Indian Music - The Divine Vina and The World Monochord - 623 Pages
Indian Music - The Divine Vina and The World Monochord - 623 Pages
Indian Music - The Divine Vina and The World Monochord - 623 Pages
Title Of Dissertation:
Dissertation directed
by:
An
by
Anthony P e t e r Westbrook
Advisory Committee:
Professor
Professor
Professor
Professor
Professor
Professor
Copyright 2001 by
Westbrook, Anthony Peter
Allrightsreserved.
UMI*
UMI Microform 3035834
Copyright 2002 by ProQuest Information and Learning Company.
All rights reserved. This microform edition is protected against
unauthorized copying under Title 17, United States Code.
Copyright by
Anthony Peter Westbrook
2001
11
iii
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
I would like to thank the many people who have provided
me with assistance with my research for this project and in
the preparation of this manuscript. All the members of my
committee made invaluable suggestions, but I would
especially like to thank Prof. Jonathan Shear for many hours
of his time helping me come to grips with Plato. Also the
section on India could not have been prepared without the
assistance and support of Prof. Debu Chaudhuri at Delhi
University.
For further insights, suggestions, and encouragement I
wish to thank Prof. Suheil Bushrui, Dr. Ernest McClain,
Prof. Joscelyn Godwin, Dr. Siegmund Levarie, Paul Jones, and
Prof. Michael Cain.
I am particularly indebted to my advisor, Prof. E.
Eugene Helm. Without his endless and kindly patience, along
with unwavering attention to detail, this project would
never have come to fruition.
Above all, I want to thank my wife Gina and my two
children Alan and Jessica for their love and emotional
support for almost two decades while I have been occupied
with this project.
iv
TABLE OF CONTENTS
LIST OF FIGURES
CHAPTER I : THE MUSICAL UNIVERSE
The Music of the Spheres
Musical Cosmology in Art, Architecture,
and Education
The Literary Canon
Iconography
The Divine Monochord
Gafori's Frontispiece
The Modern World
The Watershed
The Three Strands of Greek Thought
The Organic Tradition
The Mechanist Tradition
The Magical Tradition
The Corpus Hermeticum
Kabbalah
Rosi crucian ism
A Matrix of Ideas
The Magical Tradition and Fludd's Vision
The Magical Tradition And Kepler's Vision
The Fludd-Kepler Dispute
Kepler's Vision as Balanced Viewpoint
Treacherous Waters
Ren Descartes
Marin Mersenne
Isaac Newton
The Enlightenment
The Unmusical Cosmos
ix
1
4
5
9
11
11
17
21
22
26
27
30
32
35
38
39
44
45
52
56
60
64
64
72
75
77
79
83
85
92
94
101
110
12
117
122
126
132
The Watershed ..
..
Number, Kosmos, Music
The Musical Application
A Caveat
136
139
140
.. 146
Sanglta
Ratnkara
148
149
151
154
157
160
161
166
169
172
172
184
194
202
203
209
211
216
217
221
222
224
227
232
234
Sound
Gandharva and Marga
The Source of the Vedas ..................
The Inner Value of Music
The Vibrating String .....................
The Intellectual Continuum
Egypt
The Orphic Creed
Kabbalah
Sufism ........................................
Polarity and Division
Sarawati, Rhea, Isis
235
237
243
245
246
248
249
253
254
263
264
266
269
269
vi
The Theory of Knowledge
270
Symbolic Teachings: Riddles and Puzzles
274
The Pythagorean Plato
281
The Timaeus
282
History
282
Content
288
Context
289
The Ideal World
290
The World of Number
292
One, two, three
295
The Three Steps of Creation
296
Existence, Sameness and Difference
297
Division, Number and the Musical Scale
301
Modern Analyses
306
Ernest McClain
306
The Lambda, Plato's Cross and the Means
310
John Michell and the Ancient Canon
314
The Lambda and the Lambdoma
317
Keith Critchlow and Harmonic Symmetry
318
Hans Kayser and the Pythagorean Table
325
Timaeus as Symbol
328
One, Two, Three
but Where Is The Fourth? .. 330
The Divided Line
334
The Sun: Light and Intelligence
335
The Four Realms
336
The Dialectic
339
Ken Wilber and The Three Eyes of Knowledge .... 343
The Good, The True and the Beautiful
344
Epistm or
Theria?
349
Four Levels of Interpretation
351
CHAPTER VI: THE GREEK SOURCES; THE MYTH OF ER
The Context
The Myth
The Musico-Mathematical Interpretation
The Axis Mundi
Archetypes and Forms
The Forms
The Archteypes
Plato and the Yoga Sutras
Samyama
The Pole Star
Platof s Forms as Archetypes
The Prelude to the Song Itself
Dialectic and Yoga
The Magical Tradition and the Realm
of Death
355
355
356
358
360
381
381
384
388
390
392
399
401
403
407
..
..
408
412
viii
SELECTED BIBLIOGRAPHY
551
ix
LIST OF FIGURES
Fig.
Page
1.
2.
13
3.
15
4.
16
5.
18
6.
19
7.
24
8.
49
9*
50
10.
86
11.
87
12.
89
13.
90
91
91
15.
103
16.
111
17.
113
18.
Pythagoras by J. A. Knapp
123
19.
134
20.
152
21.
170
22.
183
23.
188
24.
192
25.
195
26.
27.
Saraswati
28.
Gematria
257
29.
307
30.
308
31.
Crantor's Lambda
312
32.
Plato's Cross
312
33.
34.
T h e Lambdoma,
35.
364
3 6.
365
37.
366
38.
367
39.
368
40.
369
41.
42.
214
228
or Pythagorean Table
313
329
372
43.
373
44.
374
45.
37 6
46.
394
47.
396
48.
397
49.
50.
398
Athens," detail
426
51.
516
52.
538
540
53.
1
CHAPTER I
THE MUSICAL UNIVERSE
3
On February 24, 1607, at the Accademia degl'Invaghiti
in Mantua, Claudio Monteverdi and Alessandro Striggio
presented L'Orfeo:
4
world. "Of all the musical conceptions handed down from the
ancient Mediterranean world," Gary Tomlinson tells us, "two
more than any others have captivated European minds: the
ideas of music's ethical power to affect man's soul and of
the presence of harmony in the cosmos."3 The first of these
conceptions, the idea of the affective power of music, has
formed a recurrent theme in writings on music theory over
the centuries. The second, however, went much further.
5
became the presupposition for astrology and the first
astronomical inquiries of all ancient peoples.5
Jamie James links the idea of a musical universe with
another enormously influential concept, the Great Chain of
Being, the view of the world as consisting of multiple,
interwoven, ontological levels.13 Together, these two ideas
constitute for him "The Great Theme" of Western thought. As
he explains, these concepts
. . . originate in the classical bedrock of our
culture, flow through the Christian tradition, and
remain firmly centered in the Renaissance and the Age
of Reason. They are at the core of the culture/
6
music, considered one of the seven liberal arts, was seen as
a central subject of mathematical and cosmological study,
along with arithmetic, geometry and astronomy. Such a study
may seem far removed from the practicalities of music
making, but, in the ancient and the medieval world, music
was seen as having both practical and philosophical aspects.
This approach is reflected in the well-known categories
established in the writings of the sixth-century Roman
statesman Boethius: musica mundana, the mathematical harmony
of the cosmos; musica
and body/ and musica
music as we normally
7
The third kind of music is that which is said to
rest in various instruments.*
The relationship between these three aspects of music is
summarized by Peter J. Ammann: "The commonly known and
practiced music, musica
Instrumentalis,
Boethius, De institutione
musicar trans. Calvin M. Bower
as The Fundamentals of Music, Claude V. Palisca, ed. (New
Haven & London: Yale University Press, 1989), pp. 9-10.
9
8
design of which reflects a mathematical canon of proportion,
often referred to as sacred geometry, that is closely linked
with musical cosmology. This influence can be found in many
famous buildings in Europe, from the Gothic era to the
Italian Renaissance and beyond and is reiterated in mosques
and temples throughout the Middle East and Asia, in a form
designed to reflect the divine rather than the personal.
Sacred art of any kind is art attached to and dependent
on a metaphysical doctrine, from which it receives not
only its subject matter, but also rules for the
composition of images and the treatment of form. Such
art does not exist for the sake of its own
achievements, but for the sake of realization of
transcendent Truth . . . It will not therefore deal
with the varied aspects of phenomenal life for the sake
of their own emotional and pictorial interest, but only
in the sense in which they are the mirror of divine
Reality.11
Such an emphasis imbues sacred art with a universal quality:
Truly sacred art, whether it be architecture or
painting, poetry or music, pierces through the veils of
temporal existence to confront the beholder with a
reality which shines from the other shore of existence,
from the Eternal Order. When one stands before the
Himpi temple near Madras, in the interior of the Jami*
Mosque of Isfahan or before the portals of the Chartres
cathedral, one is not only standing in India, Persia or
France but at the "center" of the cosmos joined by the
forms of the sacred art in question to that Center
11
9
which is beyond time and which is nothing other than
the Eternal.12
It will be seen in a later chapter that the image of
the cosmic "center" is of great significance to musical
cosmologies; in fact, it has a direct bearing on the
significance of the spindle held by the figure of Necessity
in figure l.13 Here, suffice it to say that such an approach
to cosmology appears to be a tradition of universal
application. While it is seen as the "Great Theme" of
Western culture, for example, it is by no means restricted
to Europe; it has many Arab and Jewish sources;14 it is an
important feature of Oriental thought, particularly in
India; and it flourished in China as long ago as 400
B CE
13
14
Haar, iv-v.
15
10
At regard of the hevenes quantit;
And afterward shewed he hym the nyne speres,
And after that the melodye herde he
That cometh of thilke speres thryse thre,
That welle is of musik and melodye
In this world here, and cause of armonye.16
and as late as Dryden:
From harmony, from heav'nly harmony,
This universal frame began:
From harmony to harmony,
Through all the compass of the notes it ran,
The diapason closing full in man.17
The influence of musical imagery on literature reached a
climax during the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries,1,5
when perhaps the most famous literary representations of
this theme can be found in the work of Shakespeare and
Milton. First in The Merchant
of
Venice:
16
11
Is thick inlaid with patens of bright gold.
There's not the smallest orb which thou behold'st
But in his motion like an angel sings,
Still quiring to the young-eyed chrubins.
Such harmony is in immortal souls,
But while this muddy vesture of decay
Doth grossly close it in, we cannot hear it.:?
and in Milton's
Arcades:
Iconography
The Divine Monochord. Along with its influence on
poetry and architecture, the musical universe has its own
iconography. One of the most famous examples appeared in
print just ten years after the time of Monteverdi's
Orfeo.
19
12
This is the illustration known as the Divine Monochord (fig.
2) that appeared in the Utriusque
Cosmi Maioris11
of 1617,
Utriusque
Cosmi Maioris
scilicet
et Minoris
Terra,
Metaphysica,
13
14
Aqua, Aer,
and Ignis.
is
15
16
Fludd, Utriusque
Cosmi Maioris,
i,
17
illustrating a famous story that we will examine in Chapter
III.
Gafori's Frontispiece, Almost as well known as these
engravings is the woodcut (fig. 5) that appeared as the
frontispiece of a 1496 treatise, Practica
musicae,
by the
aqua,
of the diagram, and from this basis rise the eight musical
notes of the diapason coupled with eight modes.
The mythical and cosmological significance of these
musical phenomena are established by their systematic
linking with the muses and the planets; the planets, each
with its presiding deity, are pictured on the right-hand
side of the diagram, the muses on the left. Thus, for
example, Venus is associated with the note Parhypat, the
Hypolydian mode, and the muse Terpsichore, while Mars is
associated with Eratho and plays upon the Phrygian mode and
the note Hypateme. There being only seven planets, the realm
of the fixed stars is added to accommodate the eight notes,
while the ninth muse, Thalia, is incorporated by association
18
19
20
with the element of Earth, or Terra, at the bottom of the
diagram. At the top, we see the presiding deity of the whole
pictured cosmos, Apollo. Holding a lute, or a lira da
braccio, he is attended by the three Graces and sits beneath
a banner that reads "The power of the Apollonian mind
completely controls these muses."22 "The intention is
clear," writes S.K. Heninger; "each Muse, each note, each
planet, though playing an individual part, contributes
concordantly to a larger whole, represented in the single
figure of Apollo."23
Both Fludd's engravings and Gafori's woodcut contain
elements common to musical cosmologies. The universe is seen
to be created by musical vibration and given order by the
structure of a musical scale. Relationships between the
notes of the scale and the planets are explored in a
systematic way, and the relationship between God and the
world is explicitly demonstrated. In the Gafori, it is
Apollo who represents the deity, while Fludd's diagrams show
both the hand of God and the name of God. Above all, the
universe is presented as a unified and integrated whole in
which each element occupies its assigned place and fulfills
its divine purpose.
22
Heninger, p. 38.
21
24
The Watershed
In 1619, two years after Fludd1 s Utriusque
Mai oris
Cosmi
James, p. 4.
28
James, p. 140.
23
Mundi, Kepler builds upon an earlier treatise,
cosmographicum
Mysterium
and
24
1619
30
31
James, p. 140.
26
The Three Strands of Greek Thought
Many elements of the modern world view that emerged and
were assimilated into our culture during the critical years
between 1500 and 1700 were the result of a gradual
rediscovery of Greek science that took place between the
twelfth and sixteenth centuries. While this process was
complex, historians have argued that the key to interpreting
its origins and its course lies in seeing two or three
distinct trends within Greek philosophy and science that
have contributed to the Western intellectual tradition
in
32
Tarnas, p. 69.
27
individualism, and secular humanism from the Sophists."34
The idea of both a mystical and an empirical impulse
emerging from the Greeks has been echoed elsewhere. The
English historian Hugh Kearney adds another dimension to
this view. Rather than attributing a dualistic vision to the
Greeks, he finds that European sensibilities were influenced
by three main paradigms or "strands" of Greek thought, the
Organic, the Mechanist, and the Magical, originating in
Aristotle, Archimedes and Plato, respectively.35 It is the
last of these strands, the Magical view, that is most
frequently associated with a musical cosmology. We shall
find, however, that all three of these strands of knowledge,
and the interactions among them, are essential for a
complete understanding of the music of the spheres tradition
and its emergence and eventual disappearance from Western
thought.
The Organic Tradition
The Organic tradition, while influenced by Galen and
Ptolemy, stems mainly from the work of Aristotle and was
particularly influential during the mediaeval centuries.
Even though Aristotle was Plato's student for many years,
34
Tarnas, p. 71.
35
(New York:
Plato
36
Tarnas, p. 57.
Kearney, p. 26.
38
30
his work was more available to scholars than that of other
Greek philosophers. (Particularly important were the
Metaphysics,
the Physics,
and De Anima.)
Eventually,
31
fantastic stage settings of Baroque opera. Archimedes' work
also resulted in the development of the mechanistic
analogies that came to dominate scientific thinking and
provided one aspect of a two-pronged attack on Aristotle and
the Organic viewpoint:
It was impossible to look upon the universe as a
machine and to leave intact the existing Aristotelian
assumptions about the nature of God, Christian
revelation, miracles and the place of purpose in the
world. The mechanist assumption was that the universe
operated on the basis of mechanical forces, and, as
Mersenne explicitly put it, God was the great engineer.
Thus the task of the scientists was to explore the
inter-relationship of the various parts of the
universe, on the assumption that they would fit
together like those of a machine.39
Marin Mersenne, whom Kearney cites here, wrote an important
work on music theory to which we will refer later. Here it
is sufficient to say that, along with Thomas Hobbes, Ren
Descartes and others, he was responsible for articulating
the world view that dominates contemporary thought and that
has largely rejected the idea of musical cosmology. Before
discussing this fundamental shift further, however, we must
examine the third strand of Greek thought, since this was
the ground upon which the music of the spheres tradition
flourished.
39
32
none
34
Ammonius Saccas (a mysterious figure about whom
virtually nothing is known) .40
The influence of Plato's philosophy was therefore introduced
second and third hand into the West for several centuries.
Even the high Scholastic tradition of Albertus and
Aquinas, although necessarily focused on the challenge
of integrating Aristotle, was nevertheless still deeply
Platonic in disposition. But this had always been an
indirect Plato, highly Christianized, modified through
Augustine and other church fathers: a Plato known from
afar, largely untranslated, passed on by digests and
references in another language and mind-set and seldom
in his own words.41
In many instances, it was in the application of mathematics
to problems of physical research where the Platonic
influence came to be most clearly felt, particularly as the
impetus towards science was gaining momentum in the late
Middle Ages:
Scholastics in England such as Robert Grosseteste
and his pupil Roger Bacon were performing concrete
scientific experiments (moved in part by esoteric
traditions such as alchemy and astrology), applying the
mathematical principles held supreme by the Platonic
tradition to the observation of the physical world
recommended by Aristotle.4:
40
Tarnas, p. 103.
41
42
Tarnas, p. 200.
36
Trismegistus's time, who was indeed long before the
sages and philosophers of Greece."43
As for the content of the Hermetic literature, James gives
the following description:
The two big books ascribed to Hermes, the Asclepius
and
the Corpus Hermeticum, amounted to an occult
encyclopedia that dealt systematically with astrology,
the secret powers of plants and stones, talismans to
summon forth airy spirits and demons of the underworld
(and charms to ward them off), as well as philosophical
literature of a distinctly Pythagorean cast.44
So influential was Hermes Trismegistus in the fifteenth
century that Cosimo ordered Ficino to put aside Plato until
he had translated the Corpus Hermeticum,
a task Ficino
43
James, p. 116.
44
Kearney, p. 38.
was
Yetzira
ha-bahir,
or
39
on the development of Jewish esoteric mysticism and, to a
certain extent, on Judaism in general. It extended and
developed the underlying mystical symbolism, introducing
such notions as the transmigration of souls. Further
elaboration of the tradition, dealing with mystical
speculation about evil, salvation, and
40
the Fama Fraternitt
is,
41
translations of Classical texts from the great ancient
libraries such as the one at Alexandria. Also, the French
philosopher Arnaud is said to have brought the tradition
into France at the time of Charlemagne (742-814 C E . ) . It
thereafter spread into the rest of Europe where its next
overt manifestation was its sixteenth- and
seventeenth-century revival of the order with the Fama
Fraternitatis.
In the late seventeenth century, according to this
version, Rosicrucianism gained a foothold in America under
the leadership of Johannes Kelpius, master of a Rosicrucian
Lodge in Europe, who came first to Philadelphia and later to
Ephrata, Pennsylvania. During the nineteenth century, the
order was active in France, Germany, Switzerland, Russia,
Spain and elsewhere. Since this time it has flourished as a
semi-secret society in both Europe and the United States,
with its headquarters in California and its own site on the
World Wide Web.
A key component of this account is that Rosicrucians
have suffered persecution at many times and, consequently,
have frequently had to function in considerable secrecy. The
result is that they claim involvement in a wide range of
philosophical and religious movements, sharing ideas with
the Egyptians, the Pythagoreans and Neoplatonists, the early
Christians, the Alchemists and the Knights Templar. They
48
As part of this claim, Rosicrucians point to the allseeing pyramid on the U.S. $1 bill, which, they claim,
directly reflects Rosicrucian doctrines.
49
Rosicrucian web-site:
www.rosicrucian.org/rosicruc/mastery/6-history.html#anchor
216739
50
Ibid.
51
Ibid.
44
treatment. "5C This is an important consideration, because
whole topics in the history of music, philosophy and
science, touch upon traditions whose esoteric elements are
ignored. Thus, for example, alchemy can be viewed as a
primitive form of chemistry replete with superstitious
elements. It appears, however, that alchemy was concerned
less with chemistry than with human development:
In Europe the transcendental alchemistsmystics and
philosopherssought to transmute the base elements of
human character into the more noble virtues and to
release the wisdom of the divine self within the
individual. Some of the renowned alchemists who were
also Rosicrucians were Albertus Magnus, Roger Bacon,
Paraclesus, Cagliostro, Nicholas Flamel, and Robert
Fludd.53
A Matrix of Ideas. Finding Fludd's name in this context
provides some insight into the multiple sources of his ideas
and the complexity of the Magical tradition. The Organic and
Mechanist traditions can be described much more simply and
quickly than the matrix of ideas that, as we have seen,
constitute the Magical strand of thought. With so many
competing and interacting ideas from such a variety sources
appearing under so many different names (Hermetic,
Rosicrucian, Pythagorean, Neo-Platonic, Kabbalistic,
52
46
appearing in the section of his work called Musica
mundana.
54
56
57
Ammann, p. 206.
56
59
Yates (1964), p. 1.
48
of his cosmology belongs squarely in the Magical tradition,
particularly with its emphasis on musica mundana and musica
humana and the macrocosm-microcosm relationship between
them, there is a sense in which the spirit of his work looks
back as much to scholasticism as to Christiam Rosenkreuz and
Hermes Trismegistus, particularly where his methodology is
concerned.
. . .to Fludd's mind there is an essential distinction
between things natural and things mathematical, which
make the two incommensurable, a view which in the last
resort results from his Aristotelian concept of the
physical world.0'0
Typical of the approach adopted by Rosicrucian writers, the
fundamental concepts underlying Fludd's work,
interpenetrating pyramids representing the upper and lower
realms of celestial and earthly creation (see fig. 8),
hierarchies of angels ordered by musical relationships (see
fig. 9), even the world monochord itself, are presented in
the form of images which are purely allegorical and not
intended to correspond to any observable physical reality.
Even the acoustical information used in the presentation of
the World Monochord is inaccurate. As Joscelyn Godwin points
out:
Ammann, p. 211.
49
50
51
There is an error in the "Diapente matrialiser it
should join the Sun's G to the C of fire, as should the
corresponding proportio
sesquialtera.
And in order for
the tones and semitones to be correct (to the right of
the string), we have to imagine the Fs as sharp.61
While he conforms to acoustical phenomena in the ratios used
to divide the octave,
61
Ammann, p. 202.
52
phenomena in the construction of a symbolic system of the
world that constitutes the crux of the dispute between Fludd
and Kepler, a dispute that became a protracted controversy,
carried on in a series of publications.64
53
is considered of great importance because it helped to
establish empirical observation as an essential component of
scientific methodology and led eventually to the
establishment of the mechanistic paradigm of modern
scientific thought. However, such an outcome does not
necessarily represent Kepler's own priorities or intentions.
For many years Kepler was engaged in painstaking
analysis of data compiled by astronomer Tycho Brahe at
Brahe's observatory near Copenhagen. All of this work was
aimed primarily at substantiating an internal vision of the
solar system that had come to him many years previously
during a flash of inspiration. He perceived the solar system
as built out of a series of concentric spheres, each
representing the orbit of one of the planets, their sizes
determined by the shapes of the five Platonic solids nestled
one within the other. It is a fascinating story that has
been well documented elsewhere.66 What is significant here
is, first, that Kepler1s vision was just that, an internal,
mental perception of the nature of the heavens that he
subsequently strove to substantiate through physical
observation, and, second, that the vision expressed in
Harmonice Mundi was an essentially musical one, although on
an abstract level of perception. As he himself wrote: "The
66
67
68
69
Kearney, p. 137.
cosmographicum,
engineer but
in the
nature
as clues to
Caspar, p. 267.
Kearney, p. 140.
See Chap. IV, pp. 149-151.
classicus
Kearney, p. 130.
74
Kayser, p. 59.
analytica,
quoted in James, p.
Mundi, which
77
Ibid.
Ammann, p. 211.
79
Ammann, p. 212.
80
Pauli, p. 194.
01
Pauli, p. 205.
82
Tarnas, p. 229.
J. Kepler, Weltharmonik,
1967), p. 291.
62
completion: it was inserted late and has little to do
with the actual proof, but provided a final
confirmation.84 85
There is another aspect of Kepler's work that tends to be
overlooked in discussions of its significance; Kepler's own
words suggest a different purpose underlying his life's
work:
To find a proper proportion in the sensile things is to
discover and to recognize and to bring to light the
similarity in this proportion in the sensile things
with a certain Archetype of a most true Harmony, which
is present in the soul.96
The insight expressed here is essential to the
understanding of musical cosmology. Kepler's insistence on a
link between the archetypes of the soul and the structures
of the external world is a key element of the Pythagorean
84
of
Reality
64
mathematical treatment. . . Thus Kepler wrote that the
true test of consonance (harmonic proportion) was the
reaction of the soul, viz., joy; and for him, this was
tied to a larger astronomical scheme, in which the same
consonance could be found in the numerical
relationships that he believed subsisted between the
planets.98
Kepler' s efforts were clearly directed to the end of
attuning the inner world to the outer. Other influences were
to prove more powerful, however, plunging Europe and the
world into the treacherous waters of the modern era.
Treacherous Waters
Ren Descartes
In 1619, the year after Kepler's Harmonice Mundi
appeared, on November 10, Ren Descartes spent the day shut
up alone in a stove-heated room near Ulm, in Holland, with
nothing to occupy him other than his own thoughts. Seventeen
years were to pass before he was to publish a treatise, the
Discourse
on Method,
65
of emphasis in our understanding of the world, Descartes'
formulation had a far more devastating effect upon the music
of the spheres than any specific criticisms, such as those
of Johannes de Grocheo in the fourteenth century, had
achieved.
89
66
edifice; his original goal was more modest. In the
Discourse,
90
Descartes, p. 46.
91
Ibid.
Tarnas, p. 276.
93
68
second of his Meditations,
famous cogito
69
that man perceives as outside his mind. Only in man did
the two realities come together as mind and body. And
both the cognitive capacity of human reason and the
objective reality and order of the natural world found
their common source in God.94
Whether or not they come together in man, this
separation of subjective and objective destroys the basis
upon which so much Renaissance thought depended, especially
Pythagoreanism and Hermeticism. As Frances Yates explains
it:
In his eagerness to establish a purely objective view
of nature as a mechanism, in his enthusiasm for pure
mathematics as the only safe tool for objective
enquiry, Descartes was left with the problem of mind
somewhat embarrassingly on his hands. He provisionally
solved the problem in a very crude way, by his so
called dualism, f,one world consisting of a huge
mathematical machine, extended in space; and another
world consisting of unextended thinking spirits. And
whatever is not mathematical or depends at all on the
activity of thinking substance . . . belongs with the
latter."95 96
It is with these steps of logic that Descartes destroys the
interdependence of microcosm and macrocosm because the
macrocosm comprises the physical universe while the
microcosm dwells within the mind. Separating these thus
70
destroys the ontological ground upon which the Magical
tradition had been built.
Descartes' separation of mind and matter was enormously
important for the development of the modern scientific
approach to knowledge. Matter can now be conceived as a
substance in its own right, understandable in terms of
purely mechanical, geometric, spatio-temporal laws that do
not refer to subjectivity or mind. And this conception of
science has led to enormous advances in our understanding
of, and mastery over, the physical world. But, when
conjoined with the lack of any comparable progress in
understanding mind, the successes of modern materialistic
science have also led to the view that man is really nothing
but a complex material machine, with no soul at all. For the
soul would now seem to be, in the philosopher Gilbert Ryle's
famous expression, a mereand completely unnecessary
"ghost in the machine." Thus Yates could remark:
This strangely inadequate way of dealing with mind did
not long remain unquestioned and since Descartes1 day
many philosophers and thinkers have struggled with the
problem of knowledge, of epistemology, of the relation
between mind and matter. Nevertheless, this bad start
of the problem of knowledge has never been quite made
up. About the external world, man has discovered ever
more and more. About his own mind, why he can reflect
nature in it and deal with nature in this amazing way,
he has made much less progress.97
97
71
A correspondence between microcosm and macrocosm,
between mind and matter, is an essential component of all
musical cosmologies. Now, with Descartes, we see a split
emerging between these two components of reality. Musical
cosmologies break down further with the other effects of the
mechanistic world view. As Clause V. Palisca explains:
... it is important to keep in mind in analyzing
music's relationship to science that music, unique
among the arts, is at the opening of the scientific age
inseparable from science. It is not surprising under
these circumstances that the area of musical thought
most affected by the scientific revolution were those
bordering on the fields of science that underwent the
greatest transformation. These, it will be recalled...
were astronomy and dynamics. Astronomy, music's sisterscience in the quadrivium, had until the middle of the
sixteenth century bolstered the idea that earthly music
contained in microcosm the divine harmony of the
universe; but now there was growing evidence
that
the
universe
was not a harmony after all In the fields of
dynamics the studies of the nature of vibration and of
sound likewise upset many of the widely held notions of
number-symbolism and of the way music affects the
senses and the mind.98 (Author's italics)
In light of these discoveries, and the conclusions made
concerning them, astronomy moved away from its former
sister-science. Within music itself, the trend, begun in the
thirteenth century, for theory to focus exclusively on
musica instrumental!s accelerated.
98
Swarthmore College,
Press, 1961), p. 93.
72
Marin Mersenne
In 1636 a work appeared that clearly showed the new
direction in music theory of which Palisca speaks. The title
of Marin Mersenne's 1636 treatise Harmonie Universelle
might
instrumentalis,
Mersenne
Revolutions
73
of the Heavenly
spheres,100
100
101
De
revoiutionibus
orbium coelestium,
Nuremberg, 1543.
75
scientific revolution was gathering momentum.
on Method,
Mathematics
Isaac Newton
So significant is the Principia
to the development of
76
From our point of view the significance of Newton lies
in his bringing together the mechanistic and magical
traditions. In one of them/ the world was a work of art
and God was an artist. In the other, the world was a
machine and God was an engineer. The two world pictures
were clearly incompatible but Newton himself managed to
meet the difficulty by creating a Deity who combined
engineering skill with artistic solicitude. Newton1s
God was an aesthetic mechanic who was forever tinkering
with his creation. This compromise barely survived
Newton's death. The general trend of scientists in the
eighteenth century was to see the world in terms of a
machine. Newton the Great Amphibium managed to span two
worlds but his successors could not. Hence the
Principia
came to be regarded as the foundation of a
mechanistic view of the universe.103
The view Hugh Kearney is espousing here is that Newtonf
like Descartes and Keplerf was striving for a comprehensive
and balanced world viewf but his successors were unable to
maintain this balance of vision. Two factors contributed to
this failure. More than normal ability is required to
synthesize seemingly opposing viewpoints/ and great geniuses
do not appear in every generation. At the same time/ the
political and religious climate of eighteenth-century
England/ dominated by the Puritan ethicf did not encourage
Platonic modes of thought. Numerous other factors come into
playf the adoption of atomism/ for example/ and the tendency
toward secularism and away from traditional religious
belief/ but the end result was the same. Unable to maintain
the comprehensive vision of Keplerf Descartes and Newtonf
Kearney/ p. 196.
The Enlightenment
Having argued that the emergence of the mechanistic
world view to predominance in the Western world resulted
from the abandonment of efforts to integrate opposing
strands of thought, it would appear contradictory to observe
that the Enlightenment also represented an attempt to unify
knowledge. But it was an attempt on its own terms.
. . . having extracted whatever was useful for its
present needs, the modern mind reconceived classical
culture in terms respectful of its literary and
humanistic accomplishments, while generally dismissing
the ancients' cosmology, epistemology, and metaphysics
as naive and scientifically erroneous.104
With the Enlightenment came a view of history that has
predominated for the last two centuries and that sees the
modern scientific world as a triumph over ignorance and
superstition and the culmination of two thousand years of
Western thought.
Tarnas, p. 294.
105
of
Knowledge
107
80
result provided an impetus for the development of scientific
thought in its early years, but now the limitations of this
fragmented view are beginning to become apparent. "Among
scientists in particular," writes the physicist Wolfgang
Pauli, "the universal desire for a greater unification of
our world view is greatly intensified by the fact that,
though we now have natural sciences, we no longer have a
total scientific picture of the world."108 With the
disappearance of a comprehensive world view, the discipline
of music has become far more restricted in its scope,
relinquishing its goal of comprehensive understanding. For
the most part, musica mundana and musica
humana have
Pauli, p. 209.
110
111
and Idea
(Zuckerkandlf s
112
(Tulsa,
CHAPTER II
THE GREEK SOURCES: ORPHEUS
follow closely on
Quinci
D'Orfeo
E servo
Gloria
L'Orfeo:
English
ed. The
English
85
and the Orpheus legend was well known to them from a variety
of sources. Indeed, the figure of Orpheus is a motif of
great antiquity and widespread influence (fig. 10).
Orpheus as Archetype
In the previous chapter, the Harmonie Universelle
of
86
F i g . 1 0 : Orpheus, Roman, c .
CE.
100
88
is just one example of an extensive phenomenon reaching back
across many centuries.
The Orpheus motif is not limited to Greek mythology or
Baroque opera; it appears in one form or another from
antiquity to modern times. It is found in the bible in the
form of King Davidthe subject of the Mersenne
frontispiece; Virgil and Ovid both told the Orpheus story in
Latin verse; Orphic theology was an important influence on
early Christian theology via such figures as Clement of
Alexandria; and it entered Renaissance humanism after being
revived by Ficino in the fifteenth century. There are
numerous examples of the Orphic influence in European
poetry, from Spenser and Milton in England to Rilke in the
German romantic tradition.
89
90
91
Vicari, p. 64.
94
Fulgentius here presages the two themes mentioned by Gary
Tomlinson in Chapter I, "music's ethical power to affect
man's soul" and "the presence of harmony in the cosmos."6
Apart from their contribution to these universal motifs,
however, Orphic creeds are of more direct, historical
importance to our theme; they formed the basis of the
Pythagorean brotherhood that flourished in southern Italy
beginning in the sixth century B.C.; they greatly influenced
Plato and later Greek writers; they transmitted the motif of
musical cosmology through several centuries, and into the
Western world.
G. R. S. Mead, Orpheus
13.
96
But if the origin of the Orphic literature remains a problem
for philologists, scholars have, in M. L. West's view,
achieved some "secure results.''
It has long been settled, for example, that the extant
Orphic Hymns were composed in the Imperial period, and
the Orphic Argonautica
in late antiquity. But on many
more central questions opinions still vary widely. The
so-called Rhapsodic Theogony, much the longest and most
influential of all Orphic poems, but known to us only
in fragments, has been variously dated to the sixth
century BC, to the Hellenistic age, or even later.
Truly one can only speak of disorientation so long as
such a massive uncertainty remains unresolved.10
To counteract such uncertainty, Freden points out that it is
the influence of these ancient verses rather than their
authorship which is of vital importance. Comparing the
philological problems to those surrounding the books of
Moses, he argues that
. . .for thousands of years [... the books of Moses]
have been read and quoted and have influenced men' s
minds, as if they had been written by Moses himself at
the command of God. The same thing is true of the
Orphic writings. Whoever wrote them, they had their
authority by virtue of their connection with Orpheus'
name.11
West, p. 1.
Freden, p. 7.
French
12
14
Mead, p. 15.
15
Mead, p. 15.
16
Mead, p. 9.
100
takes to mean initiation into the mysteries. Thomas Taylor,
the translator of Proclus' On the Theology
of
Plato,
West, p. 1.
101
figure in Pythagoras, to clearly historical figures in Plato
and the neoplatonists. Pythagoras' influence on Plato is not
disputed and, as explored below, a variety of sources
explicitly mention Pythagoras' debt to Orphic teachings.
Second, whatever influence these teachings had on later
schools of philosophy or religion, it was conveyed through a
specific body of literature; even by the sixth century B.C.,
Orpheus was known purely by the poems that bear his name, by
the cosmology and cosmogony that were passed on by his
school, and by his method of expression through inspired
song.
Orpheus, of course, is not just theologus but
theologus
poeta.
He is the first poet to celebrate the mysterious
principles that underlie the universe. It is because he
is a poet, because he had skill and inspiration, that
he is able to understand and is privileged to tell of
these mysteries. . . . He is an artist and this world.
. . is a work of art; he has privileged access to its
secrets and to the mind of its architect. Here myth and
pseudo-history come together; the singer with his lyre
is the one who understands cosmic secrets.18
Orpheus and Pythagoras
It can be seen from the above discussion that Orpheus
and his teachings are frequently linked with the figure of
Pythagoras. In fact, in a discussion of musical cosmology
and its sources the most important manifestation of Orphism
18
102
is in the thought of Pythagoras. It is a complex
relationship. For one thing, they were both attributed with
magical musical abilities. The second century C.E.
biographer Iamblichus recounts several instances where
Pythagoras influences birds and animals through the power of
his voice. In one story, he tames a bear in the region of
Daumia (fig. 16); in another, he speaks to an ox and
dissuades it from eating beans. In a third, he summons an
eagle from the sky. "Through such and similar occurrences,"
Iamblichus concludes, "Pythagoras demonstrated that he
possessed the same dominion as Orpheus over savage animals,
and that he
voice."19
Such similarities between Orpheus and Pythagoras belong
to the mythical aspects of their respective stories, but
they are also linked through the transmission of ideas;
Pythagoras' biographers make many references to his debt to
Orphic thought. Iamblichus, for example, includes the
"Orphic followers" among the ancient schools that had helped
shape what he calls Pythagoras' "divine philosophy."20 One
19
Iamblichus, p. 95.
103
1687
104
passage is particularly significant, although somewhat
fragmentary. Kenneth Sylvan Guthrie renders it as follows:
Pythagoras imitated the Orphic mode of writing, and
[pious] disposition, and the way they honored the Gods,
representing them in images and in brass not resembling
our [human] form, but the divine receptacle [of the
Sphere], because they comprehend and provide for all
things, being of nature and form similar to the
universe.21
Here the influence of Orphic writings on the mode of
expression adopted by Pythagoras is seen to be of great
importance, as is the reference to his imitation of the
Orphic demeanor in worship and personal conduct(assuming
that the first "they" here refers to followers of Orpheus).
This passage also points to the transitional nature of the
Orphic mystery schools. More ancient cultures, such as those
of India and Egypt, are notable for the representation of
their deities in human and animal form. Here, however, we
read that Orphic lore adopted a more abstract form of
representation, with the end result that Pythagoras could
associate the gods with mathematical or geometrical forms
rather than with anthropomorphic or animalistic entities.
This subtle shift of emphasis demonstrates the gradual but
critical transition between the Eastern and Western approach
to knowledge and religious expression embodied by the
21
Ibid.
105
figures of Orpheus and Pythagoras and culminating in the
work of Copernicus and Kepler.22 The significance of number
in Pythagorean thought also appears to be derived directly
from Orphic sources. "From the writings of Orpheus,"
Iamblichus reports, "Pythagoras learned that the eternal
essence of Number is the source of immortality, and from
this he reasoned that the fundamental nature of the gods is
numerical."23
The significance of number is central to Pythagorean
thought, so the Orphic influence can be seen as essential.
This influence does not go in only one direction, however.
There appears to be a consensus among scholars of Greek
thought that Pythagoras contributed to the Orphic tradition
as well as drawing upon it. Freden comments upon the
closeness of the two schools:
In early West Hellenic poetry he [Orpheus] seems to
have played a particularly important rle, which is
only natural when we consider the close relationship
between Pythagorean and Orphic mysticism. Pythagoras
himself is said to have used the name of Orpheus as a
kind of pseudonym.24
22
23
Iamblichus, p. 101.
24
Fredn, p. 5.
106
Similarly, Mead relates that Pythagoreans partially revived
the Orphic brotherhood after their own disappeared, while
Plato was to incorporate aspects of Orphic mysticism into
his philosophy:
[French classicist] N. Frret states that after the
dispersal of the Pythagorean School in Magna Graecia,
at the end of the sixth century B.C., the surviving
disciples attached themselves to the Orphic
Communities. . . This for a time vitalized the sacred
tradition, which was gradually growing fainter and
fainter, and in the days of Plato fell into much
disrepute. Then it was that Plato intellectualized
it
as being the only way to preserve it from further
profanation. Thus it is that Plato in Greece did for
the theology of Orpheus what Shankarchrya in India
did for the theosophy of the Upanishads.:5
The reference to Shankarchrya is an interesting one,
as is the general parallel that Mead draws between the
Indian and Greek traditions. Earlier, he compared Orpheus
with Veda Vyasa, the semi-mythical figure credited with
arranging the four Vedas into their accepted form and with
writing the Mahabharata
25
107
nothing but a footnote to Plato, it is equally fair to see
Shankara as the source of the tradition that lies at the
heart of modern Hindu philosophy and theology. (Shankara is
credited with restoring the truths of his tradition after it
was challenged by the influence of Buddhism. By contrast,
Plato's role was to preserve what had been an oral tradition
by committing it to writing.)
Returning to the relationship between Orpheus and
Pythagoras, a major source of information comes from
Herodotus, who speaks explicitly of a connection between
Orphism and Pythagoreanism. Herodotus "contributes not only
an indication that Orphism is connected with Dionysius, but
a theory about its origin, namely that it comes from
Pythagoras, who got his teachings from Egypt.":
The
108
the philosophy of number and the foundation of exact
science as the essential ingredient of Pythagoreanism,
the antithesis of Apollonian and Dionysian mysticism
fits in very nicely. We must bear in mind, however,
that as the Greeks thought of them, Apollo and
Dionysius were brothers; the supposed clear
differentiation of Pythagoreanism from Orphism is
simply not attested to in the oldest sources.:7
The relationships mentioned here, between Orpheus and
Dionysius on the one hand and between Pythagoras and Apollo
on the other, are more direct than metaphorical, as Orpheus
was associated with the Dionysian mysteries whereas
Pythagoras, as we will see below, is linked very clearly
with Apollo; indeed, he was held to be Apollo's son in one
legend. However, Orpheus was clearly associated with both
Dionysius and Apollo and incorporates elements of both
archetypal figures in his persona and his school. In the
Birth
109
figure of Pythagoras that the story of musical cosmology
next appears.
110
CHAPTER III
THE GREEK SOURCES: PYTHAGORAS
Ovid, Metamorphoses,
Book XV, verses 60-72. Frank Justus
Miller, trans. (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press,
1976), p. 369.
Ill
112
in Raphael's famous painting the School
of Athens
(fig. 17) .
113
of Athens,
1509-1510, detail
114
Many miracles have been attributed to Pythagoras, to
the extent that his classical biographies, particularly
those by the Neoplatonic philosopher Porphyry (c. 233-c. 305
C E . ) , a student of Plotinus, Porphyry's own student,
Iamblichus (c. 250- c. 325 C.E.), and the third-century C.E.
writer Diogenes Laertius, have been labeled hagiographies by
modern commentators. Yet Koestler, writing in the twentieth
century, claims more than mere miracles for Pythagoras. To
what can we attribute this extraordinary range of influence?
