Virgins and Queers: Rehabilitating Heterosexuality?
Author(s): Celia Kitzinger and Sue Wilkinson
Source: Gender and Society, Vol. 8, No. 3, This Issue Is Devoted to: Sexual Identities/Sexual Communities (Sep., 1994), pp. 444-462 Published by: Sage Publications, Inc. Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/189715 . Accessed: 20/05/2014 14:58 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. . Sage Publications, Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Gender and Society. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 131.96.12.74 on Tue, 20 May 2014 14:58:03 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions VIRGINS AND QUEERS Rehabilitating Heterosexuality? CELIA KITZINGER SUE WILKINSON Loughborough University Radicalfeminism has critiqued heterosexuality both as a primary means through which people are constituted as women and as men, and as inherently oppressive for women. Two recent developments challenge this critique: the concept of "virgin" heterosexuality, aform of hetero- sexuality in which the performance of heterosexual sex, with or without sexual intercourse, is voluntarily chosen, and "queer" heterosexuality, a concept derived from postmodernist and queer theory, which does not only reinscribe, but also actively subverts and disrupts, oppressive categories of gender ("maleness" and "femaleness") and sexual orientation (e.g., the "gay"/ "straight" dichotomy). This article analyzes the attempts made in "virgin" and "queer" theory to rehabilitate heterosexuality, and finds both fundamentally flawed from a radical feminist perspective. It ends by considering why such rehabilitatory attempts are currently being made, and what they reveal about heterosexuality. Some years ago, one of us had a Portuguese neighbor who, about six months after the birth of her first child, burst into tears one day, and said, "I am not a real woman." Looking at her elegantly made-up face, her expensive dress and jewelry, and the child in her arms, it took some time to work out what she meant: since the birth of her child, she had not had sexual intercourse with her husband. "I am not a real woman" appeared to be a literal translation of a Portuguese phrase. It was one of the clearest demonstrations of the extent to which, at least in modem Western cultures, being a "real woman" means engaging in heterosexual sexual activity. Heterosexuality constitutes women as "real" women and men as "real" men (Wittig 1992). Those of us who are not heterosexual lose authenticity as members of our own sex and become "the third sex"-unsexed or degendered. Heterosexuality reinscribes male/female divisions by its very definition: "hetero" means other, different; "heterosexuality" means sexual involvement with one who is other, one who is different-man with woman, woman with man. The otherness of the "other" sex, the "differentness" of man from woman, is thereby immediately reinforced. There are, of course, many ways GENDER & SOCIETY, Vol. 8 No. 3, September 1994 444-463 ? 1994 Sociologists for Women in Society 444 This content downloaded from 131.96.12.74 on Tue, 20 May 2014 14:58:03 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Kitzinger, Wilkinson / PERSPECTIVES 445 in which human beings differ from each other: "heterosexuality" could mean sex between two people of different racial or ethnic backgrounds (regardless of their sex), or between two people of different religious or political persuasions, or between two people from different socioeconomic groups. Instead, "heterosexuality" marks what is seen, in some sense, as the funda- mental "difference"-the male/female division. From the beginning of first-wave feminism, feminists have produced searing critiques of heterosexuality, pointing in particular to the abuses associated with heterosexual sex (child sexual abuse, rape in marriage, clitoridectomy, wife-beating, sexual slavery), and to the compulsory nature of heterosexuality in a society that systematically inculcates and rewards heterosexuality while punishing and rendering lesbianism invisible. Such critiques, advanced from a range of different feminist perspectives (including liberal and socialist feminisms) have often left open the possibility of a (potentially) nonabusive and noncompulsory heterosexuality, freely chosen by women in egalitarian and personally rewarding relationships with men. The radical feminist critique of heterosexuality, by contrast, critiques even purportedly noncompulsory and nonabusive heterosexuality as reinscribing sex differences, and hence, inevitably, women ' subordination and men's power. This latter critique would seem to render heterosexuality political anathema for feminists. Many feminists, however, have expressed the belief that heterosexuality can be rescued and rehabilitated. Indeed, some of the very same theorists who propose the radical critique nonetheless retain the possibility of some kind of heterosexuality exempt from this analysis. In this article, we discuss and evaluate two such attempts, both (in their contemporary manifestations) originating from lesbian feminists. The first, "virgin heterosexuality" (a heterosexuality which does not reinscribe, but rather resists "maleness" and "femaleness") is advanced by Marilyn Frye, first at a speech given at the National Women's Studies Association annual conference in June 1990, published in off our backs later than same year (prompting a flood of letters in response), and subsequently revised as a chapter in her book, Willful Virgin (1992). The second rehabilitatory attempt, "queer heterosexuality" (a hetero- sexuality which not only does not reinscribe, but which actively subverts, "maleness and "femaleness") is an offshoot of postmodernist and queer theory, the former often identified with Judith Butler's enormously influential book, Gender Trouble (1990), the latter with activist groups such as Queer Nation and OutRage. In this article we discuss the attempts of "virgin" and "queer" theorists to rehabilitate heterosexuality. We analyze, from a radical feminist perspective, the problem associated with both rehabilitory attempts and consider their implications. This content downloaded from 131.96.12.74 on Tue, 20 May 2014 14:58:03 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 446 GENDER & SOCIETY / September 1994 VIRGIN HETEROSEXUALITY: RESISTING "SEX" In what seems an attempt to retain heterosexual women's allegiance to feminist politics, lesbian feminist Marilyn Frye offers the possibility of rehabilitating heterosexuality by reviving the historical meaning attached to the word "virgins." This term originally meant not women without experience of heterosexual intercourse but rather "females who are willing to engage in chosen connections with males, who are wild females, undomesticated females, thoroughly defiant of patriarchal female heterosexuality" (1992, 134). The question, then, is whether it is possible for a contemporary woman to become a "virgin" in this sense: to retain freedom of choice to take or to reject male lovers; to have many male lovers, but never be possessed or captured, to be "one-in-herself," unexploited, not in a man's control. Is it possible for women to enjoy sexual