand indeed of
analytic philosophers more generally.22
ii.
I begin with a matter that might initially appear quite unrelated. Wittgenstein, in his Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, draws a distinction between
what he calls signs and what he calls symbols (1961, 3.31 and 3.32 ff.).
Signs are the written marks or noises that we use to communicate. Symbols are signs together with their logico-syntactic use. Logical syntax is
For Deleuzes interpretation of the doctrine of eternal return see Deleuze (2006, esp.
Ch. 2).
19
See again the material cited earlier in the main text: Deleuze (2006, esp. Ch. 5, and
1994, pp. 35 42).
20
Cf. Smith (2001, p. 168), where he quotes a remark that Deleuze himself made in a
seminar: [Univocity is] the strangest thought, the most difficult to think, if it has ever
been thought.
21
For a helpful discussion of the material in this section see (in addition to Smith (2001),
to which I have already made several references) de Beistegui (2004, pp. 225 241).
22
11
adrian moore
draft paper
Is this perhaps contestable? What if someone were to insist that the word had, in this
example, is itself correspondingly ambiguous, meaning either ate or played? So be it.
The point that I am making then merely requires a different example, say with the word
enjoyed in place of the word had. If someone were to deny that there is any example
that suits my purposes, then I suspect that they would simply be assuming the opposite
of what I am assumingthat difference of logical syntax is a straightforward difference
of kindin which case their denial would lie outside the ambit of my discussion.
24
12
adrian moore
draft paper
sentence prevents the word round from functioning as one of those two
nouns but not as the other.25 However, there is no equivalent transverse
ordering. There is no meaningful sentence in which the meaning of the
rest of the sentence prevents the word round from functioning as one of
those two nouns but still allows it to function either as the other noun or
as the adjective.26
Now, are there any ambiguities that do not involve any difference of
logico-syntactic use, ambiguities that are, so to speak, simple differences
of meaning? (In current terms such an ambiguity would involve one symbol, not just one sign.27) Ones first thought is that there surely are. But on
reflection the matter seems less clear. Exact sameness of logico-syntactic
use cuts very finely indeed.28 Very crudely speaking, if there were an ambiguity that involved no difference of logico-syntactic use, there would
have to be two things such that whatever could be meaningfully said of
one could be meaningfully said of the other. This is of course weaker than
Is this perhaps contestable? What if someone were to insist that the word round, in
this example, can function as either noun; it is just that, in one case, the sentence can
only be used to say something false? I would deny that. I think an utterance of I had a
complete series of holes yesterday and I had it toasted, would be meaningless, not false.
But I agree that this is contentious. The contentiousness will be significant later.
25
See n. 23. The discussion that ensues in the main text explains the final sentence in that
note.
27
For example, consider the ambiguity of the word billion, used in American English to
denote a thousand million and used in British English to denote a million million. That
may look like an ambiguity that does not involve a difference of logico-syntactic use.
But I think there is a good case for saying that, even in that case, a difference of logicosyntactic use is involved. For it seems to me that, in the sentence The number of stars
in the Andromeda nebula is less than a billion but more than a thousand million, the
meaning of the rest of the sentence prevents the word billion from functioning as the
American-English noun. Admittedly, this is a matter of contentionessentially the same
contention as was noted in n. 25but in this context that is as much as it needs to be.
For I claim only that it is not obvious that there are ambiguities that do not involve a
difference of logico-syntactic use.
28
13
adrian moore
draft paper
the requirement that there be two things such that whatever could be truly
said of one could be truly said of the other. Even so, it is still a strong requirement. And who knows but that there are deep reasons of philosophical principle why it could never be met? Considerable work in some or all
of metaphysics, philosophical logic, and philosophy of language would be
needed to settle the issue.
But here is a more tractable issue. Is it possible to expose an ambiguity
without exposing any difference of logico-syntactic use? This time there
seems little room for doubt. Clearly it is. For it is possible to show that a
word is ambiguous by producing a sentence involving the word, the rest
of whose meaning is presumed given, and then pointing out that a single
utterance of the sentence can be interpreted as true or as false depending
on how this particular word is construed. (For instance, imagine my saying, I had a round yesterday, on the morrow of a day on which I had a
slice of toast but did not so much as set foot on a golf course.) The word is
thereby shown to be ambiguous even though the question of whether any
difference of logico-syntactic use is involved is left open.