To make such a contribution to world history,
Pythagoras must have been a personality possessed of true
genius, an attribute he shared with several of his
contemporaries. "In Confucius, Buddha, Zoroaster, Lao-tse,
the Jewish prophets, the Greek poets, artists, philosophers
and scientists, the sixth century B.C. reaches a zenith of
human achievement."3 But this, in itself, is not sufficient
to explain Pythagoras' influence. It is also necessary to
consider the source of the enormous range of knowledge that
he acquired during the extensive travels that occupied his
early years, and through which he absorbed the essence of
many ancient traditions. "While accounts of his travels
differ," writes Manley Hall, "historians agree that he
visited many countries and studied at the feet of many
3
of History
115
masters."4 Julius Portnoy emphasizes the Egyptian influence
on Pythagoras' thought:
There is great reason to believe that Pythagoras
traveled in Egypt studying the sciences and musical
philosophy of the Pharaohs, just as the historian
Herodotus did in the fifth century. Pythagoras probably
came back to Greece with some elementary acoustical
theories as well as definite ethical beliefs concerning
music which he acquired from the Egyptian priesthood.
He began to teach that mortal music was an earthly
prototype of the celestial harmony of the spheres.5
While Pythagoras' visit to Egypt was of enormous
importance in the development of his thought, it is
generally accepted that he visited other parts of the
ancient world and absorbed other traditions of knowledge,
particularly that of Babylon, but also, possibly, of India.
Porphyry reports:
As to his knowledge, it is said that he learned the
mathematical sciences from the Egyptians, Chaldeans,
and Phoenecians; for of old the Egyptians excelled in
geometry, the Phoenecians in numbers and proportions,
and the Chaldeans in astronomical theorems, divine
rites, and worship of the Gods; other secrets
concerning the course of life he received and learned
from the Magi.6
116
The exact nature and extent of Pythagoras' travels,
like many details of his life, are disputed by scholars. The
precise locus of his study seems unimportant, however, if
"there is good reason to suppose that in earliest antiquity
there existed an intellectual continuum stretching
throughout Asia, even into China, and that the wall between
East and West was erected at a later date, nl as this would
suggest that Pythagoras would have been in contact with
essentially similar knowledge in any of the ancient centers
of learning he was able to visit. Similarly uncertain is the
correct attribution of Pythagorean teaching. Little, if any,
biographical information about Pythagoras himself is
completely reliable, and information about his teaching is
interspersed with biographical accounts in the ancient
sources. The tendency of ancient writers is to attribute
much to Pythagoras which could have come from other members
of his school. As a result, many scholars, following the
practice of Aristotle, have tended to refer the matrix of
Pythagorean teaching to the Pythagoreans, or the school of
Pythagoras, in a manner similar to the attribution of
painting to the "School of Raphael" or "School of
History
7
of Philosophy
in four books.
117
Leonardo."8 While confirming this tendency among scholars,
Burkert also confirms both Pythagoras' travels and his
importance in transmitting Eastern and/or ancient wisdom to
the West.
The opinion is widespread that Pythagoras himself, who
is supposed to have traveled to the East, brought this
astronomical knowledge back to Greece with him and
passed it on through his school. In fact, he is thought
of as the most important link in the transmission of
oriental science to the Greeks. More cautious scholars
are more likely to speak not of Pythagoras, but of the
early Pythagoreans, who are supposed to be the only
Greeks before Philolaus to have any advanced
a s t ronom i c a1 knowledge.9
in
Ancient
Pythagoreanism,
trans. Edwin L. Minar, Jr. (Cambridge:
Harvard University Press, 1972), p. 316.
118
Pythagorean thought has had on the West, and the importance
of comprehending it, comes from S. K. Heninger:
Pythagorean doctrine was all-inclusive in its intention
and all-permeative in actual effect, and in some fields
it retained its potency until well into the modern
period. The notion of cosmic order and its corollaries,
perhaps better known as universal harmony, stemmed from
the school of Pythagoras in the sixth century B.C. It
flourished throughout the classical period (most
notably in the Academy of Plato and in the Roman circle
of Neoplatonists around Plotinus), cross-pollinated
with Stoics and Peripatetics, scattered seed as far
abroad as the Hermeticists and the Cabalists and the
Syrian syncretists and St. Augustine, and came to full
bloom in the renaissance. . . . Pythagorean cosmology,
though withered, did not die until the acceptance of
Newtonian science and Humian philosophy. . . . In the
meantime, however, the cosmic order first propounded by
Pythagoras had provided the stimulus and the cohesion
for the best Western thought through all the
intervening centuries. And it must be mastered, I
believe, if we wish to comprehend the art of those
centuries.:a
Alfred North Whitehead, himself a mathematician, emphasizes
Pythagoras' focus on number:
Pythagoras is said to have taught that the mathematical
entities, such as numbers and shapes, were the ultimate
stuff out of which the real entities of our perceptual
experience are constructed. As thus baldly stated, the
idea seems crude, and indeed silly. But undoubtedly, he
had hit upon a philosophical notion of considerable
importance; a notion which has a long history, and
which has moved the minds of men, and has even entered
into Christian theology. About a thousand years
separate the Athanasian Creed from Pythagoras, and
about two thousand four hundred years separate
10
119
Pythagoras from Hegel. Yet for all these distances in
time, the importance of definite number in the
constitution of the Divine Nature, and the concept of
the real world as exhibiting the evolution of an idea,
can both be traced back to the train of thought set
going by Pythagoras.11
Daniel Boorstin echoes Whitehead while giving greater
emphasis to the musical aspect of Pythagoras' discoveries:
None of Pythagoras1 own work has survived, but the
ideas fathered on him by his followers would be among
the most potent in modern history. Pure knowledge, the
Pythagoreans argued, was the purification
(catharsis)
of the soul. This meant rising above the data of the
human senses. The pure essential reality, they said,
was found only in the realm of numbers. The simple,
wonderful proportion of numbers would explain the
harmonies of music which were the beauty of the ear.
For that reason they introduced the musical terminology
of the octave, the fifth, the fourth, expressed as 2:1,
3:1 and 4:3.::
The common ground shared by these writers is the
importance of mathematics, or more accurately perhaps, of
number, to the thought of the Pythagoreans. Such doctrines
represent a fundamental break with previous Greek thought.
In their attempts to move beyond traditional mythologies to
a rational account of nature, the earliest Greek
philosophers sought one essential principle or element as
the basis of the phenomenal universe. Thaes believed this
11
12
120
element to be water; Anaximenes suggested air; and
Heraclitus, fire. Empedocles combined these views, holding
that all substances are composed of four elementsair,
earth, fire, and waterwhile Anaximander suggested that a
self-existent but vaguely defined entity beyond sense
perception was the source of phenomena. As we have already
seen, however, the Pythagorean view, derived from the Orphic
teachings, is that the essential component of phenomena is
number. Heninger puts this view directly: "The primary tenet
of Pythagorean doctrine
orientation
Heninger, p. 71.
Aristotle, Metaphysics,
1-5, 985b-986a, in Complete Works
of Aristotle,
Jonathan Barnes, ed., Bollingen Series LXXI-2
121
Aristotle disagrees with this viewpoint/ but the Pythagorean
view is echoed by other ancient writers such as Theon of
Smyrna/ who described numbers as u . . .the principle/
fountain/ and root of all things . . . that which before all
things exists in the Divine mind; from which and out of
which all things are digested into order.//I5
This ideaf in a modified form/ has emerged in the
contemporary scientific paradigm as a key theme. For however
pragmatic scientific thought may appear to bef however much
it may appear to be based on the mechanistic model/ the
power to describe reality and/ indeed/ to manipulate the
world/ rests on an essentially mystical corethe still
unexplained correlation between the essentially mental
constructs of mathematics and the objective manifestations
of the physical universe. It is this correlation that Eugene
Wigner calls "The Unreasonable Effectiveness of
Mathematics."1 Other mathematicians and physicists share
his view/ as William Irwin Thompson points out:
16
1984)/ Vol. 2, p.
of Philosophy,
2 vols.
122
If you listen to Werner Heisenberg lecturing about
Pythagoreanism in his own work on the quantum theory,
you will hear him emphasize that the basic building
blocks of nature are number and pattern, that the
universe is not made out of matter but out of music.
The historians of science I worked with in the
University regarded Pythagoras as a magician, a
shamanistic madman from the cults of the Near East; Yet
both Whitehead and Heisenberg regarded him as a genius
of the highest order who laid the foundation upon which
our entire Western civilization is based.17
These foundations of our civilization emerged at a time
of considerable intellectual tumult, and it was Pythagoras'
great contribution to bring order out of the enormous
diversity of thought prevalent at the time. Thus it is that
Arthur Koestler speaks of him as bringing harmony out of
chaos and why he is so often depicted with the tools and
instruments of music and mathematics (fig. 18).
and Scattered
Light
123
124
essencef the term harmonia
the etymology of
16
125
arranging, but one that strikes the eye or the mind as
pleasingly fitting: as setting, or keeping, or putting
back, things in their proper order. There is a marked
aesthetic component here, which leads to a derivative
use of kosmos to mean not order as such, but ornament,
adornment; this survives in the English derivative,
cosmetic,
which, I dare say, no one, without knowledge
of Greek, would recognize as a blood-relation of
cosmic. In the Greek the affinity with the primary
sense is perspicuous since what kosmos denotes is a
crafted, composed, beauty-enhancing order.19
Clearly, we have lost these dimensions of meaning;
notwithstanding poetic expressions of awe by contemporary
scientists, the modern definition of cosmos, while it
retains some sense of order,20 has lost the aesthetic value,
while the latin mundus has given us the word "mundane," in
many ways the direct opposite of Pythagoras' kosmos.
in a sense, the value of harmonia
It is,
19
(Seattle: University of
126
Pythagoras is sometimes described in histories of
philosophy as a man who had two separate interestsa
religious reformer, who taught the doctrine of
transmigration and instituted a cult society, and a man
of science who did much to lay the foundations of
mathematics, that is to say of arithmetic, geometry,
astronomy and music. Transmigration was, until very
recent times, regarded by most modern Europeans as a
rather crude and barbaric form of the doctrine of
immortality. Also, it is not at once obvious to our
minds that there is any connection between the
immortality of the soul and mathematics. So the
historian was disposed to dismiss the religious
Pythagoras with brief and apologetic notice, and to
concentrate on the scientific Pythagoras and his
mathematical doctrine that the essential reality of
things is to be found in numbers. But that is not the
way to understand a great philosopher's apprehension of
the world. The vision of philosophic genius is a
unitary vision. Such a man does not keep his thought in
two separate compartments, one for weekdays the other
for Sundays. We begin to understand Pythagoras when we
see that the two sides of his philosophy meet in the
conception of harmonya conception that has a meaning
both in the spiritual and the physical world. And the
germ of this philosophy was a discovery in the field,
not of arithmetic or geometry, but of music.:1
127
aspects to this. Some of Pythagoras' involvement with music
is of a "mystical" nature, belonging clearly to the magical
tradition, to use Hugh Kearney's term. However, it also
deals with the discovery of the musical intervals and their
mathematical relationshipsa story of empirical observation
and scientific experiment belonging to the mechanistic
tradition. The resulting suggestion is that Pythagoras was
not limited to either of these approaches but, like Kepler
two millennia later, sought to bridge the gap between them.
Certainly, in their discussion of his approach to
music, Pythagoras' biographers emphasize his magical
approach. In a lengthy passage,~z Iamblichus tells us that
Pythagoras possessed what have been termed usuper-sensory"
abilities that enabled him to perceive directly the music of
the spheres.
Not through instruments or physical voice-organs did
Pythagoras effect this; but by the employment of a
certain indescribable divinity, difficult of
apprehension, through which he extended his powers of
hearing, fixing his intellect on the sublime symphonies
of the world, he alone apparently hearing and grasping
the universal harmony and consonance of the spheres,
and the stars that are moved through them, producing a
melody fuller and more intense than anything effected
by mortal sounds.23
Similarly, Porphyry reports that:
22
23
Iamblichus, p. 72.
128
He himself could hear the Harmony of the Universe/ and
understood the universal music of the spheres/ and of
the stars that move in concert with them/ and which we
cannot hear because of the limitations of our weak
nature.24
But there is more to this ability; it is practical as
well as mystical/ inasmuch as Pythagoras put his perceptions
to good use. "He soothed the passions of the soul and bodyf"
says Porphyry/ "by rhythmsf songs and incantations. These he
adapted and applied to his friends."2b Iamblichus goes
further/ describing in some detail how Pythagoras
transformed his perceptions off to use Boethius'
terminology/ musica mundana into specific melodies and
rhythms/ through which he "obtained remedies of human
manners and passions/ and restored the pristine harmony of
the faculties of the soul."26 He is thus creating musica
Instrumentalis,
as a mirror of musica
24
25
Ibid.
26
Iamblichus/ p. 72.
It is
129
also noteworthy, as lamblichus relates, that Pythagoras
designated specific melodies for the different seasons and
times of day27 in a way that suggests the time theory of
performance of rgas
27
lamblichus, p. 85.
28
lamblichus, p. 73.
30
Ibid.
Collected
musica,
131
of hearing, for if nothing were heard, no argument
whatsoever concerning pitches would exist. Yet the
sense of hearing holds the origin in a particular way,
and, as it were, serves as an exhortation; the ultimate
perfection and the faculty of recognition consists of
reason, which, holding itself to fixed rules, does not
falter by any error.
But what need is there to speak at length
concerning the error of the senses, when this same
faculty of perceiving is neither equal in all persons
nor equal in the same person at all times? Anyone who
aspires to search for truth would to no purpose trust
wavering judgment. For this reason the Pythagoreans
follow a certain middle path. They do not yield the
whole of judgment to the ears, yet certain things are
not investigated by the, except through the ears. The
Pythagoreans estimate consonances themselves with the
ear, but they do not entrust the distances by which
consonances differ among themselves to the ears, whose
judgments are indecisive. They delegate the
determination of distances to rules and reasonas
though the sense were something submissive and a
servant, while reason is a judge and carries authority.
Although basic elements of almost every
disciplineand of life itselfare introduced through
the impression of the senses, nevertheless there is no
certain judgment, no comprehension of truth, in these
if the arbitration of reason is lacking.32
Of significance here is Boethius' characterization of
Pythagorean thought as a "middle path," balancing empirical
and rational approaches to the development of music theory,
particularly when seen against the background of the
"mystical" powers described by lamblichus. This suggests an
epistemology based on a balancing of the three strands
described by Kearney. So it is that Pythagoras is seen
pondering a way to integrate these approaches.
musice
33
Encheiridion
harmoniks,
trans, with commentary, by
Flora Levin as The Manual of Harmonics (Grand Rapids,
Michigan: Phanes Press, 1994), Chap. 6, pp. 83-86.
35
De institutione
musica, trans, by Calvin M. Bower as The
Fundamentals of Music, Claude V. Palisca, ed. (New Haven &
London: Yale University Press, 1989), Book I, sections 9-11,
pp. 16-19.
See fig. 4, p. 16.
133
principles displayed are still critical components of our
culture, even if their sources are mythical rather than
historical.
In most versions, the story begins as Pythagoras is
considering how to integrate the knowledge of music.
"Once as he was intently considering music, " Iamblichus
reports, he was
". . .reasoning with himself whether it would be
possible to devise some instrumental assistance to the
sense of hearing so as to systematize it, as sight is
made precise by the compass, rule and telescope,3* or
touch is made reckonable by balance and measures.39
As he was considering these things, Pythagoras happened
to pass by a blacksmith's shop where he heard the sound of
hammers beating out a piece of iron on an anvil. He was
struck by the fact that some of the sounds made by the
hammers seemed to be in harmony with each other; he
recognized intervals of the octave, the fifth, and the
fourth. He also noted that "the sound between the fourth and
38
While telescopes, as such, did not exist in the sixthcentury B.C.E., Guthrie has chosen to use a modern term for
what Thomas Taylor renders as "dioptric instrument." See
Thomas Taylor, Iamblichus'
Life of Pythagoras
(London: The
Author, 1818), p. 84.
39
Iamblichus, p. 86.
134
135
the fifth, taken by itself, was a dissonance, and yet
completed the greater sound among them."40
x%
40
Ibid.
41
Ibid.
42
136
substantiate his initial insight. We hear of him working
with stretched strings, lengths of pipe, bells, monochords,
triangles, and the like. (See fig. 20.) The results of this
activity are precisely what scientific experimentation is
supposed to test, namely, whether a theory, or initial
finding, is found to be universally applicable. In this
case, the empirical evidence supported Pythagoras initial
finding; the relationships between the ratios, the musical
intervals and the physical media held true in every
instance. The octave is always found in the 2:1
relationshipwhether in the length of strings or columns of
air or whatnot. It is a universal relationship, as are the
other musical intervals. This conclusion, expressed in its
simplest form, is a sequence of numbers: 6, 8, 9, 12. These
are the weights of the original hammers in the story and
represent the smallest whole numbers that express the basic
relationships Pythagoras had discovered, 1:2, 2:3 and 3:4,
or, in musical terms, the octave, fifth and fourth.
The Watershed
It is hard to imagine the impact such a discovery must
have conveyed:
To discover that these fundamental proportions, on
which every scale is built, could be expressed so
simply in ratios between the first four numbers was
43
138
modem world view. But if Pythagoras sought a balance, then
we need to take the same stance to understand his thought,
particularly his theory of number and music. Seyyed Hossein
Nasr explains the balance inherent in Pythagorean
mathematics :
Pythagoras not only believed firmly in the existence of
order in nature as did other Greek philosophers but he
also sought to explain this order not by asking what is
the nature of the constitutive substance of the cosmos,
but what is its pattern. His response to this question
was mathematical structures that constitute the forms
of things and by virtue of which things are what they
are and are distinguished from each other. It is the
mathematical structure of things that makes them what
they are and not their matter. The cosmos is
mathematically intelligible, but on the condition that
mathematics be understood in its qualitative as well as
quantitative sense and be seen symbolically.AA
Nasr suggests that it was exactly this balance that was lost
during the seventeenth-century watershed.
It is precisely this aspect of mathematics that was
denied by those in the sixteenth and seventeenth
centuries who evoked the name of Pythagoras in seeking
to mathematicize physics and reduce the science of
nature to the study of pure quantity, with results that
from the spiritual point of view can only be called
catastrophic, for what is not symbolic (from the Greek
verb symballein,
meaning to unite) cannot but be
diabolic (from another Greek verb diaballein,
meaning
to divide). Pythagorean mathematics was a means of
uniting rather than dividing, and Pythagorean numbers
and geometric patterns are so many reflections of
44
139
Unity, of the number one or the geometric point, which
echo Unity but somehow never break away from It.45
Number,Kosmos, Music
It is from this perspective that we should examine the
mathematical significance of our story. In most versions,
the writers take pains to present the actual weights of the
hammers, six, eight, nine and twelve pounds respectively.
This is the smallest sequence of whole numbers that
expresses 1:2, 2:3, and 3:4. As we shall see, these numbers
are of great cosmological significance for the Pythagoreans.
There is a further dimension to the mathematical
elegance of this simple sequence. A significant interest in
Pythagorean mathematics is the study of the various kinds of
means, or ways of dividing a numerical ratio. There are
three of these-the arithmetic, geometric and harmonic, and
two of these appear in the 6,8,9,12 sequence. The arithmetic
mean divides two numbers, a and c, such that, where the mean
is b, b-a = c-b.46 Thus, in the sequence in question, 9 is
the arithmetic mean as 9-6 = 12-9 = 3. The harmonic mean,
given in here by 8, is a little more complex. It occurs when
45
Ibid.
46
140
arc = (b-a) : (c-b) .47 In this case, 6:12 =
(8-6) : (12-8) =
48
The geometric mean does not appear here but occurs when
the terms in a sequence of numbers differs from its
immediate predecessor by a constant ratio, such as in
1,2,4,8,16... In concise form it is expressed as B = / A X
C.
49
Macrobius, p. 187.
50
51
Iamblichus, p. 87.
P e t e r Gorman, Pythagoras:
A Life
Kegan Paul, 1979), pp. 160-161.
142
By balancing the empirical and the theoretical, Pythagoras
is integrating the traditions of Archimedes and Aristotle.
Gorman reminds us that he also balanced these perspectives
with the magical tradition, often referred to in terms of
mysticism.
The experimental method which Pythagoras employed on
this historic occasion proves that he was not just a
religious mystic in the oriental mold, but a follower
of the scientific revolution which the Ionians had
initiated in his lifetime. His mysticism was always
based on reason and the empirical method which of
course he transcended by his powerful intellect.52
James expands on this assessment:
Pythagoras's discovery of the arithmetical basis of the
musical intervals was not just the beginning of music
theory; it was the beginning of science. For the first
time, man discovered that universal truths could be
explained through systematic investigation and the use
of symbols such as mathematics. Once that window was
opened, the light spread across the whole breadth of
human curiositynot least in the field of cosmology.
The genius of Pythagoras lay in the comprehensive way
he joined the inner man and the cosmos.
Before Pythagoras, the picture of the cosmos was
much closer to poetry than to science.53
In making his discoveries at the blacksmith's shop, and
translating them into both abstract and concrete
applications, Pythagoras makes a major contribution to the
future development of science while linking this modern view
,2
Gorman, p. 163.
James, p. 37
143
with the ancient cosmological traditions. His contribution
to scientific thinking has two aspects, forming the two legs
upon which modern science stands. The first, and most
obvious, is the use of empirical observation and experiment.
The second is the relationship between the abstract realm of
numbers and the concrete realm of the physical world. It is
here, as Wigner's phrase the "unreasonable effectiveness of
mathematics," so eloquently indicates, that mysticism creeps
into science by way of the magical tradition, and where
science finds itself linked, usually against its will, with
ancient number symbolism. It is this link, provided by
Pythagoras, and derived from his discoveries in music, that
forms the central tenet of his thought.
In the teaching of Pythagoras the philosophic quest for
the pxtf ["archay"], the first cause and principle of
all things, was carried to a consideration of the
problem of the Orphic lyre itself ["The Magic of the
String"], by which the hearts of men are quelled,
purified, and restored to their part in God. His
conclusion was that pxtf is number, which is audible in
music, and by a principle of resonance touches - and
adjusts thereby - the tuning of the soul. This idea is
fundamental to the arts of both India and the Far East
and may go back to the age of the pyramids . . . a
principle by which art, psychology, philosophy, ritual,
mathematics, and even athletics were to be recognized
as aspects of a single science of harmony.54
54
Mythology
144
If this is indeed a single science, it must extend to
all forms and phenomena. That is, the principles of music
and mathematics must extend to the structure of the
universe :
Having made his wonderful discovery of the mathematical
basis for the musical intervals, he came to the
conclusion that these mathematical truths must underlie
the very principles of the universe. Pythagoras, who
had inherited the notion of the spheres, made the
logical assumption that they must make sounds in their
revolutions; and that being the case, these sounds
would of necessity be musical and harmonious. The
Pythagoreans conceived of the cosmos as a vast lyre,
with crystal spheres in the place of strings.
The classical account of Pythagoras's vision of
the cosmos comes, again, from Aristotle.55
The account to which James refers is the famous statement
from Aristotle's Metaphysics,
James, p. 38.
56
Metaphysics,
57
Ibid.
145
representation of the idea, suggesting that it had two
distinct aspects. First, there is what we might call the
first principle of musical cosmology, the connection between
number, music and kosmos,
58
59
Chap. I, note 3.
146
A Caveat
Before concluding our consideration of Pythagoras it is
worth reiterating an earlier caveat. In dealing with
Pythagoras, there is uncertainty about any factual material
as he did note write anything that has survived. In
explaining this situation, however, Haar also provides some
firm ground for the consideration of Pythagorean teaching.
As for Pythagoras himself, the result of generations of
Neo-Platonic enthusiasm in crediting him with countless
inventions, achievements, and miraculous doings is that
one now hesitates to attribute anything to the man
himself. "Pythagorean" is a legitimate label for
certain elements in Greek thinking, however, and
prominent among these is the blending of astronomy with
musico-mathematical theories into the concept of a
harmoniously ordered universe. It is surely not going
too far to identify the basic elements of the
Pythagorean cosmos with Pythagoras himself.C
With this observation in mind, it is also worth
remembering Koestler's view of Pythagoras as a man "whose
influence on the ideas, and thereby on the destiny, of the
human race was probably greater than that of any single man
before or after him."61 It is remarkable that Pythagoras
could have had such an enormous impact while leaving no
written record of his teaching, particularly when we
remember how dependent upon written documents the Western
60
61
147
tradition was to become. Perhaps only one other figure has
been able to have a similar intellectual influence without
leaving us any writings, and that is Socrates. To a large
extent, we draw on one writer to represent both Socrates and
Pythagoras. That is the great philosopher Plato, who, among
his other achievements, produced two major sources of the
music of the spheres tradition. Before examining these
sources, however, we will go more deeply into Pythagorean
number symbolism and compare it to similar ideas of great
antiquity.
148
CHAPTER IV
NUMBER, TONE AND KOSMOS
149
The Quadrivium
The most convenient framework within which to examine
Pythagorean number theory itself invokes the numbers one
through four. This is evident when we consider the
categorization of the various branches of mathematics that
was implicit in Pythagorean doctrine from the earliest
times.
In the field of theoretical and applied science,
Pythagoras through his preoccupation with numbers
established arithmetic and geometry as systematic
studies. Diogenes Laertius reported that Pythagoras
"also discovered the musical intervals on the
monochord" (VIII.ii), and consequently he was credited
with instituting musicology. Because of his explanation
of several celestial phenomena and because of his
formulation of the first cosmologyhe instituted, in
fact, the word KopoPythagoras was the progenitor of
astronomy as a science.1
It is no accident that Pythagoras is credited with
discovering four branches of learning, nor that all of these
depended upon number. Every aspect of Pythagorean doctrine
has a symbolic component, and the symbolism was typically
based on numerical values, in which the number four had a
particular significance.
150
. . . These "four paths'' to knowledge were four
distinct disciplinesarithmetic geometry, music and
astronomy. But they all depended upon the Pythagorean
assumption that number is the basic principle in the
universe and that relationships between items are
determined by numerical ratios, thereby producing a
structure of harmonious proportions.2
The term Quadrivium
Heninger, p. 53.
Heninger, p. 149.
151
cosmogony that lies at the center of both Pythagorean and
Platonic doctrine.
Arithmetic
Within Pythagorean mathematics/ arithmetic consists of
much more than rules for manipulating numbers. It reflects
the view of numbers as fundamental entities underlying all
forms and processes in nature/ as archetypes or, in Platonic
terms/ as "Formsf" a view that is explicated in The
of Arithmetic,
Theology
152
153
the subject matter of the Pythagorean discipline of music or
harmonics. The reference to the third discipline/ geometry/
is equally clear.
Iamblichis is careful to expound on the nature of
number in the very first statement of the Theology
Arithmetic
of
6
7
154
enough to convey the meaning of the monad and the other
entities dealt with in such texts as The
of Arithmetic.
Theology
155
The significance of this pattern lies in its representation
of completeness. It contains all four dimensions. Line one
constitutes a point. The two points in line two form a line,
thus two dimensions. The three points in lines one and two
together, or the six points in the first three lines, form
what are known as triangular numbers:
156
of the numbers that added up to it. Thus, by dealing with
just the first ten numbers, The Theology
of Arithmetic
runs
10
11
Dechas,
12
13
157
reiterate the symbolism of wholeness or perfection, while
others symbolize the processes whereby wholeness is
differentiated and regained through higher levels of
integration in the processes of creation. Thus, as we will
see, the monad, manifest as the number one, represents the
fullness of the creator, the abstract principle of wholeness
and potentiality underlying the creation itself. The tetrad,
on the other hand, representing the number four, is said to
be equivalent to the decad or tetraktys, because the first
four numbers add up to ten; 1+2+3+4=10. Thus the qualities
of wholeness can be also expressed in these four numbers. If
we look at these numbers in turn, we can see the fundamental
qualities of the creative process in the Pythagorean
cosmogony.
The Monad. If the decad and the tetrad are perfect,
what of the monad? We have already noted the distinction
between the monad and the number one. As Theon of Smyrna
puts it, "The monad is then the principle of numbers; and
the one the principle of numbered things."u In its more
abstract form, oneness was seen as a unified basis of
existence.
14
158
The Pythagoreans considered the Monad as the origin
(arche) of all things, just as a point is the beginning
of a line, a line of a surface, and a surface of a
solid, which constitutes a body. A point implies a
preceding Monad, so that it is really the principle of
bodies, and all of them arise from the Monad.15
As Macrobius explains:
One is called monas, that is Unity, and is both male
and female, odd and even, itself not a number, but the
source and origin of numbers. This monad, the beginning
and ending of all things, yet itself not knowing a
beginning or ending, refers to the Supreme God.16
Macrobius's statement reveals the potential of
Pythagorean thought to translate number theory into
religious as well as cosmological terms; the concept of
Oneness lends itself as easily to the idea of the monad as
the origin of all number as it does to the idea of God as
the source and origin of the universe. Theon reflects this
view in his description of the monad:
Unity is the principle of all things and the most
dominant of all that is: all things emanate from it and
it emanates from nothing. It is indivisible and it is
everything in power. It is immutable and and never
departs from its own nature through multiplication
15
16
18
160
This deepest of all mysteries is dealt with in every
cultural setting, in terms that are shrouded in various
kinds of mythical, often highly cryptic, symbolism. In
Pythagorean terms, where numbers are seen as the essential
elements of creation, this story is told through the
cosmological significance of numbers and the sequence
through which they unfold.
The Dvad. From the monad, we progress to the dyad. If
the monad represents the unity that underlies all existence,
the dyad is the first principle whereby that One becomes
many. As a result, its qualities are sharply contrasted with
that of the monad. "Number Two, or Dyad," Porphyry tells us,
"signified the dual reason of diversity and inequality, of
everything that is divisible, or mutable, existing at one
time in one way, and at another time in another way."19 The
Theology
of Arithmetic
161
changing and altering, while God is the cause of
sameness and unchanging stability.20
Here the dyad is associated with the essential bifurcation
of nature that is the prerequisite for the manifestation of
the physical universe. It is without form; form depends upon
the value of three. And yet it is absolutely opposed to, or
contrasted with, the nature of God, or of the value of
unity. In the simplest terms, as we will see in Chapter V,
monad and dyad represent sameness and difference, limit and
the unlimited, good and evil. And yet, as Iamblichus tells
us, both values are present in everything. "So each thing
and the universe as a whole is one as regards the natural
and constitutive monad in it, but again each is divisible,
in so far as it necessarily partakes of the material dyad as
well."21 And yet, "The dyad is also an element in the
composition of all things, an element which is opposed to
the monad, and for this reason the dyad is perpetually
subordinate to the monad, as matter is to form.//22
The Triad, The nature of the triad is made manifest in
the relationship between the monad and the dyad. "The first
conjunction of monad and dyad results in the first finite
20
21
Ibid.
22
Iamblichus ( a t t r i b u t e d t o ) , p, 4 2 .
162
plurality/ the element of things, which would be a triangle
of quantities and numbers."23 Thusf "The triad has a special
beauty and fairness beyond all numbers/ primarily because it
is the very first to make actual the potentialities of the
monadoddness/ perfection/ proportionality/ unification/
limit."24 Pseudo-Iambiichus goes on to articulate the
relationship between the first three numbers.
The monad is like a seed in containing in itself the
unformed and also unarticulated principle of every
number; the dyad is a small advance towards number ,
but is not number outright because it is like a source;
but the triad causes the potential of the monad to
advance into actuality and expression. *Thisf belongs
to the monad/ ^either' to the dyad/ and *eachf and
*every' to the triad. Hence we use the triad also for
the manifestation of plurality/ and say ^thrice ten
thousand' when we mean *many times many/' and * thrice
blessed.'25
Springing from this quality of realized potentiality/
the number three is the first number that represents
quantity in the real world. Heninger expresses this clearly.
First he reviews the values of monad and dyad. "The monad/"
he writes/ "represents the unity of the conceptual world/
while the dyad represents the idea of extension and
23
24
25
163
therefore the divisibility of the physical world."26 Both of
these are abstractions. The number three, however, is u . . .
the first arithmetical number per sethat is, a ^quantity
composed of units' . . . whose physical extension is proved
by the fact that it has a terminus
ad
26
Heninger, p. 87.
27
Ibid.
28
Ibid.
29
164
triangle is the only intrinsically stable geometric figure.
Fuller developed an alternative system of mathematics by
suggesting that the Cartesian system, based on 90-degree coordinates, is profoundly counter-intuitive, and replacing
the 90-degree system with 60-degree constructions. Moving on
from there, he found the tetrahedron to be a fundamental
building block in physics, chemistry, crystallography and a
host of other areas.
On a more abstract level, in the field of cultural
history, Ken Wilber and Erich Neumann find a tripartite
structure in the evolution of consciousness, breaking down
into the realms of the pre-personal, the personal and the
trans-personal. It is Neumann's thesis that ". . .a series
of archetypes is a main constituent of mythology, that they
stand in an organic relation to one another, and that their
stadial succession determines the growth of
consciousness."30 Examining the whole field of mythology,
Neumann finds one underlying motif which he defines as "the
history of this self-emancipation of the ego, struggling to
free itself from the power of the unconscious and to hold
its own against overwhelming odds."31 The achievement of
30
165
this emancipation gives rise to the hero myth which exists
at the central point in this three-stage process. The figure
of the hero, in which we see modern man, is preceded by preegoic consciousness on the one hand, while potentially
leading to the possibility of the trans-personal on the
other. Ken Wilber sums up this process succinctly. *There
are only two stations at which men and women are perfectly
content. One is slumbering in the subconscious, the other is
awakened in the superconscious. Everything in between is
various degrees of pandemonium."3~
From Fuller's perspective, threefold structures
underlie the very fabric of matter. According to Wilber's
and Neumann's views, the value of three is expressed in the
structure of history. Iamblichus adds another dimension in
applying the value of the triad to the fields of knowledge
and action.
The triad is called ^prudence' and ^wisdom'that is,
when people act correctly as regards the present, look
ahead to the future, and gain experience from what has
already happened in the past: so wisdom surveys the
three parts of time, and consequently knowledge falls
under the triad.33
32
166
So it is that one, two, three outlines the process of
the one becoming the many. But what about the fourth? How
does it complete this process?
The Tetrad. It is Iamblichus who answers this question,
again most succinctly. "Everything in the universe turns out
to be completed in the natural progression up to the
tetrad."34 Thus the tetrad symbolizes completion both in its
form, representing, as it does, the structure of the
tetraktys, but also in its position in the sequence 1,2,3,4,
which itself, through the numerical symbolism of this
tradition, represents the sequential unfolding of creation
from unity through extension to the full range of
manifestation. Everything participates in this process,
Iamblichus tells us, everything "in general and in
particular, as does everything numericalin short,
everything whatever its nature."35 He continues:
The fact that the decad, which is gnomon and joiner, is
consummated by the tetrad along with the numbers which
precede it, is special and particularly important for
the harmony which completion brings; so is the fact
that it provides the limit of corporeality and threedimensionality. For the pyramid, which is the minimal
solid and the one which first appears, is obviously
contained by a tetrad, either of angles or of faces,
just as what is perceptible as a result of matter and
34
35
Ibid.
167
form, which is a complete result in three dimensions,
exists in four terms.36
Here Iamblichus provides double significance to the
first three numbers and their completion through the fourth.
Within the realm of arithmetic, the symbolism of these
numbers suggests the process of creation and evolution by
virtue of the original unity, the monad, dividing within
itself to produce the dyad, thus providing the impetus to
move forward in the creation of the first real number, the
triad, which represents all processes in nature that have a
beginning, a middle and an end. The process finds its
fulfillment in the tetrad, which represents the full value
of the created world, the principle of soul and justice. The
combination of the first four numbers, 1+2+3+4, add up to
the most perfect number of all, the decad, the number of
Nature itself. And in its manifestation as the tetractys,
this symbol of fullness or completion was regarded as so
holy that members of the Pythagorean brotherhood would swear
the most solemn of oaths on the "holy Tetractys."
I swear by the discoverer of the Tetraktys,
Which is the spring of all our wisdom,
The perennial root of Nature's fount.37
Ibid.
Iamblichus, in Guthrie, p. 98.
168
The second element mentioned by Iamblichus, in his
description of the qualities of the Tetrad, deals with the
structure of the Quadrivium; he mentions several four-fold
groupings, the four seasons, the four elements, etc., and
also includes the four branches of mathematics and their
significance.
Moreover, it is better and less liable to error to
apprehend the truth in things and to gain secure,
scientific knowledge by means of the quadrivium of
mathematical sciences. For since all things in general
are subject to quantity when they are juxtaposed and
heaped together as discrete things, and are subject to
size when they are combined and continuous, and since
in terms of quantity, things are conceived as either
absolute or relative, and, in terms of size, either at
rest or in motion, accordingly the four mathematical
systems or sciences will make their respective
apprehensions in a manner appropriate to each thing:
arithmetic apprehends quantity in general, but
especially absolute quantity; music apprehends quantity
when it is relative; and geometry apprehends size in
general, but especially static size; astronomy
apprehends size when it is in motion and undergoing
orderly change.38
Following through with Iamblichus' recommendation, we should
consider the next discipline within the quadriviummusic,
or harmonics.
169
Music
Music is of fundamental important to Pythagorean
thought, not only for its practical applications but even
more for its symbolic significance, such as, for example,
the process of unlocking the meaning of one, two, three,
four. These express the basic relationships used in music,
the perfect consonances.
1:2
octave
2:3
fifth
3:4
fourth
39
Heninger, p. 95.
170
171
Thus Pythagoras' findings in his earliest musical
experiments dovetail perfectly with the whole realm of
symbolism inherent in Arithmetic.
There is another level to the symbolism/ however. We
have seen that lamblichus defines music as the branch of the
quadrivium that deals with quantity when it is relative/ as
opposed to arithmetic/ which deals with quantity in and of
itself. Thus/ the Theology
of Arithmetic
defines the
40
NicomachuS/ Encheiridion
harmoniks,
trans, with
commentary by Flora Levin as The Manual of Harmonics
Rapids/ Michigan: Phanes Press, 1994).
41
(Grand
BoethiuS/ De institutione
musica, trans, by Calvin M.
Bower as The Fundamentals of Music, Claude V. Paliscaf ed.
(New Haven & London: Yale University Press, 1989).
172
The Octave. The primary example is the 2:1
relationship. Seen in arithmetical terms, there is a great
deal of information contained in this ratio, as we have seen
in our examination of the monad and the dyad. The monad has
the quality of wholeness, the primal unity at the basis of
creation. The dyad represents diversity, inequality,
divisibility. The relationship between them symbolizes the
mystery of the One becoming the Many. From a musical
perspective there is something more, however. 2:1 is the
ratio of the musical octave, the most fundamental
relationship in music. If we hear two tones, one after the
other, where one is twice the frequency of the first,
something extraordinary occurs. We perceive them both as the
same and as different.
Fitch, Note and Tone. To help understand this
phenomenon, music theorist Gary Peacock42 suggests using
three different terms to describe each musical sound: pitch,
note and tone. The pitch is a simple physical phenomenon,
the number of vibrations per second. Secondly, the note is
the name we give to it, using letter names. Thus the
vibration rate of 440 cycles per second is given the note
name A. The concept of tone is more abstract, however. It
corresponds to what Victor Zuckerkandl has called the
42
173
"dynamic quality of tone,"43 a term that denotes the degree
of tension or resolution exhibited by each note within a
tonal system, rather than the more common musical usage of
degrees of volume from piano
to forte.
that.
If we
43
174
. . ;" Zuckerkandl writes; "after 5 it is an advance toward
. . . ; 5 is the turning point."44 All tones point back
toward the 1 until the 5th tone is reached. After that,
however, something remarkable happens. The final tones in
the sequence, those subsequent to 5, no longer point back
toward 1. They no longer give the sensation of wanting to
return to the origin. They now point toward 8. They have the
dynamic sense of wanting to resolve toward the eighth tone.
When the eighth tone is reached, however, another remarkable
sensation is found. The eighth tone has the same quality as
the first. The pitch is different, but it is the same note.
The scale starts on C and ends on C. It is also, in
Peacock's terminology, the same toneit has the same
dynamic quality.
All of this seems obvious, even trivial, to a musician
or music theorist. Yet, as Zuckerkandl painstakingly brings
out, there is a great mystery in this experience.
This is the phenomenon that has fittingly been
called "the miracle of the octave"; Ernst Kurth
characterizes it as "one of the greatest riddles . . .
the beginning of irrationality in music, a thing
unparalleled in all the rest of the phenomenal
world."45
44
Zuckerkandl, p. 97.
45
Zuckerkandl, p. 102.
175
Of course, all tonal and modal music is built out of the
tensions and releases inherent in the dynamic qualities of
tones and the particular sequence of the scale. But when we
return to the field of cosmology, we find that the miracle
of the octave gives further meaning to Plators symbolism.
This is inherent in the sequence of one, two, three and
four.
For generations of Pythagorean theorists throughout the
Middle Ages and at least until the seventeenth century, the
musical relationships among these numbers were discerned
through the use of the monochord, a process of dividing a
string. Since the time of Joseph Sauveur (1653-1716), the
discovery of the harmonic overtone series has revealed all
of the same relationships occurring simultaneously within a
vibrating string or air column. In each case the sequence of
sounds reveals the same properties. The 2:1 ratio of the
octave is revealed through the first division of the string.
This relationship outlines the scale and gives it the sense
of leaving and returning. It gains the name of octave from
the eight notes in the scale, but this is a misleading term.
More revealing is the Greek nomenclature, the diapason.
The
176
Thus, ianaacv means "the total extent of a continuum."46
When we hear the 2:1 relationship, apart from the remarkable
sensation of sameness coupled with difference, we also gain
the sense of the outline of a tonal space, a space that has
been created by its boundaries, its beginning, 1, and its
end, 2, a sense that is confirmed and reinforced when this
relationship is heard in the context of, or as the boundary
conditions of, a musical scale.
In evaluating the significance of this interval,
Siegmund Levarie and Ernst Levy focus on the number 2. "What
is the relationship of the number
x %
46
47
177
which all problems arise and within which they demand a
resolution.46
James Haar agrees with this analysis: "Pythagoras must have
identified the structure of the universe with his most
perfect consonance, the octave. . . . "4? It follows that
Plato can discuss the structure of the world and its soul in
terms of the arrangement of relationships within the
boundaries of the octave, as a musical scale. The same
relationship is hinted at in the discipline of arithmetic,
in the nature of the monad and the dyad. But to fully
understand the relationship
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 ... etc.
48
49
Haar, p. 76.
178
Its only logical conclusion is at infinity, in the sense of
the uncountably large, signified in set theory as the Hebrew
letter aleph, N.
If we consider the same sequence in terms of the
harmonic overtone series, it has a profoundly different
structure. The 2:1 relationship and its characteristic of
closure is repeated at every power of two. Rather than an
open-ended structure extending to infinity, we have a series
of cycles whose nature is defined in the first manifestation
of 1:2, and which then repeats itself indefinitely, with
more and more information being unfolded with each
repetition, thus:
2
4
3
5
4
7
8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 . . .