interactions which "are not sites where people with penises make themselves men and people with vaginas are made women" (Frye 1992, 134)? Frye's own answer to this question is somewhat ambiguous. Many women heard her original speech, and the article based on it, as an- swering "no," and as claiming lesbianism as an essential component of feminism. What she actually says is this: I think everything is against it, but it's not my call. I can hopefully imagine, but the counter-possible creation of such a reality is up to those who want to live it, if anyone does. (1992, 136; emphasis in original) In putting the burden of creating "heterosexual virginity" onto those women who wish to engage in sexual connection with men, while maintaining independence and autonomy, Frye poses an important challenge to hetero- sexual feminists, and her analysis has far-reaching implications for radical feminist theory. We raise three key concerns here: (1) the politics of penetra- tion; (2) the method of heterosexual virginity; and (3) the problem of power. First, in suggesting that sexual intercourse is compatible with virginity, Frye's analysis runs counter to a long-standing radical feminist political analysis of the politics of penile-vaginal penetration. It is precisely penile- vaginal penetration, rather than any other acts of heterosexual sex, which has been critiqued by those who point to the particular set of cultural and political meanings attached to penile penetration of women (being "had," "pos- sessed," "taken," "fucked"), meanings which are "oppressive, humiliating and destructive" (Duncker 1993, 148). The Leeds Revolutionary Feminist Group argued that: This content downloaded from 131.96.12.74 on Tue, 20 May 2014 14:58:03 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Kitzinger, Wilkinson / PERSPECTIVES 447 No act of penetration takes place in isolation. Each takes place in a system of relationships that is male supremacy. As no individual woman can be "liber- ated" under male supremacy, so no act of penetration can escape its function and its symbolic power. (1981,7) This analysis of penile penetration is independent of whether or not a particular woman happens to enjoy penile-vaginal penetration-although these two arguments have often been confused, as though the experience of "pleasure" in sexual intercourse somehow mitigates against its oppressive function. Although for some women, penetration "can feel like one more invasion... [and is] less pleasurable than other forms of sexual contact" (Gill and Walker 1993, 70), many others can, and do, take pleasure from the experience of penile-vaginal penetration and want to distinguish between "compulsory" or "abusive" penetration and "consensual" penetration: Penetration is not always rape. Having experienced penetration which was, I know the enormous difference between the feeling of fear, anxiety and disem- bodiment which come with forced sex, and the feeling of intimacy, oneness and sensuality which comes with intercourse which is not. (Rowland 1993,77) If there is safety, trust and love in the relationship, having the man's penis inside your vagina can signify as the ultimate in closeness.... I want to open to him. He wants to be wanted by me, and therefore welcomed inside me. He wants to give me something: I want to be given ... I get pleasure from feeling his penis inside my vagina because it means feeling him (with all that means about loving, accepting and respecting this particular person) inside me. (Hollway 1993) In a sociopolitical context in which many women have long been denied a right to sexual desires and pleasures, attempts to experience pleasure are represented by some feminists and sex radicals as a struggle against oppres- sion: expansion of the "possibilities, opportunities and permissions for pleasure" is part of a "necessary feminist strategy on sexual matters" (Vance 1992, xvi). Within radical feminist analyses, however, women's pleasure is not a "pure" erotic force welling up from within, but rather is seen as having been constructed under heteropatriarchy. Male power does not simply deny and repress women's sexuality; it also actively constructs it. It is neither the relative scarcity nor the impoverished quality of female heterosexual orgasm that concerns many radical feminists; rather, as Jeffreys (1990) argues, it is a serious problem that, despite the conditions of women's oppression, women can have orgasms in heterosexual sex. According to this analysis, heterosex- ual pleasure (and much lesbian and gay male sexual pleasure too) is based on the eroticizing of subordination (Dworkin 1987; Jeffreys 1990; Kitzinger 1994; MacKinnon 1987). Frye's analysis simply sidesteps this radical femi- nist critique. This content downloaded from 131.96.12.74 on Tue, 20 May 2014 14:58:03 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 448 GENDER & SOCIETY / September 1994 Moreover, some women are virgins in the modern sense of the term: women whose vaginas are untouched by any penis (Jo 1993). Accepting the analysis of penile-vaginal penetration as inherently oppressive (and/or sim- ply disliking the sensations it produces), other women-and, indeed, some men (e.g., Stoltenberg 1990)-either refuse heterosexual sex altogether, or choose heterosexual sex that does not include intercourse itself. This rebel- lion against the "coital imperative" (Jackson 1984, cited in Gavey 1993, 100) is difficult for women to achieve in the context of heterosexual relationships. "For several years of my life I was raped," says Amanda Sebestyen. "I was penetrated against my will because I didn't dare insist on any other kind of sex. And I still have a fight any time I start a sexual relationship with a man" (1982, 235). If heterosexual sexual intercourse is not seen as a key site of oppression, then women's valiant attempts to resist it are reduced to mere acts of personal preference. Of course, some women happen to dislike sexual intercourse (and prefer not to do it), whereas others happen to like it, but liking or disliking it is not the point here: personal preferences do not address the key question of the function of intercourse in maintaining women's op- pression. The refusal of coitus, whether or not accompanied by a more general refusal to engage in any form of sex with men, has long been a deliberate strategy of resistance for feminists (cf. Jeffreys 1985). The political impera- tives guiding these choices are obscured by Frye's reversion to an archaic definition of virgin. Second, it is not at all clear how "virginity" (in Frye's terms) can be accomplished, and what the methods are by which a woman can remain "free," "sexually and hence socially her own person" (Frye 1992, 133), when engaging in heterosexual sexual intercourse and otherwise connecting with men. If the refusal of penile-vaginal penetration is conceptualized as resis- tance to heteropatriarchal oppression, then women's "voluntary" engagement in coitus can be (and often is) characterized as compliance with, or capitula- tion to, the enemy-rather than as free choice (Leeds Revolutionary Feminist Group 1981). Despite her intentions, Rich's (1980) concept of "compulsory heterosexuality" has, paradoxically, been