Let us now reconsider the univocity of being. And let us think of this
issue as an issue about whether the word being and its various cognates
are relevantly ambiguous.29 To be sure, this may not be as innocent as it
appears. It is not entirely obvious that the issue can be cast in this linguistic form without some loss. But even if it cannot, the new casting of the
issue will at the very least be of (highly pertinent) interest.
Anyone committed to the non-univocity of being would in these terms
be committed to an ambiguity in the word being. But the commitment
would, I claim, be unsustainable unless the ambiguity could be exposed
in a way other than that just described. The ambiguity would have to be,
and would have to be seen to be, an ambiguity involving a difference of
logico-syntactic use.
Why do I claim this? For two principal reasons. Or perhaps rather, for
one principal reason that can be broached in two ways. First, to think that
the word being is ambiguous is to think that some things are so different in kind from others that talk about the being of the former cannot
be understood in the same way as talk about the being of the latter. But
unless the cannot here means cannot, as far as the meaningfulness of the
talk is concerned as opposed to cannot, as far as the truth of the talk is
concerned, then it is just not clear why anyone would think such a thing.
Unless there are differences in kind between things that are so great that
I add relevantly because the word being itself functions as a non-count noun, as a
count noun, and as a present participle, but these ambiguities cut right across the issue of
the univocity of being. Henceforth, I shall take such a qualification for granted.
29
14
adrian moore
draft paper
the very business of characterizing some of these things requires a different logical syntax from the business of characterizing others, what is to
prevent the devising of vocabulary that can be truly applied to all of them?
And if nothing is to prevent this, then what is to prevent the devising of a
term that can be truly applied to whatever the word being can be truly
applied to, under each of its supposed interpretations? But given such a
term, and given the work that it has to do (notably, enabling us to refer to
the character of whatever exists), what is the rationale for thinking that
the word being is ambiguous in the first place? Why not accept that this
new term is just a synonym for being, with (as we now see) its single
generic meaning?30
This question leads naturally to the second way of broaching the
matter. Unless the ambiguity in the word being involved a difference of
logico-syntactic use, what rationale would there be for acknowledging
different senses of the word being as opposed to acknowledging differences among the entities to which the unambiguous word being can be
truly applied? This is an old idea, famously and marvellously captured
by Quine in 27 of his Word and Object. Quine is there concerned with
a somewhat different issue: whether the terms true and exist are ambiguous. But his response to the claim that they are is essentially the same
as the response that I am now recommending to the claim that being is
non-logico-syntactically ambiguous. Quine writes, specifically in connection with true:
There are philosophers who stoutly maintain that true said of logical
or mathematical laws and true said of weather predictions or suspects
confessions are two usages of an ambiguous word true... What mainly
baffles me is the stoutness of their maintenance. What can they possibly
count as evidence? Why not view true as unambiguous but very general,
and recognize the difference between true logical laws and true confessions as a difference between logical laws and confessions? (1960, p. 131)
These are rhetorical questions: but see Turner (2010) for discussion.
Cf. Deleuze (1990b, p. 185). This relates to the point that I made about McDaniel in
n. 6.
31
For the distinction between a who and a what see Heidegger (1962, p. 71/p. 45
in the original German). For the recognition of different kinds of being see Heidegger
32
15
adrian moore
draft paper
I add arguably for at least two reasons. First, it is not entirely uncontroversial that
has both these uses: for some famous dissent see Quine (1970, pp. 66 ff.); see also van
Inwagen (2002). Secondly, even if does have both these uses, it is not obvious that
they are logico-syntactically different uses: some material later in the main text bears on
this point.
34
I am taking for granted in this essay that if a sign is common to more than one symbol,
then it is ambiguous. For a fascinating argument to the contrary see Williams (1996). But
I wonder how deep the disagreement between Williams and me is: see e.g. Williams own
reference to the possibility of settling this matter by stipulation (1996, pp. 59 60), and
see David Wiggins reply to Williams in Wiggins (1996, 35 40).
