Jump to content

Phylogenetic nomenclature

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
(Redirected from Phylogenetic name)
The clade shown by the dashed lines in each figure is specified by the ancestor X. Using the hypothesis that the relationships are as in the left tree diagram, the clade includes X, A, B and C. Using the hypothesis that the relationships are as in the right tree diagram, the clade includes X, A and B.

Phylogenetic nomenclature is a method of nomenclature for taxa in biology that uses phylogenetic definitions for taxon names as explained below. This contrasts with the traditional method, by which taxon names are defined by a type, which can be a specimen or a taxon of lower rank, and a description in words.[1] Phylogenetic nomenclature is regulated currently by the International Code of Phylogenetic Nomenclature (PhyloCode).

Definitions

[edit]

Phylogenetic nomenclature associates names with clades, groups consisting of an ancestor and all its descendants. Such groups are said to be monophyletic. There are slightly different methods of specifying the ancestor, which are discussed below. Once the ancestor is specified, the meaning of the name is fixed: the ancestor and all organisms which are its descendants are included in the taxon named. Listing all these organisms (i.e. providing a full circumscription) requires the complete phylogenetic tree to be known. In practice, there are almost always one or more hypotheses as to the correct relationship. Different hypotheses result in different organisms being thought to be included in the named taxon, but application to the name in the context of various phylogenies generally remains unambiguous. Possible exceptions occur for apomorphy-based definitions, when optimization of the defining apomorphy is ambiguous.[2]

Phylogenetic definitions of clade names

[edit]

Phylogenetic nomenclature assigns names to clades, groups consisting solely of an ancestor and all its descendants. All that is needed to specify a clade, therefore, is to designate the ancestor. There are a number of methods of doing this. Commonly, the ancestor is indicated by its relation to two or more specifiers (species, specimens, or traits) that are mentioned explicitly. The diagram shows three common ways of doing this. For previously defined clades A, B, and C, the clade X can be defined as:

The three most common ways to define the name of a clade: node-based, branch-based and apomorphy-based definition. The tree represents a phylogenetic hypothesis of the relations of A, B and C.
  • A node-based definition could read: "the last common ancestor of A and B, and all descendants of that ancestor". Thus, the entire line below the junction of A and B does not belong to the clade to which the name with this definition refers. A crown group is a type of node-based group where A and B are extant (living) taxa.
Example: The sauropod dinosaurs consist of the last common ancestor of Vulcanodon (A) and Apatosaurus (B)[3] and all of that ancestor's descendants. This ancestor was the first sauropod. C could include other dinosaurs like Stegosaurus.
  • A branch-based definition, often termed a stem-based definition, could read: "the first ancestor of A which is not also an ancestor of C, and all descendants of that ancestor". Thus, the entire line below the junction of A and B (other than the bottommost point) does belong to the clade to which the name with this definition refers. A pan-group or total group is a type of branch-based group where A and C are extant (living) taxa.
Example (also a total group): The rodents consist of the first ancestor of the house mouse (A) that is not also an ancestor of the eastern cottontail rabbit (C) together with all descendants of that ancestor. Here, the ancestor of A (but not C) is the very first rodent. B is some other descendant of that first rodent, perhaps the red squirrel.
  • An apomorphy-based definition could read: "the first ancestor of A to possess trait M that is inherited by A, and all descendants of that ancestor". In the diagram, M evolves at the intersection of the horizontal line with the tree. Thus, the clade to which the name with this definition refers contains that part of the line below the last common ancestor of A and B which corresponds to ancestors possessing the apomorphy M. The lower part of the line is excluded. It is not required that B have trait M; it may have disappeared in the lineage leading to B.
Example: the tetrapods consist of the first ancestor of humans (A) from which humans inherited limbs with fingers or toes (M) and all descendants of that ancestor. These descendants include snakes (B), which do not have limbs.

Several other alternatives are provided in the PhyloCode,[4] (see below) though there is no attempt to be exhaustive.

Phylogenetic nomenclature allows the use, not only of ancestral relations, but also of the property of being extant. One of the many methods of specifying the Neornithes (modern birds), for example, is:

The Neornithes consist of the last common ancestor of the extant members of the most inclusive clade containing the cockatoo Cacatua galerita but not the dinosaur Stegosaurus armatus, as well as all descendants of that ancestor.