used to promote the notion of a "freely chosen," "consensual" heterosexuality (Brunet and Turcotte 1988,455), and to some extent Frye's concept of virgins is dependent on such a notion: that women have, as Warer says, "freedom of choice: to take [male] lovers or reject them" (1990, 15). The methods for living heterosexual feminist virginity could begin to "make sense" (according to Frye) if they included the following: refusal to attire or decorate the body in ways that signal female compliance with male-defined femininity; defense of women-only spaces; refusal of male protection and the institution of marriage (despite the eco- This content downloaded from 131.96.12.74 on Tue, 20 May 2014 14:58:03 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Kitzinger, Wilkinson / PERSPECTIVES 449 nomic pressures); and ardent passion for, and enduring friendships with, other virgins, including lesbians. Some women do attempt such "virginal" strategies: "woman-identified radical feminist" Robyn Rowland (1993), for example, takes responsibility for her choice to be heterosexual; is not married; lives apart from her male partner 75 percent of the time; and identifies her "crucially important" commitment to "putting women first." In parallel with these demands on women in heterosexual relationships, hetero- sexual feminist Naomi Volf (1993) has produced an account of what is needed from "the men we love" for successful feminist heterosexual relationships. Among the defining criteria of such men, she includes the following: they "understand that we are engaged in a cross-cultural relationship ... and that they know little of our world"; they "don't hold a baby as if it's a still squirm- ing, unidentifiable catch from the sea... don't tell women what to feel about sexism ... are willing to read the books we love ... undertake half the care and cost of contraception ... make a leap of imagination to believe in the female experience ... don't drive without gender glasses on ... know that just because sex can be irrational doesn't mean we're insane." Such models for living positive feminist heterosexual virginity are de- pendent on a great deal of unacknowledged social privilege. Many women are trapped in marriages with men for whom such demands are irrelevant and many others have marriage and/or other heterosexual partnerships denied them for reasons of racism, class oppression, or disability. Others are forcibly separated from their male partners (and children) by war, famine, political intrigue, scarcity of work, or economic necessity. The woman who, forced by her own poverty or the exigencies of her country's national debt, leaves her family to work as a domestic servant or as a migrant coffee picker may well be apart from her husband for 75 percent (or more) of the time, but where is her opportunity to "invent and embody modes of living positive virginity"? Third, Frye's analysis fails to centrally address the radical feminist critique of heterosexuality that she herself advances: the function of heterosexuality in constructing us as "men" and as "women," and hence as oppressor and op- pressed. Sexuality, as Catherine MacKinnon says, "is a social construct, gendered to the ground" (1987, 149). Heterosexuality is a key mechanism through which male dominance is achieved. Male dominance is "not an artificial overlay" upon heterosexuality that can somehow be stripped away to leave an uncorrupted, pure, sexual interaction; rather it is intrinsic to heterosex itself: It has often been asserted that [sissy] men have too much in common with women or either of them to feel much excitement. There is no gap for the spark to jump. You get two sweet, nice people together, and nobody's going to do anything except with the permission of the other, assuming that anyone has the This content downloaded from 131.96.12.74 on Tue, 20 May 2014 14:58:03 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 450 GENDER & SOCIETY / September 1994 "balls" to bring the subject up.... Opposites attract... women want real men, and that's all there is to it. (Hunter 1993, 159) More than this, there is a strong link between heterosexuality and masculinity, such that "heterosexuality is largely conceptualized unthinkingly as a rela- tionship between women and masculine males" (Hunter 1993, 163)-that is, between subordinated and dominator. Many feminist theorists have analyzed the extent to which sex is eroticized power difference and have critiqued the phenomenon that Jeffreys (1990) labels "heterosexual desire"-by which she means not just desire between women and men, but the eroticizing of dominance and submission. The problem for feminists is not just man's eroticizing of power, but also women's eroticizing of powerlessness. Erotic excitement, according to this analysis, is modeled on a heterosexual paradigm constructed around power difference. When (as in lesbian or gay male sex) the sex (as in "gender") hierarchy is missing, other social stratifications (e.g., race, class) or specially constructed power differentials (as in sadomasochism) can sometimes be eroticized (Jeffreys 1993). As we have noted, critiques of heterosexual sexual activity often proceed as though sexual pleasure-or lack of it-was the sole criterion on which a feminist assessment could be made; yet, for many women, the problem is their serious political concern about how sexual pleasure is produced, and the form that such pleasure takes. Segal (1983) points out that "it does not feel like personal liberation to be able to orgasm to intensely masochistic fantasies"; and Bartky's decision "not to pursue men whose sadism excited me" (1993, 42) was made at the cost of "the powerful erotic charge" found in such relationships. Jeffreys recommends that women seek to shut down those sexual responses which eroticize subordination: 'The question we have to ask ourselves is whether we want our freedom or whether we want to retain heterosexual desire" (1990, 134). Frye's acceptance of heterosexual desire and activity as unproblematic parts of the virgin's repertoire represents a failure to engage with this radical feminist critique. In sum, then, although Frye's portrayal of virgin heterosexuality may seem attractive-particularly in its links with feminist traditions of defying patri- archal conventions and reclaiming or investing feminist alternatives-it is not convincing, either as a strategy for resisting the traditional inscription of "woman," or as a means of rehabilitating heterosexuality. Frye's analysis overlooks heterosexual sexual intercourse as a key site of women's oppres- sion and resistance; is unclear as to the methods by which virgin heterosexu- ality is to be accomplished under heteropatriarchy; and, most important from the radical feminist perspective, does not address the central role of heterosex in reinscribing "sex" as power relations. This content downloaded from 131.96.12.74 on Tue, 20 May 2014 14:58:03 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Kitzinger, Wilkinson / PERSPECTIVES 451 QUEER HETEROSEXUALITY: SUBVERTING "SEX" In recent years the word "queer," long used as a term of insult and self- loathing, has been reclaimed by lesbians, gay