35
36
16
adrian moore
draft paper
But this presents a challenge of its own: how to show that they do. The
sheer fact that the word is used in linguistic contexts which themselves differ in their logico-syntactic use is not decisive. Consider these two contexts:
That person is... and That tree is... These differ in their logico-syntactic
use. But it does not follow that the phrase exactly two metres in height,
which can be meaningfully inserted into both, is logico-syntactically ambiguous37not granted the assumption that difference of logico-syntactic
use is a difference of degree.38 Similarly, the fact that we can talk about the
being of that person and the being of that tree does not show that being is logico-syntactically ambiguous. It may be a necessary condition of
the non-univocity of being that being should have application to things
that are so different that there is no single logico-syntactic way of making
reference to all of them; but it is not a sufficient condition.
The difficulty is exacerbated by the following fact. The simple way of
exposing an ambiguity which we considered earliernamely, producing
a sentence involving the ambiguous word and pointing out that a single
utterance of it can be interpreted as true or as false, leaving open whether
the word is logico-syntactically ambiguoushas no counterpart when it
comes to showing that a word is logico-syntactically ambiguous. It is of no
avail to produce a sentence involving the logico-syntactically ambiguous
word and then to point out that a single utterance of it can be interpreted
as meaningful or as meaningless. Provided that interpreting an utterance
as meaningless is not a contradiction in terms, then this is something that
one can do to any utterance whatsoever. (One can always construe some
word in the utterance as occurring without either its standard meaning
or any other meaning.) It cuts no ice at all where ambiguity is concerned.
Given an utterance of the sentence, Her brooch is round, for example,
we can construe round as occurring without either its standard adjectival meaning or any other meaning. But that is quite irrelevant to the use
of round as a noun. Nothing about this sentence is relevant to the use
of round as a noun, given the meaning of the rest of the sentence. The
meaning of the rest of the sentence precisely precludes the use of round
as a noun here.39
I am not suggesting that there is no way of exposing a logico-syntactic
ambiguity. In the case of the word round, it is perfectly acceptable simThis is the material that I had in mind at the end of in n. 34: the sheer fact that can
occur alongside both individual variables and predicate variables, if it is a fact, is not decisive for the logico-syntactic ambiguity of . For pertinent discussion see Quine (1970,
Ch. 2); but note that Quines notion of grammar is considerably looser than the notion
of logico-syntactic use at work in this essay.
37
38
39
The considerations in this paragraph owe much to Wittgenstein (1961, 5.473 5.4733).
17
adrian moore
draft paper
ply to point out that the word has both a nominal use and an adjectival
use. Or, if there are certain theoretical purposes at hand for which further
detail is required, either in connection with the word round or in connection with the difference between nouns and adjectives, then we can go into
just such further detail. Even in cases where the difference of logico-syntactic use is less marked, as it would be in the case of the word being, and
where the tools for characterizing the difference are not ready to hand, as
they might not be in the case of the word being, we can do what we did
where the two uses of round as a noun were concerned: produce a sentence involving the ambiguous word (I had a round yesterday) together
with a context within which the sentence can be meaningfully embedded
under one interpretation but not under the other (... and I had it toasted).
The problem, however, is that this would be a way of exposing the ambiguity only to those who were already disposed to see it. If there were
genuine controversy about whether the word had more than one logicosyntactic use, as there is in the case of the word being, no such expedient
would help to settle the matter. The denier of logico-syntactic ambiguity
could simply deny that embedding the given sentence in the given context
resulted in any relevant meaninglessness40whilst also of course acknowledging the ever-present and uninteresting possibility noted in the previous
paragraph, that the word in question be construed as occurring without
any meaning whatsoever.
The advocate of the non-univocity of being may now appear to be in
trouble. I have been urging, on the one hand, that the relevant ambiguity
in being would have to be exposed as a logico-syntactic ambiguity while
suggesting, on the other hand, that there would be no exposing it as such
that did not essentially involve preaching to the converted. But actually
the trouble is just as great for an advocate of the univocity of being. In so
far as there is a kind of surd in what one of them wants to assert, there is a
kind of surd in what the other wants to deny. This is why there is an issue,
not merely concerning how the univocity of being can be established, but
concerning how it can even be properly thought. What can an advocate
of the univocity of being do, to impress his doctrine on himself as well as
on others, beyond blankly proclaiming that being has just one meaning?