The first cycle, which is nothing but the first two numbers,
1 and 2, presents no qualities of creation itselfonly the
boundary conditions within which creation can occur, the
process of unity reproducing itself with a value essentially
identical to itself. Thus, the qualities of unity,
diversity, and the relationship between them are all
179
contained within this relationship. We could argue that all
these qualities are also contained within the number 1
itself because it must exemplify the quality of unity. Yet,
in traditional cosmologies, unity contains within itself all
the values of multiplicity:
Traditional arithmetic conceives of numbers as so many
elements of multiplicity which somehow never leave
Unity. It sees arithmetic as applied metaphysics and at
the same time as the quantitative aspect of a reality
whose qualitative aspect is revealed in music.50
When we move to the second cycle of the series, the
next iteration of the 2:1 relationship, we find it in the
ratio of 2:4. This time, however, there is additional
information contained in the cycle, the number three. As
soon as we hear the third partial it is clear that this a
qualitatively different experience from either the first or
second. This can also be seen arithmetically; while the
first two numbers exemplify the unique number one and the
first power of two, three is also a prime number and
therefore completely unique. The quality it presents to our
aural experience as the third partial is what the Greeks
called the diapente, translated as the fifth. It is the note
in the scale, as Zuckerkandl describes it, that represents
the dynamic mid-point, the farthest removed from the quality
50
180
of the tonic, before the ear starts to seek resolution in
moving on to the eighth note in the series rather than in
moving back to the first. We call it the dominant. The 3:2
relationship is the simplest ratio other than the octave,
the first real consonance.
Whatever qualities we attribute to the 3:2
relationship, the one of significance here is that it is the
first manifestation of any interval outside of the
generating tone or its octave. Thus, as in arithmetic, "the
triad causes the potential contained within the monad to
advance into the true expression of number," so the third
partial gives the first expression of the potential
contained in the fundamental. More and more of this
potential will be brought out in each successive cycle,
bounded by each power of 2.
According to the Pythagoreans, the Monad is the origin
of all things; similarly, the fundamental is the source of
all possible musical relationships. Within the first cycle
of manifestation we are introduced to the dyad in its
reflection of the monad. "With the dyad arises the duality
of subject and object, the knower and the known."51
In the second cycle we are presented with the Triad:
51
Guthrie, p. 22.
181
With the advent of the Triad, however, the gulf of
dualism is bridged, for it is through the third term
that a Relation or Harmonia (ujoining together") is
obtained between the two extremes. While Two represents
the first possibility
of logos, the relation of one
thing to52 another, the Triad achieves that relation in
actuality.
52
Ibid.
182
exception is the number 1, which, like the monad and the
fundamental, is qualitatively different from any other
number. After that, all octave, or diapason, repetitions are
found in the powers of two. The first number in the sequence
that has a distinctly different quality from either 1 or 2,
the fundamental or its first octave repetition, is 3, the
next prime. The significance of this number is seen in the
2:3 ratiothe perfect fifthand beyond that in the general
principle of the progressive emergence of changing values
out of the fundamental source, the number 1. The same
quality is found in all the reiterations of the power of
three, 4:6, 8:12 and so on.
Taken together, therefore, the numbers 1, 2, 3 embody
the basic ontological principles of creation and evolution,
from unity to diversity, that Plato's discourse is devoted
to describing. And the number 4 provides completion to this
first fully manifest reiteration of the cycle. This is true
in the area of number, but when manifest in the field of
harmonics, a theoretical value is made available directly to
the senses. Furthermore, the harmonic series is structured
in such a way that all subsequent cycles are summed up in
the qualities heard in 1,2,3, and completed in 4.
183
Gregor
1503
184
Geometry
Inquiring into the nature of one, two and three
inevitably leads to the consideration of geometry. For just
as three, either as a number or a musical interval,
symbolizes relativity emerging out of the unmanifest values
of unity via duality, so geometry, as the third branch of
the quadrivium,
53
185
superficial manner in all the mysteries of the Gods."54
Indeed/ evidence is emerging that geometry had cosmological/
as well as practical application in ancient Egypt.55
Pythagoras is said to have used this knowledge to create the
foundations of what has come to be called sacred geometry.
Having mastered the practical applications of geometry,
Pythagoras transformed it into a form of philosophical
inquiry/ examining its principles from the beginning and
applying its theorems to immaterial and conceptual realms.
"Whatever Pythagoras received/ however/ he developed
further, he arranged them for learners/ and personally
demonstrated them with perspicuity and elegance."56
Whatever its original sources, a tradition of sacred
geometry has existed for centuries/ one in which cosmology
blends with more practical concerns. "The principles that
underlie disciplines such as geomancy,57 sacred geometry/
magic or electronics/" according to Nigel Pennick/ "are
54
55
186
fundamentally linked with the nature of the universe."56
Thus, as Robert Lawlor explains, the foundations of the
discipline are bound up with the task of the physical
representation of cosmological principles:
Those who use geometric figures to describe the
beginning of Creation must attempt to show how an
absolute Unity can become multiplicity and diversity.
Geometry attempts to recapture the orderly movement
from an infinite formlessness to an endless
interconnected array of forms, and in recreating this
mysterious passage from One to Two, it renders it
symbolically visible.59
Lawlor's statement places geometry in line with
arithmetic and music, presenting the same cosmology in a
different, though related, symbolic form. The world is seen
as emanating from an underlying unity and progressing into
multiple forms of creation. The mechanics of this process
reflect the same understanding about the nature of the monad
derived from arithmetic.
From both the metaphysical and natural points of
view it is false to say that in order to arrive at two,
you take two ones and put them together. One only need
look at the way in which a living cell becomes two. For
One by definition is singular, it is Unity, therefore
all inclusive. There cannot be two Ones. Unity, as the
perfect symbol for God, divides itself from within
58
in
Practice
187
itself, thus creating Two: the "self" and the "me" of
God, so to speak; the creator unity and the created
multiplicity.60
In the field of geometry, however, there is more than
one way of representing this process. "Unity creates by
dividing itself, and this can be symbolized geometrically in
several different ways, depending upon how the original
Unity is graphically represented."61 Lawlor includes an
example of Japanese Zen calligraphy that shows the process
of creation as a progression from the Unity of the circle,
through the triangle, to the manifest form of the square.
(See fig. 23.) There are other versions of this process, but
the figures of circle and square appear repeatedly. "Unity
can be appropriately represented as a circle," Lawlor
writes, "but the very incommensurability of the circle
indicates that this figure belongs to a level of symbols
beyond reasoning and measure."62 This is evocative of the
nature of the monad, an original form that stands before
other forms, in this case manifesting as the irrational
number n that emerges from any attempt to measure the
circle. He continues: "Unity can be restated as the square,
which with its perfect symmetry, also represents wholeness,
60
Ibid.
61
Ibid.
62
Ibid.
188
189
and yields to comprehensible measure"63 (although the square
mirrors the incommensurable in the value of its diagonal,
the irrational >/2) . Once again, it is significant that,
however it is represented, the intermediary stage between
original Unity and the fullness of the manifest world is an
important step and cannot be omitted. In arithmetic it is
the dyad, in music the second partial. "In geometrical
philosophy the circle is the symbol of unmanifest Unity,
while the square represents Unity poised, as it were, for
manifestation."64 John Michell has a similar analysis of
these two figures:
The first figure of sacred geometry is the circle,
whose circumference has neither beginning nor end and
is therefore the geometer's image of entirety and
eternity. As the simplest and most self-sufficient of
space-enclosing shapes, and the matrix of all others,
it is the natural symbol of that unique living
creature, the cosmos.65
His view of the square is slightly different, seeing it as
an opposite rather than an alternative form:
The symbolic opposite of the circle is the square.
Whereas the circle represents the unknowable, spirit
and the heavens, the square is material and of the
63
Ibid.
64
Ibid.
65
190
earth. The ratio between its width and its perimeter,
instead of being the irrational n as in the case of the
circle, is simply and rationally 4. The circle and the
square, made commensurable with equal perimeters, form
a diagram of the fusion of matter and spirit and
together illustrate human nature and the nature of the
universe.66
The same reconciliation of opposites, or completion of
the world, seen in the tetrad and the octave reiterations of
the tone sequence can also be depicted through geometric
forms. "The object of sacred geometry being to depict that
fusion of opposites, the squared circle is therefore its
first symbol. Temples and cosmological cities throughout
antiquity were founded on its proportions."67 Heninger
expands upon this idea:
In essence, the problem of squaring the circle is
a geometrical formulation of the incongruity between
the world of concept and the world of matter. As a
geometrical figure, a circle has certain properties
which set it apart from all other forms: it has no
beginning or end, every point on its circumference is
equidistant from the center, and its circumference
considered as linear distance encloses a maximum area.
It, like the point and the monad, represents unified
perfection, and therefore infinity and eternity and
deity. The circle emblematizes the conceptual world.
God himself had long been described as a circle (with
center everywhere and circumference nowhere). In
contrast to the circle, the square has a finite number
of sides. Moreover, in Pythagorean terms the square is
the number 4, which in turn represents the physical
universe because a minimum of four points is required
66
Ibid.
67
191
for three-dimensional extension. The square
emblematizes the material world.68
Heninger makes a telling comparison between the
symbolism of geometry and that of arithmetic. The circle has
the same qualities of unity as the monad; the triangle's
symbolism mirrors that of the triad. Similar parallels exist
with the fundamental and the third partial in music. Before
we can equate the square with the tetrad, however, we have
to go one step further by reconciling two opposing values,
because the square represents the physical world.
Any attempt to change a circle to a square therefore
involves reducing the infinite to the finite, involves
transmuting the divine to the physical . . Conversely,
any attempt to circularize a squarefor example, by
increasing its sides an infinite number of times
becomes an effort to make continuous what is
discontinuous, an effort to raise the physical to the
level of perfection. The problem of squaring the
circle, then, crosses the boundary between the abstract
conceptual world and the measurable space-time
continuum.69
It may be inferred from this that the solution of how
to square the circle, however avidly it was pursued from
antiquity until as late as the sixteenth century, had little
practical application for construction or engineering.
Rather, it was a kind of holy grail of geometry, whose
68
Heninger, p. 111.
69
Ibid.
192
193
purpose was purely for the edification of the individual.
And not merely intellectual edificationits solution was
always linked with some esoteric or alchemical practice the
purpose of which was the spiritual advancement of the
individual. This is very much in line with the Platonic and
Pythagorean view of geometry. Speaking of geometry in the
Republic,
Plato comments:
70
Republic,
526d-e, Desmond Lee, trans. (London: Penguin
Books, 1974), p. 334.
71
Commentary on Euclid,
Book I, in Thomas, Greek
Mathematics,
pp. 175-177. Cf. Plato, Republic,
526D-527C
(above).
194
diversity of creation. With the introduction of the idea of
squaring the circle a new dimension is addedthe
reconciliation of the opposite values that inevitably
follow. And both Plato and Proclus indicate that the result
will be the upliftment of the soulan experience beyond
what should normally be expected from studying mathematics.
This idea is also of significance in considering the field
of astronomy.
Astronomy
As part of the quadrivium, astronomy has been defined
as the study of spatial relationships in motion, a concept
quite different from the modern understanding of this field.
We will see the influence of this idea when we examine
Plato's cosmology in the Timaeus.
72
Gregor
1503
"Reasons" = logoi,
productive principles, ratios,
patterns, etc. (Guthrie's footnote)
74
75
197
biographers do not have much to say on this subject. The
best source we do have is Aristotle. Even though he is
highly skeptical about the Pythagorean viewpoint/ we can
learn a good deal about it from him. It is interesting, for
example, that he describes the fundamental principle
underlying Pythagorean cosmology not in the De Caelo,
the Metaphysics.
but in
76
77
198
According to Aristotle, the aesthetic component of
kosmos appears to have been the dominant factor for
Pythagoras in working out cosmological details, and this
component is derived from the properties of numbers. It
appears that these properties can be elaborated following
the sequence inherent in the quadrivium, with the principles
of arithmetic providing the foundation for the subsequent
mathematical disciplines. This relationship is clarified by
the second-century writer Nicomachus of Geresa, a key figure
in the history of mathematics and the Pythagorean tradition.
In his own day and for generations thereafter,
Nicomachus seems to have been to arithmetic what Euclid
was to geometry. Indeed, it was even said of
Nicomachus: Aritmeticam
Samius Pythagoras
invenit,
Nicomachus scripsit
(Pythagoras of Samos invented
arithmetic, Nicomachus composed it) .78
In his Arithmetike
eisagoge
(Introduction to Arithmetic),
199
as a design and archetypal example the creator of the
universe sets in order his material creations and makes
them attain to their proper ends. . .7?
Given such a hierarchy within the quadrivium, it is the
Theology
of Arithmetic
79
200
toward closure indicated by the cosmology of one, two,
three, four; the inherent perfection of both the tetrad and
the decad allow for the former to be the source of
perfection in the musical scale, while the decad has to be
invoked to account for the perfection of the more complex
structure of the physical universe. The relationship between
the two numbers allows for a relationship to be developed
between these two structures, the scale and the planets.
Herein lies the origin of the music of the spheres
tradition. By the time of Nicomachus, at least, this
cosmology is expanded through the establishment of
relationships between planets and musical notes. In his
Manual of Harmonics,
were derived from the seven stars which traverse the heavens
and travel around the earth."80 The explanation he gives
stems from a mixture of second-century astronomy and
physics:
For they say that all swiftly whirling bodies
necessarily produce sounds when something gives way to
them and is very easily vibrated; and that these sounds
differ from one another in magnitude and in region of
the voice either because of the position in which the
motion of each is accomplished, these positions being
more subject to fluctuation or, conversely, more
resistant. These three differences are clearly observed
in the case of the planets, which differ from one
another in size and speed and position as they whir
with its
Ibid.
of Western
Philosophy
is entitled "The
of Western
85
86
204
with this viewpoint if we are trying to build a more
complete perspective on history. A number of scholars
support this view. Charles Bakewell writes:
It is customary to speak of Greek philosophy as ancient
philosophy. This is quite misleading. It is evident of
our inveterate temporal provincialism. For there is a
provincialism that comes from isolation in time which
can prove a more formidable obstacle to understanding
than that which comes from isolation in space. . .
The fact is that viewed in the true perspective of
time Socrates lived but yesterday. . . It would be far
more accurate to regard the Greeks as having written
the first chapters in modern philosophy. Greek
philosophy is our own philosophy, and science, in its
beginning.*8
Greek philosophy did not appear out of nowhere; it must
have its own sources. Greek thought is better understood
when these sources, as well as parallel developments
elsewhere, are given due consideration. Philosopher Antonio
T. de Nicolas agrees that omitting such considerations
provides a uformidable obstacle to understanding":
. . by returning to Greece as the origin of Western
man, what Western man does is to draw an imaginary line
between himself and the rest of humanity. By acting
thus, all he does is reinforce the controls of his
present cultural isolation and sickness. "The whole of
Western philosophy," Whitehead said, "is just a
footnote to Plato." But what hardly anyone has bothered
to find out is how Plato himself is a footnote to
previous cultures; for neither Plato nor Greece are
88
Charles
Culture,"
and World
1963), p.
205
absolute beginnings for Western man and Western
culture. Underlying them there is still man, the maker
of cultures and ideas of man."
There can be no doubt that the Greek contribution was a
unique one, but one that planted a seed in an already
fertile field. "Much of what makes civilization had already
existed for thousands of years in Egypt and Mesopotamia,"
writes Bertrand Russell, "and had spread thence to
neighbouring countries. But certain elements had been
lacking until the Greeks supplied them."90 It is when we ask
what it is that the Greeks supplied that a certain prejudice
becomes evident. It emerges more clearly when Russell speaks
of Pythagoras; while he agrees that Pythagoras ". . . was
intellectually one of the most important men who ever
lived,"91 he cannot resist adding, "both when he was wise
and when he was unwise."9: Russell presumably justifies this
statement with his next, "Mathematics, in the sense of
demonstrative deductive argument, begins with him, and in
89
Russell, p. 3.
91
Russell, p. 29.
92
Ibid.
206
him is intimately connected with a peculiar
mysticism."
form of
(Russell's italics.)93
93
Ibid.
207
essential to this study. Nevertheless, our concern is to
strive for some balance between these views, and thus to
avoid falling into the errors to which both extremes are
prone. Cornford expresses a similar view in his essay on the
music of the spheres. Speaking of Pythagoras and his view of
number, he warns against a partial vision of ancient
thought:
. . . \A11 things are number.' That is the barest
extract; the words, just in themselves mean little, and
that little might be understood, while the feeling is
neglected. The man of science, tracing from its source
in that formula the main stream of mathematical
physics, will be inclined to take the formula as
preserving the only element of truth and value in
Pythagoras' system, and to discard the harmony of the
soul and of the spheres as so much dross. For the man
of religion, on the other hand, the scientific
statement will have no interest; he will find his
profit in the recognition that the soul is immortal and
may achieve perfection by becoming attuned to some
divine principle in the universe. Pythagoras would say
to both: What is your warrant for valuing one part of
my experience and rejecting the rest? One of you will
listen only to the head, and the other only to the
heart. If I had done so, you would never have heard my
name. It may be that nothing I taught is true in the
letter: but if any part is true in the spirit, then the
whole is true. Seek truth and beauty together; you will
never find them apart. With the Angel of Truth your
mind may wrestle, like Jacob:'I will not let thee go
except thou bless me'; but Beauty is the Angel of
Annunciation, before whom the soul must be still as a
handmaid:'Be it unto me according to thy word.'94
94
208
In spite of the admonitions of such a respected scholar
as Cornford, it is ironic that a philosophical mind such as
Russell sees fit to judge the work of Pythagoras and Plato
on the basis of an assumption that Plato himself takes great
pains to deny: that discursive thought, along with empirical
testing, are the only proper criteria of knowledgemerely
because they are the basis of the scientific method. Thus
Greek philosophers are to be judged favorably to the extent
that they are scientific in their thinking.
By contrast, Russell's colleague Alfred North
Whitehead, even as he delves deeply into the history of
science, is capable of a more balanced view. Speaking of the
Ionian school of philosophy, whose ideas have been conveyed
to us through Plato and Aristotle, he writes that
. ..
it
was better."
(Author's italics.)95
209
is clear, however, with regard to the music of the spheres
tradition, that an element of mysticism is at the root of
this phenomenon, and that to understand it fully we cannot
flinch from dealing with mystical or otherwise esoteric
material. We have already quoted Joscelyn Godwin's statement
that "the subject of esotericism is so new to humanistic
scholarship that no conventions yet exist for its
treatment."9* From what we have already learned, however, it
seems that it will be necessary to move beyond this
limitation in order to understand our topic more completely.
Historical Links
It is in this context that we must examine the sources
from which both Pythagoras and Plato derived, or inherited,
their ideas. We have mentioned the legends surrounding
Pythagoras' travels and studies in Egypt and elsewhere,
citing Manly Hall that "he visited many countries and
studied at the feet of many masters."97 And Plato mentions
Solon's travels in Egypt, where the Greeks were regarded as
a very immature race.
96
97
210
It would take an extensive study to explore all the
points of contact between the Greeks and more ancient
civilizations. Two things come to our aid, however. First,
it is the view of James that "there is good reason to
suppose that in earliest antiquity there existed an
intellectual continuum stretching throughout Asia, even into
China, and that the wall between East and West was erected
at a later date."98 Such a notion receives some support from
musicological studies. Albert von Thimus' Die
Symbolik
des Alterthums"
harmonikale
98
James, p. 26.
99
100
Builder:
Druid
(Edinburgh: Floris
211
This still does not explain the reason for these
parallels and whether there was contact among these various
traditions.
China
212
was known in China prior to its discovery in Greece,101 but
it is hard to establish clear historical links between the
two civilizations. Yet there are distinct and sometimes
striking similarities in their cosmologies. For example,
having seen the multiple levels of meaning associated with
the first four numbers in Pythagorean lore, consider the
following from the Tao Teh Ching:
Tao gave birth to One
One gave birth to Two
Two gave birth to Three
Three gave birth to all myriad things.102
Levy and Levarie expand on this:
Lao-Tse, around 600 B.C., wrote in China: "One has
produced Two, Two has produced Three." One of the
commentators adds: nThese words mean that One has been
divided into Yin, the female principle, and Yang, the
male principle. These two have joined and out of their
conjunction came (as a Third) Harmony. The spirit of
Harmony, condensing, has produced all beings."103
The parallels with the Pythagorean cosmology outlined
above are striking but they do not end there. In both cases
the cosmos is seen as a holistic and orderly continuum in
101
213
which music is an important component. In the case of the
Chinese, this view developed during the Han Dynasty of 206
B.C.E-220 C.E. Its approach mirrors the universal patterns
common to traditional cosmologies, although with a
distinctively Chinese character. To quote Derk Bodde:
The Universe, according to this view, is a harmoniously
functioning organism consisting of multitudinous
objects, qualities and forces which, despite their
seeming heterogeneity, are integrated into coherent
patterns by being subsumed under one or another of many
numerical categories. (The best known such category, of
course, is that in sets of fives, such as the five
elements, five directions, five colors, etc.) Among
items belonging to a common category, a particular
affinity exists between those having the same relative
position within their respective sequences . . .1Q4
The range of these correspondences can be seen at fig.
26. Among these categories we will find the five planets,
Jupiter, Mars, Saturn, Venus, Mercury, and the five notes
known as Chueh, Chih, Kung, Shang, and
Yu. These
104
214
Category
Wood
Fire
Earth
Metal
Water
Calendar
Chia 1
Ping 3
Wu 5
Keng 7
Jen 9
Sicms
Ting 4
Chi 6
Hsin 8
Kuei 10
Seasons
Spring
Summer
Between
Autumn
Winter
Directions
East
South
Center
West
North
Emperors
Fu-hsi
Shen-nung Huang Ti
Shao-hao
Chuan-hsu
Political
Structure
Musical
Tones
People
Chueh
Affairs
King
of Country
Chih
Kung
Ministers Natural
World
Shang
Yu
Planets
Jupiter
Mars
Saturn
Venus
Mercury
Tastes
Sour
Bitter
Sweet
Salt
Acrid
Internal
Organs
Liver
Heart
Spleen
Lung
Kidney
(Alternate
Order)
Spleen
Lung
Heart
Liver
Kidney
Colors
Virid
Red
Yellow
White
Black
Human
Faculties
Demeanor
Speech
Vision
Hearing
Thought
Virtues
Charity
Courtesy
Wisdom
Justice
Fidelity
Creatures
Feathered Hairy
Fleshed
Shelled
Scaly
Creatures Creatures Creatures Creatures Creatures
(Humans)
Domestic
Animals
Fowl
Fig. 26 -
Pig
Cow
Sheep
Horse
215
It is evident that such correlations not only cut
across the usual categories of time and space, the
abstract and the concrete, but also bridge the apparent
gap between the human and the natural worlds. These two
worlds, in fact, actually merge to form a single
continuum, the halves of which are so closely
interwoven that the slightest pull or strain on the one
spontaneously induces corresponding pull or strain on
the other. A primary function of the ruler is to
prevent or relieve such pulls and strains by the
correct performance of periodic rituals designed to
reinforce the normal affinities between the two
halves.105
If we examine this statement carefully, we will see two
main themes appearing. The first of these is the importance
of numerical symbolism. The second is the relationship
between the human and the natural worlds. Both ideas arise
out of the perception of the universe as a single,
harmoniously functioning organism, and both are essential
features of Chinese thought since the earliest times. To a
large degree, the history of Chinese thought has been a
perpetual dialectical process within which these two main
themes both rival and complement each other. As Fritjof
Capra puts it:
The Chinese sage . . . does not dwell exclusively on
this high spiritual plane, but is equally concerned
with worldly affairs. He unifies in himself the two
complementary sides of human natureintuitive wisdom
and practical knowledge, contemplation and social
actionwhich the Chinese have associated with the
images of the sage and the king. Fully realized human
105
Ibid.
216
beings, in the words of Chuang-Tzu, "by their stillness
become sages, by their movement kings."106
a table harp or
the
ch'un-
is from Clack:
The Emperor desired to base all the other sciences on
music, but owing to its chaotic state that was
107
108
218
impossible until it had been thoroughly systematized.
Accordingly he ordered Ling Lun, one of his ablest
Ministers, who was also an enthusiastic musician, to
retire to the mountains and remain there in seclusion
until he had found a solution to the problem.110
The mythical nature of this narrative is revealed in the
name Ling Lun itself, as ling
Clack, p . 6.
111
Picken, p . 94.
112
Ibid.
113
Ibid.
219
five other notes. The female phoenix's song added six more
notes at a higher pitch. The minister quickly cut more
bamboo pipes corresponding to these twelve notes. "And when
Ling Lun started to compare his pipes he found that if he
arranged them according to pitch the length of each pipe was
exactly two-thirds that of the one giving the next lower
tone."114 Ling Lun's pipes were all arranged at intervals of
a perfect fifth. The 2:3 ratio had a cosmological
significance as well as a musical one for the Chinese,
however. It follows from Lao Tze's Pythagorean statement and
is described in the Book of Rites: "Since three is the
number of Heaven, and two that of the Earth, sounds in the
ratio of two to three will harmonize as perfectly as do
Heaven and Earth."115
The result was that the pitch pipes, when perfected,
not only formed the basis of the correct musical scale but
also of standards of measurement in other fields such as
length, weight, and capacity. Through the relationship of
music with the months of the year, the pitch pipes were
linked with calendrical calculations and were even used as
instruments to measure and observe the cosmic movements of
Yin and Yang in their manifestation as Ch'i,
114
Clack, p .
115
Ibid.
7.
or ether.
220
The development of the scale in China that followed
from this discovery has been well documented.116 It is not
necessary to reiterate its details here as our concern is
with its cosmological underpinnings. Suffice it to say that
cosmology continued to play a role in the process. The
adherence to the numbers 1, 2, 3 & 4, because of their
cosmological significance, caused the Chinese theorists to
continue the process of generating ascending fifths and
descending fourths past twelve iterations until a complete
series of sixty-six had been reached. A distinct problem
revealed itself at the twelfth step, however, as the Chinese
discovered what was to become known as the Pythagorean
comma, the discrepancy between twelve fifths and seven
octaves for which they sought practical solutions for
centuries.117 But cosmological and other purely theoretical
considerations ran parallel with the practical concerns of
music making for a similarly extended period.
The liuhleu
(66) (the complete note series) was not a
"chromatic scale, " but an array of all the notes in the
Chinese musical firmament of the third century B.C. The
process of generation described in the writings of Leu
Buhwei presumably provided an approximate theory,
116
221
satisfying the desire for order of those engaged at
that time in systematizing the sum total of human
knowledge.118
The cosmological associations upon which the ancient Chinese
theorists drew in the development of their music theory
extended into every area of concern, including the
fundamental qualities of yin and yang,
Picken, p .
119
See D a n i e l o u
95.
(1995), pp. 30-33.
222
divisions of the book of odes) to guide it. They caused
its music to be joyful, not degenerate, and its beauty
to be distinct and not limited. They caused it in its
indirect and direct appeals, its complexity and its
simplicity, its frugality and richness, its rests and
notes, to stir up the goodness in men's minds and to
prevent evil feelings from gaining a foothold. This is
the manner in which the early kings established
music.120
Thus we can see that, in ancient China, music was
afforded a place of great significance both in its
theoretical aspect, as the basis for much proto-scientific
thought, and, in performance, as the basis for the moral
order of the state and even of the universe. All this stems
from the underlying cosmology, one that parallels
Pythagoras' in a number of ways, even though it is expressed
in a very different form. We can now go on to see the same
essential cosmology given yet another form of expression by
the ancient Vedic tradition of India.
India
India more readily exhibits cultural links with Greece
than does China. Indeed, in Chapter V we will discuss
parallels between Platonic thought and the Vedic tradition
of India. Several other writers have commented on this
120
and the
Upanishads,
224
Dionysos, claim that the origin of music is almost
entirely Asiatic. Thus, one of them, speaking of the
lyre, will say: the strings of the cithara of Asia
resound."
Megasthenes (quoted by Arrian in his Indika, VII,
8, written in 150 B.C.) tell us that Dionysos "taught
the Indians to worship the other Gods and himself by
playing cymbals and drums; he also taught them the
satyr dance which the Greeks call kordax."
This is because they are, of all peoples, the
greatest lovers of music and have practiced dancing
with great love since the days when Bacchus and his
companions led their bacchanalia in the land of India."
(Arrian: Anabasis of Alexander VI, 3, 10.)lz-
Indian
Music
Sama,
Yajur,
(New York:
225
and Atharva.
226
On the surface, the Vedic literature seems to have
little connection with Greek thought. Yet it contains an
expression of the same cosmological view contained in the 1,
2, 3, 4 of Pythagorean symbolism; only the medium is
different. Instead of number it is expressed in soundthe
root sounds of the Sanskrit language.
It is the greatest understatement to say that the Rg
Vedic methodology draws its main clue to interiorizing
all perception, the whole sensorium, from sound. Rg
Vedic man was enveloped by sound; surrounded and
excited by sound; made aware of presences by sound;
looked for centers of experience in the experience of
sound; found the model of complete, absolute
instantaneity and communication in sound.116
The specific aspects of sound most relevant to the
Vedas, and the subsequent Hindu tradition, are language and
music; Hindu cosmology, for example, is truly a musical one.
"According to Hindu mythology," writes Seyyed Hosein Nasr,
"the first art to have been revealed to mankind by iva was
music. The harmony of music is also the key to the
understanding of the universe, which is structured upon
musical harmony."127 David Reck writes:
In India, it is said, the universe hangs on sound. Not
ordinary sound, but a cosmic vibration so massive and
subtle and all-encompassing that everything seen and
126
de Nicolas, p. 50.
127
129
Ibid.
228
F i g . 27: Saraswati
230
Both of these scholars agree that the symbolism
contained in the word hinges on the interpretation of the
ideas of movement, or flow, and the idea of a river, pool or
other body of water. Vedic scholar Maharishi Mahesh Yogi has
carried out a further parsing of this word in which he
introduces an additional element. To the first root sr
indicating motion or flow, Maharishi adds sva which refers
to the Self.134 From this perspective, therefore, Saraswati
represents the dynamic flow of the Self, and it is this
Self-referral value that places Saraswati at the heart of
Vedic knowledge. To appreciate why requires an examination
of
231
from the effects that it produces. The influence of
maya may be understood by the example of the sap
appearing as a tree. Every fibre of the tree is nothing
but the sap. Sap, while remaining sap, appears as the
tree. Likewise, through the influence of maya, Brahman,
remaining Brahman, appears as the manifested world.
On the individual level, Vedanta explains the
relationship of the absolute Self (atman) and the
relative aspect of individual life by the principle of
avidya. Avidya, or ignorance, is nothing but maya in a
coarser form. If maya can be likened to clear water,
then muddy water is avidya.
Under the influence of maya, Brahman appears as
Ishvara, the personal God, who exists on the celestial
level of life in the subtlest field of creation. In a
similar way, under the influence of avidya, Atman
appears as jiva,
or individual soul.135
The relationship between Atman and jiva
is given by
Ratnkara:
is part of the
135
232
Atman; it is only an illusion that they are separate. The
nature of Saraswati is revealed in the mechanics of the
process whereby Atman becomes jiva,
the text
137
233
this is superficial and tells us little. When we look more
deeply into it, and apply the same kind of analysis used to
unlock the meaning of Saraswati, a very different picture
emerges. What is described are the same mechanics of
creation symbolized as 1, 2, 3, 4, or monad, dyad, triad,
tetraktys.
When the first letter, A, is pronounced, it requires
the mouth and throat to be fully open, AAA . . . This
represents the fullness of the unmanifest, Brahman. The
unmanifest begins to manifest through the introduction of
the first boundary, represented by the letter G. When
articulated, the closure of G imposes itself on the full
openness of the sound A. A full stop is created as nonexistence imposes itself on the full value of Being. From
the imposition of this boundary, the full stream of
manifestation, or becoming, emerges and continues as
represented by the syllable Ni, another sound without
closure. The details of the process and the content of
manifestation and evolution are unfolded through the rest of
the verses of Rg Veda and commented upon by the rest of
Vedic literature.
There are musical parallels here, as well as numerical
ones, and Pythagoras would recognize them both. When a
string is set vibrating it produces the fundamental tone,
but when it is stopped, when one becomes two, three, etc.,
234
the potential note values inherent in the fundamental are
made manifest. A, G, Ni; monad, dyad, triad; C, C, G. And it
is interesting that the syllable Ni, which, as part of Agni,
represents the duality of A and G, uleading on" to the full
value of the manifest world, is also used to describe the
leading tone in Indian music, Sa, Re, Ga, Ma, Pa, Dha, Ni.
Mythological Symbolism. The Vedic tradition reiterates
the same information on multiple levels. An anthropomorphic,
or mythical, description of the same processes expressed in
A-G-NI is presented in terms of the Brahma, the creator. In
the beginning, Brahma is completely alone, without a second.
But then, the first boundary occurs within the unbounded
value of Brahma by virtue of the fact that he becomes aware
of one thinghimself. This act of awareness, even though it
was not of any object other than his own nature, turns the
unity of the Self into the trinity that is required for the
act of perception: the subject, the process of perception,
and the object, known in Sanskrit as Rishi,
Chhandas.138
Samhita,
and Chhandas.
138
Devata and
Devata
235
traditional arithmetic, where "elements of multiplicity . .
. somehow never leave Unity."139
The same structure, with further similarities to
Pythagorean symbolism, is described by the Sanskrit theory
of soundNda.
Ratnkara
Sanglta
musica in the
and anhata.
The
236
two forms, viz., the created and the uncreated, the
former being an object of sense perception and the
latter a matter of mystic experience of Yoga in which
sound and light are fused together and there is direct
perception.140
Danilou expands on this description:
In Indian musical theory, it is said that there are two
kinds of sound, one a vibration of ether the other a
vibration of air. The vibration of ether, which cannot
be perceived in the physical sense, is considered the
principle of all manifestation, the basis of all
substance. It corresponds to what the Neo-Pythagoreans
called the "Music of the Spheres." It forms permanent
numerical patterns which are the basis of the world's
existence. This kind of vibration is not caused by a
physical shock as are audible sounds. It is therefore
called "anahata" or "unstruck." The other kind of
sound is an impermanent vibration of air, an image of
the ether vibration. It is therefore called "ahata" or
"struck."141
What Danilou refers to here as "ether" is a
translation of the Sanskrit akasha.
nda,
or "unstruck" sound,
140
141
Danlilou (1969), p. 21
237
relationship between these two levels of sound is an
integral aspect of Indian music theory:
The sounds used in music are those whose mutual
relationships form an image of the basic laws of the
Universe as represented by the unstruck sounds. Thus
musical sounds have it in their power to reproduce the
first creation of the Primordial Intellect.142
Gandharva and Marqa. This definition results in a
highly elevated view of music and also one that provides
further parallels with the Pythagorean tradition.
Both of these aspects are found in a statement from the
music faculty at Maharishi International University:
Everyone finds a tremendous appeal in music because
music arises from so fundamental a source that it is
parallel to the structure of life and to that of the
cosmos as a whole. This is why Pythagoras wrote that
music and the universe of heavenly bodies are governed
by the same mathematical laws.143
The parallels are not restricted to the Vedic and
Pythagorean traditions; the same connection between
macrocosm and microcosm is found in Chinese thought, as we
have seen. It is, in fact, characteristic of most ancient
cosmological systems and lies at the heart of the "magical"
tradition. To illustrate it further, we can look at the
142
143
Danlielou(1969), p . 22.
238
mythologies surrounding Indian music and its origins. Reck
picks up the story after Shiva has created music and passed
it on to Saraswati:
In time the Himalayas, the abode of the gods, were
filled with joyful music making, drama, and dance. But
on earth civilization was in utter and hopeless
decline. People, bogged down in earthly desires,
sickness and death, bored with the four vedas, the holy
scriptures of Hinduism, begged the gods for something
to relieve them of their sorrows and hardships,
something to ornament their lives and turn their hearts
toward the sweet nectar of the gods. The god Brahma
meditated for a hundred thousand years and then decided
to give them music as a fifth Veda, equal to the
scriptures, a divine gift that contained the seeds of
both happiness on earth and the path to moksha,
ultimate release, supreme salvation. Bharata, a great
sage, wrote it all down in a gigantic manual, the
classic Natya sastra, and music has filled the Indian
subcontinent ever since. :44
It is said that Brahma took speech from the Rg Veda,
music from the Sama Veda, action from the Yajur Vedaf and
Rasa,
or Natya Shastra
Veda,
known as Gandharva
Reck, p. 7.
Ratnakara,
239
at Chapter I, verses 21c-24b, we find a critical definition
of
Sanglta:
Gltam (vocal melody), vdyam (playing on instruments)
and nrttam (dancing), all the three together are known
as sanglta which is twofold, viz. mrga and de. That
which was discovered by Brahma and (first) practiced by
Bharata and others in the audience of Lord iva is
known as mrga (sanglta),
which definitely bestows
prosperity; while the sanglta comprising gtam,
vdyam
and nrttam, that entertains people according to their
taste in different regions, is known as de. .:45
240
Ritual music must necessarily follow the rules
imposed by rnarga theory. This is why most of the rnarga
definitions are kept in the ritual that regulates the
singing of the Samaveda. On the other hand, the object
of del music is usually only pleasure or the
expression of human feelings and passions, so del
systems vary greatly from country to country and from
time to time. Their influence may be good or bad. All
modern musical systems are of this empirical and
unstable kind, and their relative value can be measured
only by comparing them with the permanent definitions
of the rnarga theory, which alone is based on absolute
laws.14"
Danielou concludes with a statement from the sixteenthcentury writer Rmmtya.
The music that is called gndharva
{rnarga) is
that which has been, from time immemorial, practiced by
the gndharvas and which leads surely to moksa
(liberation), while the gana {del) music is that which
has been invented by composers (vaggeyakaras), in
conformity with recognized rules, and which pleases
people. Gndharva music always follows the rules of
theory.147
It is for this reason, as William P. Malm points out, that
the Vedic hymns have been preserved for so many centuries:
In India the physical vibrations of musical sound
(Nada) have always been inextricably connected with the
spiritual and metaphysical world. As a result, the
intoned word has great power in its combination of
religious text and musical sound. Thus the correct
singing of a Vedic hymn is essential not only to the
146
Rmmtya, Svaramela-kalnidhi.
Sanskrit text and trans.
M.S. Ramaswami Aiyar (South India: Annamalai University,
1932), cited in Danilou (1995), p. 59.
147
Ibid.
241
validity of the ritual but also to the stability of the
universe.148
It is important to remember that these terms, mrga and
de,
148
150
therefore indicates a
gandharva
152
243
The Source of the Vedas. The antiquity of the Vedic
tradition raises the issue of its origins. The Vedas
themselves suggest an answer. At Rg Veda 1164.39, we find:
richo akshare par ante vyoman
yasmin deva adhi vishve
nisheda
Maharishi Mahesh Yogi translates this as:
The Richa (hymns of the Veda) reside in the
imperishable transcendental fieldpure awareness, pure
intelligence, pure consciousness, in which reside all
the impulses of creative intelligence.153
The implication here is that the hymns of the Vedas are not
composed as other literature or music are. Rather, they are
said to exist within
consciousness
itself,
nada.
Ibid., p. 196.
244
The same term, is used for the microtonal divisions of the
scale in Indian music. By contrast, commentaries on the
Vedas, and other aspects of Vedic literature that are
authored rather than cognized, are known as smritis,
which
or
155
156
157
245
The Inner Value of Music, This emphasis on inner
perception is another area of agreement between Pythagoras
and the Vedic rishis; both valued inner knowledge over
external perception. One effect of this in India is that
music, in its manifestation as Gndharva Veda, has always
been seen as relating to rishi,
By contrast, Sthapatya
Purana.
It
246
replied, "Instrumental music can be learnt only if you
study deeply the art of singing.n "If singing is the
fountainhead of all arts, I beg you, 0 Master, to
reveal to me the secrets of vocal music.w This prime
place given to the voice in ancient times still abides,
and many of the qualities of Indian music derive their
characteristics from this fact.158
The Vibrating String. So it is that, in the form of the
intoned word, this most ancient of cosmologies has been
conveyed intact into the modern world. And how remarkable
that, when we probe into the subtleties of its expression
and go beyond its culturally determined peculiarities, we
find essentially the same picture of the world described by
Pythagoras, and later Plato, with the nature of sound, and
music, playing a central role.
The essential components of the Pythagorean cosmology
find a correspondence in the Vedic tradition. The process of
creation and manifestation, of the monad becoming the dyad
and then the triad, is expressed in the wholeness value
inherent in A, being stopped by the value of G, or the
wholeness value of Brahman becoming duality and then trinity
in the values of Rishi,
Devata
and Chhandas.
158
247
The relationship between sacred sound and music is, of
course, familiar to students of Pythagoras and his
"Harmony of the Spheres." The Pythagorean school,
however, based the sacrality of music on the sacredness
of numbers instead of words, as explained by a modern
scholar conversant in both traditions: "Words are the
Vedic Yoga: they unite mind and matter. Pure, ecstatic
contemplation of phonetic sound reverberating on the
ether in the sacred chant may be compared to the
contemplation of geometrical forms and mathematical
laws by the Pythagoreans. The Word is God, Number is
Godboth concepts result in a kind of intoxication.
Only the Pythagorean Master can hear the music of the
spheres: only the perfected Hindu sage can hear the
primordial soundNda.*159 16C
The reasons for both the cosmological parallels and the
methodological differences remain obscure. Sri Aurobindo
does propose a hypothesis, however:
The hypothesis I propose is that the Rig Veda is itself
the one considerable document that remains to us from
the early period of ancient thought of which the
historic Eleusian and Orphic mysteries were the failing
remnants, when the spiritual and psychological
knowledge of the race was concealed, for reasons now
difficult to determine, in a veil of concrete and
material figures and symbols which protected the sense
from the profane and revealed it to the initiated.161
159
248
This remains a hypothesis, however interesting. What is
notable is the underlying thread of musical symbolism tying
together these diverse traditions. Whether it is the divine
vina of Saraswati, the lyre of Orpheus, or the monochords of
Pythagoras and Fludd, the image of the vibrating string
pervades these musical cosmologies. And let us not forget
the bamboo pipes of Ling Lun in China. All of these give the
same basic information: 1, 2, 3, 4.
162
249
250
itself11; this is the unfaithful angel of the
Judeo-Christian tradition, another image of Adam's sin
in Genesis. We call this Unity God, or nonpolarized
energy, in its aspect of indivisible Unity, and God the
Creator, or polarized energy, in its aspect as
Unity-conscious-of-itself.