men, bisexuals, transvestites, and transsexuals as a proud declaration of nonconformist sexualities: "We're here, we're queer; get used to it!" In place of the medicopsychiatric "homo- sexual," or the euphemistic and self-justificatory "gay," the word "queer" is seen as confrontational and as underscoring the fact that we are "queer" ("deviant" and "abnormal") to a world in which normality is defined in rigid and suffocating terms: The insistence on queer-a term defined against "normal" and generated precisely in the context of terror-has the effect of pointing out a wide field of normalization, rather than simple tolerance, as the site of violence. (Warner 1990) The notion of "queer heterosexuality" has come to refer to those people who, while doing what is conventionally defined as "heterosexuality," nonetheless do so in ways which are transgressive of "normality." Just as Marilyn Frye and others have expanded the notion of "virgin" to include a particular way of doing heterosex, so the queer theorists have expanded the notion of "queer" to include, among other things, a particular way of doing heterosex. Like "virgin" theorists, "queer" theorists start from the position that "straight sex" reinscribes its participants as "man" and "woman." Queer the- ory differs from virgin theory in that, whereas the concept of "virgin" hetero- sexuality denotes the doing of heterosex while resisting being "sexed," "queer" heterosexuality denoted the doing of (what used to be called) heterosex while actively subverting its constructive function. Rather than simply resisting the equation between sex (as activity) and sex (as gender), queer theory explicitly acknowledges this link, and by deliberately drawing attention to and playing with it, attempts to denaturalize and hence subvert the equation. "Fucking with gender" implies the possibility of doing sex in such a way that it not merely resists, but actively disrupts normative defini- tions of "sex" and "gender." Influenced by, and in many ways an offshoot of postmodernism, it is nonetheless possible to critique queer theory without engaging in an attack on the whole of the postmodernist and poststructuralist movements, some aspects of which (especially the notion of disciplinary power) have been found useful by many feminists, ourselves included (see also Weedon 1987; Diamond and Quinby 1988). In this section of the article, our focus is on queer theory (rather than on postmodernism) and, more narrowly still, on that This content downloaded from 131.96.12.74 on Tue, 20 May 2014 14:58:03 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 452 GENDER & SOCIETY / September 1994 aspect of queer theory that relates to heterosexuality. In general, queer theory aims to deconstruct and confound normative categories of gender and sexu- ality, exposing their fundamental unnaturalness. There are no "true" gender identities or natural sexes: rather maleness and femaleness are "perform- ances" or "simulations." Maleness and femaleness are performative in the sense that the essence or identity that they otherwise purport to express are fabrications manufactured and sustained through corporal signs and other discursive means ... an illusion discursively maintained for the purposes of the regulation of sexuality within the obligatory frame of repro- ductive heterosexuality. (Butler 1990, 136) "Simulation" means not a replica of something that actually exists, but an identical copy for which there has never been an original. Disneyland, for example, has been described as a simulation whose function in proclaiming its status as "unreal" precisely to make the rest of the United States look "real" (Baudrillard 1988). Gender, too, is conceived as an exact copy of some- thing that never really existed in the first place: there is no "real," underlying maleness or femaleness on which we base our performances. The postmoder body "is the body of the mythological Trickster, the shape-shifter or indeter- minate sex and changeable gender ... who continually alters her/his body, creates and recreates a personality ... and floats across time from period to period, place to place" (Bordo 1993, 144, paraphrasing Smith-Rosenberg 1985). This is, in the language of postmodernism, indicative of an identity in flux, a protean fantasy, an intricate textual dance, a narrative heteroglossia, a choreography of multiplicity, and a celebration of a transcendent polyvocal self at a time when "the rigid demarcations of the clear and distinct Cartesian universe are crumbling, and the notion of the unified 'subject' is no longer tenable" (Bordo 1993, 144). In this theory of fluctuating and continually altering selves, sex is an area "of fashion and style rather than biology and identity" (Chapkis 1986, 138). "Being" man or woman is conceptualized not as core identity, but rather as "a put-on, a sex toy" (Schwichtenberg 1993, 135) or as a "temporary positioning" (Gergen 1993, 64). In conceptualizing what have previously been seen as "core" identities (man/woman; hetero/homosexual) as no more than fluctuating fashions or performances, queer theory, like postmodernism more generally, expresses the hope for future abolition of such divisive patriarchal binarisms, ushering in the age of the post-lesbian and-of course-the post-heterosexual. In this imagined world ("this world of my fantasy," Gergen 1993, 64), man does not exist, nor woman either; hence, the concepts of heterosexuality, homosexu- ality and bisexuality are literally unthinkable. The sex of the person you have sex with is not only irrelevant in terms of social meaning and identity: it is This content downloaded from 131.96.12.74 on Tue, 20 May 2014 14:58:03 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Kitzinger, Wilkinson / PERSPECTIVES 453 also unspecifiable, because "sex-as-gender" is no longer a meaningful con- cept. Many feminists (Gergen 1993; Ruby 1993) and sex radicals (Sprinkle 1992) are attracted by the deconstructive power of queer theory, which vividly uncouples the inscription of gender through heterosexuality; how- ever, this vision of the future uncoupling of "heterosex" and "gender" is not, of course, specific to postmodernist and queer theory: it has a long (though rarely acknowledged) history within radical feminism (e.g., Radicalesbians 1970; Piercy 1979), as well as in the early writings of both the British and the North American gay liberation movements. What is distinctive about postmodern and queer (as opposed to radical feminist) theory is the strategy envisioned for getting "there" from "here." The notion of "queer heterosexuality" is one component of the postmod- ern strategy for transition into the brave new world of the future. Such a world would have no use for the concept of "queer heterosexuality" because there would be no such thing as heterosexuality, no men and women to perform it, nor any heteronormativity against which to be positioned as "queer." In the interim, queer theorists give "queer heterosexuals" a walk-on role. "There are times," says queer theorist Cherry Smyth (1992), "when queers may choose to call themselves heterosexual, bisexual, lesbian or gay, or none of the above." According to Schwichtenberg, one