Well, one option that he might take is to identify being as an entity in
its own right and to insist that any talk of the being of a thing is a reference to this entity. But as we saw in I, this would not be enough. An
Aristotelian would insist that any talk of the healthiness of a thing is a
reference to health, but would deny that healthiness has just one logicosyntactic use. The advocate of the univocity of being would need to insist
further that any talk of the being of a thing is not just a reference to this
40
18
adrian moore
draft paper
42
19
adrian moore
draft paper
place. Substance, the entity to which the noun substance refers, is now
thought of as turning, the activity to which the verb turn refers, around
the modes.
Furthermore, to think of difference as the character of being43 is to allow for the affirmation of the affirmation of difference to which I referred
in I. What I have in mind is this. The affirmation of difference is what enables being, univocal being, to be seen in the differences between things. It
is a making sense of difference, as the face of univocal being, where this is
as much differences making sense as it is differences being made sense of.
But if difference is the very character of being, then it is itself what enables
univocal being to be seen in the differences between things. It is its own
affirmation. The making sense of difference is simply things differing. The
affirmation of difference is the affirmation of the affirmation of difference.
What we have been witnessingat least, what we have been witnessing if Deleuzes reading of Nietzsche and Spinoza is correctis the power
of the Nietzschean verb over the Spinozist noun, or the power of Nietzschean differing over Spinozist substance. Spinozist substance is an entity
that differs from other entities in various ways. Nietzschean differing is
not an entity at all. It cannot be said to differ from other entities. It cannot
be said to differ from anything in the way in which entities differ from one
another. On the other hand, it can in a way be said to differ. For there is a
sense in which, in the differing of entities from one another, differing itself
is ever different. (If it were not, the differing of entities from one another
would stand to it in something like the relation of instantiation to a universal, and it would count as an entity after all.) But how can it be said to
differ if it cannot be said to differ from anything in the way in which entities differ from one another? One way is through a break with traditional
grammar: it can be said to differ from itself.44 And if differing is said to
differ from itself, this gives further fillip to the idea that the manifestation
of being through differing is itself a differing of sorts, a differing through
which being is manifest; in other words, that the affirmation of difference
is the affirmation of the affirmation of difference.
This is the line taken by Deleuze, in his exposition and defence of the
univocity of being. As I have tried to make clear, I have not myself been
concerned to defend the doctrine, still less to defend any of the associated
exegesis; I have been concerned with what it takes to think the doctrine.
A famous remark of Nietzsches is pertinent here: To impose upon becoming the character of beingthat is the supreme will to power, (1967, 617).
43
See Moore (2012, Ch. 7, 7) for a discussion of this sort of break with traditional
grammar, and Moore (2012, Concl., 3(b)) for application of the discussion to this very
case.
44
20
adrian moore
draft paper
But I have had a more particular aim too: to connect what it takes to think
the doctrine with issues that exercise analytic philosophers.
Not that this kind of linkage is likely to win any converts. Just the opposite in fact. It is likely to crystallize alternative ways of thinking in the
minds of analytic philosophers. Thus many analytic philosophers will recoil from unadorned talk of anythings differing from itself by demanding
some kind of relativization, such as that which allows for talk of Ellens
differing from herself by being both a child and an adult: a child then and
an adult now. Others will recoil no less from relativized talk of somethings
differing from itself and they will deny that there is strictly any identity between that girl and this woman.45 Again, many analytic philosophers will
insist that the word differing, as it occurs in the sentence Differing is not
an entity, functions as a singular term, andan entity being nothing but
what is picked out by a singular termthat the sentence is self-stultifying.
They are then liable to conclude that, if differing is anything at all, then it
is (perforce) an entity. Others will take a leaf out of each of Freges and the
early Wittgensteins books: they will acknowledge the self-stultification in
the sentence Differing is not an entity and they will conclude that there is
an insight here to which the sentence is gesturing but which cannot strictly
be expressed.46 Those who take this last option will of course be manifesting an element of conciliation. How close they will be to a convergence of
view with any champion of the univocity of being is going to depend in
part on how comfortable any champion of the univocity of being is with
this kind of appeal to the inexpressible: in some cases, I submit, very comfortable.47 But that is not the point. The point is not about convergence
of view. It is not even about rapprochement. The point is about dialogue.