Therefore, the Universe is only consciousness
and
presents only an evolution
of consciousness,
from
beginning to end, which is the return to its Cause. The
aim of every "initiatory" religion is to teach the way
that leads to this the ultimate merging.164
Unity creates by looking at itself; creation occurs
entirely between One and Two; all tones in the harmonic
series occur between the first and second partials. It is
precisely the same idea. In the notions of polarized and
unpolarized energy, de Lubicz gives it a new perspective.
But by far the most important idea that he brings out here
is that the universe is consciousness,
164
devata
252
But Two is reconciled to unity, included within
unity, by the simultaneous creation of Three. Three
represents the principle of reconciliation, or
relationship. (This three-in-one is of course the
Christian trinity, the same trinity that is described
in innumerable mythologies throughout the world.)165
Lamy describes this same process which we have already
characterized as the greatest of all mysterieshow the One
becomes the many. She confirms that one explanation was
common to all the centers of learning in Egypt.
Before there was any opposition, any yes and no,
positive and negative; before there was any
complementarity, high and low, light and shadow; before
there was presence and absence, life or death, heaven
or earth: there was but one incomprehensible Power,
alone, unique, inherent in the Nun, the indefinable
cosmic sea, the infinite source of the Universe,
outside of any notion of Space and Time. This vision of
the original unity was common to every period and
initiatory centre Heliopolis, Memphis, Hermopolis
and Thebes.
The great mystery is the passage from invisible
into visible, to be realized by the Power which from
the incomprehensible One will call forth the Many.
The first impulse is a projection of the inner
desire of the Creator-to-be to know himself, to realize
his own consciousness. This originating power is
symbolized by the heart.166
Reading this, it becomes evident that, on one level at
least, any debate about where Pythagoras traveled is largely
165
253
irrelevant. Whether he went to Egypt or India, he would have
learned essentially the same cosmology.
167
254
Bamford does not only invoke Islamic and Platonic sources.
He goes on to cite Coleridge, who rejected the idea that
matter precedes mind.
Coleridge, in fact, is very good on these things. As
what he calls a *transcendental philosopher" he says
not "Give me matter and motion and I will construct you
the universe," as Descartes does, but rather: "Grant me
a nature having two contrary forces, one which tends to
expand infinitely, while the other strives to apprehend
or find itself in this infinity, and I will call up the
world of intelligences with the whole system of their
representations to arise before you." In other words:
"Every power in nature and spirit must evolve an
opposite as the sole means and conditions of its
manifestation: and all opposition is a tendency to
reunion." This is true universally. Even God, the
Unknowable Cause without Cause, must evolve an opposite
by the necessity of Himself, and that opposite can only
be Himself, so that the principle of polarity becomes
the principle of identity.168
Kabbalah
"In the beginning God created the heaven and the
earth." Everyone in the Judao-Christian tradition is
familiar with this statement; it is Genesis, I.l. And yet
this appears to be as misleading a translation as "Come, God
of fire, to the sacrifice" is of Rg Veda, I.l. Just as the
early translators of Vedic literature were unaware of its
many levels of symbolism, so King James' panel of scholars
was not conversant with Kabbalah.
168
Ibid.
255
The Kabbalah tradition, outlined in Chapter I, concerns
itself extensively with the deeper levels of meaning
contained in the Hebrew language and the Jewish canon. It is
this discipline to which Suares refers when he speaks of the
first sequence of letter numbers containing the seed of the
whole.169 And the sequence in question is Genesis, 1.1.
The term letter-numbers used by Suares refers to an
ancient system of codes, applicable to several ancient
languages including Sanskrit, Greek, and Hebrew, among
others.
Hebrew writing has no numerals to indicate numbers.
These are expressed by the letters of the Hebrew
alphabet, each letter corresponding to a number. The
origin of these numbers, so we believe, goes back to an
epoch long before history, and ancient tradition
purports to show their significance, which is that each
number has a meaning in relation to cosmic forces. A
similar tradition is found at the origin of the
civilization of ancient Egypt. None can say whence it
arose.170
Strachan writes that
. . . generations of biblical scholars have either
dismissed this dimension as worthless or not even
believed it existed. The fact that it is indeed there
and has by no means been considered worthless,
particularly in the Judaic tradition, is attested by
the lengthy entry in the Encyclopedia
Judaica under
256
Gematria, for such is the name of this branch of number
symbolism.171
Strachan continues, "The origins of the numerical alphabet
are evidently shrouded in the mists of antiquity.''17- He
cites various researchers who have concluded that "it first
developed in Syro-Phoenicia during the fifth century BC
although an earlier Eastern source could not be ruled
out."173 Regarding the latter, he reports that
. . . the use of letters to signify numbers was known
to the Babylonians and the Greeks. The first recorded
use of it was on an inscription of Sargon II (727-707
BC) which says that the king built a famous wall 16,283
cubits long to correspond with the numerical value of
his name.174
At fig. 28 Strachan supplies a table of the two gematria
systems, the older, or "lesser" and the more recent, or
"greater" system, applied to both Hebrew and Greek
alphabets.
John Michell has devoted many years to the study of
gematria
writes:
171
172
Strachan, p. 113.
173
Ibid.
174
Ibid.
Gematria
The Gematria
Hebrew
Aleph
Beth
Gimel
Daleth
He
Waw
Zayin
Heth
Teth
Yodh
Kaph
Lamedh
Mem
Nun
Samekh
*Ayin
Pe
Tzadhe
Qoph
Resh
Sin, Shin
Taw
Lesser
3
2
7
1
f
*
D
5
&
J
X
p
1
lif
J1
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
Greater
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
20
30
40
50
60
70
80
90
100
200
300
400
500
600
700
800
Alphabets.
Greek
e
F
Alpha
Beta
Gamma
Delta
Epsilon
Digamma
Zeta
Eta
Theta
Jota
Kappa
Lambda
Mu
Nu
Xi
Omicron
Pi
Quppa
Rho
Sigma
Tau
Upsilon
Phi
Chi
Psi
Omega
or
Bar ah Elohim et Ha
175
259
associate with Agni. The reason for this can be found within
the Kabbalistic doctrine of tsimtsum
or "withdrawal." It was
value of Brahman
176
260
philosophy, whereby iva becomes akti*179 In Kabbalah, this
leads to the process whereby, in a progression reminiscent
of Pythagoreanism and the quadrivium, a point becomes a
line, and a line becomes a plane. Ouaknin represents these
thus (reading, as in Hebrew, from right to
left):
vav,
dalet,"11'-
or > 1 1. From
constructed, thus
This same process is represented through the
of Bereshyt, or
gematria
179
to Tantra
astra
261
The number 2 has essentially the same meaning as the
Pythagorean dyad, the duality of existence. It appears first
in the sequence because, according to Kabbalah, it
represents a dwelling, a form into which the formless can
enter. When multiplied by 10 to become 200, it forms the
Kabbalistic symbol for the entirety of the universe, the
Pythagorean Tetraktys. It is only now, when this immense
dwelling is established, that we come to the value of K,
the unity, or monad. Why this sequence? Because the next
number, 300, represents motion, or flow, "Prodigious cosmic
motion. Motion of everything that exists," as Suars puts
it.I6G Thus we see it is essentially the same process, but
seen from the standpoint of the relative world; the
receptacle is described first, one so vast that it
encompasses the entire universe, and then the value of unity
is breathed into it, in the same way that God breathes life
into other aspects of his creation at later stages of the
process.
We are left with two numbers. Yod, the number 10, also
bears a resemblance to the tetraktys. Suars defines it as
"a projection of Aleph
Suars, p.66.
262
Aleph,
Ibid.
182
Ibid.
263
are simply the gross manifestations of the subtle
letters that exist in the upper worlds as
configurations of divine light. In this perspective the
full reality of Torah can be apprehended only through a
visionary experience of the subtle realms of the
Godhead where the light of the supernal Torah eternally
shines.
According to such traditional formulations, then,
the explanation for the differences in the conceptions
and practices associated with Veda and Torah lies in
the essential character of the mystical experiences
through which their subtle reality can be apprehended.
Even though these experiences may be described as
involving both hearing and seeing, in brahmanical
representations of Veda the auditory channel is
emphasized, while in certain kabbalistic
representations of Torah, such as those found in the
Zohar, visionary experience is given priority. The
implication of these conceptions is that it is this
fundamental difference in the perceptual structure of
mystical experience that accounts for the different
modes of transmission of the earthly texts - whether
oral or written - not vice versa.183
Sufism
Sufism, the esoteric branch of Islam, is represented
here by one statement, but it is a profound one, summing up,
in the most simple and eloquent terms, the understanding of
creation and the structure of the world that underlies all
of the cosmologies we have been examining. The statement is
from Hazrat Inayat Khan, musician turned Sufi teacher, from
whom we have heard in previous chapters. He writes:
193
264
THE Life Absolute from which has sprung all that is
felt, seen, and perceived, and into which all again
merges in time, is a silent, motionless and eternal
life which among the Sufis is called Zkt. Every motion
which springs forth from this silent life is a
vibration and a creator of vibrations. Within one
vibration are created many vibrations; as motion causes
motion so the silent life becomes active in a certain
part, and creates every moment more and more activity,
losing thereby the peace of the original silent life.
It is the grade of activity of these vibrations which
accounts for the various planes of existence. These
planes are imagined to be different from one another,
but in reality they cannot be entirely detached and
made separate from one another. The activity of
vibrations makes them grosser, and thus the earth is
born of the heavens.164
265
essential. Growth without limitation leads to a kind of
universal cancer, an annihilation of form and of
meaningful organization, whereas limitation without a
generative counterforce remains an empty concept, a
denial of matter and of vitality. Neither process alone
is capable of yielding a structure, but their
polarization is a central concern of all morphology,
musical and otherwise.185
G. Spencer-Brown has conducted a similar study in the
area Lavarie mentionsmorphology. The principle he finds to
be fundamental is related to polarity; it is that of
division, bringing to mind de Lubicz's idea of the
"Primordial Scission." Spencer-Brown finds this notion
underlying both cosmology and abstract mathematics.
The theme of this book is that a universe comes
into being when a space is severed or taken apart. The
skin of a living organism cuts off an outside from an
inside. So does the circumference of a circle in a
plane. By tracing the way we represent such a
severance, we can begin to reconstruct, with an
accuracy and coverage that appear almost uncanny, the
basic forms underlying linguistic, mathematical,
physical, and biological science, and can begin to see
how the familiar laws of our own experience follow
inexorably from the original act of severance.
. . . Although all forms, and thus all universes,
are possible, and any particular form is mutable, it
becomes evident that the laws relating such forms are
the same in any universe. It is this sameness, the idea
that we can find a reality which is independent of how
the universe actually appears, that lends such
fascination to the study of mathematics.166
185
266
We know that mathematics and music are closely related.
So it is no surprise that, along with the principle of
polarity, Levarie finds the idea of division as basic to his
musical morphology. It is, in fact, the principle Pythagoras
discovered through the use of the mono chord.
The whole idea of genesis by division is a
transcendental heritage of mankind. It dominates the
first chapter of the Bible. . . The same idea
determines Plato's explanations of creation. . . . For
this explanation of the principle of any
genesis, Plato was indebted to Pythagoras whose
experiments on the monochord taught a general truth
about the universe. Just as division of a string
creates individual tones and leads to the discovery and
establishment of basic musical laws, such as consonance
and dissonance or major and minor, so the whole world
can be understood as a multiplicity of phenomena
initiated by one process and governed by polarity.187
267
universe manifests itself through the octave reflection of
its own nature. We can find the same symbolism in the Greek
goddess Rhea and the Egyptian Isis:
The dyad was called *Rheaf, mother of the gods, because
the name of this goddess is similar to the Greek verb
rhein meaning to *flowf. Since matter was always in a
state of flux, Rhea and the dyad became synonymous with
it. In later Pythagoreanism the dyad was also called
*Isisf for the name of this goddess is like the Greek
word for *equalf or *isos';this etymology referring to
the equality of the single units in the two . . . . The
Pythagoreans were very interested in the origin of
words and their meanings for they were searching for
the language of the gods which held the key to ultimate
reality.1'6
Gorman indicates that the Greek language had inner
meanings similar to those we have found in Sanskrit. When we
add the element of gematria,
188
A Life
268
The Monad, so conceived, is not the first in the series
of numbers; indeed, it is not a number at all, but it
is the original undifferentiated unity, from which
emerge the two opposite principles Limit and Unlimited,
the elements of number and of all things.
. . . This view has also the advantage that it
brings the Pythagorean scheme of thought into line with
the other early systems, both mythical and scientific.
The abstract formula which is common to the early
cosmogonies is as follows: (1) There is an
undifferentiated unity. (2) From this unity two
opposite powers are separated out to form the world
order. (3) The two opposites unite again to generate
life.183
We will find this view, and the understanding of the
symbolism through which it is conveyed, to be of great
importance when we go on to study Plato and the two main
sources of the music of the spheres tradition contained in
his writings.
189
CHAPTER V
THE GREEK SOURCES: THE TIMAEUS
270
As part of this tradition Plato was himself deeply
influenced by Pythagorean doctrine. This is nowhere more
evident than in the area of musical cosmology. As James Haar
puts it, "Plato did not invent the music of the spheres. For
the fact that the theory was Pythagorean in origin there is
abundant testimony."2 Furthermore, at least one of the
source texts for this tradition, the Timaeus,
is perhaps the
271
science of things which are truly existing beings, but
not of the mere figurative entities. Corporeal natures
are neither the objects of science, nor admit of a
stable knowledge, since they are indefinite, and by
science incomprehensible; and when compared with
universals resemble non-beings, and are in a genuine
sense indeterminate. Indeed it is impossible to
conceive that there should be a science of things not
naturally the objects of science; nor could a science
of non-existent things prove attractive to any one.3
Reading this, one might forget the aspect of balance in
Pythagoras' thought posited in the previous chapter, a
balance between the ideal and the empirical, between the
magical, organic, and mechanical traditions. It re-confirms
that, if Pythagoras flirted with empirical observation and
experimentation, his primary focus was on eternal and
universal entities. This view dominated his approach to
teaching, since his main emphasis was on the cultivation of
the mind and the soul, rather than the accumulation of
information or acquisition of skills. This is what Boorstin
refers to as "pure knowledge" aimed at "the purification
(catharsis)
Pythagoras,
The purified mind should be applied to the discovery of
beneficial things, which can be effected by certain
arts,
which by degrees induce it to the contemplation
of eternal and incorporeal things which never vary.5
One example of this approach is seen in Pythagoras'
approach to mathematics. Although he is perhaps best known
for his contribution to geometry, the theorem regarding
right-angled triangles, for Pythagoras the practical
applications of the objects of mathematics were secondary to
their role as objects of contemplation, used to purify and
refine the very processes of thinking. Porphyry again:
That is the reason he made so much use of the
mathematical disciplines and speculations, which are
intermediate between the physical and the incorporeal
realm. . . [These disciplines he used] as degrees of
preparation to the contemplation of the really existent
things, by an artistic principle diverting the eyes of
the mind from corporeal things, whose manner and state
never remain in the same condition, to a desire for
true [spiritual] food. By means of these mathematical
sciences, therefore, Pythagoras rendered men truly
happy. . . ."(Guthrief s insertions.)
We will find the same approach to mathematics in
Plato's Republic.
Ibid.
273
approach to the study of astronomy, Plato emphasizes the
importance of the universal realm of the Forms rather than
the empirical world as a fitting subject of study. "The
stars that decorate the sky," says Socrates,
though we rightly regard them as the finest and most
perfect of visible things, are far inferior, just
because they are visible, to the true realities; that
is to the true relative velocities, in pure numbers and
perfect figures, of the orbits and what they carry in
them, which are perceptible to reason and thought but
not visible to the eye.7
After his discussion of astronomy, Plato goes on to
discuss the study of harmonics, and it is here that he takes
issue with the Pythagorean viewin particular, the interest
in empirical experiment that emerges from Pythagoras'
experience in the blacksmith's shop.
"As we said when dealing with astronomy just now,
our pupils must not leave their studies incomplete or
stop short of the final objective. They can do this
just as much in harmonics as they could in astronomy,
by wasting their time on measuring audible concords and
notes against each other."
"Lord, yes, and pretty silly they look," he
[Glaucon] said. "They talk about ^intervals' of sound,
and listen as carefully as if they were trying to hear
a conversation next door. . . They all prefer to use
their ears instead of their minds."
"You mean those people who torment the strings and
try to wring the truth out of them by twisting them on
pegs. [I am thinking of] the Pythagoreans, who we said
would tell us about harmonics. For they do just what
the astronomers do; they look for numerical
7
Plato, Republic,
529, c-d, Desmond Lee, trans. (London:
Penguin Books, 1974), p. 338.
274
relationships in audible concords, and never get as far
as formulating problems and examining which numerical
relations are concordant, which not, and why."8
This is a curious passage, in view of Iamblichus' and
others' descriptions of Pythagorean epistemology. It
suggests that, in the two centuries between Pythagoras and
Plato, the former's followers had fallen into Aristoxenes'
camp in preferring the evidence of the ear over that of the
intellect in developing music theory. Such an approach runs
counter to Pythagoras' emphasis on universals as the focus
of epistemology. Perhaps the utormenting of strings"
described by Plato reflects only the empirical side of the
Pythagorean approach, the verification of subjective
experience sought for in Pythagoras' acoustical experiments.
His criticism that Pythagorean theorists were not involved
in theoretical considerations seems unjustified. When
examining the passages from Plato that reflect Pythagorean
doctrine, it will be important to examine both sides of this
picture.
Republic,
275
Porphyry report that the Pythagorean brotherhood was divided
into a hierarchy, with the deepest teachings reserved for
those who passed a series of tests, including spending five
years in silence, before gaining admittance to an inner
circle. Such practices were characteristic of the ancient
wisdom traditions in general and the Greek mystery religions
in particular. They appear to have been based on the desire
to preserve the integrity of an oral tradition over many
generations while maintaining at its essence the intimate
relationship between teacher and student. Pythagoras
experienced this himself during his studies in Egypt and
Babylon, when he received instruction from the priests only
after proving himself through his patient demeanor, a
process that repeats itself even into the present day for
those wishing to gain acceptance into a monastic tradition.9
In keeping with such an approach, Pythagoras kept his
teaching under tight control. He hesitated to put it into
writing and adapted it according to the level of preparation
of his audience. "His utterances were of two kinds, plain or
symbolical," reports Porphyry.
His teaching was twofold: of his disciples some were
called Students {mathematikoi),
and others Hearers
9
276
{akousmatikoi).
The Students learned the fuller and
more exactly elaborate reasons of science, while the
Hearers heard only the summarized instructions of
learning, without more detailed explanation.10
This distinction must always be kept in mind when dealing
with references to the "Pythagoreans." We cannot always know
with certainty to which group reference is being made. It
may well have been merely the akousmatikoi
Porphyry, p. 130.
11
277
to the first comer; for the very first thing Pythagoras
is said to have taught is that, being purified from all
intemperance, his disciples should preserve the
doctrines they heard in silence.12
It is well known that the members of the Pythagorean
brotherhood were appalled when one of their number revealed
a secret of Pythagorean mathematics, the existence of
incommensurable quantities, or irrational numbers. According
to Iamblichus, the guilty party was vilified and expelled
from their community, a tomb being erected to symbolize his
leaving It is assumed that the reason for this action was
that this knowledge threatened the foundations of
Pythagorean mathematics, which was based purely on
commensurable quantities. But revealing any aspect of the
inner knowledge of the brotherhood was enough to elicit
horror and revulsion from its members.
Such an attitude toward publicly revealing the inner
nature of secret teachings is one aspect of Pythagoreanism
that was inherited by Plato. In the seventh of his preserved
letters, Plato makes it clear that there is an inner core of
teachings that he would never commit to writing:
One statement at any rate I can make in regard to all
who have written or who may write with a claim to
knowledge of the subjects to which I devote myselfno
matter how they pretend to have acquired it, whether
from my instruction or from others or by their own
Iamblichus, in Guthrie, p. 116.
279
. . . the subject treated cannot have been his most
serious concernthat is, if he is himself a serious
man. His most serious interests have their abode
somewhere in the noblest region of the field of his
activity. If, however, he really was concerned with
these matters and put them in writing, "then surely"
not the gods, but mortals "have utterly blasted his
wits."14 15
A similar point can be found in the Phaedrus.
Socrates
14
Iliad
15
280
. . . they seem to talk to you as though they were
intelligent, but if you ask them anything about what
they say, from a desire to be instructed, they go on
telling you just the same thing forever. And once a
thing is put in writing, the composition, whatever it
may be, drifts all over the place, getting into the
hands not only of those who understand it, but equally
of those who have no business with it; it doesn't know
how to address the right people, and not address the
wrong. And when it is ill-treated and unfairly abused
it always needs its parent to come to its help, being
unable to defend or help itself.17
Socrates asks if there is another sort of discourse "brother
to the written speech, but of unquestioned legitimacy" that
is better and more effective. Phaedrus asks what sort of
discourse he has in mind and Socrates replies, "The sort
that goes together with knowledge, and is written in the
soul of the learner, that can defend itself and knows to
whom it should speak and to whom it should say nothing."18
It is clear, therefore, that great care has to be taken
in interpreting Pythagorean literature, as well as those of
Plato's dialogues most influenced by Pythagoreanism. However
it might look on the surface, there are hidden meanings and
multiple levels of interpretation.
All Pythagoric discipline was symbolic, resembling
riddles and puzzles, and consisting of maxims, in the
style of the ancients. Likewise the truly divine
Pythian oracles seem to be somewhat difficult of
17
Ibid.
18
Ibid.
281
understanding and explanation to those who carelessly
receive the answers given. These are the indications
about Pythagoras and the Pythagoreans collected from
tradition.19
This approach to teaching is of great importance in
considering the tradition of musical cosmology that stems
from Orpheus, Pythagoras and Plato. And there is good reason
to assume that subsequent writers had no more than a partial
understanding of these sources.
are
20
Haar, p. 1.
282
true natures; and the use of symbolic forms of expression in
articulating knowledge. Given the last of these
considerations, it should be no surprise that we find
passages in Plato filled with "riddles and puzzles." We will
also find that Haar's characterizations of these dialogues
as myths may provide a better basis for understanding them
once we understand the level of knowledge that myth
contains.
The Timaeus
History
The Timaeus is an appropriate place to begin; the
partial Latin translation by Calcidius in the fourth century
C.E. was the only Platonic dialogue available in Europe from
the end of the classical era until Ficino's translations
appeared during the Renaissance.
The Timaeus, as it turned out, was the only Platonic
dialogue that never sank into oblivion in the West.
During the Dark and Middle ages its first and most
essential part was known in the Latin version of
Calcidius. This freak of survival was probably the
single most important fact in the transmission of the
doctrines of cosmic and psychic harmony.21
21
283
Certainly, it was widely known. "There was hardly a medieval
library of any standing which had not a copy of Chalcidius'
version and also a copy of the fragment translated by
Cicero."22 Furthermore, the Timaeus deals directly with the
musical structure of the universe, and it is the main source
for the concept of cosmic harmony expressed in the term
harmonia.
as ascribing
23
24
Haar, p. 71.
I a m b l i c h u s , In Timaeus, f r . 74 ( t r a n s l . J.M. D i l l o n ) ,
c i t e d i n Dominic J. O'Meara, Pythagoras Revived:
Mathematics
and Philosophy in Late Antiquity
(Oxford: Clarendon Press,
1989), p . 99.
284
Academy, and the importance of Plato for passing on his
predecessor's teachings:
Through Plato's writings, especially the Timaeus,
Pythagorean doctrine had entered the mainstream of
Greek thought. It oversimplifies but slightly, in fact,
to say that Socrates provided the method and the
Pythagoreans the curriculum for Plato's Academy* This
is not to denigrate the achievement of Plato or to
diminish his honor, but to place the Pythagorean school
in better perspective. There is no doubt that much of
Plato's teaching was a graft on the stock of
Pythagorean doctrine.25
Heninger's view is not new; a similar statement can be found
from the Byzantine scholar Photius (c. 820-891 C.E.):
Plato is said to have learned his speculative and
physical doctrines from the Italian Pythagoreans, his
ethics from Socrates, and his logic from Zeno,
Parmenedes and the Eliatics. But all of these teachings
descended from Pythagoras.26
The Timaeus not only reflects Pythagorean thought, it
directly contributed to its revival in Europe; Guthrie cites
the "brief and beautiful Renaissance of Pythagorean thought
at the cathedral school of Chartres during the 12th century,
due in part to a Latin translation of Plato's
Timaeus."21
25
26
27
285
But this dialogue is also one of the most difficult of
Plato's works to understand, and its most significant
section, the description of the creation of the World Soul,
"is the most perplexing and difficult of the whole
dialogue. "28
Given the difficulty of understanding the Timaeus,
especially the passages concerning the music of the spheres,
there has been no shortage of commentaries on it; over forty
appeared during ancient and medieval times alone. In the
modern era, Albert von Thimus-9 wrote extensively on the
Timaeus in the nineteenth century; Thomas Taylor,30 A. E.
Taylor31, Francis Cornford,3- Ernest G. McClain,33 and
Cosmology
(London/New
Prelude
to
the
286
Michell,34 among others, have contributed to this literature
in the twentieth.
The complexity of the task of interpreting this
dialogue becomes clear in the enormous divergence of
viewpoints among these various commentaries. A.E. Taylor and
Cornford provide solid classical views, carefully fitting
Plato's description of the World Soul into the general
context of the cosmological statements found throughout his
writings. They are, however, unable to account for the
dimension emphasized in the fullest ancient commentary, that
of Proclus, who finds the source of Plato's description in
Orphic and Chaldean theology.
In recent years, McClain and Michell have placed the
Timaeus in the context of the ancient systems of
mathematical symbolism with which Plato would have been
familiar. Michell finds that the number symbolism within the
Timaeus embodies the ancient canon that he also identifies
as contained in megalithic monuments, Gothic cathedrals, and
even the Greek language. McClain, following von Thimus,
finds the work to be a musical cypher based on the ancient
obsession with tuning systems. Hans Kayser, Ernst Levy and
Keith Critchlow sum up centuries of speculative mathematics,
34
Godwin, p. 4.
288
289
Context
To begin the dialogue, Socrates is asked to give a
brief summary of the previous day's discussion, which turns
out to have been the content of The Republic.
However,
Critias,
the first dealing with cosmology and the second with the
story of ancient Athens and Atlantis. The second of these
themes, the Atlantis myth, is briefly introduced at the
beginning of the Timaeus,
290
which gives a further indication of the ideas to be
presented.) The story of Atlantis is picked up again in the
Critias.
36
291
description of the creation which is to follow is an ideal
one. Rather than a description of the universe in its purely
physical manifestation, the Timaeus sets forth the abstract
principles fundamental to the processes of creation and
manifestation, and it is these principles, essentially
mathematical and musical in their nature, that form the
basis for the numerical symbolism found in the dialogue. It
is from this perspective that we arrive at the notions of
universal harmony and the music of the spheres. Thus the
context within which we should consider these writings is
that described by Danielou,37 the ancient view of music as a
key to the understanding of a cosmology based on abstract
mathematical symbolism.
This passage is particularly significant in view of any
tendency to interpret or to refute the cosmology presented
in the Timaeus solely in terms of its application to the
physical solar system. Timaeus seems to anticipate, and to
attempt to avoid, this confusion at the outset of his
presentation, reminding us of Pythagoras' admonitions about
the nature of reliable knowledge as derived from unchanging
universals rather than from phenomena in the ever-changing
physical world.
292
The World of Number
As well as the emphasis on the realm of Being rather
than becoming, and its employment of a symbolic mode of
expression, the Timaeus reflects Pythagoreanism through a
symbolism based on numbers. This is apparent from the very
beginning of the dialogue.
Having established that what he is about to describe is
essentially an eternal archetype upon which external forms
of creation are based, Timaeus continues by explaining the
motivation in the mind of the Creator when framing the
creation. Being perfectly good and therefore completely
lacking in envy, God wished that all things should be as
good as He. He therefore determined to create order
throughout the whole range of creation, as order is the
measure of perfection. To create this order He set up the
universe as a body containing a soul which itself contains
intelligence. It is this intelligence that is expressed
through the elaborate number symbolism upon which the
dialogue rests.
Positing number to be the primary element of creation
is consistent with the view expressed by Plato in the
statement at the beginning of the Timaeus,
where he demands
2 93
becomes from that which is always becoming but never is."38
Here Plato is making a distinction between one level of
creation, where the essential archetypal Forms exist, and a
lower realm, where the physical phenomena of the world,
which mirror the ideal forms, have their existence. From
this view, it necessarily follows that there are different
modes of apprehending these different levels of creation.
"The one is apprehensible by intelligence with the aid of
reasoning," Plato tells us, "being eternally the same. The
other is the object of opinion and irrational sensation,
coming to be and ceasing to be, but never fully real."3*
Plato's view mirrors that of Pythagoras's distinction
between the appearance of things and their true natures.40
It accounts for the direction of his philosophy, distrusting
the senses and putting his faith in the eternal realm of
being. In the first century C.E., the same view was
expressed by Plutarch:
The very world and every part thereof is compounded of
a substance intelligible or spirituall, and of a
substance sensible or corporall: whereof the one hath
38
Timaeus,
39
Ibid.
40
294
furnished the thing that is made and engendred with
forme and shape, the other with subject matter.41
This bifurcated view of nature is of great importance in
understanding the context of the Pythagorean approach to
mathematics.
One of the theorists who have been involved with
Plato's puzzles and riddles in the form of hidden
mathematical symbolism is Ernest McClain. He suggests that
this symbolism was not fully understood even by Plato's
immediate followers:
Plato' s later dialogues abound in mathematical
allegories. Timaeus begins with a very long one,
Statesman contains a short one, the Republic has three,
and both Critias
and Laws are permeated with them from
beginning to end. When Plato died in 347 B.C. his
pupils and friends immediately began to argue about
these mathematical constructions and about Plato's
purpose in using them for models of souls, cities, and
the planetary system. By the beginning of the Christian
era much of Plato's mathematics had become a riddle.4*1
McClain belongs to a small group of music theorists who
suggest that a knowledge of music is necessary to decipher
Plato's allegories. He also finds musical keys to other
ancient literature such as vedic and Islamic sources. In
41
McClain, p. 1.
295
this instance, the nature of the allegory is revealed in one
key sentence.
McClain, p .
44
Timaeus,
57.
17a.
296
dialogue. Plato is setting out to describe the structure of
the cosmos and having seen the cosmological context in the
ancient world, with which Plato would have been familiar,
will be helpful in interpreting the complex and obscure myth
that Plato is about to unfold.
McClain, p. 58.
297
Others, such as Desmond Lee, believe he is referring to the
model of the solar system known as an annillary sphere.46
These are reasonable interpretations, but central to Plato's
symbolism is the qualities of the numbers themselves, as
understood from the Pythagorean perspective.
47
Timaeus,
35.
298
existing."48 The three elements in Plato's scheme are these
two poles with a third value intermediate between them. This
reflects the principle that Plato has already enunciated,
"...it is not possible to combine two things properly
without a third to act as a bond to hold them together. And
the best bond is one that effects the closest unity between
itself and the terms it is combining."49
Plato's demiurge follows this process, establishing an
intermediary aspect between two extremes. This could have
been accomplished in one stage but the Creator is not
satisfied with this. Following the tripartite pattern
suggested in the opening sentence, the demiurge continues
the process through three steps. The second and third steps
of composition of the World Soul continue thus:
. . . again with the Same and Different he made, in the
same way, compounds intermediate between their
indivisible element and their physical and divisible
element: and taking these three components he mixed
them into [a] single unity, forcing the Different which
was by nature allergic to mixture, into union with the
Same, and mixing both with Existence.C
With the concepts of Sameness and Difference, Plato is
again dealing with ideal forms of knowledge with a variety
48
49
Timaeus,
31.
50
Timaeus,
35b.
299
of meanings. On one hand, the terms are related to basic
principles of logic, as Plato held that reasoning consisted
essentially of judgments of sameness (affirmation) and
difference (negation).51 They also represent the values of
number in the fundamental dualism of the Pythagorean number
symbolism that we examined in detail in Chapter IV.
Nicomachus, as Cornford reports, makes a connection between
the Pythagorean concepts of monad and dyad and Plato's
notion of sameness and difference:
Nicomachus . . . tells us that the ancients, Pythagoras
and his successors, found *the other or otherness' in
*two','the same or sameness' in *one'. They regarded
*one' and *two' as the principle of all things/In keeping with this concept, the Pythagoreans associated
the value of two, or the dyad, with a list of ten
fundamental pairs of opposites, as preserved by Aristotle:!
limit
odd
one
right
male
at rest
51
52
unlimited
even
plurality
left
female
in motion
Lee, p. 4 6.
(New York:
straight
light
good
square
crooked
darkness
evil
oblong54
peras,
suggests an indefinite,
54
Guthrie, p. 23.
55
301
necessary to arrive at the final composition of the soul.
According to Cornford,56 this gives the following three-part
structure to the composition of the World Soul:
First Mixture
Indivisible Existence
Divisible Existence
Second Mixture
Intermediate
Existence
Indivisible Sameness
Divisible Sameness
Intermediate
Sameness
Indivisible Difference
Divisible Difference
Intermediate
Difference
Final Mixture
Soul.
Plato
302
times the third, a sixth eight times the first, a
seventh twenty-seven times the first.57
Again, Plato is exploiting the numbers one, two, and
three. There is no more complete way of doing this as the
sequence of numbers given, 1, 2, 3, 4, 9, 8, 27, is nothing
other than the first three powers of the first three
numbers, that is, 1, 2, 3, 2 squared, 3 squared, 2 cubed,
and 3 cubed.56 Timaeus is thus giving the full dimensions
of
A
/
/2
/
/4
/
/8
3\
\
9\
\
27\
Timaeus,
58
35.
303
Next he filled in the double and treble intervals by
cutting off further sections and inserting them in the
gaps, so that there were two mean terms in each
interval, one exceeding one extreme and being exceeded
by the other by the same fraction of the extremes, the
other exceeding and being extended by the same
numerical amount. These links produced intervals of 3/4
and 4/3 and 9/8 within the previous intervals, and he
went on to fill all intervals of 4/3 with the interval
9/8; this left, as a remainder in each, an interval
whose terms bore the numerical ratio of 256 to 243. And
at that stage the mixture from which these sections
were being cut was all used up.5*
We recognize the resulting structure as the Dorian
scale in Pythagorean tuning. This description has led to an
enormous amount of commentary. Plato's description is
sufficiently general to allow for many different
realizations of the basic formula which he sets forth,
realizations that bring out both the arithmetical and the
musical qualities of the basic relationships. Of greatest
importance is the use of the means.
Three kinds of means, or mathematic divisions, were
commonly used in Pythagorean arithmetic, the arithmetic, the
harmonic and the geometric. Of these Plato uses the first
two, the arithmetic (exceeding and being exceeded by the
same numerical amount) and the harmonic (exceeding one
extreme and being exceeded by the other by the same fraction
Timaeus,
36a-b.
304
of the extremes). To demonstrate these using all whole
numbers, we can take the sequence:
12
2 : 1 ) or, as Plato
6 8
3:4
6
2:3
8
2:3
12
3:4
305
6
12
Tonic
Sub-dominant
Dominant
Tonic
4:3
Series:
Intervals: 9:8
9:8
81:64
9:8
4:3
256:243 9:8
3:2
27:16
9:8
243:128
9:8
256:243
306
processes Plato describes, and many of these have been
explored by commentators in recent years.
Modern Analyses
Ernest McClain
Among modern writers, it is Ernest McClain who analyzes
these number sequences in terms of musical phenomena,
believing them to be at the root of most, if not all, of the
symbolism found in Plato's writings. McClain's
interpretation of these passages consists largely of
extensions of realizations by ancient writers, including
Crantor, Nichomachus and Proclus.-'0
There are two main ways of generating numerical
realizations of Plato's description, both of which contain
much information, both musical and arithmetical. The first
of these is somewhat more complex, consisting of an
arithmetic sequence "exponed in one row".
6I
The resultant
60
61
307
Item
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.
9.
10.
11.
12.
13.
14.
15.
16.
17.
18.
19.
20.
21.
22.
23.
24.
25.
26.
27.
28.
29.
30.
31.
32.
33.
34.
35.
36.
37.
38.
39.
40.
41.
Completed
Progression
768
864
972
1024
1152
1296
1458
1536
1728
1944
2048
2187
2304
2592
2916
3072
3456
3888
4096
4374
4608
5184
5832
6144
6561
6912
7776
8192
8748
9216
10368
11664
12288
13122
13824
15552
16384
174%
18432
19683
20736
Falling
Pitch
D
C
Bb
A
G
F
Eb
D
C
Bb
A
Ab
G
F
Eb
D
C
Bb
A
Ab
G
F
Eb
D
Db
C
Bb
A
Ab
G
F
Eb
D
Db
C
Bb
A
Ab
G
Gb
F
Rising
Pitch
D
E
F#
G
A
B
C#
D
E
F#
G
G#
A
B
C#
D
E
F#
G
G#
A
B
C#
D
D#
E
F#
G
G#
A
B
C#
D
D#
E
F#
G
G#
A
A#
B
Original
"Portions"
"Means"
Inserted
8
9
12
16
3
18
24
27
32
36
48
54
81
108
27
162
308
Notice that the first octave shows the model
diatonic scale; in later octaves, chromatic tones
appear as members of overlapping tetrachords. The last
octave 1 : 2 = 10,368 : 20,736 summarizes the entire
tonal material, showing that the sequence consists
merely of octave replications of ten different
tone-values.6:
We can derive more information from the second method of
setting forth these values that McClain gives us. This is
developed from a table of proportions after Nichomachus and
consists of a triangular matrix with the powers of 2 along
one side, the powers of 3 along the hypotenuse and the
resultant ratios of 3:2 in the vertical columns:
Frequency Wave Length
1
16
32
64
128
256
512
6 12
24
48
96
192
384
768
9 18
36
72
144 288
576
1152
27
54
864
1728
81
2592
3888
Bb
F#
Eb
C#
Ab
G#
6561 13122 =
Db
D#
19683 =
Gb
A#
McClain, p. 62.
63
McClain, p. 63.
: 8
: 9
64
Ibid.
65
McClain, p. 62.
310
6
: 9
::
12
according
McClain, p. 63.
67
McClain, p. 3.
311
of the Circle of the Same and the Circle of the Different,
the section at the heart of the music of the spheres
tradition:
He then took the whole fabric and cut it down the
middle into two strips, which he placed crosswise at
their middle points to form a shape like the letter X;
he then bent the ends round in a circle and fastened
them to each other opposite the point at which the
strips crossed, to make two circles, one inner and one
outer. And he endowed them with uniform motion in the
same place, and named the movement of the outer circle
after the nature of the Same, of the inner after the
nature of the Different. The circle of the Same he
caused to revolve from left to right, and the circle of
the Different from right to left on an axis inclined to
it; and made the master revolution that of the Same.
For he left the circle of the Same whole and undivided,
but slit the inner circle six times to make seven
unequal circles, whose intervals were double or triple,
three of each; and he made these circles revolve in
contrary senses relative to each other, three of them
at a similar speed, and four at speeds different from
each other and from that of the first three but related
proportionately.8
McClain refers back to the Lambda pattern in this
context. Pointing out that Pythagorean theory associates the
number one with existence, even numbers with difference and
odd with sameness, a version of the Lambda can be
constructed as follows:
Timaeus,
36c-d.
Existence
1
/2
3\
/4
9\
/8
27\
Difference
Sameness
1/8
1/9
1/4
1/3
D
E
1/2
D
A
1
2
4
8
D
D
D
9
D
27
69
McClain, p. 65.
70
Ibid.
G
C
F
1/27
1/18
1/9
1/12
1/6
1/3
1/8
1/4
E
E
1/2
A
A
1
2
4
8
D
D
D
D
3
6
12
D
9
18
D
27
G
G
C
C
71
McClain, p. 67.
314
more traditional interpretation of this passage that led to
the idea of the Harmony of the Spheres and centuries of
speculation in astronomy.
McClain's analysis reveals that a sophisticated
numerical symbolism lies at the heart of the Timaeus and
that musical relationships are the key, or at least one key,
to unlocking these puzzles and riddles. The exact purpose of
these musical allegories, even if we accept them, is less
clear, however. Further work in this area may help to
clarify the purpose of this obscure symbolism.
72
315
understanding forward by placing Plato's work into the
context of this ancient canon. After extensive analysis of a
wide range of phenomena, from megalithic monuments to the
traditions of sacred geometry and the hidden meanings of the
scriptures of various cultures, Michell suggests the
existence of a common symbolism based on number.
The special regard paid to mathematical studies in the
ancient world arose from the understanding that number
is the mean term in the progression from divine reason
to its imperfect reflection in humanity. At some very
early period . . . certain groups of numbers were
brought together and codified. Thus was created that
numerical standard, or canon of proportion, which was
at the root of all ancient cultures and was everywhere
attributed to some form of miraculous revelation. It
was taken to be the nucleus and activating principle of
number generally, a summary of all the types of
progressions and relationships which occur within the
field of number and thus a faithful image of the
numerically created universe.73
Michell's analysis overlaps McClain's to a large
extent, describing the use of musical intervals in
determining the proportions of the World-soul. From this
point, however, Michell goes one step further:
It is not doubted that Plato intended the World-soul to
form a musical scale extending over four octaves and a
major sixth. Yet that was not his only intention. In
accordance with the Pythagorean doctrine of the primacy
of number, he depicted the essence of the universe, its
Soul, as a numerical sequence containing every
canonical form of harmony and proportion discovered in
music, geometry and the philosophical study of nature.
Michell, p. 7.
316
The World-soul is more than a scale of music, which is
but one of its aspects. Throughout his account of how
it was constructed Plato clearly implies that it was
first and foremost a code of number. From it he derived
the natural formulas which, he believed, should be
followed by artists and musicians and which he made the
basis of his own philosophy.74
In attempting to show the connection between Plato's
dialogue and this ancient code of number, Michell analyzes
the various sequences of numbers associated with the Worldsoul, assembles them into an aggregate value, and compares
this with similar numbers from other sources of sacred
numerology such as the Timaeus Lochrius
(first century
74
75
Michell, p. 169.
317
While Michell's work appears similar to McClain's in
many respects, it goes one step further both by placing
Plato's work into the context of an ancient canon of
knowledge and by suggesting a purpose to the number patterns
that Plato presents in the dialogue.