could "come out" and partici- pate in a range of identities "such as a lesbian heterosexual, a heterosexual lesbian, a male lesbian, a female gay man, or even a feminist sex-radical" (1993, 141). Another writer offers this list: 'There are straight queers, biqueers, tranny queers, lez queers, fag queers, SM queers, fisting queers" (Anonymous leaflet 1991, cited in Smyth 1992, 17). Although queer hetero- sexuality is rarely explored in any detail (and still less are queer heterosexuals themselves queuing up to describe their experiences), the notion of the "queer heterosexual" has become established in queer theory. It has gained (a limited) currency not, apparently, because many people are convinced of either its possibility or its desirability, still less because it names significant contemporary identities, but because queer heterosexuality is a necessary component of "gender-fucking" (Butler 1990). If all is artifice, simulation and performance, if "sex" is only a passing fashion, there is no point in opposing this by looking for some underlying re- ality or truth about "men" and "women;" rather, the strategy becomes to ac- tively participate in the artifice precisely in order to underscore the fragility of "sex" and "gender" as artifice. This strategy is described by queer the- orists as "gender play" (Schwichtenberg 1993), "gender bending" (Braidotti 1991) or, most popularly in the queer movement, as "gender-fuck" or "fucking with gender." The gender-fuck is supposed to "deprive the natural- izing narratives of compulsory heterosexuality of their central protagonists: This content downloaded from 131.96.12.74 on Tue, 20 May 2014 14:58:03 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 454 GENDER & SOCIETY / September 1994 'man' and 'woman' " (Butler 1990,146) and to illustrate the social construct- edness of"sex," in all its multiple meanings. This key queer strategy, the gender-fuck, is about parody, pastiche, and exaggeration. It replaces resistance to dominant cultural meanings of sex with carnivalesque reversals and transgressions of traditional gender roles and sexualities, which revel in their own artificiality. Media figures like Boy George and Annie Lennox have been cited as gender benders (Braidotti 1991, 122-3), but the most famous example of contemporary gender-fucking is undoubtedly Madonna, described as both a "postmodern feminist heroine" (Kaplan 1987 in Mandzuick 1993, 169; Schwichtenberg 1993, 132) and as a "queer icon" (Henderson 1993, 108). Her postmodern "queerness" lies in the way in which she is "dressing up and acting out to expose the constructedness of what in other settings passes as 'natural' male, female, or heterosexual" (Henderson 1993, 122). This same celebration of denaturalization is evident in the work of lesbian photographers often called queer. The controversial collection of lesbian photography, Stolen Glances, by Fraser and Boffin (1991) (the latter explic- itly identifies herself as queer in Smyth 1992), was compiled not in the "attempt to naturalize a 'lesbian aesthetic' . . . but rather to celebrate that there is no natural sexuality at all," and out of an interest in "subversive strategies of representation" (p. 21): these photos include Boffin's images of lesbian Casanovas in a Victorian cemetery and Della Grace's portrayal of a lesbian couple, one in gestapo cap, chains and black leather, the other in a bridal veil. Sex radicals such as Grace are often admired by queer theorists for their transgressive gender-fucking strategies, and are increasingly draw- ing on queer theory as an explanatory framework. Love Bites, a collection of photographs by Della Grace, has been cited by Smyth (1992) as an example of gender-fucking: one photograph, "Lesbian Cock," shows two lesbians dressed in leather and biker caps, both sporting moustaches and one holding a lifelike dildo protruding from her crotch. Lesbian feminists think things like lesbians giving blow-jobs to dildos should be kept quiet.... [F]or women to indulge in gender-fucking somehow isn't acceptable. But lesbians do. Lesbians even have "gay male sex." (Grace, quoted in Smyth 1992, 44) A varied selection of lesbians, bisexuals, gay men, transsexuals, transves- tites and sex radicals have claimed (or been ascribed) the "queer" label and have been lauded for their gender-fucking prowess. In the name of queer, some lesbians reclaim butch-fem roles as "changeable costuming" (MacCowan 1992, 300), and some gay men reclaim camp as "the pervert's revenge on authenticity" (Dollimore 1991). Transvestism (and cross-dressing) "draws This content downloaded from 131.96.12.74 on Tue, 20 May 2014 14:58:03 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Kitzinger, Wilkinson / PERSPECTIVES 455 the binary logic of sexual identity into question" (Bristow 1992). Transsexuals have a part to play because "the surgical removal and implan- tation of body parts reveals that one's flesh can be cut, so to speak, like a suit" (Bristow 1992) and because symbolically speaking "we are all transsexuals" (Baudrillard 1988). Hermaphrodites, too, are "a pornotopian escape from ... rigid binarism" (Williams 1992, 261) and Annie Sprinkle, "Post- Porn Post-Modernist" and "bi-girl" (Sprinkle 1992), sometimes bracketed with Madonna as a queer performance artist (Williams 1992, 234), delights in the gender-fucking ambiguity of her "first time with a F2M-transsexual- surgically-made hermaphrodite." With queer support for such a dazzling variety of "perversions," and given that the "biological sex" of sexual partners is dismissed in favor of gender as performance, it is hardly surprising that "many queer activists are wondering what's stopping gay men and lesbians from developing a sexual politics that also embraces bi- and hetero- sexuals" (Pickering 1992). But here imagination falters. Despite the fact that queer politics includes many bisexuals (Kennedy 1992) and supports lesbians having sex with men as "transgressive" (Wilson 1992), lesbian and bisexual queer theorists have not offered any details on "queer heterosex." It is as though merely the doing of sex with men is (for a lesbian, or for one who also has sex with women) transgressive in and of itself, and need not be subjected to further analysis. Even if this were true (which we don't accept), heterosexual sex for straight women cannot fulfill this allegedly transgressive function: does it then become a "queer-approved" activity only if it violates some other purported taboos-if it's sadomasochistic, or fetishistic, perhaps? Queer theorists have never satisfactorily answered the question, What makes straight heterosexu- ality "queer"? From a radical feminist perspective, then, our first criticism of queer heterosexuality is that (as with virgin heterosexuality) its proponents offer little or no indication of the methods for doing it. Queer heterosexuality is advanced as a conceptual and practical possibility, a supporting cameo role in the queer masquerade, but its characterization is largely content free. Extrapolating from queer theory more generally, it would obviously have to be a form of heterosexuality that "fucked with gender," that is, actively transgresses, parodies and subverts the "woman subordinate," "male domi- nant" sexual equation. It is not clear that, as a political strategy, this is any more sophisticated than is reclaiming as feminist the female dominatrix scenes of male pornography or celebrating women's fantasies of raping men. A second problem with the notion of queer heterosexuality is that, by definition, it elides heterosexuality and homosexuality as sexually-and hence politically-equivalent, sometimes literally so: This content downloaded from 131.96.12.74 on Tue, 20 May 2014 14:58:03 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 456 GENDER & SOCIETY / September 1994 The sexual ambiguities, finally, are just that-ambiguous. We do not know for sure that Madonna does not kiss a woman, nor do we know for sure that she does. In a pop cultural universe that makes heterosex abundant and abundantly clear, allusions to homosex are nice but not enough. Postmoderism's playful indeterminacy becomes gay activism's short shrift. (Henderson 1993, 113) The presentation of lesbianism and heterosexuality as interchangeable is not as radical as queer theorists would have us believe. It was Kinsey's (Kinsey, Pomeroy, and Martin 1948; Kinsey et al. 1953) famous invention of the "homosexual-heterosexual" continuum (borrowed in part from Freud's [1977] theories of innate bisexuality and polymorphous perversity) that set the stage for a widespread dissolution within psychology of any specific differences between lesbians and heterosexual women (cf. Kitzinger, 1987). The presentation of lesbianism and heterosexuality as equivalent betrays the underlying liberalism of queer theory. As the meanings of heterosexuality and homosexuality become blurred within a fantasy world of ambiguity, indeterminacy and charade, the material realities of oppression and the feminist politics of resistance are forgotten: It is difficult... to acknowledge the divided self and engage the pleasure of masquerade while at the same time fighting a strikingly antagonistic legal and social system for your health, your safety, your job, your place to live, or the right to raise your children. (Henderson 1993, 123) Third, in promoting a flexible polysexuality (mono-, bi-, tri-, multi- transsexuality; categories to be transgressed and transcended), queer and postmodern theory provide renewed justification for heterosexual women's refusal to notice that they are heterosexual-or for their tendency to dismiss such an observation as unimportant, based on transitory and provisional attributions. Asked to identify themselves as heterosexual, many feminists react with defensive anger: Why address me so categorically as a heterosexual? Why was anyone so sure? Because I am married? Or because my husband seems "straight"? Is it about my hairdo or my shoes or the things I have said, or not said? ... Perhaps it is a political question. Do I not belong to some inner circle? Is there a conspiracy afoot? How did the heteros get picked out? (Gergen 1993, 62) Gergen draws explicitly on postmodernism to defend her refusal of the "heterosexual" label, paying "a special tribute to Judith Butler for her book, Gender Trouble: Feminism and the Subversion of Identity, from which I borrow heavily in this text" (1993, 64). Using such theories, then, the lesbian feminist insistence that heterosexual feminists make their choice intelligible (Frye 1992, 55-6) is, at best, sidestepped as unnecessary; at worst, dismissed as meaningless. This content downloaded from 131.96.12.74 on Tue, 20 May 2014 14:58:03 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Kitzinger, Wilkinson / PERSPECTIVES 457 Finally, queer theory is centrally antagonistic to much of radical feminist theory. This is partly because queer theorists see all forms of feminism as totalizing "grand narratives," whose meanings and values must be subverted and thrown into question along with the other explanatory frameworks in politics, science and philosophy, mere fodder for deconstruction in the postmodern age. More than this, however, queer politics is often expressed in terms explicitly oppositional to feminism, especially radical feminism, characterized as "moralistic feminist separatism" (Smyth 1992, 36). "Queer" functions as apologia or justification for much behavior seen by radical feminism as damaging to women and lesbians: imitation of gay male sexu- ality, the defense of pornography, and sadomasochism. There is no attempt to problematize pleasure, much less to engage with radical feminist attempts to do so (Jeffreys 1990; Kitzinger and Kitzinger 1993; Kitzinger and Perkins 1993), other than to characterize these as repressive, restrictive and totalitar- ian in effect or intent. We cannot, then, as radical feminists, turn to queer the- ory in any attempts to salvage heterosexuality from radical feminist critiques, because queer theory simply ignores or mocks such critiques. In this section, then, we have outlined attempts to rehabilitate heterosexu- ality by subverting it as "queer." Although queer theory appeals to those attracted by its sense of possibility, its promise of fun, and its celebration of pleasure, we find it seriously lacking as a feminist political strategy. Its propositions are unclear; it falsely attributes sexual and political equivalence to hetero- and homosexuality; it permits heterosexual women to continue ignoring, and failing to render problematic, their heterosexuality; and it is in direct conflict with key tenets of radical feminist politics. REHABILITATING HETEROSEXUALITY? As we have shown, neither virgin nor queer theory offers a coherent feminist agenda sufficient for the rehabilitation of heterosexuality. At this point we would like to raise the question as to why heterosexuality is so vigorously defended, even (or perhaps, especially)-it seems-by lesbians? Why are some feminists apparently so desperate to continue the doing of heterosexual sex that they are prepared to accept such bizarre concepts as virgin and queer heterosexuality in order to justify themselves? The lengths to which feminists (including lesbians) are prepared to go in defending sex with men is surely a clue to its political importance. To some extent, and despite the bravado of the language in which both are couched, we see virgin and queer theory as defeatist. Recognizing the failure This content downloaded from 131.96.12.74 on Tue, 20 May 2014 14:58:03 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 458 GENDER & SOCIETY / September 1994 of lesbian feminism to communicate radical political analyses of heterosexu- ality and acknowledging the strong hold that heterosexuality apparently exerts on so many women (even those who could choose, even those who once did choose, lesbianism) (Bartky 1993), it is perhaps easier to revert to attempts to reform heterosexuality, exploring what feminist goals might be achievable within that institution, rather than attacking the institution per se. The abandonment of the radical critique of heterosexuality as inherently oppressive can be read as a tacit admission of defeat. In an increasingly right-wing political climate, this defeat is perhaps not surprising. Many oppressed groups are moving toward coalition politics: radical feminist