Some analytic philosophers might eventually feel at home with these ways
of thinking; some might even eventually be persuaded by Deleuze to subscribe to the univocity of being. But first they have to be able to listen to
what he is saying.48
St Hughs College
Oxford ox2 6le
United Kingdom
[email protected]
45
See Frege (1997, esp. p. 184/p. 195 in the original German); and Wittgenstein (1961,
4.12 ff.).
46
I particularly have in mind Heidegger: see Heidegger (1999, 27 and 265). This relates back to the apparent tension in Heidegger to which I referred in n. 4. I believe that
the tension is real, and that Heideggers own appeal to the inexpressible serves a similar
function to that of the analytic philosophers envisaged in the main text.
47
I am very grateful to Denis McManus and Philip Turetzky for comments that helped
me to improve this essay.
48
21
adrian moore
draft paper
references
Aristotle, 1941a: Categories, trans. E.M. Edghill. In his The Basic Works
of Aristotle, ed. Richard McKeon, pp. 3 37. New York: Random
House.
1941b: Physics, trans. R.P. Hardie and R.K. Gaye. In his The Basic
Works of Aristotle, ed. Richard McKeon, pp. 213 394. New
York: Random House.
1941c: Metaphysics, trans. W.D. Ross. In his The Basic Works of Aristotle, ed. Richard McKeon, pp. 681 926. New York: Random
House.
Black, Max 1964. A Companion to Wittgensteins Tractatus. Ithaca:
Cornell University Press.
Carnap, Rudolf 1956: Empiricism, Semantics, and Ontology. Reprinted
as Appendix A in his Meaning and Necessity: A Study in Semantics
and Modal Logic, 2nd edn, pp. 205 221. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Chalmers, David J., Manley, David, and Wasserman, Ryan 2209. Metametaphysics: New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
de Beistegui, Miguel 2004. Truth and Genesis: Philosophy as Differential
Ontology. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Deleuze, Gilles 1990a. Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza, trans.
Martin Joughin. New York: Zone Books.
1990b. The Logic of Sense, trans. Mark Lester and Charles Stivale
and ed. Constantin V. Boundas. New York: Columbia University
Press.
1994. Difference and Repetition, trans. Paul Patton. New York:
Columbia University Press.
2005. Francis Bacon: The Logic of Sensation, trans. Daniel W. Smith.
London: Continuum.
2006. Nietzsche and Philosophy, trans. Hugh Tomlinson. London:
Continuum.
Descartes, Ren 1984. Meditations on First Philosophy. In The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, Vol. 2, trans. John Cottingham,
22
adrian moore
draft paper
23
adrian moore
draft paper
24
adrian moore
draft paper
van Inwagen, Peter 2009. Being, Existence, and Ontological Commitment. In David J. Chalmers, David Manley, and Ryan Wasserman
(eds), Metametaphysics: New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology, pp. 471 506. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Wiggins, David 1996. Replies. In Sabina Lovibond and S.G. Williams
(eds), Essays for David Wiggins: Identity, Truth and Value, pp. 219
284. Oxford: Blackwell.
Williams, Bernard 1978. Descartes: The Project of Pure Enquiry. Harmondsworth: Penguin.
2006. Tertullians Paradox. Reprinted in his Philosophy as a Humanistic Discipline, ed. A.W. Moore, pp. 3 21. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Williams, S.G. 1996. Ambiguity and Semantic Theory. In Sabina Lovibond and S.G. Williams (eds), Essays for David Wiggins: Identity,
Truth and Value, pp. 49 72. Oxford: Blackwell.
Williamson, Timothy 1987. Equivocation and Existence. In Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 88, pp. 109 122.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig 1961. Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, trans. D.F.
Pears and B.F. McGuiness. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
1969. The Blue Book. In his The Blue and Brown Books: Preliminary Studies for the Philosophical Investigations, 2nd edn, pp. 1
74. Oxford: Blackwell.
Wright, Crispin 1998. Why Frege Did Not Deserve his Granum Salis: A
Note on the Paradox of The Concept Horse and the Ascription
of Bedeutungen to Predicates. In Johannes L. Brandl and Peter
Sullivan (eds), New Essays on the Philosophy of Michael Dummett, a special issue of Grazer Philosophische Studien, 55, pp. 239
263.
25
w w w. a r i s t o t e l i a n s o c i e t y. o r g . u k