Plato's evident intention was to identify number as the
archetype of creation and to draw attention to those
particular numbers which constitute its core and which,
in various combinations, generate the entire field of
number. His purpose was to provide for the use of
rulers and reformers an objective standard, thus
allowing statecraft to become a science, firmly based
on those numbers and proportions which constitute the
essence of the universe.T6
Whatever Plato's intentions, many mysteries and enigmas
continue to surround the numbers and proportions he
describes, and interpretations of their significance
continue to proliferate. Several of these emphasize the
significance of the lambda formation.
Michell, p. 169.
318
associated with the fundamental principles, Existence,
Sameness and Difference.
A
/
/2
/
/4
/
/8
Difference
3\
\
9\
\
27\
Sameness
of
319
biographer Iamblichus,77 he investigates the internal
symmetries of Plato's 1,2,3,4,9,8,27 sequence, taking as his
starting point their Lambda arrangement.
1
A
/
/2
/
/4
/
/8
3\
\
9\
\
27\
he writes,
Critchlow, p. 13.
A
/
/2
/
3\
\
/4
/
/8
9\
12
18 27\
Following the same process using the powers of two from the
left leg produces the same results as 3x2=6,x2=12 and
9x2=18.
1
A
/
/2
/
3\
/
/4
/8
12
9\
/
18 27\
A
/
/2
3\
/4
/8
9\
\
12
18 27\
/8' 12
18 27\
322
Similarly, the harmonic means, in which u . . .the mean
exceeds one extreme and is exceeded by the other by the same
fraction of the extremes (see Timaeus
A
/
\
/2/3\
f4lPl8 27\
All of these relationships are filled in below, along with
the musical ratios of octaves (2:1), fifths (3:2), fourths
(4:3), and the whole tone (9:8).
***~
Critchlow, p. 18.
A
/
/2
3\
/4
9\
/8
12
18 27\
A
/
12/
M8
24/
36
\54
48/
72
108
\162
(Venice, 1525).
324
giving the sequence: 6,8,9.12,16,18,24.27.32.36.48,54,81,
108,162, The original numbers are underlined. The others are
arithmetic and harmonic means and "display musical
ratios."*-2 Critchlow says Giorgi describes these
relationships in terms of three ontological domains, the
geometric referring to the heavenly or theological realm,
the arithmetic to the earthly or cosmological and the
harmonic as "the harmony of the other two," which Critchlow
interprets as ". . . the human, psychological or
anthropological domain. This links the three domains through
the metaphor of musical proportion, and with the pattern of
the Sacred Decad or Tetraktys."*5 His conclusion reinforces
the significance of symbolism in Pythagorean lore in general
and the Timaeus in particular. "Our intention," he writes,
"is mainly to indicate that the ^literature' of the
Pythagorean tradition tends to be a stimulus
recall
of the unwritten
or an aid
doctrines"
(emphasis
82
Critchlow, p. 19.
83
Ibid.
84
Ibid.
for
15
Critchlow, p. 21.
Republic,
531c.
1/1
2/1
3/1
4/1
5/1
1/2
1/3
1/4
1/5
etc.
87
327
1/1
2/1
3/1
4/1
5/1
1/2
2/2
3/2
4/2
5/2
1/3
2/3
3/3
4/3
5/3
1/4
2/4
3/4
4/4
5/4
1/5 . . . etc.
2/5
3/5
4/5
5/5
etc.
328
some time in Europe. In an overview of Kayser's work, they
summarize his contributions to "mathematics and music,
philosophy and theology, architecture, physical science, and
organic science."89 Kayser himself speculated widely on many
aspects of these fields, taking as his starting point the
basic theorems of harmonics derived from the table.9G He
also wrote volumes specifically devoted to philosophy,^
Greek architecture,^ and botany93 as well as articles on a
wealth of other subjects. The complete Pythagorean Table is
given at fig. 34.
Timaeus as Symbol
It can be seen that the applications of the musicomathematical symbolism at the heart of Plato's cosmology, as
found in the Timaeus and developed by subsequent
89
91
der
329
Fig 34 -
330
contributors to the Pythagorean tradition, have a wide range
of influence, illuminating many phenomena both in nature and
in human thought. To pursue all of these is well beyond the
scope of this study. The preceding sets forth some of the
work in this area that makes it abundantly clear how
dependent this dialogue is on a mathematical symbolism
pregnant with potential interpretations. This will be
important when we come to consider which of these
interpretations were carried forward into the modern world.
Before doing this, however, we can go one step further in
our analysis of the symbolism involved. We will restrict our
commentary to one brief statement within the dialogue.
331
speculative literature that these "riddles and puzzles" have
spawned.
But there is more to the Timaeus'
opening statement; it
94
Timaeus,
95
17a.
333
theme, the Primordial Scission allows the One to become the
Many. In Pythagorean lore, the number 4, in the form of the
tetrad, and associated with the Tetraktys, indicates
closure, as the octave reiteration creates the sense of
closure at the fourth partial. Thus, when Socrates asks,
"where is the fourth?" he is asking for completion. As the
Timaeus is involved with the creation of the world, Socrates
is asking for it to be a complete picture, for the wholeness
that is greater than the sum of the parts, for the
value of rishi,
devata
and chhandas,
for
samhita
kosmos.
is
not
limiting
solar
himself
simply
to a description
of the
physical
system.
There is, however, yet another level of interpretation
of the Divided Line," and immediately preceding the betterknown allegoryy of the Cave,100 Plato sets forth perhaps the
most explicit formulation of his theories of ontology and
99
100
Republic,
Republic,
509d-511e.
514a-521b.
335
epistemology. In light of the opening of the Timaeus,
it is
Republic,
502d-509c.
336
activity through which each of the four realms may be
apprehended. Three of these realms are well known through
ordinary experience. A fourth is posited, however, that is
reached through more unusual or esoteric means and throws
light on the inner meaning of all of Platonic doctrine.
"One, two, three, . . . but where is the fourth?"
The Four Realms. Dealing first with the external world,
which he refers to as the "visible" realm, Plato divides
this into two sub-sections, one containing merely "images,"
reflections or shadows of various objects, and the other
realm containing the objects themselves, "the animals around
us, and every kind of plant and manufactured object."10"Would you be prepared to admit," asks Socrates, "that these
sections differ in that one is genuine, one not, and that
the relation of image to original is the same as that of the
realm of opinion to that of knowledge?"103
Moving to what he calls the "intelligible" realm, that
of internal, mental objects, Plato again creates a higher
and a lower division:
In one sub-section the mind uses the originals of
the visible order in their turn as images, and has to
base its inquiries on assumptions and proceed from them
not to a first principle but to a conclusion: in the
other it moves from assumption to a first principle
102
Republic,
103
Ibid.
510a.
337
which involves no assumption, without the images used
in the other sub-section, but pursuing its inquiry
solely by and through forms themselves.104
This appears difficult to understand and, indeed, Socrates'
questioner asks him to clarify the distinction. In order to
do this, Plato points out that the mental processes utilized
in mathematical reasoning not only uses visible images but
require basic assumptions based on a knowledge of numbers,
geometric figures and so forth. Starting from these we can
proceed through consistent steps to a conclusion. He
contrasts this with another mental process that is based not
on the concept of any triangle, or square, or other figure,
but starts from the actual form of that figure itself:
. . . it treats assumptions not as principles, but as
assumptions in the true sense, that is, as starting
points and steps in the ascent to something which
involves no assumptions and is the first principle of
everything. . . the whole procedure involves nothing in
the sensible world, but moves solely through forms to
forms, and finishes with forms.105
Plato concludes by associating each of the four levels he
has described with a specific state of mind:
So please take it that there are, corresponding to the
four sections of the line, these four states of mind:
to the top section intelligence, to the second reason,
Republic,
510b.
Republic,
511b
338
Object
Faculty
Type o f
IV
ill
Forms
mathematics
etc.
physical
obj e c t s
shadows
dialectic
thinking,
reasoning
sense
perception
illusory
perception
transcendental c o g n i t i o n
s c i e n t i f i c understanding
II
I
Knowledge
common-sense b e l i e f
illusion107
Republic,
5lie.
340
and 3) synthesis is at the root of all twenty of
Plato's dialogues.108
As Desmond Lee points out, however, this definition results
in "a term whose modern associations are quite misleading in
interpreting the Republic."109
(1974), p. 311.
Republic,
540a, trans. Paul Shorey, reprinted in
Collected
Dialogues
of Plato, Edith Hamilton and Huntington
Cairns, eds., Bollingen Series LXXI (Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 1973), 518b, p. 750.
341
turn upward the vision of their souls and fix
their gaze on that which sheds light on all [and
behold] the good itself. 111
It is thus clearly this second, final phase that Plato
was referring to in the discussions of "dialectic" in
the context of the Divided Line that w e have been
examining. 112
Elsewhere, Shear clarifies the unique nature of this
"second, final phase" of the dialectic:
The dialectic, according to Plato, is so different from
the discursive reasoning characteristic of mathematics
and physics that he describes it as
(a)
(b)
(c)
(d)
111
Republic
112
113
342
results in something quite different from the discursive
mode of discourse that philosophy is typically assumed to
be. "The vision of the Good/" writes Shear, "according to
Plato, is of something quite extraordinary."114 Second, Shear
concludes that "there can really be no question ... that
Plato intends us to recognize that he is
kind of experience."
talking
about
some
directly:
the last thing to be seen and hardly seen [in the realm
of the Forms] is the idea [Form] of the good, and ...
when seen it must needs point us to the right
conclusion that this is indeed the cause for all things
of all that is right and beautiful ... being the
authentic source of truth and reason ... and anyone who
is to act wisely in private or public must have caught
sight of this.116
Plato does indeed seem to be describing a process of direct
experience rather than merely a thought process. Research by
three other scholars supports this view.
114
115
116
Republic
343
Ken Wilber and The Three Eves of Knowledge
The idea that knowledge exists on different levels is
not peculiar to Plato; such a theory of knowledge is common
to many ancient cultures, including the medieval tradition
of
Wilber:
St. Bonaventure, the great Doctor Seraphicus of the
church and a favorite philosopher of Western mystics,
taught that men and women have at least three modes of
attaining knowledge "three eyes," as he put it
(following Hugh of St. Victor, another famous mystic):
the eye of flesh, by which we perceive the external
world of space, time and objects; the eye of reason, by
which we attain a knowledge of philosophy, logic and
the mind itself; and the eye of contemplation, by which
we rise to a knowledge of transcendental realities.
. . . that particular wording . . . is Christian; but
similar ideas can be found in every major school of
traditional psychology, philosophy and religion.::7
The eye of flesh covers both levels of external
perception mentioned by Plato in the Divided Line allegory,
but when we come to the inner, mental realm, there is a
definite correspondence between Bonaventure's categories and
the Platonic analysis. In each case the distinction is a
critical one.
Having introduced the notion that these different
ontological levels exist, Wilber suggest that different
117
344
categories of phenomena can be properly understood only if
we clarify the different modes of gaining knowledge that
result and the way in which they interact with one another.
He sees a major difficulty arising when this consideration
is overlooked, resulting in what he calls "category errors,"
where one kind of knowledge is mistaken for another. He goes
on to point out numerous instances in the history of
science, philosophy and religion in which such category
errors have led to distortions and misunderstandings. Could
this not also apply to the reading of the Platonic dialogues
themselves?
345
process involves cosmic principles, for Plato's
universe is organic and organismic, a living entity
endowed with intelligence and a soul, as he says in the
Timaeus. In consequence, nothing exists in isolation;
the particular truth and being of everything is
indissolubly wedded to the truth and being of the
whole. Such an insight is wrung from experience only by
arduous effort and philosophical training. It demands
de-emphasizing the world of perception which, by virtue
of its unrelated randomness, is inimical to the
synoptic vision of truth.118
In an elegant analysis, Weber goes on to relate this
epistemology to the cosmology in which all phenomena are
related to the ultimate value, that of the Monad. At the
same time, she explains why even the third level of the
divided line is insufficient to provide comprehensive
knowledge according to Plato.
The ineffability of ultimates applies above all to the
sacrosanct Platonic concept, the One, regarding which
Plato demonstrates that all predication leads to
contradictions {Parmenides). He therefore ends the
dialogue with an ontological generalization: "Then we
may sum up the argument in a word and say truly: if One
is not, then nothing is." (166) Thus, the limitless One
can neither be defined nor described. For these
reasons, Plato in the Republic rejects even the most
exact and exalted of languages, mathematics, as
insufficient to the region of Being, to which
dialectic
alone can lead us.
The stricture upon mathematics is striking, since
in such works as Meno, Phaedo, Republic,
and Timaeus
Plato elevates it to the privileged human language. Yet
even mathematics can be faulted on two counts: First,
118
346
it utilizes diagrams and equations, both of which are
rooted in the sensible world (lines, chalk, dimensions,
etc.) and hence subject to distortion. Second and more
significant, even mathematics employs unexamined
definitions, axioms and hypotheses, which are assumed
but not known, to be true. By contrast, dialectic,
"that other sort of knowledge," yields unmediated
intuitive insight.
[Dialectic] treats its assumptions not as
first principles but as hypotheses
in the literal
sense, things "laid down" like a flight of steps
[cf. Symposium] up which it may mount all the way
to something that is not hypothetical, the first
principle of all; and having grasped this, may
turn back and . . . descend at last to a
conclusion, never making use of any sensible
object, but only of Forms, . . . (Republic 511)
If mathematics fails to explicate true being, all
language will fail. Nevertheless, if being could be
designated, Plato would do so in terms of goodness,
truth and beauty.119
Goodness, truth and beauty are ultimate principles for
Plato, yet exist in a paradoxical relationship as each one
is descriptive of the highest form. This relationship can be
explained, Prof. Weber suggests, by virtue of its parallels
with a similar concept from Vedanta philosophy.
To students of Indian philosophy, the Platonic
concepts of good, true, and beautiful find correlates
in sat (being), cit (consciousness), and ananda
(bliss) Let us note that like Plato, the Indian
philosophers denied the possibility of predicating any
properties whatever of the ultimate, exemplified in
their phrase neti,
neti: "not this, not that."
Nevertheless, they provide some approximate attributes
for Brahman, the immutable principle of reality: it is
347
one rather than many, abstract and universal rather
than concrete and particular; ideal and nonmaterial;
eternal because uncompounded, i.e. "unborn"; infinite,
not localized; hence field rather than finite thing;
beyond words, thoughts, or concepts"the one-withouta-second," as the Upanishads and later Shankara,
propounding Advaita Vedanta, term it.
Brahman, not a god but a principle, corresponds to
Plato's intelligible world, the source of being and the
principle of life. As in Plato, knowledge thereof leads
away from sense experience; after consciousness becomes
commensurable with the object it seeks, it can know
true being. "The subtle Self . . . is realized in that
pure consciousness wherein is no duality [the
meditative state] . . 12c I:i
From this parallel, Weber goes on to add her voice to
the view that Plato's description of the dialectic parallels
techniques derived from Eastern schools of philosophy.
Meditation, we are told, transmutes the conditioned and
partial into the unconditioned absolute. In Mahayana
Buddhism, for example, the aim of meditation is to
achieve the state of sunyata, emptiness, which is to
say devoid of "self-nature" or delineable properties.
It seems reasonable to conjecture that
meditation
functions
in Oriental
philosophy
as dialectic
does in
120
The Upanishads,
tr. Prabhavananda and Manchester (N.Y.:
New American Library, 1957), p. 47. (Weber's note.)
121
Weber, p. 138.
122
Ibid..
348
This "contemplation of the highest of all realities"
corresponds with the Pythagorean concept of "pure knowledge"
as referred to by Daniel Boorstin in Chapter II,123 that
results in the purification, or catharsis,
of the soul.
of
Amritabindu
Upanishads:
124
Weber, p. 140.
125
Ibid.
349
lavishes twenty accurate, nicely defined different
terms on what Western languages brutishly lump together
as "consciousness. "lZ6
The experience reported by Weber, Zolla and others
supports a kind of knowledge that is quite different from
the mere acquisition of information. The Greeks appear to
have understood this, as Greek has almost as many different
words for knowledge as Sanskrit does for consciousness. It
is illuminating to compare their meanings.
Epistm
or
Therial
of
Neoplatonic
episteme.
Sophia, gnm, gnosis,
synesis,
mathma,
mathsis,
historia,
and nous are familiar and, like
epistm and techn, have been studied. I suggest that
theasthai-theria
belongs in this constellation of
Greek words of knowing in its particular use to refer
to mental seeing, a mental image or vision.127
Press suggests that much of Plato's dialogues contained an
element that falls into a different category. He proposes
. . . that we consider theria rather than epistm as
the kind of knowledge that is to be found in the
dialogues, the kind of knowledge that Plato can have
intended to communicate, can have intended to teach,
can have expected his readers or hearers to acquire
from the dialogues, can have believed defined
philosophy and philosophers. The solution to the
puzzle, I am suggesting, is that there is knowledge of
a sort to be found in the dialogues, but that it is not
the dogmatic sort of knowledge that has been sought by
many interpreters of Plato.126
Press goes on to suggest the kind of knowledge that Plato
presents in much of his writing.
By theria or vision I mean something that is in
one way the opposite of the kind of knowledge that has
been the focus of much of Western Philosophy since
Aristotle. For one thing, it refers to a mental image
or seeing rather than to a proposition or set of
propositions. Theria in this sense refers to something
inner, immediate, comprehensive, and experiential. It
is not mediated, at least in the beginning, by
discursive thought or language, nor is it inferential.
127
351
Thus it will not take the form of an argument in the
usual technical sense.1-9
Cornford reinforces Press's view, relating the concept of
theoria
129
130
Ibid.
Timaeus,
should
not be
that.
131
132
354
practices of symbolic representation have been assumed to be
discursive philosophy in the modern manner. The various
passages that describe Plato's musical cosmology, on the one
hand the Timaeus,
355
CHAPTER VI
THE GREEK SOURCES: THE MYTH OF ER
The Context
For the second of our two Platonic sources of the music
of the spheres tradition, we turn from the Timaeus to the
Republic.
Scipio,
Plato's
that we have
356
The Myth.
The subject of Plato's narrative is an account of the
journey, or vision, of Er, a brave man whom Plato describes
as being a native of Pamphylia,
Republic,
616c, p. 450.
Republic,
617a-d, p. 451.
358
1589 intermedio
of P l a t o ' s work. He
especially
McClain, p . 5.
to
the
360
The Axis Mundi
We have noted James Haar's characterization of these
dialogues as myths, so understanding them as such requires
consideration of the insight into the nature of myth that
emerges from the work of C. G. Jung, Erich Neumann, Mircea
Eliade, Joseph Campbell and others over the last few
decades.
The first point to be made in this regard is that the
central motif in the structure described by Plato,
subsequently named the "Spindle of Necessity," falls into a
well-defined category of archetypal images known as the
axis
10
361
a stairway or ladder, a pole or, very commonly, a
tree.11
Roger Cook finds three main categories for this symbol, of
which the first applies directly to Plato's myth:
This idea of the cosmic axis and the "centre of the
world", which is extremely ancient (fourth or third
millennium B.C.) and widely diffused, is embodied
primarily in three images, which are to be found in a
great variety of forms throughout the world. These are
the Pillar or Pole, the Tree and the Mountain.1Cook's definition places the vision that Er receives
into a much broader contextthe overarching need of men and
women to locate a center in the universe, or to place
themselves at "that Center which is beyond time and which is
nothing other than the Eternal."13 This notion links the
music of the spheres tradition with large areas of
mythological symbolism, including, for example, notions of
sacred space.
Cook, p. 9.
362
inferred the only possible conclusion: namely, that the
sacred space in which the "Center of the World" is
inscribed has nothing to do with the profane space of
geometry; it has another structure and responds to
another experience.14
The desire for a sacred center appears in every cultural
setting:
Every holy place in every tradition is looked upon as a
center of the world, a place where the sacred enters
the profane, where the immeasurable is reflected back
to that which can be measured and the energy of
eternity pours itself into timeMount Olympus, for
instance, from which the Greek gods descended to the
earth; Mount Meru of the Hindus, Mount Zion and Mount
Tabor in Palestine; the Rock of Jerusalem, which was
thought to be the navel from which the whole earth
unfolded; the field of Golgotha, which is homologized
to the Garden of Eden in order that the new Adam could
be crucified at the place where the old Adam was
created; the Kaaba in Mecca, the sacred spot of the
world community of Islam; Borobudu, the great Buddhist
navel in Java; the sacred lodge of the Algonquin
Indians; the underground kiva of the Hopis. One could
go on with this list forever for, as Mircea Eliade has
truly said, "The multiplicity of even infinity of
centers of the world raises no difficulty for religious
thought, concerned as it is not with geometrical or
geographical space but with existential and sacred
space." Therefore it can be said that for religious man
his temple, his cathedral, his church, his dwellinghouse, even, indeed, his own body is symbolically
situated at the center of the world. For where is the
spring, where are the hearth and home of myth,
tradition and symbol? Where else could these be but in
man himself? How could they be outside of him?15
14
Parabola,
363
It is at the center of the world that the World Tree is
foundf an image with the broadest cultural diffusion. It has
Christian (fig. 35), Hindu (fig. 36), Buddhist (fig. 37),
and Scandinavian (fig. 38), sources among others. World tree
symbolism is central to the Garden of Eden story (fig. 39)
as well as to "pagan" creation myths (fig. 40) . In the form
of the ten sefiroth,
16
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
(See figs. 42-44.) In the manner of myth, there are
several images here that are culturally determined in the
context of Native American cosmology, while, at the same
time, the underlying image appears to be parallel to the
vision presented to Er in the afterlife.
As a further variation, in many sources a connection is
made between the axis
and the spine as the center of the human nervous system, and
thus of consciousness within the individual.
In this ancient system of symbology, which comes down
apparently from Old Bronze Age times, 2000 B.C. or so,
the human spine is represented as equivalent, in the
individual body, or microcosm, to the axial tree or
mountain of the universe, the macrocosmthe same
mythical axis mundi symbolized both in the tree of Eden
and in the towering ziggurats in the centers of ancient
Mesopotamain cities. It may be recognized, also, in the
Dantean Mount Purgatory, where the seven ascending
stages represent steps in the purification of the soul
on its way to the Beatific Vision.
The stages of the ascending Kundalinl also are
seven, there being between the root base and crown five
intermediate lotuses; and as each is touched and
stirred by the rising serpent energy, the psychology of
the yogi is transformed.18
Within this group of symbols we also find that of the
inverted tree. "The idea of the cosmic tree as imperishably
fixed in the empyrean is also expressed in the image of the
inverted tree, with its roots above and its branches below.
18
372
373
374
375
This image appears in widely different traditions."19 One of
the oldest versions of this image is from the Vedic
tradition:
Rk Veda speaks of the eternal
Ashvattha, the World Tree, whose roots
are on top and branches with leaves below.
They are the Vedic hymns.
He who knows it knows the Veda.:G
The inverted tree image also appears in the Judaic mystical
tradition. A good example of this is to be found in an
engraving from the Philosophia
sacra
(Fig. 45).
As a further dimension to this imagery, John Michell
unearths multiple examples of axis
mundi, or polar,
19
20
Cook, p . 1 8 .
376
377
born creature, never the same, never at rest, but with
a still, unvarying centre which, like the core of a
magnetic field, governs everything around it.:i
Such a world-view is reflected in highly traditional social
orders:
A natural product of this world-view is a social
order which is designed to reflect the order of the
universe. It is centred in every sense upon a symbol of
the world-pole, which is itself a symbol of eternal
law. In imitation of the universal pattern, every unit
in society replicates the entire social structure, so
an image of the world-pole is found at the centre of
every community and every household.::
The center of the world is located on a subtler, nonphysical level and equated with a unity that existed before
the manifestation of the world.
Eliade has shown how all aspects of mankind's "mythical
behaviour" reflect an underlying desire to grasp the
essential reality of the world. This is particularly
evident in man's obsession with the origin of things,
with which all myths are ultimately concerned. The
centre is, first and foremost, the point of "absolute
beginning" where the latent energies of the sacred
first broke through; where the supernatural beings of
myth, or the Gods or God of religion, first created man
and the world. Ultimately all creation takes place at
this point, which represents the ultimate source of
reality. In the symbolic language of myth and religion
is often referred to as the "navel of the world",
"Divine Egg", "Hidden Seed" or "Root of Roots"; and it
is also imagined as a vertical axis, the "cosmic axis"
21
Ibid.
378
or "axis of the world" (Axis Mundi) which stands at the
centre of the Universe and passes through the middle of
the three cosmic zones, sky, earth and the underworld.
It is fixed at the heavenly end to either the Pole Star
or the sun, the fixed points around which the heavenly
bodies rotate. From here it descends through the disk
of the earth into the world below.:3
Such a cosmology is central for practitioners of
traditional religious techniques induced through ecstatic
trance states for the purpose of gaining visionary insight:
Cook, p. 9.
Wisdom
379
darkness, or separation of sky from earth. The All is
for the present impounded in the first principle, which
may be spoken of as the Person, Progenitor, Mountain,
Tree, Dragon, or endless Serpent.25
The same imagery can also be an aspect of an anthropomorphic
figure, as with the Vedic figure of Siva:
The word Siva means "auspicious" and Lord Siva is
venerated as the source of all that is good and
auspicious, and as the primordial source of all
creation. Siva who is unmanifest, arupa, or without
form, chose to manifest Himself on this night
[Mahasivaratri] as an effulgent pillar of light,
without beginning or end. This light represents the
primal, cosmic energy or vibration that is the source
of all creation. From this light emanated Brahma, the
Creator, Vishnu, the Protector and Rudra, the Destroyer
that causes the final dissolution of all things back
into the unmanifest.
While this is the abstract concept of the
unmanifest, which is difficult to comprehend, Siva also
takes shape as the Linga or cosmic egg and this is the
abstract and concrete symbol that is usually worshiped
in Siva temples.26
In another of his forms, Siva, according to Danielou,
manifests himself centuries later as Dionysius. Thus, on the
level of myth, another link is forged between the Greek line
that leads to Orpheus, Pythagoras and Plato as well as far
more ancient, legendary figures. It is in alchemy, however,
that all the symbols are brought together, cosmic tree,
25
26
380
cosmic mountain, and the numerical symbolism of Pythagoras
that harks back to the opening of the Timaeus:
The seedling atop the Cosmic Mountain symbolizes the
fusion of earth and sky. In the alchemical tradition
Maria [Prophetessa] is said to shriek out in ecstasy:
"One becomes two, two becomes three, and out of the
third comes the One as the fourth." As a formula of the
alchemical process, her saying also describes the
germination of the seedling into the Cosmic Tree.27
This telling conjunction of images demonstrates the
multi-dimensional nature of symbolism embedded in ancient
literature in general, and the music of the spheres
tradition in particular. Again, Plato's Divided Line analogy
provides the framework for the consideration of these
various levels of interpretation. Plato has also provided
sources for each of the main aspects of musical cosmology.
The Timaeus presents the basis for the underlying
mathematical symbolism while the Myth of Er conveys the
axis
27
381
aspect of Plato's intelligible worldlevels three and four
respectively of the Divided Line scheme.28 It is also valid
to consider these patterns as they manifest in the visible
world. The mistake that Socrates tries to avert by asking
"where is the fourth?" consists of considering everything
only on one level. Like Kepler, we have to try to understand
both the archetype
28
29
382
ordinary knowledge as waking is from dreaming.3C As Lee
writes, "Unfortunately, Plato never gives in his dialogues a
full or direct exposition of the theory [of Forms] . . .
[or] developed a set technical terminology."31 Lee refers us
to Cornford, who defines Platonic Forms as "ideals or
patterns, which have a real existence independent of our
minds and of which the many individual things called by
their names in the world of appearances are like images or
reflections."32 Images and reflections require light in
order to be seen, and Plato provides this in the form of the
sun in the analogy of the same name33 that immediately
precedes the section on the Divided Line. Immediately
subsequent to the latter section, which acts as an
introduction to it, is the analogy of the Cave, and here the
light is provided by a fire. But Plato indicates that he is
using the sun as an analogy for the highest object of
knowledge, the Form of the Good itself, calling it the
"child of the Good."34 Plato goes on, "The good has begotten
30
31
Lee, p. 264.
32
Republic,
34
Republic,
508c, p . 308.
383
it in its own likeness, and it bears the same relation to
sight and visible objects in the visible realm that the good
bears to intelligence and intelligible objects in the
intelligible realm."35
As Lee points out, the actual nature of the Forms has
to be inferred from passages such as this. But etymology
provides another clue. One of the main terms Plato uses for
the Forms is eidos.
nada.
on the level of
Ibid.
36
384
principle of all lesser things, concluded that its nature is
number.37 Campbell puts all of this into the context of
mythology:
There is a beautiful saying of Novalis:"The seat of the
soul is there, where the outer and the inner worlds
meet." That is the wonder-land of myth. From the outer
world the senses carry images to the mind, which do not
become myth, however, until there transformed by fusion
with accordant insights, awakened as imagination from
the inner world of the body. The Buddhists speak of
Buddha Realms. These are planes and orders of
consciousness that can be brought to mind through
meditations on appropriately mythologized forms. Plato
tells of universal ideas, the memory of which is lost
at birth but through philosophy may be recalled.39
These correspond to Bastian's "Elementary Ideas" and
Jung's "Archetypes of the Collective Unconscious."39
The Archetypes. The theory of archetypes was developed
by Jung after extensive clinical studies of the dreams,
artwork, etc., of patients suffering from, and frequently
recovering from, disorders such as schizophrenia. Jung
noticed patterns in these phenomena, with similar forms
arising in different patients at similar stages of their
disease and recovery.
38
385
unconscious mind contains inherited patterns, modes of
functioning similar to the instinctive patterns that
influence animal and, to some extent human, behavior. He
half borrowed, half coined the term archetype from the Greek
arche
and History
a Thousand Faces.
of Consciousness*1
and
In his writings,
40
386
representations that vary a great deal without losing
their basic patternsThere is a close connection between Jung's theory of
archetypes and Plato's doctrine of the Forms; Jung states
that he based his concept on Plato's. There is a distinct
difference, however. The concept of archetypes is almost
Aristotelian, as universals are determined from the
examination of particulars; myths, stories, and dreams are
essentially the phenomenology that suggest the existence of
underlying patterns. There is no question
perceiving
the archetypes
themselves.
of
directly
42
387
An archetypeso far as we can establish it
empiricallyis an image. An image, as the very term
denotes, is a picture of something. An archetypal image
is like the portrait of an unknown man in a gallery.
His name, his biography, his existence in general are
unknown, but we assume nevertheless that the picture
portrays a once living subject, a man who was real. We
find numberless images of God, but we cannot produce
the original. There is no doubt in my mind that there
is an original behind our images, but it is
inaccessible. We could even be aware of the original
since its translation into psychic terms is necessary
in order to make it perceptible at all.44
To use an analogy of our own, if we hold a magnet under
a sheet of paper on which we scatter iron filings, the
filings form a definite pattern that reflects the influence
of the magnetic field. We see the pattern; we do not see the
field. Similarly, we see clinical and mythological
phenomena. We see patterns in them. We speak of archetypes,
but we do not see them. We infer their existence from
observation of the phenomena. However compelling the
clinical evidence reported by Jung, and the cultural
evidence collected by Neumann, Eliade, Campbell, et al.,
lacking empirical evidence, the theory of archetypes remains
thata theory. Thus, for example, the axis
44
388
in his Divided Line analogy, Plato makes it clear that
direct perception of the forms themselves is not
only
possible
education.
but absolutely
necessary
for a complete
Stras
45
389
archetypal forms of experience. The study involved the use
of mental techniques described by Patanjali in the third
chapter of the Yoga Sutras,
antiquity.46
The Yoga Stras
of
390
create the state of pure consciousness, and then
perturbing it in various ways, using specific stras or
phrases which contain ideas which determine the nature
of the subsequent effects.47
Two different sections of the Yoga Stras
are important
Patanjali
dharana,
391
experiments to be carried out on pure consciousness" to
which Josephson refers. Studies such as this reflect the
growing interest in consciousness studies which has led to
the kind of conference at which Josephson made the abovequoted statement,46 as well as to the creation of some new
academic journals. Shear, whose analysis of Plato's Divided
Line allegory we cited above, is the one of the founding
editors of the major journal in this field,49 and has been
involved in some of the experiments in question.
As part of a program in the psychophysiology of
consciousness,50 Shear conducted research with subjects who
were working with Patanjali's text, not as an item of
philosophical attention, but as an experimental tool in the
manner described by Josephson. Such an approach, to some
degree, parallels Press' view of the intended application of
all or part of Plato's dialogues. One stra
in particular
48
Journal of Consciousness
Studies,
published in the United
Kingdom and United States by Imprint Academic, Thorverton,
UK.
50
392
The Pole Star. At chapter III, verse 29 of the Yoga
Sutras
as
theoria.the subjects in
51
Dvivedi, p. 82.
52
393
reported in the 1978 American Psychological Society meeting
as follows:
According to Patanjali, proper use {samyama) of this
stra should enliven the already established background
state of pure consciousness and produce the indicated
result. One would naturally expect to gain (internal)
awareness of the motion of the stars as we normally
perceive and conceive of them. Such perceptions do
represent frequent early phases of the experience. But
in many cases, where samadhi or pure consciousness is
particularly well established/ the experience quickly
develops into something quite different. The pole star
is seen as a point on a long rotating shaft of light.
Rays of light come out from the shaft like the ribs of
an umbrella. The umbrella-like structure on which the
stars are embedded is seen rotating. Along the axis of
light are other umbrella-like structures, one nested in
the other, each rotating at its own ratef each with its
own color, and each making a pure lovely sound.
Remarkably/ we find the same experience recorded in
detail in Plato's Republic.**
Shear is here referring to the Myth of Er. The
structure that Plato depicts therein is remarkably similar
to the ones described by the experimental subjects. (Fig.
46/ sections A through E, presents an artist's impression of
how these might look that was used in the publication of the
study.) While the participants had extensive training in the
Yoga practices involved/ none of them were Plato scholars or
had any familiarity with the Myth of Er or Plato in
general.55 During the study, they were asked to submit
54
55
395
sketches and/or drawings of any experiences resulting from
the use of this particular stra
57
58
400
potentials which underlies all of our subsequent
knowledge.59
Elsewhere Shear expands on this description.
Plato . . . held that we are capable of recognizing
things only because of the existence and enlivenment of
transcendental, inborn Forms or structures of pure
intelligence. According to his theory, our experiences
cause particular corresponding Forms to be enlivened,
and we then classify the objects experienced in terms
of these Forms.*c
He goes on to describe the influence of this idea on
Western philosophy and psychology, and to mention some
modern proponents of similar concepts, such as Jung, but
also Chomsky and Piaget. However, Shear acknowledges that:
In the absence of any technique for isolating,
activating and experiencing innate archetypes . . .
modern scientific thinkers have generally rejected them
as illusory, and the generally accepted position about
Plato is that his reasoning to the Forms (whether
correct or incorrect) led him to invent them.*1
Shear is referring to the unavailability of such
techniques to scientific researchers, at least until
recently. Plato himself, however, makes direct mention of
such techniques. He argues that there is
59
Shear (1981), p. 3.
60
61
Shear (1981), p. 2.
401
. . . a capacity which is innate in each man's mind,
and that the organ by which he learns is like an eye
which cannot be turned from darkness to light unless
the whole body is turned; in the same way the mind as a
whole must be turned away from the world of change
until its eye can bear to look straight at reality, and
at the brightest of all realities which is what we call
the good.62
Plato is not referring here to gaining empirical knowledge;
for that the attention is turned outwards, through the
senses, towards the visible realm. It is for the higher
knowledge of the Forms for which the attention must be
turned inward. He continues:
Then this turning around of the mind itself might be
made a subject of professional skill,63 which would
effect the conversion as easily and effectively as
possible. It would not be concerned to implant sight,
but to ensure that someone who had it already was not
either turned in the wrong direction or looking the
wrong way.64
The Prelude to the Song Itself. Shortly after this
passage, Plato embarks on a discussion of the later stages
of the training required for his studentsfuture
philosopher kings if he is successful. The curriculum set
forth includes the mathematical arts, but presented in a
sequence that is slightly different from that of the
62
Republic,
63
Techn.
64
Republic,
518c-d, p . 322.
(Translator's note).
518d-e, p . 322.
402
Pythagorean quadrivium. That schema, as we have seen, has a
cosmological component, describing the unfolding of creation
through one, two, three and four dimensions. Plato's purpose
in this passage is educational, presenting the sequence in
which these disciplines should be tackled. He begins with
arithmetic, skips to plane geometry and then to astronomy.
At this point, however, Plato changes his mind and adds
solid geometry, considering it a mistake to proceed
"straight from plane geometry to solid bodies in motion
without considering solid bodies first on their own. The
right thing is to proceed from second dimension to third."""5
He then proceeds to astronomy, and finally to harmonics. His
emphasis, as we have noted, is on the perception of the
Formsthe eternal, unchanging phenomena that represent
aspects of Being rather than becoming. But these subjects
are "only a prelude to the main theme we have to learn."66
At the culmination of the entire process (after thirty or
more years), Plato's students turn to the study of the Form
of the Good itself, and for this, the technique to be used
is the higher form of the dialectic, referred to by Plato as
"the coping-stone that tops our educational system; it
Republic,
528b, p. 336.
Republic,
531e, p. 341.
403
completes the course of studies and there is no other study
that can be placed above it."67
Dialectic and Yoaa In light of the foregoing
discussion, both in this chapter and the previous one, it
appears that this coping-stone is a technique, or series of
techniques, aimed at bringing direct knowledge of the
fourth, and highest, level of knowledgeknowledge of the
Forms and the Form of the Good itself. These structures have
also been referred to as archetypes, which Shear defines as
"deep universal potentials of intelligence."66 Moreover:
[Plato] held that they can be experienced, that they
are responsible for giving form to all of our knowledge
and experience, and that knowledge of them is therefore
necessary for one to understand what knowledge really
is and how to live a fully knowledgeable and effective
life. And they are properly known not by inference, but
only by experience of the highest level of reality.69
This understanding is not unique to Plato, however.
Similar accounts are found in Vedanta, Taoism and other
Eastern philosophical traditions. In Vedanta, for
example, the 'Veda1 or (fundamental) truth is held to
be the collection of resonances of the unmanifest,
subsets of which are selectively activated by our
particular experiences. When we see something the
^impression' of that object is said to *fall' upon this
transcendental field within and enliven corresponding
resonances which, when thus amplified, then produce the
67
Republic,
66
Shear (1981) , p. 3.
69
Ibid.
534e, p. 347.
404
subjective phenomena that we refer to as knowledge and
perception.70
As an extension of this understanding, the
prescriptions of the Yoga-Stras
or "Yoga
svarupe
Wasthnam,"
70
71
Yoga-Stras,
I,ii. Dvivedi, p. 1.
72
Yoga-Stras,
I,iii. Dvivedi, p. 3.
73
74
405
the Good. This is the application of the "Eye of Spirit" of
St. Bonaventure, the "lumen superius,
the light of
75
Ken Wilber, Eye to Eye: The Quest for the New Paradigm
(New York: Anchor/Doubleday, 1983), p. 3.
76
77
Ibid.
406
Peter Gorman writes, "This analysis of number by Pythagoras
is a forerunner of the Platonic dialectic which became a
mystical vehicle by which man attained to the divine."79
However this level of experience is attained, it has
been described with various degrees of sophistication. Hindu
sstras,
78
A Life
407
course of involution,
or the emergence of the lower
from the higher, the archetypes are the first
created
forms, upon which all subsequent
creation
is
patterned
(from the Greek archetypon,
meaning "that which was
created as a pattern, mold, or model"). (Wilber's
italics)80
The Magical Tradition and the Realm of Death
Undoubtedly, we are dealing here with what Kearney termed
the "magical tradition,"81 one that appears to be
represented in diverse cultural settings. Terminology
differs from one tradition to the next; we do not find Plato
speaking of samadhi,
Meno, Theaetetus
and Phaedrus,
Plato explicitly
death,"
that is,
accustoming the soul "to withdraw from all contact with the
80
81
408
body and concentrate itself by itself . . . alone by
itself."8- This is remarkably similar to Patanjali's
description of the goal of yoga where "the seer abides in
himself."63
The Orbits of the Soul. The similarities do not end
there. If we turn back to the Timaeus,
82
83
84
Timaeus,
43, p. 59.
409
of the body and of the senses settles down to the point that
allows for the experience of consciousness in its state of
least excitation "a flame which does not flicker in a
windless place," as Lord Krishna describes it in the
Baghavad-Gita.86
stras.
86
AA, p. 60.
410
dramatic reduction in the metabolic rate.86 It seems
reasonable to interpret Plato1s reference to the "stream of
growth and nourishment11 as the metabolism and its slowing
down to the physiological correlates of the state of
samadhi.
samadhi.
that is frequently
Sutras:
66
411
In each case, a technique is applied to calm the disturbance
of mind, which according to Plato, is caused by the activity
of the senses and according to the Hathapradipika
results
Patanjali describes a
50
412
which we could term Sameness, and intellectfor Patanjali
the subtlest aspect of individual mind. As the role of
intellect is defined as the perceiving of distinctions
between the various aspects of experience,9- it is not
unreasonable to associate this with Difference.93
rather than
epistm.
92
93
Yoga-Sutras,
413
symbolism according to a schema that Plato himself sets
forthf both in detail in the Republic
form at the opening of the Timaeus.
On another
414
Given that Plato, along with Pythagoras, admonishes us
repeatedly that such fundamental levels of knowledge are the
only ones worth pursuing, it should be no surprise to find
these themes echoed in his work and thus at the very source
of the music of the spheres tradition. Whether Plato has
usually been understood in this way is quite another thing.
To determine this we have to examine the writers who
conveyed Plator s ideas from ancient Athens into medieval
Europe and beyond.
415
CHAPTER VII
THE LATER SOURCES
himself,
those
considered
most important
by
416
From the time of Plato's death until the presentation
of the Florence intermedin
1,931
particularly the
Calcidius
It was a very uncertain path. The Republic
had appeared
for example,
417
dependent upon Latin translations. In the case of the
Timaeus,
418
encompasses the structure of the world-soul, including the
essential numbers of the underlying riddle, and Plato's
admonitions regarding the primacy of universals. But we have
seen that one of the keys to the interpretation outlined in
the present study does not come from the Timaeus
from the Divided Line analogy in the Republic.2
at all but
It seems
Aristotle
A further barrier to such an interpretation existed in
the person of Aristotle. If Plato had a limited influence
during the Middle Ages, it was Aristotle who filled the
vacuum, since many of the latter's works were available both
in the original Greek and in translation from the twelfth
century onwards. Aristotle's influence on medieval thought
was profound; his writings were one of the mainstays of
university life in Europe. And his influence went well
beyond the medieval era, as James Hankins points out. "No
one," he writes, "would any longer maintain the facile
generality, once the staple fare of textbooks, that the
419
Middle Ages were an Age of Aristotle and the Renaissance an
Age of Plato."4 But, although Aristotle was Plato's student,
he was not a supporter of all of Plato's doctrines; in fact,
he was a detractor of many of them.
refers to Aristotle as the "advocatus
Specifically, Haar
diaboli,
Renaissance
(Leiden:
Haar, p. 85.
doctrine
as a statement
of physical
fact, denies the
music of the spheres with obvious delight (De caelo,
290bl2-291a27;.8 (Author's italics.)
Heninger understands Plato's doctrine to be essentially
symbolic and mathematical rather than a "statement of
physical fact." Referring to the concept of cosmos as
formulated by the Pythagoreans, and again by Renaissance
thinkers, he writes:
The most comprehensive representation of cosmos . . .
was the concept of universal harmonyin its simplest
form, the music of the spheresand this concept
embraced not only arithmetic, music and geometry, but
also astronomy. It was, in fact, the statement of
cosmos to which each of the quadrivial sciences
contributed coordinately.9
Therefore universal harmony u . . . represents the
concept of order as order prevails in the heavens, a divine
plan that informs and controls our universe.":c To take this
concept and reduce it to a mere statement of physical fact,
or even to emphasize the primacy of physical fact, is to
contradict Plato's specific instructions regarding the
correct way to approach astronomy, harmonics, and so forth,
421
and does not appear to reflect Plators intentions.11 Plato,
like Pythagoras, was interested above all else in direct
knowledge of unchanging essences, in Plato's case in
perceiving the Forms at the highest level of the Divided
Line schema. But Aristotle does not accept Plato's theory of
the Forms.
Aristotle's critical study of Plato1s theory of
universals had convinced him that universals could not
exist by themselves, but only in particular things.
Since substances must be capable of independent
existence, it appears that they cannot be universals
but must be particulars. However, this generated a
dilemma since Aristotle also believed that only
universals were definable and the objects of scientific
knowledge (in the Analytics
model). Thus if substances
are knowable, they cannot be particulars. But now it
looks as if substances cannot exist at all since they
cannot be either universals or particulars. Aristotle's
dilemma arises because he was tempted to regard
particular substances as ontologically primary, while
(at the same time) insisting that understanding and
definition are of universals. The latter thought he
shared with Plato; but the former is very much his own,
and one which led to a fundamentally different account
of numbers and universals than the one Plato offered.::
This view with regard to ontology extended to
Aristotle's understanding of the processes of thought, and
thus to his epistemology.
11
422
Aristotle proceeds to show how reason is related to
imagination. A thought is not an image, but we cannot
think without images. More definitely, "the faculty of
thought thinks the forms in the images." An image is a
particular mental occurrence just as much as is a
sensation; thought first occurs when the mind discerns
a point of identity between two or more images. But
even when a universal has thus been grasped, it is
Aristotle's doctrine that imagery is still needed by
the mind. "The soul never thinks without an image."
Just as in geometrical proof, though we make no use of
the particular size of the triangle, we draw one of a
particular size, so in thought generally, if we are
thinking of something non-quantitative, we yet imagine
something quantitative, and if our object be something
indefinite, we imagine it as of a definite quantity.
Nothing can be thought of except in connexion with a
continuum, and nothing, however timeless, can be
thought of except in connection with time. Aristotle
seems here to be setting himself against Plato's view,
expressed in the Divided Line, that while scientific
thought needs the aid of imagery, philosophical thought
deals with pure forms without any such assistance. The
use of imagery is the price, Aristotle maintains, which
reason has to pay for its association with the lower
mental faculties.13
In this context, philosophical thought refers to the
fourth level of Plato's Divided Line analogy, accessed via
the higher level of the dialectic, as discussed in Chapter
V. According to Plato, it is the level of mental functioning
that is carried out without the use of images. When
Aristotle denies this possibility, Plato's exposition of
universal harmony as a system of underlying Forms giving
order and structure to the external world becomes untenable.
12
W. D. Ross, Aristotle
p. 148.
423
We are left to seek the source of order purely within the
world of physical phenomena.
Conflicting views of Platonic and Aristotelean thought
have been topics of debate for 2,400 years, of course.
Marjorie Grene attempts to sum up the current view.
Those who are steeped in the dialectic of the Platonic
dialogues, for whom western thought is xa series of
footnotes to Plato', see in Aristotle a pupil who
misconstrued his master. Aristotelian form is Platonic
form surreptitiously tucked away in the visible world.
For Plato, the Ideas can be known only by a painful and
profound conversion; the philosopher must climb
laboriously out of the cave to the sun above. Aristotle
denied this necessity, and was left with the dilemma
[of] the contradiction between the denial of real
universals and the assertion of the universality of
real knowledge.
. . Those more interested in the development of
logic, on the other hand, are inclined to see in
Plato' s work a first adumbration of a correct logic,
brought to full flower by his most brilliant pupil, and
so for them Plato is but a halting Aristotle.14
Grene finds both of these viewpoints one-sided and proposes
a more balanced position:
Each of these views boasts doughty supporters,
especially in contemporary English-speaking philosophy,
the second. But the latter position is as unfair to
Plato as the former is to Aristotle, and there are
also, scattered through the literature, proponents of a
third view, which respects equally both master and
pupil, but sees in the relation between them neither
essential decline nor essential progress, but two
14
(Bristol, U.K.:
424
deeply divergent attitudes to experience, to man and
the world.15
Such a view also attacks the notion that Aristotle moved
beyond Plato in developing a more "modern" world-view.
The picture of a development from Platonic
^metaphysics' to observation and *science' is based on
a shallow view of both. All science rests on some
metaphysics, some vision of reality. Moreover, the
vision of modern science in its most authoritative
branches, that is, first and foremost, in mathematical
physics, is in several important ways more Platonic
than Aristotelian: in its reliance on mathematical
forms as the instrument of all science, for example, or
in its scepticism about the power of language (even
formal language) to enunciate once and for all the
definitive answer to its problems.16
A balanced view of the Plato/Aristotle dichotomy is
important for understanding the three strands of Greek
thought. It should be remembered that Kearney attributes the
magical view not to Plato but to the Neo-Platonists, whose
focus was on the transcendental to the exclusion of the
physical world. For Plato, however, there are four levels of
the Divided Line, and while he emphasizes the importance of
the highest level it is not necessarily at the exclusion of
the others. Let us remember that at the beginning of the
Timaeus he suggests that the vision presented in the
Republic
15
16
Grene, p. 37.
425
My feelings are rather like those of a man who has seen
some splendid animals, either in a picture or really
alive but motionless, and wants to see them moving and
engaging in some of the activities for which they
appear to be formed.17
Socrates' question, "One, two, threebut where is the
fourth?" in the context of the Divided Line, can be read in
both directions; it points to the level of the Forms,
arrived at via the dialectic in its advanced mode, but it
also suggests movement in the opposite direction, from the
abstract to the concrete, from the Forms to their
actualization in the "real" world, the world of life and
motion.
Again, the issue is one of balance. Grene seeks this by
considering Plato and Aristotle together, an idea that is
reflected in Raphael's great painting, The School of
Athens
(fig. 50). Plato is seen with his hand raised to the heavens
while Aristotle points doggedly down to earth. Equally
significant (and everything in Renaissance painting is
deeply symbolic), Plato holds a copy of the Timaeus, a
highly abstract work of cosmology, while Aristotle clutches
a copy of his Ethics, which deals with far more practical
concerns.
17
426
427
There is an alternative view, however, namely that both
Plato and Aristotle strove for balance, each in his own way.
Aristotle, in rejecting Plato's view of universals, tried to
develop one of his own, characterized by Bertrand Russell as
"Plato diluted by common sense."18 This is difficult,
Russell adds, "because Plato and common sense do not mix
easily. "19 When it comes to the music of the spheres,
however, the main effect of the denial of Plato's theory of
Forms is to lead away from the Pythagorean concept of
cosmos,
18
Ibid.
(New
428
The Tradition Unfolds
Of course, the music of the spheres persisted for
several centuries before it faded away. According to
Heninger, this was in spite of Aristotle's position. After
explaining the younger philosopher's rejection of Plato's
ideas about the universal harmony, Heninger continues:
But the idea nonetheless persisted because no other
statement of cosmos conveyed its order and beauty with
Nicomachus
We have already cited a prime example of this: the
statement by the second-century philosopher Nicomachus of
Gerasa, in the Manual of Harmonics,
20
Heninger, p. 179.
429
notes were derived from the seven stars.:l He is not
entirely confident about this, however. He actually begins
this sentence with "It is probable that," and when he goes
on to describe these "swiftly whirling bodies"22 and their
relationships, he feels compelled to preface his remarks
with "For they say that . . . "2i The title of the section in
question, Chapter 3 of the Harmonics,
is equally lacking in
Theon
We find a s i m i l a r l y imprecise assessment of the
universal harmony in another second-century commentator,
Theon of Smyrna, i n h i s only surviving work, Expositio
mathematicarum
Useful
21
for
ad legendum Platonem
Understanding
utilium
rerum
(Mathematics
Plato) . As Godwin i s c a r e f u l t o
Ibid.
23
Ibid.
24
Ibid.
430
point out/25 Theon begins his dissertation with something of
a disclaimer: u . . . w e will not hesitate to relate what our
predecessors have discovered/ nor to make more widely known
the Pythagorean traditions which we have inherited without
ourselves claiming to have discovered the least part of
it.":6 Undeterred/ he proceeds to expound on u The order of
the Planets and the Celestial Concert"27 but begins with
this statement: "Here are the opinions of certain
Pythagoreans relative to the position and the order of the
spheres or circles on which the planets are moving."-8 The
planets he lists are the Earth/ the Moonf Hermes ( Mercury),
Venus/ the sunf Marsf Jupiter and Saturn. For this
arrangement he cites Alexander of Aetolia: u In these verses
Alexander has indicated the order for the spheres that he
has determined."29 Theon then proceeds to criticize
Alexander's arrangement. u It is evident that he arbitrarily
imagined the intervals which separate them/ and nearly all
25
26
rerum mathematicarum
ad
Mathematics
Useful
for Understanding
28
Theonf p. 91.
Theonf p. 93.
Plato
(San Diego:
431
the rest."30 Theon suggests that the seven-stringed lyre in
Alexander's description, the image of the divine world
created by Hermes (Mercury), falls short. There are supposed
to be nine sounds, but only six tones are mentioned, and
Alexander's account does not fit into either the diatonic or
the chromatic system. By comparison, Theon then presents the
system of Eratosthenes, who assigns a different order to the
planets, one that Theon prefers. But then he states that
"the mathematicians establish neither this order nor a like
order among the planets."31
A Dubious Beginning
It is from this beginning that the music of the spheres
tradition emerges from antiquity. There follows one and a
half millennia of speculation about the various planet-tone
relationships, a luxuriant and exotic literary edifice,
built upon a most insecure foundation. Exactly how the notes
and the planets are assigned is a prime example, for the
most part, of blind speculation, opinion, even whimsy
everything, in short, that both Plato and Pythagoras would
have condemned. By the eighteenth century this structure had
become so unsound that there was little left for the
3C
Ibid.
31
Ibid.
432
enlightenment encyclopedists but to condemn and dismantle
it.
It is beyond the scope of this study to examine all
this literature in detail. That has been done admirably by
Haar and Godwin and, to some degree, by Heninger and James.
For our purposes, it will be best to concentrate on the most
significant works through which the music of the spheres
tradition was transmitted. Claude Palisca has identified
four writers who appear to have conveyed the essential
elements of this theme into medieval Europe.
The main links to ancient music theory known during the
Middle Ages were the De institutions
musica of
Boethius, the Commentazius in Somnium
Scipionis
(Commentary on the Dream of Scipio) of Macrobius, the
De Nuptiis Philologiae
et Mercurii
(Marriage of
Philology and Mercury) by Martianus Capella, and the
Institutiones
divinarum et humanarum
litterarum
(Institutions of Divine and Human Letters) of
Cassiodorus.3:
By examining each of these in turn, we can gain some sense
of the way this tradition unfolds. In particular, we can
attempt to determine to what extent the full meaning of the
original Greek sources, specifically the passages by Plato,
is maintained in the process.
32
433
The Latin Sources
Boethius
The first of these texts, the De institutione
musics of
Both a
33
434
Christian himself or, at least, as someone sympathetic to
Christian theology, he anticipated St. Thomas Aquinas in
attempting to reconcile Greek thought with Christian
doctrine. Through these efforts he made a major contribution
to the foundation of medieval culture.
Seen by Gibbon as "the last of the Romans whom Cato and
Tully would have acknowledged as their countryman" and
by R.W. Chambers, with Cassiodorus and St. Benedict, as
"one of three founders of the Middle Ages", he is
eminent among those who served to transmit the wisdom
and graces of the Ancient World "to restore the
balance" of the new."34
Boethius' most famous treatise was a largely
of Philosophy,
which was
was
34
Boethius:
His Life,
(Oxford: Basil
435
accomplish in his philosophy. "One aspect of Boethius'
intellectual achievement," writes his biographer, "which . .
. impresses itself on the reader of the Consolation
as one
36
Lat.
xvix. 529
37
38
Ibid.
437
to be original."39 We will find this to be the case with the
authors of all four of the Latin texts under consideration
De institutione
musica.
musica
Institutione
Musica.
39
Chadwick, in Gibson, p. 3.
438
character."40
40
41
439
The influence of the Platonic tradition on The
Principles
of Music is further seen in the expressed
pedagogical purpose of these mathematical works. These
disciplines are not treated as ends in themselves but
rather are considered as a preparation for the study of
philosophy. They are described as the "ouadrivium," the
four-way path "by which one should come to those places
where the more excellent mind, having been delivered
from our senses, is led to the certainty of
intelligence."42 These places of which Boethius is
speaking are in the land of Platonic philosophy where
pure forms, essences, exist in and of themselves and
cease to "suffer radical change through participation
in the corporeal."43 Music and the other mathematical
disciplines are thus not a part of philosophy proper as
they would be in the Aristotelian tradition, but they
are rather pedagogical preparations for the ascent to
pure philosophy in the Platonic sense of the word.44 45
The Principles
of Music was thus written more for the
student who aspired to philosophy than for the
practicing musician, even though it was the practicing
musician's most authoritative theory text for almost a
thousand years.46
Boethius makes this approach explicit in discussing the
relative merits of reason and the senses in the study of
music. This is found in Book I, section 9 of De
musica,
institutione
I. i., in Boethius
43
44
45
46
Boethius, p. 17.
47
vii, 523-534.
440
judgment ought to be given to the senses/' he states,
"but
48
49
Republic,
50
of Music,
Calvin M. Bower,
441
Boethius then proceeds to tell the story of Pythagoras
and the blacksmith's shop, including the essential series of
ratios 6:8:9:12. He then goes on to consider the sense of
hearing and the nature of consonances. Following this, at
Book I, section 34, he returns to the topic of reason versus
the senses by giving us another telling classification, this
time of musicians. He gives us three categories: "The first
class consists of those who perform on instruments, the
second of those who compose songs, and the third of those
who judge instrumental performance and song."5:
The first of these groups is quickly dismissed; they
"are excluded from comprehension of musical knowledge, since
. . . they act as slaves. None of them makes use of reason;
rather, they are totally lacking in thought."-: The second
group does not fare much better. Boethius refers to them as
poets, "a class led to song not so much by thought and
reason as by a certain natural instinct. For this reason
this class, too, is separated from music."53 It is only the
third group, "that which acquires an ability for judging, so
that it can carefully weigh rhythms and melodies and the
composition as a whole," that warrant serious consideration
51
52
Ibid.
53
Ibid.
442
in Boethius' estimation. This class, he writes, "since it is
totally grounded in reason and thought, will rightly be
esteemed as musical."54
Mathematics, pragmatic and mystical. With these
passages, Boethius establishes music as a mathematical
discipline. But the exact nature of this discipline, as
Boethius understands it, is of significant in determining
the extent to which his description reflects Plato's
intentions.
It is evident from our earlier discussion that an
emphasis on mathematics characterizes two seemingly opposed
strands of knowledge emerging from the Greeks, the magical
and mechanistic traditions, symbolized by Plato on the one
hand, Archimedes on the other. To which of these schools
should Boethius be assigned? In his essay on Boethius' work
in arithmetic and music, John Caldwell brings out
information that is critical to this question. He points out
that Boethius stands at the very end of a tradition of
mathematical philosophy that had extended for nearly a
thousand years. Characteristic of this tradition was the
tendency to classify mathematical subjects into the four
areas that Boethius was to call the quadrivium, which, along
with the triviumgrammar, rhetoric and dialecticformed
54
Ibid.
443
the seven liberal arts of the medieval university
curriculum.
The emergence of this particular series of
subjects was not without its vicissitudes. Pythagoras
and his followers were much occupied with the mystical
properties of numbers and their relation to each other;
and numerical relationships are the unifying factor of
these particular arts. Plato in the Republic specified
arithmetic, plane geometry, solid geometry, astronomy
and ^harmony' for special study as conducive to the
good of the soul through the contemplation of the
eternal verities as expressed by the properties of
numbers. These had their practical application, but
they came to be sharply distinguished from, and exalted
above, such pragmatic disciplines as medicine,
geography, pneumatics and architecture. Nevertheless,
Plato's treatment implied a rather different emphasis
from that of the early Pythagoreans, and it encouraged
a more disciplined, though still speculative, treatment
of arts which were after all of practical origin and of
at least potentially practical application. Thus it was
possible for Nicomachus of Gerasa, writing in the
second century A.D., to write two completely different,
but still speculative, works of arithmetic. One, the
Theologumena, was purely mystical in content; the
other, the Introduction,
was more down to earth in
analysing the real properties of number; but neither
could be equated with the practical business of
computation, which the Greeks called logistics.
On the whole, it was the more disciplined,
analytical approach to mathematical philosophy which
prevailed in later antiquity. Occasionally a mystical
element might obtrude into a fundamentally more
disciplined work (as in Nicomachus' brief extant work
on music), but it was the latter
type which carried
the
day. (Author's italics)55
55
444
Which of these approaches was Boethius folowing? There
is something of a dichotomy here. His underlying purpose
might suggest an emphasis on the mystical:
Boethius applied the Pythagorean philosophy to
Christian thought with the intention of showing how
music related to God, the most beautiful of all things.
He felt that an aspect of the supreme beauty of God was
expressed by the perfection of audible numerical ratios
in music. Thus, music was seen as a means of gaining
some understanding of the divine.50
It is difficult, however, to extract any sense of esoteric
knowledge from the text itself. Boethius' emphasis
throughout is on the use of reason, thus the third level of
Plato's Divided Line. While distrusting St. Bonaventure's
"eye of flesh," Boethius turns to the "eye of reason," with
no sense of the "eye of spirit" entering into his discourse.
He takes pains, both in the treatise on music and that on
arithmetic, to distinguish between the unchanging immutable
and changing material values. Pythagoras, he says, "held
that philosophy was the knowledge and study of whatever may
properly and truly be said %to be.'"57 He defines these as
"forms, magnitudes, qualities, relations, and other things
which, considered in themselves, are immutable, but, which,
56
445
joined to material substances, suffer radical change and are
altered in many ways because of their relationship with a
changeable thing."5e He goes on in the next section to
define various kinds of quantities, magnitude, multitude,
different kinds of relationships. All of these are seen in
terms of number.
None of this is original; a passage from Nicomachus is
almost identical. And it certainly seems to reflect the
standard interpretation of Pythagorean and Platonic doctrine
in trusting reason over the senses. But Boethius seems to
have missed an essential distinction in Pythagorean
doctrine Pythagoras made a distinction between, for
example, the monad and the number one. We will remember
Photius' statement, "The Pythagoreans preach a difference
between the Monad, and the One; the Monad dwells in the
conceptual realm, while the One dwells among numbers.''59
Similarly, Plato distinguishes between the objects of
mathematics and the forms themselves. Boethius recognizes no
such distinction. He should not have been unaware of the
concepts; he had access to such texts as the Theology
Arithmetic,
of
60
447
It appears that Boethius himself tried his hand at
passing Greek mathematics on to Latin readers.
It is not that the Romans weren't literate. They
were. They even wrote their own Latin technical books,
but these were bastardized works adapted from their
knowledge of the Greeks. For example, the principal
translator of Euclid into Latin was a Roman Senator
from an old established family, Anicius Manlius
Severinus Boethius. . . Boethius abridged Euclid's
works, creating the kind of treatment suitable for a
multi-choice test.61
This may be unfair to Boethius, although Mlodinow does
report significant shortcomings in the Roman philosopher's
understanding of Euclid: "Boethius gave only definitions and
theorems, and apparently also felt free to substitute
approximations for exact results. And that was on a good
day. In other cases, he just plain got it wrong."*3
Boethius on the Heavens. When approaching the subject
of celestial harmony, Boethius offers a version that is
certainly speculation, but not of the mystical kind. It
appears before
62
63
Mlodinow, p. 46.
448
reflects the contradictions to be found in the various other
sources he mentions:
At this point it would seem proper to add
concerning the above tetrachords that the disposition
from the hypate meson to the nete synemmenon is, as it
were, a kind of exemplar of the celestial order and
specification* The hypate meson is assigned to Saturn,
whereas the parhypate is like the orbit of Jupiter. The
lichanos meson is entrusted to Mars. The sun governs
the mese. Venus holds the trite synemmenon. Mercury
rules the paramete synemmenon. The nete is analogous to
the orbit of the moon.
Marcus Tullius draws up a different order, for in
the sixth book of De re publica he asserts: "Nature is
so disposed that low sound emanates from its one
extreme part, whereas high sound emanates from its
other. Therefore that high celestial orbit, that of the
stars, the revolution of which is faster, moves with a
high and shrill sound, whereas the weak orbit of the
moon moves with a very low sound. The earth, in ninth
place, remaining immobile, is alone always fixed in
place." Tullius thus regards the earth as silentthat
is, immobile. Next after the earth he assigns the
lowest sound to the moon, which is closest to silence,
so that the moon is the proslambanomenos, Mercury the
hypate hypaton, Venus parhypate hypton, the sun the
lichanos hypaton, Mars the hypate meson, Jupiter the
parhypate meson, Saturn the lichanos meson, and the
highest heaven the mese.64
This is but the first of many examples of the conflicting
viewpoints among the various writers on cosmic harmony.
Boethius, in his treatise, is passing on a view of
mathematics and a version of the music of the spheres that
reflects the views of Aristotle and Nicomachus. But by
failing to include any reference to the higher levels of
64
449
perception mentioned by both Plato and Pythagoras, Boethius'
work lacks an essential dimension that, according to our
analysis in Chapter III, they considered to be essential.
Thus the tradition is passed on in an impoverished form. To
make matter worse, even Boethius' writings were themselves
poorly understood.
Partly as a result of the treatise's encyclopedic scope
and erudition, partly as a result of the exalted status
of its supposed author, the De Institutione Musica
served as the ultimate authority on music theory until
the sixteenth century. The treatise is a dense and
difficult discussion of late Hellenistic music theory,
deeply grounded in Pythagoreanism and
largely
incomprehensible
to most of the medieval scholars who
made use of it as their prime source of musical
knowledge. Nevertheless, all subsequent medieval
writing on music, however garbled, utilized the De
Institutione Musica as a theoretical base.*5 (Author's
Italics)
There are many ironies in the history of universal harmony;
this appears to be one of them. According to Chadwick, much
of Boethius' work was motivated by a desire to preserve
ancient teachings.
It is his [Boethius'] great fear that amid the general
collapse of higher studies in his time, the knowledge
acquired by the philosophers and scientists of
65
450
classical Greece may simply be obliterated by a failure
of transmission.66
Boethius certainly transmitted a substantial body of
knowledge to subsequent generations. It is another question
whether he conveyed it with all its dimensions of meaning
intact.
Cassiodorus
Flavius Magnus Aurelius Cassiodorus (c. 490-583) was
also a Roman politician and scholar. Born in southern Italy,
he succeeded Boethius as consul to Theodoric after the
latter's execution in 524 and went on to serve three other
Ostrogothic rulers. Like Boethius, he was dedicated to
preserving Roman culture at a time when the Empire was
disintegrating. He spent several years in Constantinople,
where he must have been exposed to the ancient texts that
were preserved there. Returning to Italy, he established a
monastic foundation dedicated to the preservation and
translation of such texts, along with other intellectual
activities, an approach to monastic life which was later to
influence the Benedictine order.
Cassiodorus was himself active in organizing the
translation into Latin of Greek works, but his best known
et humanarum litterarum,
Institutiones
Cassiodorus,
An Introduction
to Divine and Human
Readings, Leslie Webber Jones, trans, with intro and notes
(New York: Octagon Books, Inc., 1966), introduction, p. 27.
68
(Berkeley: University of
452
complete work, covering everything about divine and secular
learning that the student needs to know."6* In the course of
this survey, the author feels compelled to provide an
overview of secular learning which, in his day, comprised
the seven liberal arts. Thus the second part of this work
contains descriptions of the trivium and the quadrivium, and
it is here that the material on cosmic harmony appears. It
is not an exposition of either originality or imagination,
however. Cassiodorusr only goal is to
. . . provide a text of the seven artes and
disciplinae
of a sort that will reduce these studies to the
appropriate state of subservience to scriptural ones, a
state they have long avoided in the hands of their
secular practitioners. It is true that Cassiodorus
introduces the study of what we would call "humanities"
to his monastery; but he does so only in order to take
command of those subjects once and for all, to make
them a branch of "divinity," to subordinate them to
higher things/0
The result is that in Book Two, "Cassiodorus is merely
repeating what he has been told by the authors he
excerpts. "7I
Before dealing with harmony, Cassiodorus reveals his
philosophical orientation in his description of the
Dialectic.
69
O'Donnell, p . 212.
70
O'Donnell, p p . 212-213.
71
O'Donnell, p . 213.
72
75
Cassiodorus, p. 158.
73
III. xvi. I.
454
Orpheus and King David and the salutary powers of music. But
as far as the music of the spheres is concerned, it receives
only cursory mention:
The sky and earth and everything which is accomplished
in them by the supernal stewardship are not without the
science of music; for Pythagoras is witness to the fact
that this world was founded through the instrumentality
of music and can be governed by it.76
Later we find:
The sky itself, as we have stated above, is said to
revolve with delightful harmony; and to state the whole
matter succinctly, whatever heavenly or earthly
occurrence takes place in a manner consistent with the
ordering of its Author is said to not to be exempt from
this science.77
This is the full extent of the treatment universal
harmony receives; there is certainly no mention of the
Timaeus or the Republic.
76
Cassiodorus, p. 190.
77
Cassiodorus, p. 196.
78
Cassiodorus, p. 203.
Martianus Capella
The liberal arts also provide the theme for Martianus
Capella's major work, but this work contains little more
useful information about the universal harmony.
Little is known about Martianus; it is thought that he
was a native of north Africa. It has also been suggested
that he was a high-ranking politician or official, but this
is also conjectural. What is known is that his prose and
poetry introduction to the subject of the liberal arts was
of immense cultural influence down to the late Middle Ages
and was widely used as a school textbook throughout the
Middle Ages. But, writes William Harris Stahl, ". . . the
reader is immediately at a loss to explain how a book so
dull and difficult could have been one of the most popular
books of Western Europe for nearly a thousand years."79
Written probably between 410 and 439 C.E., the work's
overall title is not known, but manuscripts give the title
De Nuptiis
Philologiae
et Mercurii
De arte
rhetorica,
De astrologia,
grammatica,
De geometrica,
and De harmonia.
De
arte
De
In the allegory
456
De Nuptiis,
80
457
lowest sphere (whether the earth or the moon) and the
highest was the octave or interval of six full tones.81
Martianus's text as it stands certainly suggests that
he was following this pattern (54.15) sicque
sex
tonorum conscensionibvs
et stadiorum
defects
lassitudine
fatigati
cum diapason symphoniam quidquid
emensi erant. The problem here is that if one adds up
the stages of Philologia's journey as they are
enumerated, there is one half-tone too many.8:
Some of this problem may be due to a lack of interest
in the earlier sources, especially if these came from Plato
and other philosophical texts. Martianus was either unaware
of them or lacked respect for them. "Martianus' range of
learning did not include a serious interest in the
philosophers, for whom he expressed mild contempt."*3
He calls them "starveling and unkempt." Remigius84
identifies the philosophers described by Martianus as
Sophists, Stoics, and Cynics. Elsewhere Martianus says
that they are "abstruse and ostentatious."155
In spite of this lack of regard for philosophers, Martianus
does undertake to discuss dialectic, since this subject is
part of the trivium, or arts of language. He appears to
follow Aristotle for the most part. "The subject of
81
83
Stahl et al., p. 9.
84
458
Martianus' fourth book is in most respects the same as the
traditional formal logic derived from Aristotle which has
been taught until recently in most university courses in
%
86
Republic,
510-11.
89
Republic,
534e.
89
Phaedrus,
269-74.
90
459
influential in the formation of Aristotle's theories of
classification, definition, and the syllogism.91
We have already noted that Aristotle's views on the
dialectic differ from those of Plato. Not surprisingly, as
Stahl explains, this disagreement results in a dichotomy in
the way dialectic is understood.
Aristotle shared none of Plato's optimism for
achieving metaphysical or scientific truth by
dialectical methods. He therefore distinguishes between
philosophy and science on the one hand, and the
principles of valid reasoning used in all disciplines
employing argument and inference on the other.K
This quite separate distinction becomes amplified in the
work of later writers, then further distinctions arise and
are themselves confused. By the third or fourth century,
Stahl writes, *. . . the two separate strands of dialectic
as the pure science of logic and the practical art of
disputation become inextricably tangled."93
Martianus' discussion of dialectic reflects this
confusion:
As heir to this development, Martianus' compendium
of dialectic appears excessively weighted with
irrelevant logical material, if viewed as a debating
manual, or sadly contaminated by its subservience to
91
92
Ibid.
93
460
rhetoric, if viewed as the introduction to logic which
it more nearly resembles.94
Whatever understanding Martianus has of dialectic, he
makes no indication that he understands the higher meaning
that Plato attributes to it. Similarly, his exposition of
arithmetic, while influential, appears to have only weak
links with the Pythagorean tradition.
Martianus' extended section on arithmetic. . . is one
of the most important Latin expositions of Greek
arithmetic from the early Middle Ages. Although his
ultimate sources were Nicomachus and Euclid, it is
evident from a comparison of the three works that
Martianusf immediate sources was some compilation (or
compilations) of the Nicomachean and Euclidean
traditions. *5
Arithmetic's speech does contain some shades of the Theology
of Arithmetic. Stahl suggests that this was probably a
rather rote recitation of, perhaps, poorly understood
sources.
That Martianus occasionally introduces Neoplatonic
terminology and seems to be expressing Neoplatonist and
Neopythagorean doctrines must not be taken to indicate
that he was a follower of the Neoplatonic school of
philosophy. Neoplatonism was the only pagan philosophy
to flourish in the last century of the Western empire,
and its adherents took a leading part in the bitter
conflict with Christianity. The remnants of secular
philosophy and scientific learning that survived were
largely in the Platonic tradition, stemming ultimately
from Plato's Timaeus. From the time of its completion
Johnson in Stahl et al., p. 107.
Stahl et al., p. 156.
461
until the late Middle Ages, that book inspired
generations of commentators on, and popularizers of,
works on theoretical cosmography and arithmology, and
it is not to be expected that a Latin compiler of
traditional and conflated doctrines on the quadrivium
would wholly avoid the use of Neoplatonic vocabulary.Both aspects of the discipline are included in Arithmetic's
speech, the mystical and the practical, arithmology and
practical number theory. Stahl has little patience with the
former, stating that "it is to the credit of Martianus that
he gives much greater attention to arithmetic than to
arithmology."Q7 This certainly reflects the contemporary
view. It would not have pleased Plato.
When we come to the speech of the bridesmaid
representing harmony, we find fairly typical passages, both
classical and biblical, about the universal power of music.
We also find the most overtly Neoplatonic passage in the
whole of Martianus' text.
But when the Monad and first hypostasis of intellectual
light was conveying souls that emanated from their
original source to earthly habitations, I was ordered
to descend with them to be their governess. It was I
who assigned the numerical ratios of perceptible
motions and the impulses of perfect will, introducing
restraint and harmony into all things.96
96
97
98
462
Again, Stahl emphasizes that this does not indicate that
Martianus truly represents Neoplatonism. He is simply
reiterating concepts that were "commonplaces in the writings
of compilers who knew little else about Neoplatonism."59 What
follows is, again, a standard exposition of fifth-century
music theory, with sections on consonance, tetrachords, the
Greater Perfect System, rhythm, meter, etc., with no mention
of the cosmic harmony. It is of interest to historians of
music theory, of course, but there is no clear passing on of
the inner meaning of universal harmony.
463
commentary that Cicero's text survived through the Middle
Ages. Somnium Scipionis
publics,
Similarly, "The
- Haar, p. 90.
103
464
that parallels that of Er of Pamphylia
465
exception of the souls bestowed upon the human race by
the benevolence of the gods. Above the moon all things
are eternal. Now in the center, the ninth of the
spheres, is the earth, never moving and at the
bottom.104
This description differs in several respects from
Plato's original description in the Myth of Er. The Spindle
of Necessity, the daughters of Necessity, Lachesis, Clotho,
and Atropos, the sirens seated upon each circle singing the
notes of the scalenone of these is found in Cicero's
version. Moreover, the order of the Planets is different, a
fact that creates some problems for Macrobius, as will be
seen presently.
Whatever their order, Scipio appears to hear the notes
made by the planets as he inquires about them. "What is this
great and pleasing sound that fills my ears?" he asks. The
Elder Scipio replies:
That . . . is a concord of tones separated by unequal
but nevertheless carefully proportioned intervals,
caused by the rapid motions of the spheres themselves.
The high and low tones blended together produce
different harmonies... The ... eight spheres, two of
which move at the same speed, produce seven different
tones, this number being, one might almost say, the key
to the universe. Gifted men, imitating this harmony on
stringed instruments and in singing, have gained for
themselves a return to this region, as have those who
have devoted their exceptional abilities to a search
for divine truths. The ears of mortals are filled with
this sound yet they are unable to hear it. Indeed,
hearing is the dullest of the senses; consider the
people who dwell in the region about the Great
Macrobius, p. 73.
466
Cataract/ where the Nile comes rushing down from the
lofty mountains; they have lost their sense of hearing
because of the load roar. But the sound coming from the
heavenly spheres revolving at very swift speeds is of
course so great that human ears cannot catch it; you
might as well try to stare directly at the sun, whose
rays are much too strong for your eyes.105
Again, there are discrepancies between Cicerors version
and that of Plato. Most striking is the idea of the sounds
of the planets being inaudible to human ears. This appears
to be a contribution from the Aristotelian tradition going
back to a passage from De Caelo:
Some thinkers suppose that the motion of bodies of that
size must produce a noise, since on our earth the
motion of bodies far inferior in size and in speed of
movement has that effect. Also, when the sun and the
moon, they say, and all the stars, so great in number
and size, are moving with so rapid a motion, how should
they not produce a sound immensely great? Starting from
this argument and from the observation that their
speed, as measured by their distances, are in the same
ratios as musical concordances, they assert that the
sound given forth by the circular movement of the stars
is a harmony. Since, however, it appears unaccountable
that we should not hear this music, they explain this
by saying that the sound is in our ears from the very
moment of birth and is thus indistinguishable from its
contrary silence, since sound and silence are
discriminated by mutual contrast. What happens to men,
then, is just what happens to coppersmiths, who are so
accustomed to the noise of the smithy that it makes no
difference to them.106
105
106
467
These details are significant but what is more
important is the context. As we have seen, the
interpretation of Plators text depends upon many passages
outside of the Myth of Er itself: the Divided Line analogy
and description of the nature of the dialectic in the
Republic;
107
doctissimi,
4
sealed for a thousand years."108 Cicero was definitely aware
of this deterioration, mentioning it in Book I of his De
oratore.
He points out that the Greeks placed the philosopher
and the specialist on the pedestals of their
intellectual world, while the Romans more sensibly
reserved the place of honor for the orator. . .
Cicero's ideal orator was not a master of Greek
abstract and rigorously systematic disciplines; he
prepared his briefs from derivative handbooks. His
intellectual enthusiasms were for style and beauty in
literature and rhetoric, not for science and
philosophy, and the motivation for his professional
researches lay in their applications to the arts of
persuasion.:QQ
But even if Cicero understood this problem, he was
unable to transcend it. "Cicero did not have the background
or the temperament to transmit the specialized treatises of
Hellenistic Greek writers."no He continues:
A society whose intellectual elite does not go
beyond the level of books like Will Durant's The Story
of Philosophy and Lancelot Hogben's Science for the
Citizen,
a society that breaks contact with original
minds, as the Romans did, is doomed to intellectual
decay. The way of the popular handbook, as it is
digested and made more palatable for each succeeding
generation, is inevitably downward.111
108
Ibid.
109
110
111
469
Stahl is actually referring to Martianus Capella' s work, the
Marriage
of Philology
and Mercury,
to all
the Latin
tradition
works through
was
which
transmitted,
in Somnium Scipionis
112
Ibid.
113
114
Ibid.
115
116
in
471
Somnium Scipionis
the Timaeus,
2, XIII-XV.
116
119
1, V, 2, VI, 83.
120
1, iii.
121
In Greek, oneiros,
horama, chrematismos,
enypnion and
phantasma.
In Latin, somnium, visio,
oraculum,
insomnium,
and visum. Macrobius, p. 88.
472
types mentioned above,"122 namely the first three categories,
as the last two types "are of no assistance in foretelling
the future; but by means of the other three we are gifted
with the powers of divination."123
The contrast with the Myth of Er is important here. Er
does not have a dream; he dies and returns to life seven
days later, a reference to the idea of "practicing death," a
convention that, as we argued in Chapter VI,124 suggests a
parallel with certain yoga practices. There is no indication
of a parallel understanding from Macrobius. Yet the idea of
achieving higher states of consciousness can definitely be
found among Neoplatonists. Consider the following from
Proclus regarding the inner meaning of the Timaeus:
The mode, however, of unfolding it [i.e., the division
of the soul, as described in Timaeus 35b] should accord
with the essence of the soul, being liberated from
visible, but elevating itself to essential and
immaterial harmony, and transferring from images to
paradigms. For the symphony which flows into the ears,
and which consists in sounds and pulsations, is very
different from that which is vital and intellectual. No
one, therefore, should stop at the mathematical theory,
but should excite himself to a mode of survey adapted
to the essence of the soul; nor should he think that we
ought to direct our attention to interval, or the
differences of motions. For these are assumed remotely
[ie, metaphorically or symbolically], and are no
means adapted to the proposed subjects of
investigation. But he should survey the assertions by
122
123
124
Macrobius, p. 90.
Ibid.
S e e Chap. VI, p p .
407-408.
473
themselves, and consider how they afford an indication
of the psychical middle, and look to the demiurgic
providence as their end.125
Proclusr statement is a caveat, similar to Plato's own,
and ultimately to Pythagoras', not to seek knowledge merely
on the superficial, sensory level. Being in accord with the
essence of the Soul liberates it from purely sensory
(visible) perception. Instead, "elevating itself to
essential and immaterial harmony," that is, to the level of
Being, not becoming, "and transferring from images to
paradigms," would involve moving from the third to the
fourth level of perception in terms of the Divided Line
analogy. Even "the mathematical theory" is not the final
level of interpretation, Proclus suggests, but rather the
reader "should excite himself to a mode of survey adapted to
the essence of the soul." That is, he should achieve a level
of insight that comes from the highest functioning of
consciousnessfor Plato, the direct perception of the
Forms.
Is it possible that Macrobius understood Proclus' (and
hence Plato's) admonitions in this respect, or is he merely
parroting a more ancient source such as Porphyry? This is
125
12T
126
127
Macrobius, p. 162.
128
Ibid.
129
Macrobius, p. 163.
Timaeus."120
131
II,iii,12-16.
132
Macrobius, p. 196.
animae,
477
It is God's temple, manifest in the form of the
universe to display "the omnipotence of the Supreme God,"136
to which Macrobius refers. Such a universe is animated
throughout by Divine mind, emanating from God and touching
everything from the stars to individual souls.
Now let us explain, in accordance with the teachings of
cosmogonists, how animus, meaning "mind," is common to
us and the stars.137 God, who both is and is called the
First Cause, is alone the beginning and source of all
things. He, in a bounteous outpouring of his greatness,
created from himself Mind. This Mind, called nous, as
long as it fixes its gaze upon the Father, retains a
complete likeness of its Creator, but when it looks
away at things below it creates for itself Soul. Soul,
in turn, as long as it contemplates the Father, assumes
his part, but by diverting its attention more and more,
though itself incorporeal, degenerates into the fabric
of bodies.138
Macrobius goes on to explain the mechanics of this process.
As Soul descends into more dense realms of matter, "into the
lower regions and to the earth," it becomes progressively
more "incapable of sustaining the pure divinity of Mind.
136
Ibid.
137
478
Human bodies, on the other hand, were found to be capable of
sustaining, with difficulty, a small part of it."139 As
"divine minds were infused into all bodies which had smooth
spherical shapes, "14 then the stars "are quickened with
divine minds"141 and "man alone was endowed with reason, the
power of mind, the seat of which is in the head."14:
Macrobius then provides a classical summary of this
doctrine.
Accordingly, since Mind emanates from the supreme
God and Soul from Mind, and Mind, indeed, forms and
suffuses all below with life, and since this is the one
splendor lighting up everything and visible in all,
like a countenance reflected in many mirrors arranged
in a row, and since all follow on in continuous
succession degenerating step by step in their downward
course, the close observer will find that from the
Supreme God even to the bottommost dregs of the
universe143 there is one tie, binding at every link and
never broken. This is the golden chain of Homer which,
he tells us, God ordered to hang down from the sky to
the earth.144
What Plotinus and Porphyry, via Macrobius, have
outlined here is the doctrine that later came to be known as
the Great Chain of Being. Indeed, in a footnote, Stahl
139
Macrobius, p. 144.
140
141
Ibid.
uz
Ibid.
143
144
479
states that the idea of a single countenance reflected in
many mirrors comes directly from Plotinus' Enneads,
I.i.3.145
Great
Theme of Western
of these
two great
ideas
culture
taken
the
described
by James1**
together.
Macrobius also
consists
145
Macrobius, p. 145.
148
149
Macrobius, p. 146.
480
Parmenides, Xenophanes, Boethius and Epicurus! He concludes,
"The acceptance of the soul's incorporeality has been as
general as the acceptance of its immortality."150
This Neoplatonic cosmogony is significant when it comes
to Macrobius' treatment of music theory. His exposition is
well in line with tradition. Pythagoras appears promptly1-1
and discovers the consonances at the blacksmith's shop. He
then uses this discovery to develop the knowledge of
intervals and tuning. Next, Plato, "guided by Pythagoras'
revelation and drawing upon the godlike power of his own
genius,"1- applies this knowledge to the construction of the
World-Soul. Macrobius gives us a brief guided tour of the
number symbolism utilized by Plato's demiurge in the
Timaeus.
Macrobius, p .
151
II,i,
152
Macrobius, p. 189.
153
147.
8-12.
481
"Moreover, cosmogonists have chosen to consider the nine
Muses as the tuneful song of the eight spheres and the one
predominant harmony that comes from all of them."154 Outside
of this, however, we do find one interesting idea that
emerges directly out of the Neoplatonic concept of the
Golden Chain of Homer. Having established the relationship
between musical relationships and the structure of the
World-Soul, Macrobius ventures an answer to a very
fundamental question: why do all people seem to like music?
Every soul in this world is allured by musical sounds
so that not only those who are more refined in their
habits, but all the barbarous people as well, have
adopted songs by which they are inflamed with courage
or wooed to pleasure; for the soul carries with it into
the body a memory of the music which it knew in the
sky, and so is captivated by its charm that here is no
breast so cruel or savage as not to be gripped by the
spell of such an appeal. This, I believe, was the
origin of the stories of Orpheus and Amphion, one of
whom was said to have enticed the dumb beasts by his
song, the other the rocks. . . Thus every disposition
of the soul is controlled by song.155
We will return to the issue of the great chain of being
and the disposition of the soul controlled by song. But the
story of the transmission of sources is not complete.
154
Macrobius, p. 194.
155
Macrobius, p. 195.
482
And the Sources Begat Sources
Over a thousand years separate Macrobius from the final
flowering of the music of the spheres tradition with Fludd
and Kepler. Much was written on the subject during that
time. But, as Macrobius himself wrote, "The fact that Cicero
made mention of music . . . is no excuse for going through
all the treatises on the subject, a mass of literature that,
it seems to me, is without end."156 Space limitations force
us to follow Macrobius' suggestion here, but even a cursory
overview of this literature reveals a tradition filled with
what Haar has, in some instances, called
a "thoughtless
156
Macrobius, p .
157
Haar, p . 2 9 2 .
158
Haar, p .
320.
199.
483
tradition of musical philosophy and aesthetics."159 The
tradition that emerged was hardly monolithic and certainly
not consistent. Aurelian's treatise, Musica
Disciplina,
Newby, p. 52.
Newby, pp. 52-53.
A Change of Direction
By the time we get to the thirteenth century, a subtle
shift of emphasis occurs on two fronts, one musical, the
other scientific. The Neoplatonic emphasis derived from
Boethius, Macrobius, and others is modified somewhat by the
increasing availability of Aristotle's works. In the
scientific arena, a major figure emerges in the person of
Roger Bacon, who will challenge the supremacy of Plato and
Pythagoras.
Thirteenth-century scientific thought, taking its lead
from Aristotle, was not likely to tolerate literal
reading of Platonic myths. Roger Bacon spends a good
part of the chapter on music in his Opus Tertium
refuting, not only the standard Pythagorean theory
(referring of course to De Caelo) but also a
modification of it in terms of its physical cause. . .
Bacon does not give the names of the "Many and learned"
who propose a celestial music from the light of the
stars rather than from their movement, but this altered
form of musica mundana may well represent academic
speculation on Boethius, meant to take Aristotle's
refutation into account, at Paris or Oxford in the mid
thirteenth-century. . . Bacon concludes decisively that
u
ideo nulla est musica mundana."Ul Yet, he admits, the
theory has persisted "among the vulgar"; among the
learned it is merely recounted, not approved, and thus
Boethius mentions the theory merely to retell an
opinion of the unlettered. The revered Boethius, whose
merits as a scholar Bacon admired, thus gets off more
easily than Pythagoras, who is simply said to have been
wrong.162
161
485
Newby reports on a further development from this period:
After the discovery of Aristotle's works and the
establishment of the cathedral schools and later the
first universities/ the Neoplatonic musical tradition
continues to be maintained; but by this time there
begins to appear a growing concern: how to reconcile
that tradition with purely aesthetic observations about
current practices of music and poetry. The everexpanding corpus of paraliturgical musicf the
development of polyphony/ even the elegant and highly
sophisticated secular tradition of music-poetry of the
troubadours suggests greater awareness of man's
autonomous role in the act of artistic creativity. By
the thirteenth centuryf one finds a significant
falling-off in the number of treatises dealing with
matters of general musical philosophy and cosmology/
and an accompanying increase in the number of works
that treat the problems of performance/ notation and
composition of music.163
Jacques de Lige
We can see an example of this latter trend in the
Speculum Musicae
Newbyf p. 53.
486
deal with the "Celestial or Divine Music," however, it
receives a lukewarm treatment. He speculates that
Perhaps Boethius and the Pythagoreans understand by the
music proceeding from the motions of the celestial
bodies the connection, order, proportion, concord, or
any other suitable relationship which the orbs have
with one another in motion, position, luminosity,
virtues, inequality or equality of movement.164
Later, referring to Boethius' description of the harmony
existing among the elements, he expresses the opinion that
u
Qafori
Such a view was not uncommon in this period. Indeed, in
view of the complexity and richness of the treatises on the
celestial harmonies that extends from this period to the
164
Jacobi Leodiensis,
Speculum musicae, Roger Bragard,
trans. & ed. (Rome: American Institute of Musicology, 1955).
In Godwin (1993), Vol. I, p. 138.
165
Ibid.
Jacobi
Leodiensis,
487
time of Fludd and Kepler, it is remarkable to realize how
tenuous a connection the treatises had to their sources.
Take, for example, the following from Franchino Gafori.
"There are those who believe the muses follow the order of
constellations and modes,"167 and, "we do not think it
incongruous to agree with the conception of Pythagoras and
Plato, who said that celestial sounds are produced according
to a certain order of instrumental sounds."168 These
statements seem surprisingly lacking in conviction
considering that it was Gafori who commissioned the famous
woodcut from Guillaume de Signerre that we saw in Chapter I.
The illustration is from his earlier work, which deals with
Practica
Musica.
on Musica speculativa,
Zarlino
A generation later, the theorist Gioseffo Zarlino is
also, for the most part, focused on practical concerns in
167
Franchino
Gafori,
Franchino
Gafori,
488
his Institutione
Harmoniche.
animastica,
a category
disclaimer,
170
Scipionis.
489
Plato's view is represented via its citation in Tullius, and
then Zarlino goes on to consider Ptolemy.
Whoever will examine the heavens in detail, as
Ptolemy did with such diligence, will find by
comparison of the twelve portions of the Zodiac, in
which are the twelve heavenly signs, various musical
consonances: the fourth, fifth, octave, and others in
their turn.171
Zarlino is here citing Ptolemy's Harmonics,17" but he also
introduces a new element, adding astrological considerations
to the already confusing mix.
Not only in the things mentioned may one find such
harmony, but also in the various aspects of the seven
planets, in their nature, and in their positions or
sites. First from the aspects which they make with
inferior things, such as Trine, Square, Sextile,
Conjunction, and Opposition, and according to their
good or bad influences, comes such diverse harmony of
things that it is impossible to describe it. Then, as
to their nature, there are some (as the astrologers
say) of an unhappy and malignant nature, which come to
the good and benign ones to be tempered. From this
results harmony, and great convenience and advantage to
mortals.173
As Godwin notes, Zarlino refrains from going into too
much detail. This is in contrast with Ptolemy's original.
171
172
490
"Harmonia" in Greek never loses its root meaning of the
fitting together of disparate, potentially conflicting
elements. In the third book of Ptolemy's Harmonica,
however, cosmic harmony is seen above all in the
zodiac. . . This harmonic structure of the celestial
world is worked out in astonishing detail.174
It is interesting to find that some of the authorities
in this field, even in classical times, found some of this
speculative writing to be too much. "Macrobius felt
embarrassed," Chadwick informs us, "when cosmic harmony was
taken so far as to be traced into the smaller details."x 5
It is also interesting to note that Ptolemy was disparaged
by subsequent writers.
Commentators from Kepler to the present have been
embarrassed by it [Ptolemy's Harmonics],
calling it
ingenious nonsense. But Kepler himself suffered the
same posthumous verdict on what he considered the crown
of his work, his explanation of the elliptical
planetary orbits through musical harmony. Does each age
simply have its own distinctive nonsense?17*
Chadwick
175
Ibid.
176
Godwin (1993) , p . 2 1 .
(1981), p .
82.
491
researchers/ and these years have already been carefully
documented/ particularly by Heningerf whose book provides an
exhaustive examination of Pythagorean lore as a background
to the study of poetics.177 We will focus on a single issue
the understanding of Greek sources/ particularly Plato.
By the time of the Renaissance/ another shift of
emphasis occurred: as the trickle of Greek manuscripts
coming into Europe turned into a flood/ the pendulum swung
back towards the magical tradition after the medieval
dominance of Aristotelianism. This influence was felt in
every field of endeavor.
Plato was/ without doubt/ the darling of the
renaissance. In the early quattrocento several of the
dialogues were rendered into Latin by various
translators even before the Florentine Academy
resurrected him in toto and enshrined him as their
tutelary spirit. For centuries Plato's Timaeus had been
the basic text for cosmology/ passing over into science
and theology; his Symposium, adorned with Ficino's
expansive commentary/ provided a doctrine to guide
moralist and love poet alike; his Republic was the
touchstone for discussion of all public matters from
government to education to art.178
In this atmosphere/ Platonic and Pythagorean notions
came to the forefront in every area from cosmology to
poetrycertainly in music. But we have already noted
Tarnas' observation that Renaissance thought is not
177
4 92
monolithic but rather a "simultaneous balance and synthesis
of many opposites." 179 Thus, for example, Platonic doctrine
was also used to support a materialist philosophy:
Glarean
179
190
Heninger, p. 21.
181
493
Glarean compares multiple opinions on such topics until
conceding that "writers have fallen into diverse ways of
arranging the sounds according to their highness and
lowness,"182 before going on to add his own opinion to the
mix. He is not averse to contradicting the most
authoritative of classical sources. In discussing the sounds
made by the various planets, he writes, "to say what I
think, this place in Cicero undoubtedly has been corrupted,
and Macrobius did not understand it accurately although he
wrote four very long chapters on it."183
Glarean raises the essential question. Plato has been
turned on his head; Cicero has been corrupted; Macrobius did
not understand the planetary harmony. By the time we arrive
at the sixteenth century, can anyone claim to understand
this tradition?
Full Circle
We have come almost full circle; it is another seventy
years from the time of Glarean and Zarlino to the critical
turning point from 1617 to 1619 that we discussed in Chapter
I and the work of Fludd, Kepler and Descartes. If Kepler is
the watershed between the classical and modern worlds,
multiple streams flow into that watershed from the
182
183
494
Renaissance/ many of them crossing one another/ some
gathering strength/ others eventually drying up. On the
other side of the watershed/ however/ once the natural
scientists of the eighteenth century have done their work/
only one stream emerges/ and the music of the spheres is not
part of it. Why is this?
There are several possible reasons. The sheer muddling
of the tradition was probably enough to ensure that it could
not stand up to any serious scrutiny. Several writers/ most
notably Johannes Tinctorisf Francisco de Salinas and
Giovanni Battista Benedetti/ published invective against
it.184 At the same time/ however/ in another ironic
development/ the idea entered the mainstream of thought/
particularly in the field of poetry. And yet/ as Hollander
describes/ it seems that familiarity breeds contempt. By the
eighteenth century the whole notion had become trivialized
as "decorative metaphor and mere turns of wit."185
Before this process had run its course/ however/ the
music of the spheres tradition enjoyed a final flowering
that perfectly demonstrates the very difficulties and
inconsistences that we have been discussing.
184
495
The (Greek) Temple of Music
In 1589, in Florence, at the Medici wedding, and in
1607, in Mantua, at the presentation of Monteverdi's
Orfeo,
186
496
ancients. Is there any reason to suppose that their
understanding of these sources was any less distorted than
Bardi's, Mei' s and Peri's was of theirs? It is our thesis
that there is no reason to think so. Opera, of course, even
if in different and evolving forms, had a future. The music
of the spheres did not. Following the dispute between Fludd
and Kepler, the insights of Descartes and Hume, and the
other developments of the Enlightenment, its fate was
sealed. Gradually, the study of music began to separate
itself from the general concerns of science. At the same
time, empirical evidence was gathering that undermined the
basic assumptions of musical cosmology.
It is important to keep in mind in analyzing music's
relationship to science that music, unique among the
arts, is at the opening of the scientific age
inseparable from science. It is not surprising under
these circumstances that the area of musical thought
most affected by the scientific revolution were those
bordering on the fields of science that underwent the
greatest transformation. These, it will be recalled...
were astronomy and dynamics. Astronomy, music's sisterscience in the quadrivium, had until the middle of the
sixteenth century bolstered the idea that earthly music
contained in microcosm the divine harmony of the
universe; but now there was growing evidence that the
universe was not a harmony after all. In the fields of
dynamics the studies of the nature of vibration and of
sound likewise upset many of the widely held notions of
number-symbolism and of the way music affects the
senses and the mind.187
187
497
As scientists and explorers were discovering more about
the physical environment a general change of perspective,
known as a "paradigm shift," occurred, creating a world-view
in which the music of the spheres became more and more
marginalized as a serious scientific idea.
During this period . . . there took place a twofold
expansion of the European imagination. The first aspect
was geographical, associated with the names of great
navigators from Vasco da Gama to Drake. . .
The second expansion was cosmological, the work of
Copernicus, Kepler, and Galileo. Their new cosmologies
swept aside the tidy system of nesting spheres, turned
by the hand of God, that had served so well since the
time of Aristotle. Breaking the bounds of the Ptolemaic
cosmos required a new imagining of space, while the
infinite vistas revealed demanded a new scale of time.
Isaac Newton himself, largely responsible for the
consecration of the former, was incapable of the
latter. But all efforts at universal explanation had to
be revised in the face of the new knowledge, and this
was one of the foremost tasks that the philosophers of
the eighteenth-century Enlightenment set themselves.166
The revision that they arrived at held no place for
universal harmony; even if writers such as Mersenne
continued to pay lip service to the general idea of harmony
in the universe, and even if scientific thought had
essentially grown out of this tradition, it could not
survive much longer.
198
Godwin. Arktos:
The Polar Myth in Science,
Symbolism, and
Nazi Survival
(Grand Rapids, Michigan: Phanes Press, 1993),
p. 142.
189
499
CHAPTER VIII
THE SKY RE-TUNED?
1
2
500
interest within the tradition.3
of a musics
Theories of Music
One of the results of the disappearance of musical
cosmology is its effect on the theory of music itself. This
can be seen, for one thing, from the very change in the
definition of music theory over the ages. There can be no
501
doubt that music theory has gone through enormous changes in
the course of its history, even within Western culture.
Claude Palisca illustrates this by comparing four major
theory treatises, De institutione
musica
(c. 500) by
Boethius,4 L'arte
ridotta
in tavole
del
contraponto
pratico
al
satz
(1586-9)
cimbalo
(1935) by
Venice, 1586.
502
Palisca's insight clearly illustrates the vastly
different ideas about the nature of music and its role in
human life that have been held through the course of the two
millennia of Western thought. And compounding the diversity,
as we have seen, has been the limited understanding of the
original and fundamental contributions to this field.
One thing that stands out when we look at the examples
chosen by Palisca is the gradual disappearance of
cosmological content as we come forward in time. We have
examined the work of Boethius in the previous chapter;
having coined the term, he certainly represents musica
mundana. Artusi was a student of Zarlino and was actively
involved in disputes with Vincenzo Galilei and, later, with
Monteverdi. His concerns are strictly those of musica
instrumentalis,
503
entirely positive vision, however, since Schenker
held that
Instrumentalis
instrumentalis.
504
music. Hence modern thought can boast significant
accomplishments only on the outskirts of music, above
all in acoustics and music psychology . . . So it has
come about that the very generations that have known
more glorious music, and learned to observe it more
closely, than any that preceded them have, on the
whole, stopped thinking about music. There have been
important exceptions . . . yet so far they have
remained exceptions.10
In the quarter-century since this was written there
have been significant developments in musicology and music
theory: a great deal of early and non-Western music has been
discovered or reconstructed; new disciplines such as
ethnomusicology and systematic musicology have been
developed. But while, for example, we have learned much
about the social and political contexts within which music
has developed at different times and in different parts of
the world, it is not clear that such new knowledge has gone
any further in illuminating the essence of what music is.
Some leading musicologists share this view. John Blacking,
for example, commenting on the ubiquitous nature of certain
musical phenomena, writes:
I am convinced that the explanation for this is to be
found in the fact that at the levels of deep structures
of music there are elements that are common to the
10
(Cambridge: M. I. T. Press,
13
14
Zuckerkandl, p. 12.
507
abandonment of metaphysics. But it appears that the
limitations of "observable facts" are also recognized from
within scientific circles. For example, there is a growing
tendency to criticize scientific thinking for ignoring
larger questions and relying more and more on a purely
reductionist approach.
Faced with a system, the scientist responded
automatically by taking it to pieces. Animals were
atomized down to organs, organs microscoped down to
cells, cells studied as collections of molecules,
smashed to component atoms. This method of analysis
tends to become dogma; and, in fact, the reductionists
tended to assert that all science was to be advanced in
this way alone. Get to know the properties of each
part, and you have only to put the parts together again
and you will know the whole.15
It is true that such methodologies have been enormously
successful and have produced wonders, both theoretical and
technological. There is, however, a wide range of phenomena
with which they have not been able to deal, with a resulting
set of human, social problems.
Those of us who are part and product of Western
technological culture. . .. are unwittingly taking part
in the anomaly of attempting to conduct society without
the metaphysical or spiritual dimension. It is that
very dimension which addresses itself to origins and
humanity's overall relationship with our universe or
the "whole." Because of the distractions of
technological "magic11 and its obvious material
advantages, we have failed to achieve a wholeness in
15
Science,
vol. 18
508
industrial or post-industrial society. The paradoxes
of increased material wealth and energy greed, natural
resource destruction and the increase of mental
illness all point to the fact that never before in
human history has a culture been attempted without a
spiritual dimension; in fact one could go further and
suggest that a society is not correctly definable as
"human" without such a dimension.16
Whatever its social effects, purely reductionist, or
mechanistic, approaches have not been able to deal
effectively with music. We have been able to analyze music
down to its component parts, whether they be scales, motifs,
themes, harmonies, forms, or pitch-class-sets; what we
cannot seem to do is understand the larger questions of the
kind Zuckerkandl and Epstein outline. A case in point is
brought out by a contemporary music theorist John Rahn. He
agrees that the current world-view is profoundly
mechanistic:
The prevailing image of the present intellectual epoch,
perhaps soon to be supplanted, is that of the machine,
interpreted in its widest sense to subsume
formalizations of any kind. The work of Frege, Russell,
Godel, Hilbert, Carnap, and so many others laid the
foundations of the current civitas mentis machinosae.17
16
17
Still
(London: Gordon
509
Reflecting his intellectual epoch, Rahnfs approach to
theory has been an attempt to impose formal mathematical
models on musical form. "To explicate something is,
ultimately, to formalize it, that is to make it into a
machine at whose metaphorically whirring and clicking parts
we are happy to stare, and be enlightened. As a child of my
epoch, this is my belief."18 Rahn finds, however, that some
theorists evade such formalization, particularly Heinrich
Schenker.
Schenker, who died in 1935, was something of an
anachronism. His metaphors are overwhelmingly organic
(almost disgustingly so) and the philosophy within
which his theories swam was (insofar as it can be
determined) an idealistic one. Although Schenkerfs
philosophy has been compared to Hegel's and Goethe's,
it was "essentialist" in the mediaeval sense, and
similar in flavor to that of Plotinus or the PseudoDionysius, and Schenkerfs epistemology was the ecstatic
one of the mystic. We tend to assume that, in
principle, a mechanical model of a theory can preserve
all essential aspects of it, that whatever cannot be
formalized is nugatory nonsense. Schenker would have
fits at our presumption.15
Schenker is only an anachronism if one is completely
committed to the mechanistic view, a view that Schenker
himself did not share. But where Schenker feared to tread,
his interpreters plunge ahead. Rahn is well aware of
Schenker's view. Nevertheless, he admits that he can find no
18
Ibid.
19
Ibid.
510
alternative but to impose
a mathematical
model
anyway.
20
Ibid.
21
511
But perhaps the most striking statement in this regard is by
historian Edward Lowinsky, the beginning of which was quoted
in Chapter I.-3
The present era is characterized by a complete lack of
any philosophy which would bind together the multitude
of phenomena and of human activities into one
meaningful whole. That music has a significance deeper
than the sensual and emotional sensations it may arouse
in the listener is no longer a common belief. Nor does
music today maintain that same intimate contact with
the social and the cultural life of the public that was
so typical of the state of music in bygone ages. Music
finds itself today in an unprecedented state of
isolation. Neither performers nor composers, neither
teachers nor musicologists are able by their separate
or even by their joint efforts to overcome this
situation completely. More is necessary: man must
recapture a new unity of vision. This will be an
extremely long and arduous process, to which workers in
all fields will have to contribute.24
Musica Speculativa
What Lowinsky calls for is a tall order; he indicates
that difficulties within the field of music are a symptom of
more deep-rooted problems. He is joined in this view by
Joscelyn Godwin, who, in a 1982 article, called for a
revival of speculative music, which he defines as "looking
23
24
512
at the cosmos musically, and at music cosmically."25 "The
highest task of speculative music," he writes, is "the
solution through music of the metaphysical enigmas
surrounding man."26 Presumably, such an effort would involve
the reintroduction, in some form, of musica mundana and
musica humana into the curriculumor at least an
appreciation of what these terms signify. When he goes on to
cite writers whom he feels have contributed to such an
effort, he has to agree with Lowinsky that the task at hand
goes beyond the specific concerns of musicology.
Among modern writers who have attempted this, Marius
Schneider . . . Dane Rudhyar, and Hazrat Inayat Khan
seem to me to have had the most penetrating insights,
but much is left to be done especially in the context
of comparative religion and occultism.
All of these paths lead beyond the frontiers of
conventional musicology into the sometimes hostile
territory of other disciplines. Yet this is the
challenge faced by all who attempt to forge a holistic
vision from the shattered fragments of twentiethcentury learning.27
Godwin also cites the work of Albert von Thimus, Hans
Kayser and Ernest McClain, whose work we have discussed.
Each of these writers has a unique perspective within two
25
27
Ibid.
Quarterly,
513
distinct paths that he sees speculative music takingthe
"historical" and the "actual." "One treats it [speculative
music] from outside as a historical phenomenon; the other
seeks to make it a way of thought/ even a way of life, for
today."26 McClain, for example, follows a distinctly
historical line, finding "a musical mathematics that lie at
the very center of archaic thought,"29 not only, as we have
seen, in Plato's work but also in Hebrew, Babylonian and
Vedic texts.?c Others, such as Kayser, look for applications
of musical thinking in the development of contemporary
thought.
Godwin mentions three other contributors' work in
speculative music, Marius Schneider, Dane Rudhyar and Hazrat
Inayat Khan. Schneider is perhaps best known for a massive
work in Spanish, El Origen musical
en la mitologia
y la escultura
de los
antiguas,*1
animales
simbolos
which Godwin
:9
30
514
describes as one of the most original works of nonfiction he
has ever seen. Schneider traces the origins of musical
cosmologies to the mythology of the early Neolithic age,
which included systems of correspondences between notes,
elements, planets, signs of the zodiac, seasonal and
geographical correspondences, and associations with
psychological states, creating a proto-musical cosmology.
Godwin cites Schneider as a representative of "those
speculative musicians to whom their science is an actuality,
not merely an engaging historical study."~ His book is a
profoundly idiosyncratic work, however, and difficult to
integrate with other work in this area.
Dane Rudhyar is an accomplished composer who moved to
the United States from France. He has published a number of
piano and orchestral works in a "post-Skryabin style,"n and
has written sparingly but passionately on various musical
subjects.34 He is better known as an astrologer, however,
and has published widely on this subject as well as on
political and social issues.
32
33
515
Hazrat Inayat Khan was a musician from India who turned
to the teaching of Sufism.35 His work on music has become
something of a classic. In it he gives expression to the
essence of music cosmology: u . . . among all the different
arts,
35
See Chap. IV, note 183, p. 264 & fig. 51, p. 516.
36
Khan, p. 53.
vol. II (London:
516
\ ' '*^C-:Hr
517
with the central question. On what level could the music of
the spheres be considered a reality? Can it act as a model
for the physical world, or is it an internal, archetypal
form that shapes experience? The writers we have been
examining place it on a variety of different levels; many of
them understand it as a potent symbol of the harmony in the
universe, others bring out deep levels of mathematical
symbolism. While we have not emphasized it, there are others
who suggest that the model of musical harmony does actually
apply to the physical structure of the external world. Some
research has been directed towards proving, for example,
that Kepler's formulations were closer to the truth than is
currently accepted. Godwin reports that:
The recent researches of Rudolph Haase show that the
predominance of harmonious intervals in the solar
system, as discovered by Kepler, not only far exceeds
random expectation, but is reinforced by measurement of
the outer planets that were not yet discovered in
Kepler's day. So Kepler was right, and it remains for
us to draw conclusions appropriate to our own time and
convictions.38
Bodefs Law. Godwin is referring to a pair of articles
by Rudolf Haase, "Kepler's World Harmony and its
Significance for Today,"39 and "The Sequel To Kepler's World
38
39
518
Harmony."40 Kayser also touches on this subject.41 Both
authors refer to the principle revealed by astronomer Johann
Daniel Titus in 1116,
cosmographicum
40
41
519
speculative literature, Plato's full meaning is conveyed
into the modern world.
Why is Plato so important? There is no doubt that he
was a major source of the tradition. But it is not simply a
question of whether Platonic sources have been followed
slavishly by subsequent writers. The question
central
issue
raised
by Plato
applied
to the understanding
in those
of musical
sources
is
whether
has
cosmology.
the
been
And the
42
The central
issue,
therefore,
is primarily
ontological.
43
44
Heninger, p. 10.
521
Heninger's statement brings us to the crux of the
matter. Plato was unequivocal about the significance of this
distinction, but when we examine the literature of the music
of the spheres tradition it is rarely clear which of these
levels is being discussed, or, more importantly, which
level, if any, is causally primary. As Heninger puts it:
Given such a dichotomization . . . we have difficulty
in designating which kind of experience is real and
which is only a projection of the other.45
This is a general statement, but it is directly
applicable to the tradition we have been studying. A host of
problems flows from the dichotomy Heninger describes. We
could cite the confusion from the time of Plato onwards
regarding the ontological status of the notes, the planets
and the spheres; are these physical phenomena, metaphors,
allegories, or archetypal symbols? We could point to the
difficulties discussed above in understanding the phenomenon
of music itself, in the context of contemporary thought; is
it a mental phenomenon, or can it be reduced to its physical
components? What is more important, however, is the fact
that this ontological problem is fundamental and has an
effect on all aspects of epistemology.
45
Ibid.
522
Forgotten Truth. At this point we need to remind
ourselves again, as we were by James in Chapter I, and by
Plotinus, Porphyry, and Macrobius in Chapter V,4t that the
music of the spheres has always been linked with the more
general concept of the Great Chain of Being. It is these two
ideas together that for James constitute "The Great Theme"
of Western thought.4^ Arthur Lovejoy, in his book on this
subject, points to the philosophy that provides the
foundation to this view and that he calls
"otherworldliness." He defines this as the belief that
. . . both the genuinely "real" and the truly good are
radically antithetic in their essential characteristics
to anything to be found in man's natural life, in the
ordinary course of human experience . . the objects
of sense and even of empirical scientific knowledge are
unstable, contingent, forever breaking down logically
into mere relations to other things which when
scrutinized prove equally relative and elusive.48
Thus, for example, Plato, following Pythagoras, repeatedly
directs his students not to look for reliable knowledge in
the ever-changing field of becoming. Rather, he directs our
attention to the pure Forms in the realm of Being. As
Lovejoy puts it, philosophers of this school hold that
46
47
48
523
The human will . . . not only seeks but is capable of
finding some final, fixed, immutable, intrinsic,
perfectly satisfying good . . . only in a "higher"
realm of being differing in its essential nature, and
not merely in degree and detail, from the lower.4Q
This view, Lovejoy writes, "has, in one form or
another, been the dominant official philosophy of the larger
part of civilized mankind through most of its history,"
taught "in their several fashions and with differing degrees
of rigor and thoroughness [by] the greater number of
speculative minds and of the great religious teachers."50 A
picture emerges of the universe consisting of gradations
between different distinct levels of existence, the view
that came to be known as the Great Chain of Being,
understood and described slightly differently in various
historical and cultural settings.
According to this nearly universal view, reality is a
rich tapestry of interwoven levels, reaching
from
matter to body to mind to soul to spirit.
Each senior
level "envelops" or "enfolds" its junior dimensionsa
series of nests within nests within nests of Beingso
that every thing and event in the world is interwoven
with every other, and all are ultimately enveloped by
Spirit, by God, by Goddess, by Tao, by Brahman, by the
Absolute itself.51
49
50
Ibid.
51
524
Ken Wilber, citing Huston Smith, agrees with Lovejoy as
to the universal diffusion of the idea:
Huston Smithwhom many consider the world's leading
authority on comparative religionhas pointed out, in
his wonderful book Forgotten
Truth, that virtually all
of the worldfs great wisdom traditions subscribe to a
belief in the Great Chain of Being. Smith is not alone
in this conclusion. From Ananda Coomaraswamy to Rene
Guenon, from Fritjof Schuon to Nicholas Berdyaev, from
Michael Murphy to Roger Walsh, from Seyyed Nasr to Lex
Hixon, the conclusion is consistent: the core of the
premodern religious world view is the Great Chain of
Being.5:
Plato is essentially outlining this concept in the
Divided Line analogy; he describes a graded series of four
ontological levels, two of which exist within ourselves with
the other two referring to the external world. But, as with
many ideas expressed by Plato, it was given a slightly
different interpretation by Aristotle, with some loss of
clarity regarding the location of these various levels. In
developing systems of classification of natural phenomena,
"it was he [Aristotle] who chiefly suggested to naturalists
and philosophers of later times the idea of arranging (at
least) all animals in a single graded scala
according to their degree of ^perfection.' "53
52
Wilber (1998) , p. 6.
53
naturae
525
The result was the conception of the plan and structure
of the world which, through the Middle Ages and down to
the late eighteenth century . . . most educated men
were to accept without questionthe conception of the
universe as a "Great Chain of Being," composed of an
immense, or ... infinite, number of links ranging in
hierarchical order from the meagerest kind of existents
. . . through "every possible" grade up to the ens
perfect!
ssimum.54
54
Ibid.
55
Tradition
526
This theme keeps returningthe development of science
and its resulting effect on the world-view we have been
considering. We have mentioned the separation of mind and
body resulting from the work of Descartes. We have pointed
to the reductionism that follows from a purely mechanistic
methodology. Now we see a further, ontological,
ramification. According to Smith, and Wilber, the effect of
scientific thinking on the Great Chain of Being was to
collapse it. The method of empirical verification of
knowledge is enormously powerful; it removes doubt,
superstition, guesswork, factually false theories, and a
dependence upon scriptural authority. But, by definition,
empirical methodology takes place on the physical level.
Objects can be larger or smaller, forces can be
stronger or weaker, durations can be longer or shorter,
these all being numerically reckonable. But to speak of
anything in science as having a different ontological
statusas being better, say, or more realis to speak
nonsense.
Itself occupying no more than a single ontological
plane, science challenged by implication the notion
that other planes exist. As its challenge was not
effectively met, it swept the field and gave the modern
world its soul.56
Both Wilber and Smith, along with the other researchers
he cites, such as Guenon,57 Schuon,58 Nasr,59 argue that
Smith, p. 6.
57
Vedanta,
Becoming
527
science has solved many questions over the last three
centuries but has also caused many others, particularly the
loss of wholeness in our understanding of ourselves and
nature. This was not,
science
itself,
result
of
scientism.
according
to Vedanta
58
528
latter two have been discarded in the single pursuit of
trutha noble intention with unintended consequences. He
calls the result the "disaster of modernity."
We can also call this disaster "the collapse of the
Kosmos," because the three great domainsart, science
and moralsafter their heroic differentiation, were
rudely collapsed into only one "real" domain, that of
empirical and monological science, a world of nothing
but meaningless Its roaming a one-dimensional flatland.
The scientific worldview was of a universe composed
entirely of objective processes, all described not in
I-language or we-language, but merely in it-language,
with no consciousness, no interiors, no values, no
meaning, no depth and no Divinity.61
It is not just that we need more holistic thinking, Wilber
explains. The thinkers and philosophers who forged the
scientific revolution had a holistic view of the world.
"This *great interlocking order,' as numerous theorists from
Charles Taylor to Arthur Lovejoy have carefully
demonstrated, was one of the defining conceptions of the
Enlightenment and of the modern scientific worldview.": The
problem is that it was a flatland
holism.
62
529
the value spheres to monological Its perceived by the
eye of flesh that, more than anything else, constituted
the disaster of modernism.63
Wilber refers here to the three eyes of knowledge of
St. Bonaventure,64 a concept that corresponds closely with
Plato's divided line analogy. Both he and Huston Smith are
suggesting that scientific methodology is built around the
eye of flesh and the eye of reason, and, crudely understood,
is taken to exclude the eye of spirit, thus dealing only
with levels two and three of the divided line. But there are
signs that this limited view of the range of science has
already become obsolete in view of recent findings in some
areas of research. As long ago as 1955, physicist Wolfgang
Pauli could report the following:
Since the discovery of the quantum of action, physics
has gradually been forced to relinquish its proud claim
to be able to understand, in principle, the whole
world. This very circumstance, however, as a
correction of earlier one-sidedness, could contain the
germ of progress toward a unified conception of the
entire cosmos of which the natural sciences are only a
part.65
63
Ibid.
64
65
530
There are other scientists whose insight runs along
similar lines. Eugene Wigner, whose comment on the
"unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics in the physical
sciences" we have already noted,66 relates this to the role
of consciousnessa factor ignored in Wilber's flatland.
Until not many years ago, the "existence" of a mind or
soul would have been passionately denied by most
physical scientists. . . and it was nearly universally
accepted among physical scientists that there is
nothing besides matter. There are several reasons for
the return, on the part of most physical scientists, to
the spirit of Descartes's "Cogito ergo sum," which
recognizes the thought, that is the mind, as primary. .
. . It may be premature to believe that the present
philosophy of quantum mechanics will remain a permanent
feature of future physical theories; it will remain
remarkable, in whatever way our future concepts
develop, that the very study of the external world led
to the conclusion that the content of the consciousness
is an ultimate reality.67
Wigner sees consciousness as one polarity in the
Cartesian dualism and the pendulum of modern thought
swinging toward that side of the dichotomy. Sir James Jeans
conceived of the resolution of the dichotomy itself, and
this was in 1948!
Today there is a wide measure of agreement, which
on the physical side of science approaches almost to
unanimity, that the stream of knowledge is heading
towards a non-mechanical reality; the universe begins
66
67
531
to look more like a great thought than a great machine.
Mind no longer appears as an accidental intruder into
the realm of matter; We are beginning to suspect that
we ought rather to hail it as the creator and governor
of the realm of matternot of course our individual
minds, but the mind in which the atoms out of which our
individual minds have grown exist as thoughts.
The old dualism of mind and matter . . . seems
likely to disappear, not through matter becoming in
any way more shadowy or insubstantial than heretofore,
or through mind becoming resolved into a function of
the working of matter, but through substantial matter
resolving itself into a creation and manifestation of
mind.66
This is a challenge to the mechanistic world-view from the
standpoint of physics. Freeman Dyson also challenges that
view within the field of biology.
The mind, I believe, exists in some very real sense, in
the Universe. But is it primary or the accidental
consequence of something else? The prevailing view
among biologists seems to be that the mind arose
accidentally out of molecules of DNA or something. I
find that very unlikely. It seems more reasonable to
think that mind was a primary part of nature from the
beginning and we are simply manifestations of it at the
present stage of history. It's not so much that mind
has a life of its own, but that mind is inherent in the
way the Universe is built and life is naturefs way to
give mind opportunities it wouldn't otherwise have.69
Many great scientists have observed that there is more
to the universe than mere matter; the very experience of
68
Report,
532
deep intuitive understanding itself demands more than a
purely mechanical explanation. Einstein related it to music.
Somewhere I have heard the phrase "The matchless beauty
of Einsteinfs mathematics." I am sure this beauty of
conception was the outcome of pure musical skill.
Einstein was only sixteen when he had the idea that was
to bring about such a revolution in physics, and he
himself says, "It [the optics of motion] occurred to me
by intuition. And music is the driving force behind
this intuition. My parents had me play the violin from
the time I was six. My new discovery is the result of
musical perception."70
Such minds are at the cutting edge of science; the
mainstream is a different matter. There has been an upsurge
in interest in the understanding of consciousness, but, as
we know from Thomas Kuhn, scientific paradigms shift very
slowly.71 However, the need for such a shift to occur with
some urgency has been noted on the most practical level.
The World Problematique
In a famous statement in 1968,72 the Club of Rome set
forth what they termed the "world problematique"the
70
72
Revolutions
533
complex of social/ economic/ and environmental problems that
threaten human life on our planet. Following from thisf in a
landmark 1970 study, a group of futurists at the Stanford
Research Institute, headed by Willis Harman and Joseph
Campbell/ were commissioned by the U.S. Department of
Education to provide some insight into future trends as a
guideline for educational policy.
After projecting a total of forty "future histories"
and studying the results, they concluded that the current
world-view and the technologies it supports, even though it
has created enormous benefits on one level/ has become
obsolete/ even pathogenic/ and is now responsible for
generating the world macroproblem. They write:
On the whole, it looks as though of some 40 feasible
future histories, there are very few that manage to
avoid some period of serious trouble between now and
2050. The few that dof appear to require a dramatic
shift of values and perceptions with regard to what we
came to term the world "macroproblem."'73
The authors do propose a solution/ but their
recommendation has nothing to do with economics/ technology
or politics. Rather, it hinges upon a complete change in our
way of understanding ourselves and our world.
73
534
If we are correct in this tentative belief that the
various aspects of the world macroproblem, although
they may be ameliorated or postponed by certain
technological achievements/ are intrinsic in the basic
operative premises of present industrialized culture
if this is correct/ then it follows that education
toward changing those premises/ directly or indirectly/
is the paramount educational task for the nation and
the world. This means that education should be directed
toward responsible stewardship of life on earth with
the associated changes in values and premises. It
probably includes adaptation to a new and evolving
metaphysic that will support these changes (since
values are always rooted in an implicit picture of manin-relation-to-his-world) .74
The action they propose is on several levels: they wish to
change fundamental premises through education/ while
simultaneously indicating that such an approach rests
ultimately upon a conceptual
74
535
places that Huxley has termed it the "Perennial
Philosophy. "75
536
world; its metaphysical claim of a "divine reality" in
particular goes beyond what the modern scientific mind may
be willing to entertain. But the Stanford Research Institute
team, in the second of their two studies, are firm in their
belief that
. . . this view of man, if it can be experienced by
more than the small minority of persons who have
apparently realized it through the centuries, would
seem to provide the needed sense of direction and the
holistic perspective and understanding described.78
537
of the magical, organic and mechanistic strands of thought,
the use of all three eyes of knowledge, and the traversing
of all levels of the divided line analogy as Plato demanded
and as Pythagoras suggested when he sought empirical
justification of his own mental, or spiritual, insights.
Some excellent minds continue to be absorbed in these
ideas. As a student of religion, Huston Smith contributes
the insight that the Great Chain is understood in strikingly
similar ways in different religious traditions. The
different ontological levels are represented primarily in
four categories, as seen in fig. 52. He offers this model as
a starting point for the development of a new paradigm.
Ken Wilber has done perhaps the most sophisticated work
in this area, drawing on Eastern philosophical traditions as
well as the most recent work in psychology to develop what
he calls the Spectrum of Consciousness model/9 Noting that
reality, and our description of it, fall into a series of
unrelated categories, each with its own academic disciplines
and self-serving terminology, he proposes a model that
provides a holistic context within which any phenomenon can
be understood. The model has essentially four components.
Reflecting the primary distinction between inner and outer
79
LEVELS OF REALTTY
A
CHINESE RUCIOUS I
COMPLEX
JUDAISM
CHRISTIANITY
LEVELS OF SELFHOOD
539
worlds, he goes one stage further and adds the categories of
individual and communal or collective to arrive at four
quadrants/ encompassing what he calls the "intentional,"
"behavioral/' "social," and "cultural" spheres (fig. 53).
Within each sphere he introduces a series of sub-categories
to allow for different organizational and ontological
hierarchies. From there, he proceeds to integrate concepts
from the different disciplines, particularly the physical
and social sciences, to provide a single framework within
which all phenomena can be understood.
Wilber's goal is to develop the holistic vision that
Godwin calls for, and particularly to move toward a
reintegration of science and religion. Reintegrating
scientific and esthetic values must be a corollary of this.
But there is no doubt that this is indeed "a complex and
extremely long and arduous process, to which workers in all
fields will have to contribute."80 At this point, one of the
fields of research that is most important in such an effort
is consciousness studies.
What is consciousness?
One conclusion that has emerged from our review of the
music of the spheres is that it cannot be regarded merely as
80
540
'
(R4haU..r4
: ' j
j
| "1 T
hunt- ..^ i
"1r
\ !
':XI, W
,. !
{* J ^ w n o i - * ti*
IT
-I'< X ^ TI'ffM^f
"
i
; _ ; 1 ! >[
JH*4*
j 1*4- | "
W e r Right1!r
p-
,.r\
(Soc.ll)
,
te^
I
"i H"M<M
* I
541
a phenomenon in the external, physical, world; the research
we have examined suggests that there is an important
internal, mental component. Thus, the separate development
of the concept within the magical and mechanistic strands of
thought, and its eventual rejection by the latter tradition,
reflects an incomplete understanding of its nature and
significance. To re-evaluate the tradition in terms of a
new, more integrated world-view, requires a deeper
understanding of the mental component. This has been
difficult up to now because, following Descartes' separation
of mind and matter, science found it both easier and more
productive to focus on the physical side of the picture, and
an understanding of mind has largely lagged behind. That is
not to say that the various fields of psychology have not
observed and classified the activity and content of mind in
great detail, and that neuroscience has not gone a long way
in charting relationships between mental events and activity
in the brain. But none of this has answered the fundamental
question of what the mind, or consciousness, itself is. In
recent years, however, this has become a subject of much
greater interest among scientists. Pauli expressed such a
need almost fifty years ago, in the essay already cited81
about the dispute between Fludd and Kepler, which was
Pauli, p. 208.
83
Consciousness," Journal
of Consciousness
Studies,
Vol 2, No.
543
Chalmers does not agree that the problem is
intractable, but he does divide it into two parts, the
"easy" problem and the "hard" problem. He lists some
examples of so-called "easy" problems:
the ability to discriminate, categorize, and react to
environmental stimuli; the integration of information
by a cognitive system; the reportability of mental
states; the ability of a system to access its own
internal states; the focus of attention; the deliberate
control of behavior; the difference between wakefulness
and sleep.*4
These phenomena lend themselves fairly readily to
explanation in terms of neurophysiology and similar
disciplines. "All of them are straightforwardly vulnerable
to explanation in terms of computational or neural
mechanisms," Chalmers reports. "This is why I call these
problems the easy problems." Of course, he adds, "easy" is a
relative term; solving these problems will require an
enormous amount of work over a considerable period of time.
But at least the path to their solution is understood.
"There is every reason to believe that the methods of
cognitive science and neuroscience will succeed."85 The
philosophers, including Chalmers, can be found in Jonathan
Shear, ed., Explaining
Consciousness:
The Hard Problem
(Cambridge: MIT Press, 1997)
84
Ibid.
85
Ibid.
544
problem of mind itself is quite another matter; it goes
beyond these phenomena and becomes a problem of much greater
magnitude.
The really hard problem of consciousness is the problem
of experience.
When we think and perceive, there is a
whir of information-processing, but there is also a
subjective aspect. . . This subjective aspect is
experience. To make further progress, we will need
further investigation, more refined theories, and more
careful analysis. The hard problem is a hard problem,
but there is no reason to believe that it will remain
permanently unsolved.86
If this problem does indeed yield to scientific
explanation, Chalmers feels, the effects will be felt well
beyond the narrow realms of cognitive science and
neuroscience. It is worth reproducing Chalmers's analysis of
this potential in its entirety:
Once a fundamental link between information and
experience is on the table, the door is opened to some
grander metaphysical speculation concerning the nature
of the world. For example, it is often noted that
physics characterizes its basic entities only
extrinsically,
in terms of their relations to other
entities, which are themselves characterized
extrinsically, and so on. The intrinsic nature of
physical entities is left aside. Some argue that no
such intrinsic properties exist, but then one is left
with a world that is pure causal flux (a pure flow of
information) with no properties for the causation to
relate. If one allows that intrinsic properties exist,
a natural speculation given the above is that the
intrinsic properties of the physical - the properties
that causation ultimately relates - are themselves
phenomenal properties. We might say that phenomenal
86
Ibid.
545
properties are the internal aspect of information. This
could answer a concern about the causal relevance of
experiencea natural worry, given a picture on which
the physical domain is causally closed, and on which
experience is supplementary to the physical. The
informational view allows us to understand how
experience might have a subtle kind of causal relevance
in virtue of its status as the intrinsic nature of the
physical. This metaphysical speculation is probably
best ignored for the purposes of developing a
scientific theory, but in addressing
some
philosophical
issues it is quite
suggestive.97
It is suggestive because it reintroduces the notion of the
"thing in itself' that scientific methodology had felt the
need to abandon, and relates this *thing in itself" to the
function of experience. Whether such a framework would go
some way towards satisfying Zuckerkandl's plea for deeper
insight is certainly speculative. But are these not the kind
of questions with which speculative music should deal?
The Role of Musicoloav
All of the foregoing raises a basic question. Can the
study of music itself contribute to the effort Lowinsky
outlines, or answer questions raised by Epstein when he
calls for "a new and broader frame of reference for
theoretical inquiry in music"?88 A new approach is called
for, Epstein writes, because current methods "cannot deal
17
Ibid.
546
with the kinds of questions concerning affect and
expression," because their operative assumptions are
"limited to the handling of primarily objective musical
data."69 They certainly do not extend to an understanding of
the subjective realms that are an essential part of music.
Epstein agrees that "we may be ready for another of those
shifts of perspective whose need arises on an almost
cyclical basis in theoretical inquiry."90 But can such an
approach grow out of the disciplines of music theory and
musicology themselves, or can it only be the beneficiary of
a more integrated world view developed within other
disciplines, such as consciousness studies? Currently, while
aspects of the physical and social sciences, including
anthropology, are well represented, disciplines of a
philosophical or metaphysical nature play a very limited
role in the musicology and music theory curricula. If
speculative musicology is to make a greater contribution, it
will have to take a form that differs considerably from the
one Godwin sketches. The context in which Godwin places
speculative music is the "occult," something that can be a
subject of academic study but not an academic category in
89
Ibid.
90
547
its own right; lacking a proper foundation there is no
context into which such work can be placed and evaluated.
91
548
Mediterranean world," that "have captivated European minds"
cited by Gary Tomlinson in Chapter I, namely
"music's
Conclusion
In this study I have suggested that if we are to find
any value in the music of the spheres tradition, it is not
in re-establishing an archaic view of astronomy, or music
theory, but in gaining a deeper understanding of the links
between the inherent structure of human consciousness and
the nature of the physical world, with special regard to
phenomena such as music. Such an intention can be found at
92
93
Addis, p. 72.
549
the core of the Platonic literature that forms the source of
the tradition in the Western world, but this intention was
largely lost in the transmission of the tradition over two
and a half millennia. It has been suggested, however, that
we may be ready to reconsider such a viewpoint.
Only now, in the last quarter of our century, the
knowledge won through the Scientific Revolution is
ready to be incorporated into a new system that again
takes account of metaphysical realities. The spiral of
human development is leading many people back to a
world view not so very different from Fluddfs, yet, (as
is the way with spirals) a little more advanced.94
For the world view to be more advanced it will have to draw
on the kind of work being done by Chalmers, Shear, et al. In
the field of music, Addis' work makes a significant
contribution by suggesting a link between musica mundana and
musica instrumentalis.
94
550
95
SELECTED BIBLIOGRAPHY
Addis, Laird. Of Mind and Music
University Press, 1999)
(Lee1s Summit,
552
Apatow, Robert. "The Tetraktys: The Cosmic Paradigm of the
Ancient Pythagoreans," Parabola, Vol. 24, No. 3
(August 1999)
ranya, Swmi Hariharanda. The Yoga Philosophy of
Patanjali.
P.N. Mukerji, trans. (Calcutta: University of
Calcutta, 1977)
Aristotle. De caelo. W. K. C. Guthrie, trans. (Cambridge:
Harvard University Press, 1939)
. Metaphysics,
1-5, 985b-98 6a, in Complete Works of
Aristotle,
Jonathan Barnes, ed., Bollingen Series
LXXI-2, Vol. 2 (Princeton: Princeton University
Press, 1984)
Artusi, Giovanni Maria. L'arte
tavole
(Venice, 1586)
Ashe, Geoffrey The Ancient
1979)
del
contraponto
ridotta
in
Dualism
553
Bakewell, Charles M. "The Philosophical Roots of Western
Culture," in F. S. C. Northrop, The Logic of the
Sciences and the Humanities
(New York: Macmillan &
Co., 1947), pp, 69-89
Bamford, Christopher, ed. Rediscovering
(Edinburgh: Floris Books, 1994)
Sacred
Science
the
554
Blacker, Carmen & Michael Lowe, eds. Ancient
Cosmologies
(London: George Allen & Unwin Ltd., 1975)
Blacking, John. How Musical is Man? (Seattle: University of
Washington Press, 1973)
Bodde, Derk. "The Chinese Cosmic Magic Known as Watching for
the Ethers," in Scren Gerod & Else Glahn, eds.,
Studia Serica Bernhard Karlgren Dedicata
(Copenhagen:
Ejnar Munksgaard, 1959), pp. 14-35
Boethius, De institutione
musica, trans, with commentary by
Calvin M. Bower as The Principles
of Mjsic (Ph.D.
dissertation, George Peabody College for Teachers,
1967)
. The Principles
of Arithmetic,
in Boethius, The
Principles
of Music, Calvin M. Bower, trans, and
commentary (Ph.D. dissertation, George Peabody
College for Teachers, 1967)
. De institutione
musica, trans, by Calvin M. Bower as
The Fundamentals of Music, Claude V. Palisca, ed.
(New Haven & London: Yale University Press, 1989)
Bonner, Alice. "The Symbolic Aspect of Form,n Journal of the
Indian Society
of Oriental
Art, Vol. 10 (1942), pp.
42-50
Boorstin, Daniel. The Discoverers
1983)
Bose, Hiren. Philosophy
Co., 1988)
in Indian
555
Brendel, Otto J. Symbolism of the Sphere: A Contribution
to
the History of Earlier
Greek Philosophy
(Leiden: E.
J. Brill, 1977)
Brisson, Luc and F. Walter Meyerson. Inventing
the
Universe:
Timaeus, the Big Bang, and the Problem of
Platofs
Knowledge (Albany: State University of New York
Press, 1995)
Brumbaugh, Robert S. Plato's
Mathematical
Imagination
(Bloomington: Indiana University Publications, 1954,
and New York: Kraus Reprint Corporation, 1968)
Bukofzer, Manfred. "Speculative Thinking in Medieval Music,"
Speculum, XVII (1942), pp. 163-171
Burkert, Walter. Lore and Science in Ancient
Pythagoreanism,
Edwin L. Minar Jr., trans. (Cambridge: Harvard
University Press, 1972)
Burnet, John. Early Greek Philosophy,
Meridian, 1957)
of Outer Space
Mythology
Essays
(New York:
1959-1987
(San
556
Camphausen, Ruf us C. The Divine Library : A Comprehensive
Reference Guide to the Sacred Texts and
Spiritual
Literature
of the World (Rochester, Vermont: Inner
Traditions International, 1992)
Capra, Fritjof. The Tao of Physics:
An Exploration
of the
Parallels
Between Modern Physics and Eastern
Mysticism
(Boulder, Colorado : Shambhala, 1983)
Carpenter, Nan Cooke, Music in the Medieval and
Renaissance
Universities
(Norman, Oklahoma: University of
Oklahoma Press, 1958)
Carrasco, David. Religions
of Mesoamerica:
Cosmovision
Ceremonial Centers (Prospect Heights, Illinois:
Waveland Press, 1990(
and
Cassiodorus,, Institutiones
humanarum litterarum,
Book 2,
Chapter 5, Helen Dill Goode & Gertrude C. Drake,
trans. (Colorado Springs: Colorado College Music
Press Translations, 1980)
Cassiodorus Senator, An Introduction
to Divine and Human
Readings,
Leslie Webber Jones, trans. (New York:
Octagon Books, Inc., 1966)
Cassirer, Ernst. Individuum und Kosmos in der
Philosophie
der Renaissancer
trans, by Mario Domandi as The
Individual
and the Cosmos in Renaissance
Philosophy,
(Oxford: B. Blackwell, 1963)
. The Philosophy
of Symbolic Forms, Ralph Manheim,
trans., Charles W. Hendel, intro. (New Haven: Yale
University Press, 1965)
. Die philosophie
der Aufklrung,
trans, by Fritz, C.
A. Koelin and James P. Pettegrove as The
Philosophy
of the Enlightenment
(Boston: Beacon Press, 1955)
557
the Consolations
of Music,
Logic,
Chadwick, Henry. Boethiusf
Theology, and Philosophy
(Oxford: Clarendon Press,
1981)
Chakravarthy, G. N. The Concept of Cosmic Harmony in the Rg
Veda (Mysore: Prasaranga, University of Mysore, 1966)
Chalmers, David J. "Facing Up to the Problem of
Consciousness," Journal of Consciousness
Vol. 2, No. 3 (1995), pp. 200-219
. The Conscious
1996)
Studies,
of
Chinese
Cohen, H. F. Quantifying
Music (Dordrecht/Boston/Lancaster:
D. Reidel Publishing Co., 1984)
Coleman, R. G. G. "The Dream of Cicero," Proceedings
of the
Cambridge Philological
Society
10 (1964), pp. 1-14
Coleman-Norton, P. R. "Cicero and the Music of the Spheres,"
The Classical
Journal 45 (1949-1950), pp. 237-241
Cook, Roger. The Tree of Life:
Thames & Hudson, 1974)
Image for
558
Coomaraswamy, Ananda, K. The Dance of iva: Fourteen
Indian
Essays (London: Simpkin, Marshall/ Hamilton, Kent &
Co., 1924)
. Hinduism and Buddhism
Library, 1943)
.The Transformation
Publications, 1956)
in Nature
of Art
(London:
(Cambridge: Cambridge
Still
Mathematics?
559
Crocker, Richard L. wPythagorean Mathematics and Music, "The
Journal of Aesthetics
and Art Criticism,
Pt. 1, XXII
No. 2 (Winter 1963), pp. 189-98; Pt. 2, XXII No. 3,
(Spring 1964), pp. 325-35
. A History
of Musical
Style.
musicale
. Northern Indian
Praeger, 1968)
Music,
560
with N. R. Bhatt. Textes des Purna sur la Thorie
Musicale,
Vol. 1 (Pondichery: Institute Franais
d'Indologie, 1987)
. Le Gitalamkara:
L'Ouvrage Original
de Bharata sur la
Musique (Pondicherry: Institute Franais dfIndologie,
1987)
Dear, Peter Robert. Mersenne and the Learning of the
Schools: Continuity
and Transformation
in the
Scientific
Revolution
(Ph.D. Dissertation, Princeton
University, 1984)
De Vogel, C.J. Pythagoras and Early Pythagorism
Holland: Van Gorcum Co., 1966)
(Assen,
561
as Lives
of the Philosophers
dogmatis
et
. "The Life of Pythagoras," from De vitisr
apophthegmatis
clarorum philosophorum,
trans. Kenneth
Sylvan Guthrie, in Kenneth Sylvan Guthrie, ed., The
Pythagorean Sourcebook and Library
(Grand Rapids:
Phanes Press, 1987), pp. 141-156
Dobbs, Betty Jo Teeter. The Foundations of Newton's
Alchemy
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1975)
. The Janus Face of Genius: The Role of Alchemy in
Newton's Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1991)
and Margaret C. Jacob. Newton and The Culture
Newtonianism
(Atlantic Highlands, New Jersey:
Humanities Press, 1995)
Dyson, Freeman. Interview in U.S. News and World
April 18, 1988, p. 72
Edelstein, Ludwig. Plato's
Brill, 1966)
Seventh
Letter
of
Report,
(Leiden: E. J.
(San Diego: Point
Religions
(New York:
. Yoga: Immortality
and Freedom (Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 1969)
. Patafijali
1976)
et le
562
. "Sacred Architecture and Symbolism," in Symbolism,
the Sacred, and the Arts, Diane Apostolos-Cappadona,
ed. (New York: Crossroad, 1985), pp. 105-129
Encyclopedia
Judaica
(Jerusalem, 1971)
of the
Elementary
M.A. Thesis, University
comme science
Fabre d1Olivet, Antoine. La musique explique
et comme art et considre
dans ses
rapports
analogiques
avec les mystres religieux,
la
mythologie
ancienne et l'histori
de la
terre.
(Paris: Jean Pinasseau, 1928), trans, as Music
Explained as Science and Art: and Considered
in its
Analogical
Relations
to Religious
Mysteries,
Ancient
Mythology,
and the History of the World, by Joscelyn
Godwin (Rochester, Vermont: Inner Traditions
International, 1987)
Farrow, J. T. and Herbert, R. "Breath suspension during the
transcendental meditation technique,"
Psychosomatic
Medicine,
44(2), 1982, pp. 133-153
Favonius, Disputatio
de Somnio Scipionis,
R. E. van
Weddington, ed. (Brussels: Latomus, 1957)
Fideler, David. Jesus Christ,
Sun of God: Ancient
Cosmology
and Early Christian
Symbolism (Wheaton, Illinois &
Madras, India: Quest Books/ Theosophical Publishing
House, 1993)
Finney, Gretchen Ludke. Musical Backgrounds for
English
Literature:
1580-1650 (Westport, Connecticut :
Greenwood Press, 1976)
Fischer, Ernst Peter. Beauty and The Beast: The
Aesthetic
Moment in Science,
Elizabeth Oehlkers, trans. (New
York & London: Plenum Trade, 1999)
563
Fisher, Fred. "Mathematical Techniques in Music History,"
Proceedings
of the College Music Society,
Vol. 18
(1978), pp. 24-33
Fludd, Robert. Tractatus
apologeticus
(Leiden, 1617)
. Anatomiae amphitheatrum
(Frankfurt, 1623). (Includes
Monochordum mundi, 1621, pp. 287-331)
. Monochordvm mvndi symphoniacvm, seu, Replicatio
Roberti Flvd, alias de Fluctibus ad apologiam Ioannis
Kepleri aduersus demonstrationem suam analyticam,
nuperrime editam in qua Robertvs Validoribvs Ioannis
obiectionibus, harmoniae suae legi repugnantibus,
comiter respondere aggreditur.(Francofvrti: Apud
loan, Theodor de Bry, 1622)
Franklin, John Curtis. Harmony and Indo-European
Cosmology,
Oxford University, Ph.D. dissertation, in progress
Freden, Gustaf. Orpheus and the Goddess of Nature (Gteborg:
Gteborgs Universitets Arsskrift, Vol. LXIV, No. 6
(1958)
Gaffurio, Franchino. Theoricum opus musiche
discipline
(Naples, 1480), trans, by Walter Kurt Kreyszig as The
Theory of Music, Claude Palisca, ed. (New Haven: Yale
University Press, 1993)
Gafori, Franchino. Practica musicae, reprint of Milan 1496
edition (Farnborough, England, 1967)
. Theorica musicae,
York, 1967)
564
ed., Music Theory Translation Series, no. 1 (New
Haven, Connecticut: Yale School of Music, 1963)
Ghosh, Niranjan. r Sarasvati
in Indian Art and
Literature,
Sri Garib Das Oriental Series, No. 11 (Delhi: Sri
Satguru Publications, 1984)
Ghyka, Matila. "The Pythagorean and Platonic Scientific
Criterion of the Beautiful in Classical Western Art,"
in F. S. C. Northrop, The Logic of the Sciences and
the Humanities
(New York: Macmillan & Co., 1947), pp.
90-116
. The Geometry of Art and Life
Thought and
Gibson, Margaret, ed., Boethius:
His Lifef
Influence
(Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1981)
Gikatilla, Rabbi Joseph. Gates of Light: Sha'are Orah, Avi
Weinstein, trans. & intro. (San Francisco & London:
HarperCollins, 1994)
Gingerich, Owen. "Copernicus: A Modern Reapprisal," in
Corson, David W. Man's Place in the
Universe:
Changing Concepts (Tucson Arizona: University of
Arizona, College of Liberal Arts, 1977), pp. 27-49
Giorgi, Francesco. De Harmonia Mundi Totius
Glazerson, Matityahu. Music and Kabbalah
Jersey: Jason Aronson, 1997)
(Venice, 1525)
(Northvale, New
(London:
565
. Harmonies of Heaven and Earth: The
Spiritual
Dimension of Music from Antiquity
to the
Avant-Garde
(Rochester, Vermont: Inner Traditions International,
1987)
.ed., Cosmic Music: Three Musical Keys to the
Interpretation
of Reality,
Joscelyn Godwin & M.
Radkai, trans. (Rochester, Vermont: Inner Traditions
International, 1989)
. The Harmony of the Spheres: A Sourcebook of the
Pythagorean
Tradition
in Music (Rochester, Vermont:
Inner Traditions International, 1993)
. Arktos:
The Polar Myth in Science,
Symbolism,
and
Nazi Survival
(Grand Rapids, Michigan: Phanes Press,
1993)
. The Theosophical
Enlightenment
(Albany: State
University of New York Press, 1994)
. Music and the Occult: French Musical
Cosmologies
1750-1950 (Rochester: University of Rochester Press,
1995)
Gonda, J. Notes on Names and the Name of God in Ancient
India (Amsterdam, London: North-Holland Publishing
Co., 1970)
. Psan and SarasvatI
(Amsterdam, Oxford, New York:
North-Holland Publishing Company, 1985)
Gorman, Peter. Pythagoras:
Paul, 1979)
A Life
(Bristol, U.K.:
566
Guenon, Ren. Homme et son devenir selon le Vedanta, trans,
by Richard C. Nicholson as Man and His Becoming
according
to Vedanta (New York: The Noonday Press,
1958)
Orient
et Occident
and
of
Pythagoreismus
567
. Zwanzig Jahre Hans-Kayser-Institut
fr Harmonikale
Grundlagenforschung.
Schriften ber Harmonik/ no. 17
(Bern: Kreis der Freunde um Hans Kayser, 1988)
. "Harmonics and Sacred Tradition, " Marton Radkai,
trans., in Joscelyn Godwin, ed., Cosmic Music: Three
Musical Keys to the Interpretation
of
Reality
(Rochester, Vermont: Inner Traditions International,
1989),pp. 93-94
. "Kepler's World Harmony and its Significance for
Today," in Joscelyn Godwin, ed., Cosmic Music:
Musical Keys to the Interpretation
of
Reality
(Rochester, Vermont: Inner Traditions International,
1989), pp. 111-130
Hadingham, Evan. Early
& Co., 1984)
Disciplina,
Renaissance
(Leiden &
in
569
Howard/ Wayne. Samvedic
Press, 1977)
Principal
Upanishads,
with an Outline of the
(London: Oxford University
Philosophy
Pythagorica,
trans, by Kenneth Sylvan
Life of Pythagoras or The Pythagoric
life,
Sylvan Guthrie/ ed.f The Pythagorean
and Library
(Grand Rapids: Phanes Press,
57-122
570
Jayakar, Unnati. A Comparative Study of Some of the Ancient
Musical Systems of the World. M. Phil. Dissertation
(Delhi Universityf 1980)
Jeans,
(Cambridge:
571
Jung, Bollingen Series XX (Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 1976), Vol. 5
. "The Symbolic Life," R. F. C. Hull, trans., in
William McGuire, ed., The Collected
Works of C. G.
Jung, Bollingen Series XX (Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 1976), Vol. 18
Kapadia, Hiralal & Antsher Lobo. Three Monographs on Music
(Bombay: Indian Musicological Society, 1980)
Kaplan, Aryeh. Meditation
and Kabbalah
Samuel Weiser, 1982)
of
. Akroasis,
Die Lehre von der Harmonik der Welt
(Basel/Stuttgart: Schwabe & Co. Verlag, 1964), trans,
by Robert Lilienfield as Akroasis:
The Theory of World
Harmonics (Boston: Plowshare Press, 1970)
Kearney, Hugh F. Science
McGraw-Hill, 1971)
(New York:
572
Kepler, Johannes. Harmonices mundi (1619), trans, by C. G.
Wallis as The Harmonies of the World, Book V, in
Mortimer J. Adler, ed., Great Books of the Western
World (Chicago: Encyclopedia Britannica, c.1990), Vol.
16
. Harmonices mundi (1619), trans, with an introduction
and notes by E. J. Aiton, A. M. Duncan, J. V. Field as
The Harmony of the World (Philadelphia: American
Philosophical Society, 1997)
. Gesammelte
1937)
. Weltharmonik,
573
Koestler, Arthur. The Watershed
1960)
. The Sleepwalkers
the
of Dattilam:
A Treatise
on the Sacred
India (New Delhi: Impex India, 1978)
and Practice
(London:
Morphology:
Discourse
and a Dictionary
Press, 1983)
Bibliography
Greece
(New
the
of Freemasonry
(New
575
Maharishi Mahesh Yogi."Music and the Science of Creative
Intelligence,n Maharishi International
University
Catalog 1974/75 (Los Angeles/Heidelberg: MIU Press,
1974)
. On the Bhagavad-Gita : A New Translation
and
Commentary, Chapters 1-6 (London and New York: Penguin
Books, 1983)
. Maharishi Gandharva-Ved.
(Vishwa Vidya Peeth,
Maharishi Nagar, India & Livingston Manor, New York:
Age of Enlightenment Press, 1991)
Majumdar, R. C , ed., The History and Culture of the Indian
People: Vol. I, The Vedic Age (Bombay: Bharatiya Vidya
Bhavan, 1951)
Malm, William P. Music Cultures of the Pacific
the Near East
and Asia (Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey: Prentice Hall,
1967)
Marcotty, Thomas. The Way-Music. Rudra Vina: The Theory and
Practice
of Tantric Music (Lugano: Decisio-Editrice,
1980)
Matanga, Brhaddel
of the
Plato
Itself
. Meditations
Through the Quran (York Beach, Maine:
Nicolas Hays, 1982)
576
McKirahan, Richard D. Philosophy before Socrates
: An
Introduction
With Texts and Commentary (Indianapolis:
Hackett Publishing Co., 1994)
McLean, Adam. The Western Mandala
Research Series, 1983)
(Edinburgh: Hermetic
Mead, G. R. S. Thrice-Greatest
Hermes: Studies
In
Hellenistic
Theosophy & Gnosis, Being a Translation
of
the Extant Sermons & Fragments of the
Trismegistic
Literature,
with Prolegomena,
Commentaries,
& Notes, 3
vols. (London & Benares: Theosophical Publishing
Society, 1906)
Meadows, Donella H. et al., The Limits to Growth: A Report
for the Club of Rome's Project
on the Predicament
of
Mankind, 2nd edition (New York : New American Library,
1975)
. Orpheus
Mehta, D. D. Positive
Sciences
Arnold Heinemann, 1974)
577
Monteverdi, Claudio. "Orfeo: Favola in Musica," English
singing version by Anne Ridler, in John Nicholas, ed.,
The Operas of Monteverdi
(London: Calder Publications &
English National Opera, 1992)
Muller-Ortega, Paul Eduardo. The Triadic Heart of iva
(Albany: State University of New York, 1989)
Nader, Tony. Human Physiology:
Espression
of Veda and the
Vedic Literature
(Vlodrop, The Netherlands: Maharishi
Vedic University Press, 1995)
Nasr, Seyyed Hossein, Knowledge and the Sacred (Albany, New
York: State University of New York Press, 1989)
The Need for a Sacred Science (Albany: State
University of New York Press, 1993)
. Religion and the Order of Nature
Oxford University Press, 1996)
. The Spiritual
and Religious
Dimensions of the
Environmental
Crisis
(London: Temenos Academy, 1999)
Navon, Robert, ed. The Pythagorean Writings:
Texts From The 1st Cent. B.C.-3rd Cent.
Gardens, New York: Selene Books, 1986)
Hellenistic
A.D. (Kew
eisagoge,
to
578
Arithmetic
1926)
. Encheiridion
harmoniks,
trans, with commentary, by
Flora Levin as The Manual of Harmonics (Grand Rapids,
Michigan: Phanes Press, 1994)
Nijenhuis, Emmie Te. Dattilam:
A Compilation
of Ancient
Indian Music (Leiden/Kln: E. J. Brill, 1970)
. Indian Music:
J. Brill, 1974)
History
& Structure
(Leiden/ Kln: E.
(New
(Berkeley: University of
of
Thought (New
(Boston: The
580
of Nature and the Psyche
151-240
(Philadelphia:
(Toronto:
. The Republic,
Francis MacDonald Cornford, trans, and
intro. (London: Oxford University Press, 198 0)
. Timaeus, Desmond Lee, trans. (London: Penguin
Books, 1965)
. The Dialogues of Plato, Jowett, Benjamin, ed. and
trans., 4th ed., 4 vols. (Oxford, 1953)
Collected
Dialogues,
Edith Hamilton and Huntington
Cairns, eds.(New York: Pantheon Books, 1961)
Porphyry of Tyre. The Life of Pythagoras,
Kenneth Sylvan
Guthrie, trans., in Kenneth Sylvan Guthrie, ed. The
Pythagorean Sourcebook and Library
(Grand Rapids:
Phanes Press, 1987), pp. 123-135
581
Porphyry of Tyre. The
trans., in Moses
Gods: Spiritual
New York: Books
Life of Pythagoras,
Morton Smith,
Hadas and Morton Smith, Heroes and
Biographies
in Antiquity
(Freeport,
for Libraries Press, 1970)
Philosophy
of Indian
Music
India
582
Quintilianus, Aristeides. Peri mousikes,
trans, by Thomas
Mathieson as On music, in Three Books (New Haven: Yale
University Press, 1983)
Radhakrishnan, Sarvepalli and Charles A. Moore, eds. A
Sourcebook in Indian Philosophy
(Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 1973)
Rghavan, V. "An Outline Literary History of Indian Musicrff
Journal of the Music Academy, Madras, Vol. XXIII (1952)
. "Music in Ancient Indian Drama," Journal of the
Music Academy, Madras, Vol. XXV, parts 1-4 (1954)
Rahamin, Atiya Begum Fyzee. The Music of India
Luzac & Co, 1925)
(London:
Science
Puja
W.D. Aristotle
Musik
India
(Boulder/
Philosophy
(New
584
Rutherford, Ward. Pythagoras,
Lover of Wisdom
(Wellingborough, Northamptonshire, U.K., 1984)
Sanyal, Ritwik. Philosophy
of Music
Somaiya Publications, 1987)
Kabbalah
32 (1960)
585
Werblowsky, ed. (Princeton: The Jewish Publication
Society/Princeton University Press, 1987)
Schopenhauer, Arthur. The World as Will and Idea, in
Masterworks of philosophy: Digests of 11 Great
Classics, S. E. Frost, Jr., ed. (Garden City, New York:
Doubleday, 1946)
Schuon, Frithjof. The Transcendent
Unity of
Religions.
Introduction by Huston Smith (Wheaton, Illinois:
Theosophical Publishing House, 1993)
Schre, Eduard. The Ancient Mysteries
of Delphi:
Pythagoras,
Paul Allen, intro. (Blauvelt, New York: Rudolf Steiner
Publications, 1971)
Schwabe, Julius. Lambdoma: Tabula Phytagorica,
Mohan Singh,
ed. (Amritsar, India: Academy of Spiritual
Culture/Arorbans Press, 1958)
. Archetyp
and Tierkreis
(Basle, 1951)
and
the
Morals
Ages
Musicology
586
Shanzer, Danuta. A Philosophical
and Litereray
Commentary on
De Nuptiis
Philologiae
Book 1
Martianus Capellafs
(Berkeley: University of California Press, 1986)
Shakespeare, William. Complete Works, Stanley Wells and Gary
Taylor, general editors (Oxford: The Clarendon Press,
1986)
Shear, Jonathan. "Maharishi, Plato and the TM-Sidhi Program
on Innate Structures of Consciousness,"
Metaphilosophy,
Vol. 12, No. 1 (January 1981), pp. 72-84
. "Mystical Experience, Hermeneutics, and
Rationality," International
Philosophical
Quarterly,
Vol. XXX, No. 4 (December 1990), pp. 391-401
. The Inner Dimension: Philosophy
and the
Experience
of Consciousness
(New York: Peter Lang, 1990)
. "The Philosopher, the Yogi, and Enlightenment:
Plato1s Symposium and Patanjali's Yoga Sutras,"
Darshana International,
Moradabad, India, Vol. XXX, No.
1 (January 1990), pp. 72-86
Shearer, Alistair. The Hindu Vision: Forms of the
(London: Thames and Hudson, 1993)
Shiloah, Amnon. The Epistle
on Music of the Ikhwan
(Tel-Aviv: Tel-Aviv University, 1978)
Formless
Al-Safa
Singal, R. L. Aristotle
and Bharata: A Comparative Study of
their Theories of Drama (Hoshiarpar, Punjab, India:
Vishveshvaranand Vedic Research Institute, Sadhu
Ashram, 1977)
Singh, Jaidev. "Nada in Indian Tradition," Journal of the
Indian Musicological
Society,
Vol. 11, Nos. 1 & 2
(Mar./Jun. 1980), pp. 37-71
Smith, Huston. Condemned to Meaning
1965)
Tradition
(New York:
Music
587
Spencer-Brown, G. Laws of Form (New York: E. P. Dutton,
1979)
Spitzer, Leopold. Die Harmonikale Symbolik des A. Frh. Von
Thimus: Ein Beitrag zur Geschichte
der Harmonik
(Beitrage zur harmonikalen Grundlagenforschung, HansKayser-Institut fr harmonikale Grundlagenforschung,
Wien (Wien: Verlag Elisabeth Lafite, 1978)
Stahl, William Harris. Marcianus Capeila and the Seven
Liberal Arts, with a Study of the Allegory
and the
Verbal Disciplines
by Richard Johnson with E.L. Brge,
(New York: Columbia University Press, 1971)
Stanley, Thomas. The History
1656-60)
of Philosophy,
2 vols. (London,
. Pythagoras:
His Life and Teachings. Being a
Photographic
Facsimili
of the Ninth Section of the 1687
Edition of The History of Philosophy by Thomas Stanley
(Los Angeles: Philosophical Research Society, 1970)
Steiner, Rudolf. The Inner Nature of Music and the
Experience
of Tone (London: Rudolf Steiner Press, 1983)
Storr, Anthony. Music and the Mind (New York/Toronto:
Macmillan-The Free Press, 1992)
Strachan, Gordon. Jesus the Master Builder:
Druid
Mysteries
and the Dawn of Christianity
(Edinburgh: Floris Books,
1998)
Suars, Carlo. The Cipher of Genesis
Samuel Weiser, 1992)
Music
(Allahabad:P Swarup
588
(University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press,
1977)
Tagore, Raja Sourindo Mohun. The Seven Principal
Notes of
the Hindus with their Presiding
Deities
(Calcutta:
Stanhope Press, 1892)
Tarlekar, G. H. "Some Puranic Legends Relating to Music,"
Journal of the Indian Musicological
Society,
Vol. 18,
No. 2 (December 1987), pp. 47-51
Tarnas, Richard. The Passion of the Western Mind:
Understanding
the Ideas That Have Shaped Our World View
(New York: Ballantine Books, 1991)
Taylor, A. E. A Commentary on Plato's
Oxford University Press, 1928)
Timaeus
(Oxford:
. Plato: The Man and His Work (Cleveland & New York:
Meridian, 1966)
Taylor, Henry Osborn. The Classical
Heritage
Ages (New York: Macmillan, 1929)
of the
Middle
Voie
589
Thorn, Johan C , trans. & ed. The Pythagorean
(Leiden, New York: E. J. Brill, 1995)
Golden
Verses
Light
of
Vol.
The Upanishads,
Prabhavananda and Manchester, trans. (New
York: New American Library, 1957)
Van Aalst, J. A. Chinese
Reprint Co., 1964)
(Seattle: University of
590
Musicological
pp. 64-72
Society,
Greek Music
591
. "yur Veda, Samkhya and the Time Theory of
Performance in Hindustani Classical Music," Journal of
Indian Philosophy and Religion,
Vol. 3 (October 1998),
pp. 91-123
and John Strohmeier. Divine Harmony: The Life and
Teachings of Pythagoras
(Berkeley, California: Berkeley
Hills Books, 1999)
Alfred North Whitehead, Science and the Modern World
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1928)
Whitney, William D. "On the History of the Vedic Texts,"
Journal of the American Oriental
Society,
Vol. IV
(1854), pp. 247-261
Wigner, Eugene P. "The Unreasonable Effectiveness of
Mathematics in the Natural Sciences," in Symmetries and
Reflections
(Bloomington & London: Indiana University
Press, 1967), pp. 222-237
Wilber, Ken. Up From Eden: A Transpersonal
View of Human
Evolution
(Garden City, New York: Anchor
Press/Doubleday, 1981)
. Eye to Eye: The Quest for the New Paradigm
York: Anchor/Doubleday, 198 3)
(New
(Wheaton, Illinois:
. A Brief History
Shamfoala, 1996)
of Everything
of Knowledge
Science
in the
(New
(Madras:
Mantra-astra
592
. Shakti
1978)
and Shakta
Tradition
Enlightenment
Age
Art and
Civilization
593
Zuckerkandl, Victor. Sound and Symbol: Music and the
External World (Princeton: Princeton University
Press, 1956)
CURRICULUM VITAE
Anthony Peter Westbrook
13012 Magellan Avenue
Rockville, MD 20853, U.S.A.
Tel: (301)946-1719
Email: [email protected]
DEGREE PROGRAMS
Ph.D in Musicology, University of Maryland, College Park,
2001
Graduate program in Ethnomusicology, University of
Washington, Seattle, Washington, 1980-82
M.A. in Interdisciplinary Studies, Maharishi International
University, Fairfield, Iowa, 1977
B.A. (Hons.) in English, California State University at
Sacramento, 1974
University of London, Liberal Arts program (English,
French, History), 1965-68
OTHER EDUCATION AND RESEARCH
Flute Masterclass, Dr. William Montgomery, University
of Maryland, auditor, July 1994, July 1995, July 1998
Research project in Europe and India entitled Ayur Veda,
Samkhya and the Time Theory of Performance in
Hindustani
Classical
Music, American Institute of Indian Studies,
1993-94
Research visit to Alain Dani61ou collection, Fondazione
Giorgio Cini, Venice, March 1992
Private instruction in Bansuri (bamboo flute) with Prof.
Debu Chaudhuri, Pandit Vijay Raghav Rao, & Pandit Hariprasad
Chaurasia, U.S.A., Holland and India, 1988-95
Courses in Hindustani music, theory and performance,
Gandharva School of Music, Washington, D.C., 1988-90
developing
PERFORMANCE
Freelance performer in multiple genres, flutef saxophone
clarinet. Washington D.C. areaf 1998-present
m
Member, Spontaneous
Groundbreaking
improvisation.
Recordings for
of Number. Vedic
February 2000-present
Journal,
May/June 1996
Siva-
Music, Metaphysics
and Meaning, Lecture S e r i e s , Birmingham
Conservatory, U n i v e r s i t y of Central England, Birmingham,
UK, March, 2001
Gandharva Veda: Rhythms and Cycles in Music and Nature,
Notes and Numbers, Lecture S e r i e s , Maharishi I n t e r n a t i o n a l
U n i v e r s i t y , Skelmersdale, UK, March 2001
Perennial Philosophy:
Operating Manual for
Spaceship
Earth, Manchester U n i v e r s i t y , Manchester, UK, March 2001
Utopia
or Oblivion,
The Divine Vina and the World Monochord: Marga Sanglta and
the Symmetries of Nature. Conference on Mysticism, Reason,
Art and Literature: East West Perspectives, Ferrum College,
Virginia, September, 2000
Member, Program Committee, International Interdisciplinary
Conference in Calcutta, India, 1-4 August, 2000 on Language,
Thought and Reality:
Science,
Religion
and
Philosophy.
Society for Indian Philosophy & Religion. Paper presented on
Orpheus, Hermes, Pythagoras and the Western Guruparampara
Tradition
Language, Number and Music: Root Metaphors in
Genesis,
f
the Rig Veda and Plato s
Timaeus. Society for Indian
Philosophy and Religion, Elon College, North Carolina,
April, 2000
The Perennial
Philosophy:
Operating Manual for
Spaceship
Earth. Dept. of Religion, Virginia Commonwealth University,
Richmond, Virginia, April, 2000
Divine Harmony: The Life and Teachings of
Pythagoras.
Transitions Learning Center, Chicago, Illinois, February,
2000
Knowledge for a Positive
Future: Veda, Svara and the
Shape of Time. Maharishi University of Management,
Fairfield, Iowa, January, 2000, Maharishi International
University, Skelmersdale, UK, May 2000
Music, Cosmos and Consciousness:
The Role of Music in the
Understanding
of Cultural History.
California Institute
for Integral Studies, San Francisco, May, 1999
The Harmonious Blacksmith:
Pythagoras
and the Origins
of
Western Music Theory. Dept. of Music, California State
University at Sacramento, May 1999
Tuning, Temperament and Symmetry,
Kentfield, California, May 1999
College of Marin,
Universal
Elements in Musical Cosmology, Traditional
Cosmology Society Conference, University of St. Andrews,
Scotland, June 1996; Temenos Academy, Prince of Wales
Institute of Architecture, London, May 1996; American
Musicological Society Conference, Fredericksburg, Virginia,
October 1995
Indian and Western Sources for the Music of the
Spheres,
Center for Advanced Studies, Skelmersdale, U.K., June 1996
Participant in conference, arngadeva Samaroh, Benares
Hindu University, Benares, India. Organized by Sangeet
Natak Akademi, New Delhi, India, February 1994
Research assistant and course contributor, Music 130,
University of Maryland, College Park, 1992/93
Paradigm Change and Human Consciousness.
Conference of
World Future Society, Cambridge, Massachussetts, May 1987
Paradigm Change and the Theory of Music. Conference on
Music: A Multidisciplinary Phenomenon, Immaculata College,
Immaculata, Pennsylvania, 1983
The Concept of Rasa in Hindustani
Classical
Music.
Conference on Consciousness and the Arts, University of
Sussex, Brighton, U.K., 1977
The Liberal Arts and the Future, Dublin, Cork and Limerick.
Lecture tour of Ireland for International Meditation
Society, March 1976
Sama Veda and the Tradition
of Song in North
University of Birmingham, U.K., 1972
Music and the Science of Creative
Intelligence,
State University, Humboldt, California, 1972
India,
California
OTHER EMPLOYMENT
Regional vice-president/ Primerica Financial Services,
Seattle, Washington & Bethesda, Maryland. Full time
1982-89/ part time, 1989-present
Independent software consultant for education and business
applications/ Seattle, Washington, 1981-84
Computer programmer and systems analyst. Nordata, Seattle,
Washington 1979-81
Director of Educational Programs, Intonation Systems,
Fairfield, Iowa, 1977-79
Elementary school teacher, Birmingham, U.K., 1963-65
REFERENCES
Professor Emeritus E. Eugene Helm, University of Maryland,
College Park. P.O. Box 1115, St. Michaels, Maryland 21663.
Tel:(410)745-5548 Fax:(410)770-9530. Email:[email protected]
Professor Suheil Bushrui, Baha'i' Chair for World Peace,
Center for International Development and Conflict
Management, Tydings Hall, University of Maryland, College
Park. Tel: (301)314-7715
Professor Daniel S. Godfrey, School of Music, 215 Crouse
College, Syracuse University, Syracuse, New York 13244-1010.
Tel:(315)443-2191/422-5317. E-mail:[email protected]
Professor Jonathan Shear, Dept. of Philosophy, Virginia
Commonwealth University, Richmond, Virginia 23284-2025;
Editor, Journal of Consciousness
Studies.
Tel/Fax:
(804)282-2119. Email:[email protected]
Professor Joscelyn Godwin, Dept. Of Music, Colgate
University, 13, Oak Drive, Hamilton, NY 13346-1398.
(315)691-6945. Email: [email protected]
Dr. Brian Q. Silver, Head, Urdu Section, Voice of America.
Executive Director, International Music Associates,
P.O. Box 15526, Washington, D.C. 20003-0526. Tel:
(202)397-6769 or (202)619-1933