critiques of heterosexuality, often experienced as criticism and rejection of individual heterosexual feminists, can stand in the way of working together effectively, and lesbians have often felt compelled to mute our criticisms in the interests of immediate survival. The possibility offered by Frye's "virgin heterosexuality" (that one can, after all, be a heterosexual and a feminist) must, whatever demands it makes on the practice of that heterosexuality, be far more appealing to many heterosexual women than is the characterization of them as "collaborators with the enemy" (Leeds Revolutionary Feminist Group 1981). Queer theory, too, despite its purport- edly more confrontational stance, is far more accommodating of heterosexu- ality than is radical feminism's theory of political lesbianism: Smyth (1992, 36) even raises as a possibility (and leaves unanswered) the question: "Is straight SM automatically queer, while a monogamous 'vanilla' lesbian couple living in suburbia isn't?" This explicit endorsement and validation of particular kinds of heterosexuality at the expense of lesbianism is a striking development of queer theory, and one that feeds into heterosexual feminists' oft-voiced retort that "lesbian relationships aren't perfect either" (Rowland 1993, 77; Jacklin 1993, 35). It is hardly surprising, then, that heterosexual feminists are seduced by queer theory's "wit," "ingenuity," "panache" (Beloff 1993), and "great possibilities for freedom" (Gergen 1993, 63-4) far more often than they are enthused by the rage and rigor of radical lesbian feminism. Both virgin and queer theory bypass key radical feminist concerns. Earlier feminist analyses of sexual intercourse are crucially absent from Frye's "virgin" paper. Worse by far than mere omission, queer theory actively reverses earlier radical feminist critiques-for example, transsexualism, sadomasochism, and pornography, (Dworkin 1982; Raymond 1982; Linden et al. 1982) and celebrates its own "inclusiveness," actively welcoming not only straights and bisexuals, but also transsexuals, transvestites, sadomaso- chists and pornographers under the queer umbrella. Lesbian queers endorse as progressive "alliances between pro-sex anti-censorship lesbians and like- This content downloaded from 131.96.12.74 on Tue, 20 May 2014 14:58:03 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Kitzinger, Wilkinson / PERSPECTIVES 459 minded gay men ... so opening up the possibility of new models for the expansion of lesbian erotic possibilities," whereas "equal, nurturing" sex is characterized as "prepubescent" (Smyth 1992, 37). The "transgressive" impulse of queer theory manifests itself at least as much against feminism as against heteropatriarchy. Such aspects of the queer movement render it less a symptom of the "defeat" of, and more an indication of the "backlash" against, feminism (Kitzinger and Wilkinson, 1994). What seems to be missing, in these continuing attempts to rehabilitate heterosexuality, is any sense that it is still necessary to critique and analyze it as an oppressive mechanism of social control. Enthusiastic renditions of blow jobs on a dyke's strap-on dildo or descriptions of how to do a "politically correct" blow job with a man (avoid the "erotic phallic-power associations" of kneeling, and try the "69" position, Dennis 1992, 162-3) simply ignore crucial aspects of the radical feminist critique of heterosexuality. For many women, heterosexuality still has the status of a compulsory institution; for many, it is still in the context of heterosexuality that they are abused. Any serious attempt to rehabilitate heterosexuality must, at the very least, address these material realities, making heterosexuality both "safe" and "optional" for all women. Any rehabilitated heterosexuality worthy of feminist support must be more than the luxury of a few socially and economically privileged partners of "new men." More than this, given the radical critique of hetero- sexuality as a primary site for the reinscription of gender-based patterns of dominance and submission, the models of heterosexuality advanced by virgin and queer theorists are seriously incomplete or flawed. It is unclear how "virgins" can mysteriously evade the implications of the heterosexual act; and implausible that "queers," through "playing" with genderized symbols of power and powerlessness, can hope to "subvert" them. It is perhaps worth noting that the notions of both "queer" and "virgin" heterosexuality derive primarily from, and are being developed by, people who do not so identify themselves: queers are rarely exclusively hetero- sexual, and virgin heterosexuality is, says Frye, "not my call." Such theorists have developed or appropriated particular angles on heterosexuality in the interest of developed queer or radical lesbian theory more generally. When heterosexual feminists (even relatively privileged ones) are asked to contrib- ute their theoretical understandings of heterosexuality (as in Wilkinson and Kitzinger, 1993), their analyses are much less optimistic as to the possibility of successfully combining heterosexuality and feminism. They speak-in voices far more hesitant than those of the lesbian and gay "virgin" and "queer" theorists-of painful contradiction, struggle and compromise. We are still a long way from having a politically and theoretically adequate solution to the This content downloaded from 131.96.12.74 on Tue, 20 May 2014 14:58:03 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 460 GENDER & SOCIETY / September 1994 problem of heterosexuality. Meanwhile, in the vast majority of heterosexual relationships, which are neither "virgin" nor "queer," heterosexual sexual activity repeatedly reinscribes biological and social maleness and female- ness, continually constructing women as women and men as men in order to ensure male dominance and female subordination. In this way, nothing changes: heterosexuality continues to mean what it has always meant under heteropatriarchy, and to serve the same sociopolitical function. REFERENCES Bartky, S. 1993. Hypatia unbound: A confession. In Heterosexuality: A "Feminism & psychol- ogy" reader, edited by S. Wilkinson and C. Kitzinger. London: Sage. Baudrillard, J. 1988. Selected writings, edited by Mark Poster. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. Beloff, H. 1993. Review of Stolen glances: Lesbians take photographs, edited by T. Boffin and J. Fraser. Feminism & Psychology 3:272-4. Bordo, S. 1993. "Material girl": The effacements of postmodern culture. In The Madonna connection: Representational politics, subcultural identities, and cultural theory, edited by C. Schwichtenberg. Boulder, CO: Westview. Braidotti, R. 1991. Patterns of dissonance: A study of women in contemporary philosophy. Cambridge: Polity. Bristow, J. 1992. Cross-dress, transgress. Observer, 3 May. Brunet, A., and L. Turcotte. 