Neornithes is a crown clade, a clade for which the last common ancestor of its extant members is also the last common ancestor of all its members.

Node names

[edit]
  • Crown node: Most recent common ancestor of the sampled species of the clade of interest.
  • Stem node: Most recent common ancestor of the clade of interest and its sibling clade.

Ancestry-based definitions of the names of paraphyletic and polyphyletic taxa

[edit]

For the PhyloCode, only a clade can receive a "phylogenetic definition", and this restriction is observed in the present article. However, it is also possible to create definitions for the names of other groups that are phylogenetic in the sense that they use only ancestral relations based on species or specimens.[5] For example, assuming Mammalia and Aves (birds) are defined in this manner, Amniotes could be defined as "the most recent common ancestor of Mammalia and Aves and all its descendants except Mammalia and Aves". This is an example of a paraphyletic group, a clade minus one or more subordinate clades. Names of polyphyletic groups, characterized by a trait that evolved convergently in two or more subgroups, can be defined similarly as the sum of multiple clades.[5]

Ranks

[edit]

Using the traditional nomenclature codes, such as the International Code of Zoological Nomenclature and the International Code of Nomenclature for algae, fungi, and plants, taxa that are not associated explicitly with a rank cannot be named formally, because the application of a name to a taxon is based on both a type and a rank. Thus for example the "family" Hominidae uses the genus Homo as its type; its rank (family) is indicated by the suffix -idae (see discussion below). The requirement for a rank is a major difference between traditional and phylogenetic nomenclature. It has several consequences: it limits the number of nested levels at which names can be applied; it causes the endings of names to change if a group has its rank changed, even if it has precisely the same members (i.e. the same circumscription); and it is logically inconsistent with all taxa being monophyletic.[citation needed]

The current codes have rules stating that names must have certain endings depending on the rank of the taxa to which they are applied. When a group has a different rank in different classifications, its name must have a different suffix. Ereshefsky (1997:512)[6] gave an example. He noted that Simpson in 1963 and Wiley in 1981 agreed that the same group of genera, which included the genus Homo, should be placed together in a taxon. Simpson treated this taxon as a family, and so gave it the name "Hominidae": "Homin-" from "Homo" and "-idae" as the suffix for family using the zoological code. Wiley considered it to be at the rank of "tribe", and so gave it the name "Hominini", "-ini" being the suffix for tribe. Wiley's tribe Hominini formed only part of a family which he termed "Hominidae". Thus, using the zoological code, two groups with precisely the same circumscription were given different names (Simpson's Hominidae and Wiley's Hominini), and two groups with the same name had different circumscriptions (Simpson's Hominidae and Wiley's Hominidae).

Especially in recent decades (due to advances in phylogenetics), taxonomists have named many "nested" taxa (i.e. taxa which are contained inside other taxa). No system of nomenclature attempts to name every clade; this would be particularly difficult with traditional nomenclature since every named taxon must be given a lower rank than any named taxon in which it is nested, so the number of names that can be assigned in a nested set of taxa can be no greater than the number of generally recognized ranks. Gauthier et al. (1988)[7] suggested that, if Reptilia is assigned its traditional rank of "class", then a phylogenetic classification has to assign the rank of genus to Aves.[6] In such a classification, all ~12,000 known species of extant and extinct birds would then have to be incorporated into this genus.

Various solutions have been proposed while keeping the rank-based nomenclature codes. Patterson and Rosen (1977)[8] suggested nine new ranks between family and superfamily in order to be able to classify a clade of herrings, and McKenna and Bell (1997)[9] introduced a large array of new ranks in order to cope with the diversity of Mammalia; these have not been adopted widely. For botany, the Angiosperm Phylogeny Group, responsible for the currently most widely used classification of flowering plants, chose a different method. They retained the traditional ranks of family and order, considering them to be of value for teaching and studying relationships between taxa, but also introduced named clades without formal ranks.[10]

For phylogenetic nomenclature, ranks have no bearing on the spelling of taxon names (see e.g. Gauthier (1994)[11] and the PhyloCode). Ranks are, however, not altogether forbidden for phylogenetic nomenclature. They are merely decoupled from nomenclature: they do not influence which names can be used, which taxa are associated with which names, and which names can refer to nested taxa.[12][13][14]

The principles of traditional rank-based nomenclature are incompatible logically with all taxa being strictly monophyletic.[12][15] Every organism must belong to a genus, for example, so there would have to be a genus for every common ancestor of the mammals and the birds. For such a genus to be monophyletic, it would have to include both the class Mammalia and the class Aves. For rank-based nomenclature, however, classes must include genera, not the other way around.[citation needed]

Philosophy

[edit]

The conflict between phylogenetic and traditional nomenclature represents differing opinions of the metaphysics and epistemology of taxa. For the advocates of phylogenetic nomenclature, a taxon is an individual entity, an entity that may gain and lose attributes as time passes.[16] Just as a person does not become somebody else when his or her properties change through maturation, senility, or more radical changes like amnesia, the loss of a limb, or a change of sex, so a taxon remains the same entity whatever characteristics are gained or lost.[17] Given the metaphysical claims regarding unobservable entities made by advocates of phylogenetic nomenclature, critics have referred to their method as origin essentialism. [18][19]

For any individual, there has to be something that associates its temporal stages with each other by virtue of which it remains the same entity. For a person, the spatiotemporal continuity of the body provides the relevant conceptual continuity; from infancy to old age, the body traces a continuous path through the world and it is this continuity, rather than any characteristics of the individual, that associates the baby with the octogenarian.[20] This is similar to the well-known philosophical problem of the Ship of Theseus. For a taxon, IF characteristics are not relevant, THEN it can only be ancestral relations that associate the Devonian Rhyniognatha hirsti with the modern monarch butterfly as representatives, separated by 400 million years, of the taxon Insecta.[17] The opposing opinion questions the premise of that syllogism, and argues, from an epistemological perspective, that members of taxa are only recognizable empirically on the basis of their observable characteristics, and hypotheses of common ancestry are results of theoretical systematics, not a priori premises. If there are no characteristics that allow scientists to recognize a fossil as belonging to a taxonomic group, then it is just an unclassifiable piece of rock.[21]

If ancestry is sufficient for the continuity of a taxon, then all descendants of a taxon member will also be included in the taxon, so all bona fide taxa are monophyletic; the names of paraphyletic groups do not merit formal recognition. As "Pelycosauria" refers to a paraphyletic group that includes some Permian tetrapods but not their extant descendants, it cannot be admitted as a valid taxon name. Again, while not disagreeing with the notion that only monophyletic groups should be named, empiricist systematists counter this ancestry essentialism by pointing out that pelycosaurs are recognized as paraphyletic precisely because they exhibit a combination of synapomorphies and symplesiomorphies indicating that some of them are more closely related to mammals than they are to other pelycosaurs. The material existence of an assemblage of fossils and its status as a clade are not the same issue. Monophyletic groups are worthy of attention and naming because they share properties of interest -- synapomorphies -- that are the evidence that allows inference of common ancestry.[22]

History

[edit]
"Monophyletic phylogenetic tree of organisms".[23]

Phylogenetic nomenclature is a semantic extension of the general acceptance of the idea of branching during the course of evolution, represented in the diagrams of Jean-Baptiste Lamarck and later writers like Charles Darwin and Ernst Haeckel.[24][25] In 1866, Haeckel for the first time constructed a single relational diagram of all life based on the existing classification of life accepted at the time. This classification was rank-based, but did not contain taxa that Haeckel considered polyphyletic. In it, Haeckel introduced the rank of phylum which carries a connotation of monophyly in its name (literally meaning "stem").[citation needed]

Ever since, it has been debated in which ways and to what extent the understanding of the phylogeny of life should be used as a basis for its classification, with opinions including "numerical taxonomy" (phenetics), "evolutionary taxonomy" (gradistics), and "phylogenetic systematics". From the 1960s onwards, rankless classifications were occasionally proposed, but in general the principles and common language of traditional nomenclature have been used by all three schools of thought.[citation needed]

Most of the basic tenets of phylogenetic nomenclature (lack of obligatory ranks, and something close to phylogenetic definitions) can, however, be traced to 1916, when Edwin Goodrich[26] interpreted the name Sauropsida, defined 40 years earlier by Thomas Henry Huxley, to include the birds (Aves) as well as part of Reptilia, and invented the new name Theropsida to include the mammals as well as another part of Reptilia. As these taxa were separate from traditional zoological nomenclature, Goodrich did not emphasize ranks, but he clearly discussed the diagnostic features necessary to recognize and classify fossils belonging to the various groups. For example, in regard to the fifth metatarsal of the hind leg, he said "the facts support our view, for these early reptiles have normal metatarsals like their Amphibian ancestors. It is clear, then, that we have here a valuable corroborative character to help us to decide whether a given species belongs to the Theropsidan or the Sauropsidan line of evolution." Goodrich concluded his paper: "The possession of these characters shows that all living Reptilia belong to the Sauropsidan group, while the structure of the foot enables us to determine the affinities of many incompletely known fossil genera, and to conclude that only certain extinct orders can belong to the Theropsidan branch." Goodrich opined that the name Reptilia should be abandoned once the phylogeny of the reptiles was better known.[citation needed]

The principle that only clades should be named formally became popular among some researchers during the second half of the 20th century. It spread together with the methods for discovering clades (cladistics) and is an integral part of phylogenetic systematics (see above). At the same time, it became apparent that the obligatory ranks that are part of the traditional systems of nomenclature produced problems. Some authors suggested abandoning them altogether, starting with Willi Hennig's abandonment[27] of his earlier proposal to define ranks as geological age classes.[28][29]

The first use of phylogenetic nomenclature in a publication can be dated to 1986.[30] Theoretical papers outlining the principles of phylogenetic nomenclature, as well as further publications containing applications of phylogenetic nomenclature (mostly to vertebrates), soon followed (see Literature section).

In an attempt to avoid a schism among the systematics community, "Gauthier suggested to two members of the ICZN to apply formal taxonomic names ruled by the zoological code only to clades (at least for supraspecific taxa) and to abandon Linnean ranks, but these two members promptly rejected these ideas".[31] The premise of names in traditional nomenclature is based, ultimately, on type specimens, and the circumscription of groups is considered a taxonomic choice made by the systematists working on particular groups, rather than a nomenclatural decision made based on a priori rules of the Codes on Nomenclature.[32] The desire to subsume taxonomic circumscriptions within nomenclatural definitions caused Kevin de Queiroz and the botanist Philip Cantino to start drafting their own code of nomenclature, the PhyloCode, to regulate phylogenetic nomenclature.[citation needed]

Controversy

[edit]

Willi Hennig's pioneering work provoked a controversy[33] about the relative merits of phylogenetic nomenclature versus Linnaean taxonomy, or the related method of evolutionary taxonomy, which has continued to the present.[34] Some of the controversies with which the cladists were engaged had been happening since the 19th century.[35] While Hennig insisted that different classification schemes were useful for different purposes,[36] he gave primacy to his own, claiming that the categories of his system had "individuality and reality" in contrast to the "timeless abstractions" of classifications based on overall similarity.[37]

Formal classifications based on cladistic reasoning are said to emphasize ancestry at the expense of descriptive characteristics. Nonetheless, most taxonomists presently avoid paraphyletic groups whenever they think it is possible within Linnaean taxonomy; polyphyletic taxa have long been unfashionable. Many cladists claim that the traditional Codes of Zoological and Botanical Nomenclature are fully compatible with cladistic methods, and that there is no need to reinvent a system of names that has functioned well for 250 years,[38][39][40] but others argue that this system is not as effective as it should be and that it is time to adopt nomenclatural principles that represent divergent evolution as a mechanism that explains much of the known biodiversity.[41][42] In fact, calls to reform biological nomenclature were made even before phylogenetic nomenclature was developed.[43]

The International Code of Phylogenetic Nomenclature

[edit]

The ICPN, or PhyloCode, is a code of rules and recommendations for phylogenetic nomenclature.

  • The ICPN only regulates clade names. Names for species rely on the rules of the traditional codes of nomenclature.
  • The Principle of Priority (or "precedence") is claimed for names and for definitions within the ICPN. The starting point for priority was April 30, 2020.
  • Definitions for existing names, and new names along with their definitions, must be published in peer-reviewed works (on or after the starting date) and must be registered in an online database in order to be valid.

The number of supporters for widespread adoption of the PhyloCode is still small, and it is uncertain how widely it will be followed.

References

[edit]
  1. ^ International Commission on Zoological Nomenclature (1999). "Glossary". International Code of Zoological Nomenclature (4th ed.). International Trust for Zoological Nomenclature, c/o Natural History Museum. ISBN 978-0-85301-006-7.
  2. ^ Sereno, Paul C. (1 August 2005). "The Logical Basis of Phylogenetic Taxonomy". Systematic Biology. 54 (4): 595–619. doi:10.1080/106351591007453.
  3. ^ Benton, Michael J. (2005). Vertebrate Palaeontology. Blackwell. p. 214. ISBN 978-0-632-05637-8.
  4. ^ Cantino, Philip D. & de Queiroz, Kevin (2010). "Article 9. General Requirements for Establishment of Clade Names". International Code of Phylogenetic Nomenclature. 4c. note 9.3.1..
  5. ^ a b de Queiroz, K.; Gauthier, J. (1990). "Phylogeny as a central principle in taxonomy: phylogenetic definitions of taxon names". Systematic Zoology. 39 (4): 307–322. doi:10.2307/2992353. JSTOR 2992353.
  6. ^ a b Ereshefsky, M. (1997). "The Evolution of the Linnaean Hierarchy". Biology and Philosophy. 12 (4): 493–519. doi:10.1023/A:1006556627052. S2CID 83251018.
  7. ^ Gauthier, J., Estes, R. & de Queiroz, K. 1988. A Phylogenetic Analysis of Lepidosauromorpha. Pp. 15–98 in R. Estes & G. Pregill (eds): Phylogenetic Relationships of the Lizard Families: Essays Commemorating Charles L. Camp. Stanford University Press. ISBN 978-0-8047-1435-8
  8. ^ Patterson, C. & Rosen, D. 1977 Review of ichthyodectiform and other Mesozoic teleost fishes and the theory and practice of classifying fossils. Bulletin of the American Museum of Natural History 158: 81–172.
  9. ^ McKenna, M. C. & Bell, S. K. 1997. Classification of Mammals Above the Species Level. Columbia University Press. ISBN 0-231-11012-X
  10. ^ Angiosperm Phylogeny Group (1998). "An ordinal classification for the families of flowering plants". Annals of the Missouri Botanical Garden. 85 (4): 531–553. doi:10.2307/2992015. JSTOR 2992015. S2CID 82134384.
  11. ^ Gauthier, J. A. (1994). "The diversification of the amniotes". In D. R. Prothero; Rainer R. Schoch (eds.). Major features of vertebrate evolution. Paleontological Society. pp. 129–159.
  12. ^ a b de Queiroz, K.; Gauthier, J. (1992). "Phylogenetic taxonomy". Annu. Rev. Ecol. Syst. 23: 449–480. doi:10.1146/annurev.es.23.110192.002313.
  13. ^ Cantino, P. D. (2000). "Phylogenetic nomenclature: addressing some concerns". Taxon. 49 (1): 85–93. doi:10.2307/1223935. JSTOR 1223935.
  14. ^ Bryant, H. N.; Cantino, P. D. (2002). "A review of criticisms of phylogenetic nomenclature: is taxonomic freedom the fundamental issue?". Biol. Rev. 77 (1): 39–55. doi:10.1017/S1464793101005802. PMID 11911373. S2CID 20518066.
  15. ^ Kazlev, M. A. "Cladistic and Linnaean systems — incompatible or complementary?". palaeos.com. Archived from the original on July 10, 2017. Retrieved September 30, 2012.
  16. ^ Assis, L. C. S.; Brigandt, I. (2009). "Homology: Homeostatic Property Cluster Kinds in Systematics and Evolution" (PDF). Evolutionary Biology. 36 (2): 248–255. doi:10.1007/s11692-009-9054-y. S2CID 363300.[permanent dead link]
  17. ^ a b Rowe, Timothy (1988). "Definition, diagnosis, and origin of Mammalia" (PDF). Journal of Vertebrate Paleontology. 8 (3): 241–264. doi:10.1080/02724634.1988.10011708.
  18. ^ Winsor, Mary P. (2009). "Taxonomy was the foundation of Darwin's evolution". Taxon. 58: 43–49. doi:10.1002/tax.581007.
  19. ^ Rieppel, Olivier (2010). "New essentiaism in biology". Philosophy of Science. 36 (5): 662–673. doi:10.1086/656539. S2CID 86958171.
  20. ^ Wiggins, David (1967). Identity and Spatio-temporal Continuity. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0631103707.
  21. ^ Brower, Andrew V.Z. (2016). "Tree-thinking". Inference. 2.
  22. ^ Hennig 1966, p. 93.
  23. ^ Haeckel, E. H. Ph. A. 1866. Generelle Morphologie der Organismen. Georg Reimer.
  24. ^ Ragan, Mark A. (2009). "Trees and networks before and after Darwin". Biology Direct. 4 (43): 43. doi:10.1186/1745-6150-4-43. PMC 2793248. PMID 19917100.
  25. ^ Tassy, Pascal (May 2011). "Trees before and after Darwin: Trees before and after Darwin". Journal of Zoological Systematics and Evolutionary Research. 49 (2): 89–101. doi:10.1111/j.1439-0469.2010.00585.x.
  26. ^ Goodrich, E. S. (1916). "On the classification of the Reptilia". Proceedings of the Royal Society B. 89 (615): 261–276. Bibcode:1916RSPSB..89..261G. doi:10.1098/rspb.1916.0012.
  27. ^ Hennig, W. 1969. Die Stammesgeschichte der Insekten. Waldemar Kramer.
  28. ^ Hennig, W. 1950. Grundzüge einer Theorie der phylogenetischen Systematik. Deutscher Zentralverlag.
  29. ^ Hennig, W. (1965). "Phylogenetic Systematics". Annual Review of Entomology. 10: 97–116. doi:10.1146/annurev.en.10.010165.000525.
  30. ^ Gauthier, J. (1986). "Saurischian Monophyly and the Origin of Birds". In K. Padian (ed.). The Origin of Birds and the Evolution of Flight. Memoir 8 of the California Academy of Sciences. pp. 1–55.
  31. ^ Laurin, M. (2008). "The splendid isolation of biological nomenclature". Zoologica Scripta. 37 (2): 223–233. doi:10.1111/j.1463-6409.2007.00318.x. S2CID 85020798.
  32. ^ Brower, Andrew V. Z. (2020). "Dead on arrival: a postmortem assessment of "phylogenetic nomenclature", 20+ years on". Cladistics. 37 (6): 627–637. doi:10.1111/cla.12432. S2CID 224927279.
  33. ^ Wheeler, Quentin (2000). Species Concepts and Phylogenetic Theory: A Debate. Columbia University Press. ISBN 978-0-231-10143-1.
  34. ^ Benton, M. J. (2000). "Stems, nodes, crown clades, and rank-free lists: is Linnaeus dead?" (PDF). Biological Reviews. 75 (4): 633–648. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.573.4518. doi:10.1111/j.1469-185X.2000.tb00055.x. PMID 11117201. S2CID 17851383. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2017-08-09. Retrieved 2011-08-26.
  35. ^ Hull, David (1988). Science as a Process. University of Chicago Press. pp. 232–276. ISBN 978-0-226-36051-5.
  36. ^ Hennig 1966, p. 9.
  37. ^ Hennig 1966, p. 81.
  38. ^ Nixon, Kevin C., and James M. Carpenter. "On the other "phylogenetic systematics"." Cladistics 16, no. 3 (2000): 298-318.
  39. ^ Schuh, Randall T. "The Linnaean system and its 250-year persistence." The Botanical Review 69, no. 1 (2003): 59.
  40. ^ Brower, Andrew VZ. "Dead on arrival: a postmortem assessment of "phylogenetic nomenclature", 20+ years on." (2020) Cladistics 36(6):627-637.
  41. ^ Laurin, Michel (3 August 2023). The Advent of PhyloCode: The Continuing Evolution of Biological Nomenclature. CRC Press. doi:10.1201/9781003092827. ISBN 978-1-003-09282-7.
  42. ^ Laurin, Michel (23 July 2023). "The PhyloCode : The logical outcome of millennia of evolution of biological nomenclature?". Zoologica Scripta. 52 (6): 543–555. doi:10.1111/zsc.12625. ISSN 0300-3256.
  43. ^ Hull, David L. (1964). "Consistency and Monophyly". Systematic Zoology. 13 (1): 1–11. doi:10.2307/2411431. ISSN 0039-7989. JSTOR 2411431.

Sources

[edit]
  • Hennig, Willi (1966). Phylogenetic systematics. Translated by D. Dwight Davis; Rainer Zangerl. Urbana, IL: Univ. of Illinois Press. p. 9. ISBN 978-0-252-06814-0. (reprinted 1979 and 1999)

Further reading

[edit]

A few publications not cited in the references are cited here. An exhaustive list of publications about phylogenetic nomenclature can be found on the website of the International Society for Phylogenetic Nomenclature.

  • Bryant, Harold N. (1994). "Comments on the phylogenetic definition of taxon names and conventions regarding the naming of crown clades". Syst. Biol. 43: 124–129. doi:10.1093/sysbio/43.1.124.
  • Cantino, Philip D.; Olmstead, Richard G. (2008). "Application of phylogenetically defined names does not require that every specifier be present on a tree". Syst. Biol. 57 (1): 157–160. doi:10.1080/10635150701883873. PMID 18300028.
  • de Queiroz, Kevin (1992). Phylogenetic definitions and taxonomic philosophy. Biol. Philos. 7:295–313.
  • Gauthier, Jacques A., Arnold G. Kluge, and Timothy Rowe (1988). The early evolution of the Amniota. Pages 103–155 in Michael J. Benton (ed.): The Phylogeny and Classification of the Tetrapods, Volume 1: Amphibians, Reptiles, Birds. Syst. Ass. Spec. Vol. 35A. Clarendon Press, Oxford.
  • Gauthier, Jacques, David Cannatella, Kevin de Queiroz, Arnold G. Kluge, and Timothy Rowe (1989). Tetrapod phylogeny. Pages 337–353 in B. Fernholm, K. Bremer, and H. Jörnvall (eds.): The Hierarchy of Life. Elsevier Science B. V. (Biomedical Division), New York.
  • Ghiselin, M. T. (1984). "Definition," "character," and other equivocal terms". Syst. Zool. 33 (1): 104–110. doi:10.2307/2413135. JSTOR 2413135.
  • Keesey, T. Michael (2007). "A mathematical approach to defining clade names, with potential applications to computer storage and processing". Zool. Scr. 36 (6): 607–621. doi:10.1111/j.1463-6409.2007.00302.x. S2CID 83862527.
  • Laurin, Michel (2005). The advantages of phylogenetic nomenclature over Linnean nomenclature. Pages 67–97 in A. Minelli, G. Ortalli, and G. Sanga (eds): Animal Names. Instituto Veneto di Scienze, Lettere ed Arti; Venice.
  • Lee, Michael S. Y. (2005). "Choosing reference taxa in phylogenetic nomenclature". Zool. Scr. 34 (3): 329–331. doi:10.1111/j.1463-6409.2005.00196.x. S2CID 86329828.
  • Rowe, Timothy (1987). "Definition and diagnosis in the phylogenetic system". Syst. Zool. 36 (2): 208–211. doi:10.2307/2413270. JSTOR 2413270.
  • Rowe, Timothy; Gauthier, Jacques (1992). "Ancestry, paleontology and definition of the name Mammalia". Syst. Biol. 41 (3): 372–378. doi:10.1093/sysbio/41.3.372. S2CID 86132781.
  • Sereno, Paul C. (1998). "A rationale for phylogenetic definitions, with application to the higher-level taxonomy of Dinosauria". Neues Jahrbuch für Geologie und Paläontologie - Abhandlungen. 210: 41–83. doi:10.1127/njgpa/210/1998/41.
  • Sereno, Paul C. (1999). "Definitions in phylogenetic taxonomy: critique and rationale". Syst. Biol. 48 (2): 329–351. doi:10.1080/106351599260328. PMID 12066711.
  • Sereno, Paul C. (2005). "The Logical Basis of Phylogenetic Taxonomy". Syst. Biol. 54 (4): 595–619. doi:10.1080/106351591007453. PMID 16109704.
  • Taylor, Michael P. (2007). "Phylogenetic definitions in the pre-PhyloCode era; implications for naming clades under the PhyloCode". PaleoBios. 27: 1–6.
  • Wilkinson, Mark (2006). "Identifying stable reference taxa for phylogenetic nomenclature". Zool. Scr. 35: 109–112. doi:10.1111/j.1463-6409.2005.00213.x. S2CID 85702468.
  • Wyss, A. R.; Meng, J. (1996). "Application of phylogenetic taxonomy to poorly resolved crown clades: a stem-modified node-based definition of Rodentia". Syst. Biol. 45 (4): 559–568. doi:10.1093/sysbio/45.4.559.