1988. Separatism and radicalism. In For lesbians only: A separatist anthology, edited by S. L. Hoagland and J. Penelope. London: Onlywomen. Butler, J. 1990. Gender trouble: Feminism and the subversion of identity. London: Routledge. Dennis, W. 1992. Hot and bothered: Men and women, sex and love in the 1990s. London: Grafton/HarperCollins. Diamond, I., and L. Quinby, eds. 1988. Feminism and Foucault: Reflections on resistance. Boston, MA: Northeastern University Press. Dollimore, J. 1991. Sexual dissidence: Augustine to Wilde, Freud to Foucault. Oxford: Clarendon. Duncker, P. 1993. Heterosexuality: Fictional agendas. In Heterosexuality: A "Feminism & Psychology" reader, edited by S. Wilkinson and C. Kitzinger. London: Sage. Dworkin, A. 1982. Pornography: Men possessing women. London: The Women's Press. .1987. Intercourse. London: Arrow/Century-Hutchinson. Fraser, J., and T. Boffin. 1991. Tantalizing glimpses of stolen glances: Lesbians take photographs. Feminist Review 38:20-32. Freud, S. 1977. On sexuality. Penguin Freud Library, vol. 7. London: Penguin. Frye, M. 1990. Do you have to be a lesbian to be a feminist? off our backs (August/September): 21-3. . 1992. Willful virgin: Essays infeminism, 1976-1992. Freedom, CA: The Crossing. Gavey, N. 1993. Technologies and effects of heterosexual coercion. In Heterosexuality: A "Feminism & Psychology" reader, edited by S. Wilkinson and C. Kitzinger. London: Sage. Gergen, M. 1993. Unbundling our binaries-genders, sexualities, desires. In Heterosexuality: A "Feminism & Psychology" reader, edited by S. Wilkinson and C. Kitzinger. London: Sage. This content downloaded from 131.96.12.74 on Tue, 20 May 2014 14:58:03 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Kitzinger, Wilkinson / PERSPECTIVES 461 Gill, R. and R. Walker. 1993. Heterosexuality, feminism, contradiction: On being young, white, heterosexual feminists in the 1990s. In Heterosexuality: A "Feminism & Psychology" reader, edited by S. Wilkinson and C. Kitzinger. London: Sage. Henderson, L. 1993. Justify our love: Madonna and the politics of queer sex. In The Madonna connection: Representational politics, subcultural identities, and cultural theory, edited by C. Schwichtenberg. Boulder, CO: Westview. Hollway, W. 1993. Theorizing heterosexuality: A response. Feminism & Psychology 3(3):412-7. Hunter, A. 1993. Same door, different closet: A heterosexual sissy's coming-out party. In Hetero- sexuality: A "Feminism & Psychology" reader, edited by S. Wilkinson and C. Kitzinger. London: Sage. Jacklin, C. N. 1993. How my heterosexuality affects my feminist politics. In Heterosexuality: A "Feminism & Psychology" reader, edited by S. Wilkinson and C. Kitzinger. London: Sage. Jeffreys, S. 1985. The spinster and her enemies: Feminism and sexuality 1880-1930. London: Pandora. . 1990. AntiClimax: A feminist perspective on the sexual revolution. London: The Women's Press. 1993. The lesbian heresy. London: The Women's Press. Jo, B. 1993. 'Virgin' means never having been heterosexual-Virgins do exist. off our backs (January):22. Kennedy, M. 1992. Two sides to sexuality, Guardian, 4 September. Kinsey, A. C., W. B. Pomeroy, and C. E. Martin. 1948. Sexual behavior in the human male. Philadelphia: W. B. Saunders Co. Kinsey, A. C., W. B. Pomeroy, and C. E. Martin, and P H. Gebhard. 1953. Sexual behavior in the human female. Philadelphia: W. B. Saunders. Kitzinger, C. 1987. The social construction of lesbianism. London: Sage. . 1994. Problematizing pleasure. Radical feminist deconstructions of sexuality and power. In Gender and power, edited by H. L. Radtke and H. J. Stam. London: Sage. Kitzinger, C., and R. Perkins. 1993. Changing our minds: Lesbian feminism and psychology. New York: New York University Press; London: Onlywomen. Kitzinger, J., and C. Kitzinger. 1993. 'Doing it': Lesbian representations of sex. In Outwrite: Popular/izing lesbian texts, edited by G. Griffin. London: Pluto. Leeds Revolutionary Feminist Group. 1981. Political lesbianism: The case against heterosexu- ality. In Love your enemy? The debate between heterosexualfeminism and political lesbian- ism, edited by Onlywomen Press. London: Onlywomen. Linden, R. R., D. R. Pagano, D. Russell, and S. L. Star, eds. 1982. Against sadomasochism: A radicalfeminist analysis. East Palo Alto, CA: Frog in the Well. MacKinnon, C. A. 1987. Feminism unmodified: Discourses on life and law. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Mandzuik, R. 1993. Feminist politics and postmodern seductions: Madonna and the struggle for political articulation. In The Madonna connection: Representational politics, subcultural identities, and cultural theory, edited by C. Schwichtenberg. Boulder, CO: Westview. Pickering, B. 1992. Queer street fighters. Guardian, 8 September. Piercy, M. 1979. Woman on the edge of time. London: The Women's Press. Radicalesbians. 1970. The woman identified woman (leaflet) reprinted in For lesbians only: A separatist anthology, edited by S. L. Hoagland and J. Penelope. London: Onlywomen. Raymond, J. 1982. The transsexual empire. London: The Women's Press. Rich, A. 1980. Compulsory heterosexuality and lesbian existence. Signs: Journal of Women in Culture and Society 5:631-60. This content downloaded from 131.96.12.74 on Tue, 20 May 2014 14:58:03 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 462 GENDER & SOCIETY / September 1994 Rowland, R. 1993. Radical feminist heterosexuality: The personal and the political. In Hetero- sexuality: A "Feminism & Psychology" reader, edited by S. Wilkinson and C. Kitzinger. London: Sage. Ruby, J. 1993. A lesbian feminist fucks with gender. off our backs 32:4-5, 20-1. Schwichtenberg, C. 1993. Madonna's postmodern feminism: Bringing the margins to the center. In The Madonna connection: Representational politics, subcultural identities, and cultural theory, edited by C. Schwichtenberg. Boulder, CO: Westview. Segal, L. 1983. Sensual uncertainty, or why the clitoris is not enough. In Sex and love: New thoughts on old contradictions, edited by S. Cartledge and J. Ryan. London: The Women's Press. Smyth, C. 1992. Lesbians talk queer notions. London: Scarlet. Sprinkle, A. 1992. My first time with a F2M-transsexual-surgically-made hermaphrodite. In Discontents: New queer writers, edited by D. Cooper. New York: Amethyst. Stoltenberg, J. 1990. Refusing to be a man. London: Fontana. Warner, M. 1990. Fear of a queer planet. Social Text 9:12-31. Weedon, C. 1987. Feminist practice and poststructuralist theory. Oxford: Blackwell. Wilkinson, S., and C. Kitzinger, eds. 1993. Heterosexuality: A "Feminism & Psychology " reader. London: Sage. Williams, L. 1992. Pornographies on/scene, or diff'rent' strokes for diff'rent' folks. In Sex ex- posed: Sexuality and the pornography debate, edited by L. Segal and M. McIntosh. London: Virago. Wilson, E. 1992. Crossed wires in the gender debate. Guardian 2 (May): Wittig, M. 1992. The straight mind Boston: Beacon. Celia Kitzinger is the author of The Social Construction of Lesbianism (Sage, 1987) and co-author (with Rachel Perkins) of Changing Our Minds: Lesbian Feminism & Psychol- ogy (New York University and Onlywomen Press). Sue Wilkinson is founding and current editor of Feminism & Psychology: An Interna- tional Journal and the "Gender and Psychology" book series (both Sage Publications). Together, Kitzinger and Wilkinson have edited Heterosexuality: A "Feminism and Psy- chology" Reader (Sage). This content downloaded from 131.96.12.74 on Tue, 20 May 2014 14:58:03 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions